ArticlePDF Available

Heidegger on the History of Machination

Authors:

Abstract

Heidegger’s discussion about the rise of the arbitrary power of “machination” (Machenschaft) in his late 1930s writings does not just echo his well-known later thinking on technology, but also affords a profound insight to the ontological mechanism of oblivion behind the history of Western thinking of being. The paper shows how this rise of the coercive power of ordering (Machenschaft) signifies an emergence of historically and spatially significant moment of completion: outgrowth of the early Greek notions of tekhne and phusis in terms of globally expanding systems of calculative orderings. The paper thus aims to show how the condition of machination marks a fundamental implementation of the hidden consummation of the mechanism of oblivion now being re-adopted into the operational clarity of calculative rationality. It is argued that the rise of machination became possible through the historical process of replacing the early Greek disposition of existence, the wonder, with calculative rationalit...
[CRIT 13.3 (2012) 351-376] Critical Horizons (print) ISSN 1440-9917
doi:10.1558/crit.v13i3.351 Critical Horizons (online) ISSN 1568-5160
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012, Unit S3, Kelham House, 3 Lancaster Street, Sheeld, S3 8AF.
Heidegger on the History of Machination:
Oblivion of Being as Degradation of Wonder
Mikko Joronen
Department of Geography and Geology, University of Turku, Finland
mikko.joronen@utu.
Abstract: Heidegger’s discussion about the rise of the arbitrary power of
“machination” (Machenschaft) in his late 1930s writings does not just
echo his well-known later thinking on technology, but also aords a pro-
found insight to the ontological mechanism of oblivion behind the his-
tory of Western thinking of being. e paper shows how this rise of the
coercive power of ordering (Machenschaft) signies an emergence of his-
torically and spatially signicant moment of completion: outgrowth of
the early Greek notions of tekhne and phusis in terms of globally expand-
ing systems of calculative orderings. e paper thus aims to show how
the condition of machination marks a fundamental implementation of
the hidden consummation of the mechanism of oblivion now being re-
adopted into the operational clarity of calculative rationality. It is argued
that the rise of machination became possible through the historical pro-
cess of replacing the early Greek disposition of existence, the wonder, with
calculative rationality of ordering.
Keywords: Being; Event; genealogy, Greek philosophy; Heidegger; mach-
ination; tekhne; wonder.
In Beiträge zur Philosophie (vom Ereignis) (Contributions to Philosophy [from
Enowning]), dating back to 1936–1938, Heidegger invokes perhaps one
of the most groundbreaking discussions concerning his notion about the
Event of being (das Ereignis). Although being signicant in more than one
way, this discussion, especially its way of emphasizing the simultaneous
happening of both, being (Sein) as a “ground of beings” (Seiendheit) and
be-ing (Seyn) as a “groundless openness” for the plenitude of unfolding,
claries the ontological ambiguity constitutive for Heidegger’s understand-
ing of being and its “happening” (das Ereignis). is paper aims to show
how this ontological ambiguity also leads to ambiguous understanding
about the history of being (das Geschichte des Seyns). By inconspicuously
352 MIKKO JORONEN
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
unfolding a clearing of disclosure, yet only by concealing the fundamental
openness for the other modes of unfolding to take place, such Event leads
into a succession of nite happenings of concealing-revealing.1 e danger
is, as Heidegger claims, that we forget that particular monopolizations of
unfolding, our necessary “as”-takings and “is”-sayings through which we
understand things indirectly (i.e. ontologically) through their mode of
unfolding, only stand forth as nite Events holding sway against the open
be-ing, against the openness for the other unfolding to come about. Hence,
the danger is that we end up in the oblivion of open be-ing via its ground-
ing into metaphysically frozen and closed condition behind the presence of
things. Such metaphysical oblivion, then, is an unfortunate, yet not neces-
sary, historical epiphenomenon of the original concealment of open be-ing,
a way of grounding that completely loses the sense about the concealed
possibilities of open be-ing. By creating an illusion that there is an ultimate
ground of “beingness”(Seiendheit) behind the presence of things, a meta-
physical condition of “permanent presence”, Western tradition of thinking
has faded the nitude of unfolding to the background and hence darkened
the original openness of be-ing.2
Accordingly, such oblivion of be-ing, of its openness and nitude, con-
stitutes a double stance in relation to the question of history. On the one
hand, history builds fundamentally on the process of oblivion, on the total
concealment of be-ing and its nite happening through dierent monopo-
lizations of unfolding. On the other hand, history is an outcome of the
1. See M. Heidegger, On Time and Being, J. Stambaugh (trans.) (New York: Harper &
Row, 1972); M. Heidegger, “e Principle of Ground”, Man and World 7, no. 3 (1974),
K.Hoeller (trans.): 211–12; P. Livingston, “inking and Being: Heidegger and Wittgen-
stein on Machination and Lived-Experience”, Inquiry 46, no. 3 (2003): 327.
2. In such metaphysical understanding being becomes thought of, but only as “beingness
(Seiendheit) of beings”. Against this notion of “being as beingness”, the renewed version
of ontological dierence between Seyn and Sein proposes a possibility to think of the
unfolding of being (Sein) through its metaphysical (and onto-theological) determination
as “beingness” (Seiendheit), so that such thinking becomes possible, not out of beings
(since this would lead to a mere discovery of their “beingness”), but against the openness
of be-ing (Seyn) from which the meaning of “being” (Sein), hidden within “beingness”
(Seindheit), was granted in the rst place. e reason metaphysical thought is only capable
of thinking “being” (Sein) in terms of “beingness (Seiendheit) of beings” (Seiende) is due
to the fact that in its search of permanent ground for things metaphysical thought cannot
think of anything that is groundless, i.e., something that signies an obscure and contin-
gent openness against which all possible grounds of unfolding took place in the rst place:
the abyss of open be-ing (Seyn). See G. J. Seidel, “Musing with Kierkegaard: Heidegger’s
Besinnung”, Continental Philosophy Review 34, no. 4 (2001): 207; and R. Polt, e Emer-
gency of Being: On Heidegger’s Contribution to Philosophy (Ithaca, NY and London: Cornell
University Press, 2006), 193.
HEIDEGGER ON THE HISTORY OF MACHINATION 353
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
hidden incubation of what Heidegger calls a release of the latent powers
of “Machination” (Machenschaft), a disposition concentrating solely on
the manipulation of beings at the expense of losing the question of being.
By struggling with the issues of concealment and unfolding, limits and
openness, incubation and discontinuity, as well as of the in-historical and
non-historical ambiguity of the succession of Events the paper proposes
genealogical interpretation on Heidegger’s view of history as a process of
disposure based on inceptive metaphysical movement of the early Greek
thought.
e rst part of the paper discusses Heidegger’s understanding about
history in terms of oblivion of being in general terms. By building on
this, the second part of the paper shows how, through the mechanism of
oblivion (through the metaphysical grounding of unfolding into perma-
nent condition behind the presence of things) the legacy of Western think-
ing has created hidden incubation based on release of the latent powers
implicit in the rst metaphysical articulations of the early Greek thinkers.
It focuses on the creation of hidden potentialities for the emergence of pri-
mordial quality of unfolding Heidegger calls machination (Machenschaft),
especially on its inauguration in the early Greek notions of tekhne, phusis
and the basic attunement of wonder. e paper concludes by arguing for
spatial implications of such an incubation process: eventually the process,
the disposure of history, leads into an age of planetary technology, hence
releasing, through Nietzsches nal preparation, what is most essential for
the logic of machination.
Twofold Ambiguity: Between History and the Hidden Abyss
One can always suspect the obscurity of Heidegger’s way of discussing the
unfolding of being and its history in terms of oblivion of the self-concealing
mechanism of be-ing. At the same time Heidegger’s recovery of be-ing from
the sediments of metaphysical thinking is precisely a thinking about what
is “indenable” and comes “without ground”, and so it attempts to nd
proper ways to express this unspeakable richness and groundless abun-
dance against which the giving of every grounding intelligibility occurs.
In order to do so, Heidegger needs to articulate a way through which it
becomes possible to escape the roots of the prevailing epochal intelligibil-
ity, the imperatives and historical preparation of contemporary culmina-
tion of metaphysics in machination. As Feenberg claries, Heidegger is
“attempting to think the Western metaphysical tradition as a whole with-
out being limited to the terms of its latest stage, the stage in which, of
354 MIKKO JORONEN
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
course, he himself is situated”.3 In order to overcome the tradition of meta-
physical determinations, Heidegger simply cannot use the concepts and the
language of the tradition, but needs to struggle against the legacy, which
means the more familiar concepts of the tradition cannot serve as explana-
tions, but become something we need to explain. Instead of the concepts
of the tradition Heidegger therefore talks about “revealings” and “conceal-
ments” that these concepts bring about.
It is in this way that Heidegger is capable of providing conceptual appa-
ratuses, which rise out of the very history he is trying to explain and over-
come, while at the same the fundamental aim is to think of the lost, but
intrinsic source of the whole tradition of oblivion precisely through the his-
tory this source itself has granted and made possible. is ultimate source
is what Heidegger calls open being (or be-ing by underlining its originary
non-metaphysical openness), while the hidden history the source of open-
ness has granted he discusses in terms of the Event of being (or the Event of
“appropriation”/“unfolding” as Ereignis is also translated). Heidegger, thus,
can properly struggle against the tradition of oblivion by showing how its
conceptual bedrocks and ontological standpoints have always worked in
accordance with the same mechanism of unfolding, which due to the meta-
physical mutations has lead to the obscuring legacy based on the growing
oblivion of be-ing. Genealogical exploration should thus aim to show how
dierent metaphysical intelligibilities have a common source on a broader
mechanism – on a mechanism of unfolding that reveals things by conceal-
ing other possible modes of unfolding – by following the oblivion, the
succession of metaphysical bedrocks, and hence retrace its concealed source
as well as the origin of the whole process of concealment. Such process of
recovery is thus constituted as a historical uncovering of the fundamental
force of be-ing – a force that has been operative throughout the history
without ever being allowed to unfold its mechanism of nite giving. It
is through such recovery of the genealogy of the oblivion of being that it
becomes possible to gain an access to the deeper mechanism of Appropria-
tion, to a mechanism that has made possible the whole history of dierent
and diering mutations of unfolding by covering their ownmost source –
the inexhaustible abyss of open be-ing – and their nitude – their nature as
the nite Events. All in all, Heideggers notion of the “Event of Appropria-
tion” (Ereignis) denotes neither a new concept nor a new ontological bed-
rock that would allow for a completely new (post-modern) epochal horizon
of unfolding to come about, but something that has already constituted a
3. A. Feenberg, Heidegger and Marcuse: e Catastrophe and Redemption of History. New York
and London: Routledge, 22.
HEIDEGGER ON THE HISTORY OF MACHINATION 355
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
whole legacy of unfolding without ever being allowed to unfold its mecha-
nism of nite giving, its nature as a nite Event. Strictly speaking, then,
such genealogy of dierent modes of unfolding is not based on a “process”
at all, but upon “disposure” of nite Events appropriating their unfolding
out of the open be-ing.
According to Heidegger the originary “in-ception” (An-fang) of oblivion
was rst prepared and articulated by the early Greek philosophers. It was
Plato who collected the strains of pre-Socratic thought so that Aristotle
was capable of articulating the “unthought” of this collection in terms of
what formed the originary onto-theological constitution of “metaphysics of
presence”. Basically such “metaphysics of presence”, the “rst beginning”
of oblivion, denes what is the permanent presence of entities “that are”.
Metaphysical thinking thus has an onto-theological structure: it is both an
ontological decision concerning the essence of beings, their “whatness”,
as well as a theological decision concerning the existence of beings, their
“thatness”. e ontological sense of metaphysics thus asks what makes entity
an entity – it asks what is essential to things, what is their essence, the most
general ground shared by all entities. e theological sense of metaphysics,
in turn, seeks to explain the “thatness” of entities, the highest being which
counts for all beings. By asking “what is that which is” it thus seeks not just
the most higher and paradigmatic sense, but also in what sense this higher
sense exists.4
According to Heidegger, the onto-theological mechanism of oblivion
was rst articulated by Aristotle in his twofold notion of ousia as “pri-
mary substance” dening whether something exists (that it is present) and
4. See Heidegger, “Kant’s esis about Being”, in Pathmarks, T. E. Klein Jr. & W. E. Pohl
(trans.), 337–63 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998b), 340 and M. Heidegger,
Identity and Dierence (Chicago, IL and London: e University of Chicago Press, 2002),
70. As omson adds, theological sense of metaphysics seeks to know the two intertwined
aspects concerning the metaphysical understanding of beingness of beings: “which entity
is the highest and in what way is it”. Altogether, the onto-theological mechanism moulds
an ultimate metaphysical ground, which denes the essence (or “whatness”) of the totality
of beings as well as the highest principle (or “thatness”) upon which entities are existing
– as onto-theology metaphysics establishes the unity of permanence concerning how and
what entities are. In both occasions thinking (as onto-theology) falls to emphasize the met-
aphysical ground of things and thus ignores the question of the happening of being, the
Event of unfolding through which being took place and so aorded foundation for enti-
ties to become grounded through metaphysical mouldings. I. D. omson, Heidegger on
Ontotheology: Technology and the Politics of Education (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2005), 15, 30–35; See also A. A. Vallega, Heidegger and the Issue of Space: inking
on Exilic Grounds (University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2003), 44–56;
J. Backman, “Divine and Mortal Motivation: On the Movement of Life in Aristotle and
Heidegger”, Continental Philosophy Review 38, nos. 3-4 (2006): 241–61.
356 MIKKO JORONEN
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
“secondary substance” dening what something (that is present) is. In
other words, by articulating the notion of ousia by virtue of (1) whether
something exists (that it is present; prote ousia, “primary substance”), and
(2) what something is (deutera ousia, “secondary substance”), Aristotle
was the rst to articulate the onto-theological dierence between that-
ness (existence) and whatness (essence), so dening the rst permanently
enduring ground behind the presence of things (i.e. the “metaphysics
of presence”).5 However, as Heidegger writes, “this occurred after Plato’s
thinking had responded to the claim of being in a way that prepared that
distinction”, which means that Aristotle articulated what Plato already
prepared without yet formulating it.6 Even though Plato thought being in
terms of supraheavenly essences (ideas), while Aristotle managed to plant
these essences back to actual things (as energeia), they both shared the ini-
tial onto-theological structure manifested in all metaphysical mutations:
the idea that beings are governed by the “substance” of perfectly complete
and everlastingly enduring presence of metaphysical ground.7 In other
words, Aristotle’s notion of ousia articulated the “unthought” of Plato
by dening on what ground things are present, so that such denition
became the self-evident dierence between the existence and essence in
medieval scholasticism – a dierence that Nietzsche turned upside down
in a manner that “ultimately though indirectly” had its consequence as
a global phenomenon we are witnessing today: the undierentiated use
5. M. de Beistegui, Truth & Genesis: Philosophy as Dierential Ontology (Bloomington and Indi-
anapolis, IN: Indiana University Press, 2009), 36–48; I. omson, Heidegger on Ontotheol-
ogy, 34–36.
6. M. Heidegger, e End of Philosophy, J. Stanbaugh (trans.) (Chicago, IL: University Chicago
Press, 2003), 4, 8–10.
7. e essential dierence between Aristotle and Plato was not merely grounded upon the dif-
ference between initiation and articulation, but also upon the fact that for Aristotle ideas
were forms of “energies” housed-in actualization of things, when Plato saw ideas (essences)
independent of the existence of things they created. Unlike in Plato’s “rationalism”, in Aris-
totle’s “empirism” movement of things were an outcome of energeia, actualization of their
potential through the telos. At the same time for Aristotle the aim of such “empiric” explo-
ration of things-at-work was precisely to articulate the ever-lasting rst principles and cat-
egories behind these moving things. Even though for Aristotle the actualization process of
energeia was thus ontologically fundamental, so that it had precedence to ideas (eidos), Aristo-
tle never repressed the notion of idea (eidos). Idea and material rather always went together:
the material (hyle) had the potential to become a nished work (energeia), an actualized
potential, which instantiates and brings ideas (eidos) into presence. In other words, even
though Aristotle thought ousia as energeia he was only capable of thinking so against the
notion of ousia as idea, and thus against the background constituted by Plato. See M. Hei-
degger, e End of Philosophy, 5–6, 9; A. Feenberg, Heidegger and Marcuse, 33; A. A. Vallega,
Heidegger and the Issue of Space, 47.
HEIDEGGER ON THE HISTORY OF MACHINATION 357
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
and mobility of things as constantly present reserves for the machination
of globe-wide networks of ordering.8
Perhaps the most interesting point here is that according to Heidegger
this hidden mission of being, destined by the rst beginning, ends at the
rise of the planetary unfolding. In completed metaphysics all of its pos-
sibilities are exhausted so that we come to witness its inversion, the nihil-
ism of planetary technology, a total drive of willful ordering cast upon the
earth and things. Hence, it is “at the last (Eskaton), that is, at the depar-
ture of the long-hidden destiny of be-ing”, when the rst beginning of the
early Greeks “is gathered (Logos) in the ultimacy of its destining”, in the
total oblivion of be-ing through the self-expanding drive of technological-
instrumental manipulation and ordering of things as constantly present
and manipulable reserves.9 Eventually, even though be-ing is nothing other
than a succession of unique epochs continuously covering the nite hap-
pening of being, alteration in onto-theological unfolding forms a tradi-
tion, a legacy of oblivion, that consist of eschatological course where be-ing
withdraws to the point of its abandonment (i.e. to the total oblivion that
concentrates only on planetary-wide ordering and ecient manipulation of
beings; the machination).
How then does such maturation of oblivion take place so that nally,
in the age of planetary organization instigated by Nietzsche’s thinking, the
sphere of possibilities of the rst beginning becomes totally exhausted?
Such a claim seems to imply, as Haar observes, that the “rst beginning”
already latently included all the possible mutations of onto-theological
grounding, so that the inception of the “rst beginning” would have been
the fullest and richest moment, the completion of metaphysics in turn
8. Even though these revolutionary thinkers were apparently capable of turning the wheels
of onto-theology with an unpredictable and previously unknown manner, accordingly to
Heidegger their discoveries were at the same time always related to “what everyone sees
and grasps in comportment to beings”. M. Heidegger, Identity and Dierence, 38. Eventu-
ally these thinkers “are what they are insofar as being is entrusted to them”, such entrusting
having its origin in the originary oblivion, in the rst oblivion caused by the onto-theological
mechanism that took place through the metaphysical atmosphere of the “rst beginning” of
the ancient Greek thinking. M. Heidegger, “Vol III: e Will to Power as Knowledge and
as Metaphysics”, in Nietzsche: Volumes ree and Four, J. Stambaugh, D. F. Krell & F.A.
Capuzzi (trans.), D. F. Krell (ed.) (New York: HarperCollins, 1991c), 188. Hence, even
though Heidegger thinks that such metaphysical atmospheres constitute the basic disposi-
tions of an epoch, metaphysics can always be identied with a name of a thinker: Heidegger
is not denying the role of agency, but rather putting it into its proper place, to its position in
the historical course of being.
9. M. Heidegger, Early Greek inking (San Francisco, CA: Harper & Row, 1984), 17–18. See
also T. Schatzki, Martin Heidegger: eorist of Space (Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, 2007),
74.
358 MIKKO JORONEN
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
presenting exhaustion of these possibilities.10 Such interpretation, how-
ever, contradicts most of Heidegger’s writings, in particular with the fact
that according to Heidegger it is the open abyss of be-ing that denotes the
absolute plenitude of possibilities, not the “rst beginning”, which instead
conceals this abyssal openness. e other option is to understand these
particular concealments in terms of releasing unthought potentialities for
further articulations, these articulations in turn enabling further incuba-
tion out of what they, in their own happening, implicitly indicated and
left unthought. Heidegger seems to be implying this option, for instance,
when claiming that Aristotle’s formulation of the “metaphysics of presence”
created the unseen distinction between “existence” (that is) and “essence”
(what is), not by articulating such twofold notion of ousia out of nothing,
but out of Plato’s unthought and not yet articulated preparation. Out of
such “incubation of the unthought” it would be also possible to take into
account that Heidegger understands metaphysical postulates of intelligibil-
ity in terms of cumulating towards their nal gathering in planetary epoch,
so that the original inception was not a mere starting point in the past, but
something that remained sheltered throughout the history it inaugurated.11
e latter interpretation, however, does not explain out of what necessity
the nal recollection, blocking all further metaphysical development, takes
place. Perhaps the dramatic notion of eschatological completion should not
be taken in terms of pre-determinative condition, but in terms of phenom-
enological explanation of the actual genealogical disposal of be-ing opera-
tive ever since the inception of the rst beginning. Instead of seeing the
completion of metaphysics as a necessary outcome of the “system of his-
tory”, such genealogical reading would allow us to understand Heideggers
references to the “exhaustion of possibilities” that happens in “the end of
metaphysics” out of the conditions that actually took place.12 Moreover, it
would also be possible to understand the succession of oblivion as a free
series, which unfolds its preparatory aspects only out of its actual (but un-
predictable) happening, and thus from a viewpoint of contemporary out-
growth it so determined.
10. M. Haar, e Song of the Earth: Heidegger and the Grounds of the History of Being, R. Lilly
(trans.) (Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press, 1993), 73.
11. Cf. Haar, e Song of the Earth, 75; omson, Heidegger on Ontotheology, 33.
12. As Krell and Elden have also suggested, Heidegger’s view about the incubation of onto-
historical bedrocks comes closer to genealogy than anything else. D. Krell, Daimon Life:
Heidegger and Life-Philosophy (Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press,
1992), 109; S. Elden, “Reading Genealogy as Historical Ontology”, in Foucault and Hei-
degger: Critical Encounters, A. Michman & A. Rosenberg (eds), 187–205 (196) (Minneapo-
lis, MN: University of Minneapolis Press, 2003).
HEIDEGGER ON THE HISTORY OF MACHINATION 359
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
e ambiguity within the “continuous-discontinuous preparation” of the
nal unfolding, it seems, is a rather curious matter. Although it is possible
to think of our contemporary epoch of planetary technology as unique and
unpredictable, as a something that instead of holding historical continuity
introduces an ontological break to preceding epochs, there is also a matura-
tion of fundamental preparations, a cumulative logic of metaphysical propo-
sitions. Even though at rst glance the sense of maturation between epochs
speaks against the discontinuity and uniqueness of singular epochs, there
is also a way of incubation that is able to happen without destroying the
singularity of a dierent unfolding of being. Basically, we just have to think
through the uniqueness dierently: since the ontological bedrock of prevail-
ing epoch, for instance, was unknown to prior historical epochs, it makes
our contemporary epoch unique, even though at the same time we should
explain its development through a series of grounding postulates, which by
covering the happening of be-ing have each prepared and made possible the
contemporary planetary epoch. Perhaps it would be appropriate to claim,
like Haar does, that ontological conditions always “free up possibilities” for
the following but dierent, unpredictable and unique conditions, so that
each epoch, as Taminiaux adds, is equally a “deletion” and “obliteration” of
the directions and capabilities oered by the preceding historical layers.13
Accordingly, even though dierent epochs, the unique modes through
which be-ing holds back, spring up suddenly and unpredictably, they all do
have one thing in common: they hide the nite happening of unfolding and
thus the source of open and abundant be-ing from which their own monopo-
lizations of concealing-revealing were granted in the rst place. Even though
epochs do not derive from each other, but are instead all based on a unique
unfolding of being, this is precisely what all of these epochs have in common:
their belonging to the hidden historical mission of be-ing revealing and veil-
ing itself. Dierent epochs, then, are all granted from the “selfsame”, but
this “selfsame” is nothing more than the unity of self-concealing-revealing
Event of be-ing, such sameness of the Event being precisely what the tradi-
tion has failed to discuss. In short, all epochs share the same onto-theological
mechanism of oblivion inaugurated by the rst beginning: eventually dier-
ent epochs are connected to each other, not merely through the sameness of
their source (the open be-ing), but through the continuity of its oblivion.
us, the only “law” that links unique epochal mutations of being to each
other is the correlation between the increasing oblivion of be-ing and the
accumulative emergence of metaphysical postulates further and further cov-
ering be-ing under their sedimented layers. As a manifestation of such “law”
13. J. Taminiaux, Recoupements (Bruxelles: Ousia, 1982), 124; Haar, Song of the Earth, 73.
360 MIKKO JORONEN
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
of further oblivion, the series of epochs (i.e. the history of being) is cumula-
tive, but yet indeterminate: prior epochs only free up unthought possibilities
so that these potentialities are extended in a manner that following epochs are
always unforeseen and hence unknown for the preparing mutations of being.
As Heidegger writes in Metaphysics as History of Being, “the pro-gression of
metaphysics from its essential beginning leaves this beginning behind, and yet
takes a fundamental constituent of Platonic-Aristotelian thinking alone”.14
e “incubational maturation” of the oblivion, then, has a double outlet: the
history of being is not just a history of a loss of sense of be-ing and its nitude
through onto-theological groundings; it also presents a genealogical incuba-
tion of these grounding postulates through the unthought possibilities they
released. Conceptual progressions and purposeless changes, even seemingly
innocent linguistic translations, thereby contain a disposure, a legacy of for-
getting and veiling, by which be-ing hands itself from one epoch to another
through the veiling-revealings it denotes.
As is evident, the inquiry of the operative history of being never simply
returns to the past, but steps back to a domain, which has been systemati-
cally skipped over: the concealed destining caused by the oblivion of be-ing
and its nite Event. In so far as the coming into view of Ereignis uncovers
the primordial history of oblivion, it also brings forth and articulates this
legacy of disposure, where the oblivion of be-ing step by step incubates and
maturates until its overcoming in “other beginning” of more originary post-
metaphysical thought. Ereignis, then, is the “other beginning” that uncovers
the unnecessary oblivion of the necessary concealment, hence preventing
the obscuring power of “rst beginning” to mould grounds without ever
raising awareness about their nature as nite Events. In other words, the
history of being – throughout the process of the maturation of oblivion
from the origin of the rst beginning all the way until its consummation in
machination – is based on the oblivion of its “ownmost” source: the nite
Event that appropriates its happening from the open be-ing. Passing into
“other beginning” of nite Event thereby delivers, not just an overcoming
of the history of being as metaphysical oblivion, but also an abyssal realm of
openness, which makes a step beyond the oblivion inaugurated by the “rst
beginning”, including everything that can be imagined under its inuence.
Incubation of Machination: From tekhne to the Power of Ordering
Withheld between two decisive moments, one determined by the begin-
ning of Western thought – the onto-theological grounding of being as
14. Heidegger, e End of Philosophy, 10; See also Heidegger, On Time and Being, 24.
HEIDEGGER ON THE HISTORY OF MACHINATION 361
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
“metaphysics of presence” – and the other now prepared – coming into
view of the nite Event – the evolvement of the abandonment of be-ing
culminates today in the dominance of the manipulative way of unfolding
things as orderable reserves constantly set ready for calculation and use.
Heidegger names the fundamental condition of this commanding way of
unfolding and organizing things as “machination” (Machenschaft). Machi-
nation is above all intensication of “makingness” (Mache), thus bearing a
close relation to power (Macht) of making (Machen) – machination oper-
ates in terms of power which turns every-thing makeable (Machbar) in pro-
portion to whatever purposes we wish.15 Machination hence indicates the
endgame of technical making as arbitrary ordering, so that such ordering
manifests the completion of the early Greek notion of tekhne, the know-
how of making and creating artefacts, in terms of willful power of calcula-
tive manipulation of things. As Bernard Stiegler compresses the issue: now
“technics command (kubernao, the etymon of cybernetics) nature. Before,
nature commanded technics.16 Already in the Greek understanding of
tekhne there thus seems to be laying “the possibility of arbitrariness, of an
unbridled positing of goals”, and if this happens, Heidegger claries in the
Basic Questions of Philosophy, “then in place of the basic disposition of won-
dering, the avidity for learning and calculation enters in”.17 Such emergence
of the technical calculation and machination is thus an outgrowth of the rise
of the arbitrary ordering based on all-makeable power of human willing.
It is the “ordering”, the gure of commanding, domination, making and
manipulation, which machination characterizes: machination refers to the
power (Macht) of manipulative domination (Machenschaft), which installs
itself through what Heidegger later called a calculative and provocative
challenging (Herausfordern) of things through their total “enframing” and
“com-positioning” (Gestell) into orderable standing-reserves (Bestand).18 No
15. Heidegger, Nietzsche, Vol. III, 174–75, 180–81; cf. M. Heidegger, Die Geschichte des Seyns
(Frankfurt Am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1998c), 46–49, F. Dallmayr, “Heidegger on
Macht and Machenschaft”, Continental Philosophy Review 34, no. 3 (2001), 253, R. Sinner-
brink, “From Machenschaft to Biopolitics: A Genealogical Critique of Biopower”, Critical
Horizons 6, no. 1 (2005), 242.
16. B. Stiegler, Technics and Time, I:e Fault of Epimetheus, R. Beardsworth & G. Collins
(trans.) (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1994), 24.
17. M. Heidegger, Basic Questions of Philosophy: Selected Problems of Logic, R. Rojcewicz and
A.Schuwer (trans.) (Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press, 1994),
155, see also 153–54.
18. Despite the circumstance that in German Gestell normally refers to a “rack” or a “frame”,
in Heidegger’s use Ge-stell apparently aims to name the overall Framework, the “enfram-
ing” or “com-positioning”, through which the manipulative commanding of machination
works: since the prex ge- denotes a sense of total, the noun Stell a “position”, and the verb
362 MIKKO JORONEN
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
wonder such unfolding has a planetary completion: for the willful power of
ordering, for the technological might of total enframing, everything not-
yet-known is opened as not-yet-ordered and thus as something not-yet-
taken-into-control. It is not just that this power is total in its positioning,
but also that “the whole planet is used as product of power”; in other words,
that the calculative commanding is extending its control to the limits of
“inhabited earth”, even into “atmosphere” and “stratosphere”, thus turning
the earth into a planet subjugated under the increasingly strengthening and
self-expanding networks of orderings.19
Such abolition of distance, however, is not merely a spatial issue, but
phenomenon that belongs to the last stage of the long-lasting legacy of
metaphysical oblivion of be-ing. In order to explicate the culmination of
the ancient Greek understanding of technics (tekhne) in terms of calcula-
tive power of technological ordering and machination, one should rst of
all realize that both of these modes of technical manipulation are related
to the unfolding of things. Like phusis, which is usually translated some-
what misleadingly as “nature”, for the Greeks tekhne brought something into
appearance. Since Greek tekhne and phusis were both manners of bringing
something into appearance, they also shared the original meaning of poiesis,
the idea of production and “bringing-forth”. e Greek sense of produc-
tion, poiesis, thereby neither meant a simple creation or making, nor a mere
production, but signied a mode of unfolding, a kind of “bringing forth
into appearance” that does not exclude nature (phusis). But whereas what
came to presence by means of phusis had an unfolding in itself, what came
to presence in the manner of tekhne had a bringing-forth not in itself, but
in the craftsman or artist. Since Greek tekhne may be regarded in terms of
doing activities of a craftsman – a kind of “know-how” – or in terms of art,
and thus, since it diered from what emerges by nature (phusis), what tekhne
essentially brought forth was precisely that which did not emerge by itself.20
stellen “positioning” or “setting up in position”, Gestell refers above all to a set up under
which every-thing is makeable and thus ordered in a position to wait calls for duty. See
M.Heidegger, “e Question Concerning Technology”, in e Question Concerning Tech-
nology and Other Essays, W. Lovitt (trans.), 3–35 (New York: Harper & Row, 1977a),
W.Lovitt, “A Gespräch with Heidegger on Technology”, Man and World 6, no. 1 (1973),
52; J. Taminiaux, Recoupements, 138.
19. M. Heidegger, Mindfulness, P. Emad and T. Kalary (trans.) (New York: Continuum, 2006),
14, See M. Heidegger, What is Called inking?, J. G. Gray (trans.) (New York: Harper-
Collins, 1968), 160, M. Joronen, “Dwelling in the Sites of Finitude: Resisting the Vio-
lence of the Metaphysical Globe”, Antipode 43, no. 4 (2011), 1127–154.
20. See M. Heidegger, “e Origin of the Work of Art”, in Poetry, Language, ought, A. Hof-
stadter (trans.), 15–86 (New York: Harper & Row, 2001a), 41; M. Heidegger, “e Question
Concerning Technology”, 10; W. Lovitt, “A Gespräch with Heidegger on Technology”, 48.
HEIDEGGER ON THE HISTORY OF MACHINATION 363
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
Accordingly, for the ancient Greeks things emerged either by phusis or
tekhne. When things of phusis, the “nature”, were self-organizing and self-
manifesting – they had an arkhe in themselves – tekhne had its ground in
the making and know-how of an agent and thus consisted of producing
artefacts. Tekhne, however, was not a plain arbitrary manufacturing, but
a way of revealing that included logos about how things must come out
– be “gathered” or “collected”, as Heidegger suggests by referring to the
root meaning of the logos, the legein – through the process of artefact pro-
duction.21 Tekhne, then, required logos about how to make things that are
intelligible and thus at the end of the production process formed an intel-
ligible collection of various disperse aspects into a gathering that makes the
artefact a good and appropriate one. is logos, the act of gathering, in turn
was an articulation of certain intelligible model, the essential realm of ideas
(eidos). Accordingly, the mode of production of tekhne was based on a func-
tion of certain essential model (eidos) through intelligible gathering (logos)
of relations that made things what they were (i.e. a hammer as something
suitable for hammering). Technical knowledge was simply dened accord-
ing to its end: production of a hammer, for instance, required that in order
to produce one craftsman already needed to recognize the idea of hammer
– he needed knowledge about the essence of hammer, its “hammerness” –
as well as knowledge concerning the appropriate gathering of relationships
that were needed to nish the manufacturing process. Altogether, tekhne
signied an intelligible way of producing artefacts beyond the phusis, a way
of unfolding that did not exploit phusis, but held it into unconcealment
through the guidance of logos-oering (the intelligible gathering) eidos (the
ideal outcome).
Perhaps the most crucial point here is that, in spite of their dierence in
unfolding, tekhne and phusis were both understood on a basis of poiesis, as
modes of revealing based on the productive bringing-forth of things. For
the Greeks, then, the structure of production constituted the structure of
being.22 is, however, did not mean that for the Greeks all things, from
natural entities to artefacts, were merely manufactured, but that nature,
like the artefactual world, was a process of emergence, where things placed
themselves in appearance in proportion to their end, by producing their pre-
established telos. is process of emergence brought things into appearance
21. M. Heidegger, “On the Essence and Concept of Phusis in Aristotle’s Physics B”, in Pathmarks,
T. Sheehan (trans.), 183–230 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998a), 212–13.
22. A. Feenberg, Heidegger and Marcuse, 35–36; See also M. Heidegger, What Is a ing?
B.Barton & V. Deutch (trans.) (South Bend, IN: Regnery/Gateway, 1967), 81; Heidegger,
“e Question Concerning Technology”, 10.
364 MIKKO JORONEN
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
so that their nal looks were dened by their essence, their idea – the eidos.
Like technical artefacts, things of nature (phusis) were also considered in
terms of producing the predened essences. Phusis, then, was conceived
in terms of the end internal to things: for the Greeks phusis was a self-
producing way of revealing that had its ground and thus its telos in itself. In
other words, nature consisted of self-producing things through which ideas
(essences) placed themselves in the appearing entities directly, whereas in
the case of tekhne the craftsman was needed to nalize the production pro-
cess of artefacts. In the tekhne of craftsman ideas did not place themselves
directly in the appearance, but through the knowledge (the know-how)
concerning the essential features of artefact production.
Although diering from phusis in its mode of unfolding, it is evident that
in the “rst beginning” of the Greek thinking tekhne also belonged together
with phusis in the most essential manner: as a revealing based on a model of
production. In addition to the fact that phusis and tekhne both signied a
mode of unfolding in which structure was determined in terms of produc-
tion, as a something that emerges out of its own accord phusis also served
a precondition and thereby a limit for the craftsman’s making of tekhne. In
the Greek thinking tekhne was dependent on phusis in a way nature did not
depend on technics. According to Aristotle, for example, a carpenter can use
wood as a material for a bed, but this was only because the carpenter needs
to be mindfully attuned to the wood and its characteristics.23 Phusis, the
earth, was allowed to rise without violent and manipulative ordering. When
the type of unfolding in the Gestell is identiable as a calculative challenging,
as a manipulative extracting from the reserve constantly subjected to be on
call, in the rst beginning tekhne – in spite of its dierence with regard to
phusis – was a bringing-forth of something out of the command of phusis.24
e substantial dierence is that in the Greek understanding tekhne did
not command phusis in order to exploit it by setting it ready for the frame-
work of orderings like the manipulative power of machination does. Instead
of modern manifestation of the productive unfolding – i.e., the manipu-
lative and total producibility constituted by the coercive power of machi-
nation (Machenschaft) driving ahead into constant innovation of technical
improvements – for the Greeks production signied poiesis, a bringing forth
and appearance of things towards the ideal end dened by eidos.
What is crucial in the Greek understanding of nature and technics is
the placement of existence of things (that they are) in proportion to their
23. B. Foltz, Inhabitating the Earth, 96–97; T. Sadler, Heidegger and Aristotle: e Question of
Being (London: Athlone, 1996), 61.
24. Heidegger, “e Question Concerning Technology”, 14, 30.
HEIDEGGER ON THE HISTORY OF MACHINATION 365
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
essences (what they are). Accordingly, it was Plato who enlarged the vision
of production to consist of all beings by holding that both, the growth of
natural entities and the manufacturing of artefacts, rely on production of
the ground laid by their essences. In short, all things (natural, artefactual)
have an end dened in terms of the production of their ideal outcome.
e onto-theological duality between essence and existence, between what
makes thing a thing (its essence, the idea) and by which way that thing
becomes a thing (existence as production of common ideas), rises from the
common source of productive mode of revealing. Accordingly, the onto-
theological structure of the “rst beginning” in the early Greek thinking
was dened in term of productionist mode of revealing: all things that
emerge produce their idea, which is why their existence and movement in
the world is always full of intention and meaning. Moreover, since things
have an end dened by their essences, such intention and meaning is not
created by us, but denotes something to which we apparently correspond to
when making artefacts through the know-how of tekhne or when gaining
knowledge (episteme) from the telos of nature. As Heidegger writes, tekhne
(production of artefacts) and episteme (knowledge of nature) both meant
“to be home in something, to understand and be expert in it”.25 e dier-
ence between the productionist revealing of the Greeks and the revealing of
Gestell is obvious: the former corresponds to the natural telos of the world
(is at home in it), while the latter commands it (is over it as Machination).
In spite of its obvious antagonism to the unfolding of Gestell, from
the viewpoint of contemporary consummation the Greek notion of tekhne
already held great dangers within, in particular the possibility that tekhne
may lose its embeddedness at the fundamental attunement of “wonder”.
By this Heidegger obviously refers to the wonder of Socrates that Plato
pointed out in eaetetus – “wonder is the feeling of a philosopher, and
philosophy begins in wonder” – but goes further by claiming that this fun-
damental mood actually gave rise to the Greek thinking as such.26 Given
this, although the original sense of tekhne already diered from the mode of
unfolding of phusis, and further, although Greek understanding of unfold-
ing was based on a model of production (of ideal ends), in the Greek begin-
ning tekhne neither included a total control of beings nor did it completely
run against phusis by systematically ordering it to stand by for manipulation
and desired use. Unlike the manipulative power of “machination”, tekhne
did not originally arise from calculative and manipulative ordering, but
25. Heidegger, “e Question Concerning Technology”, 13.
26. Plato, eaetetus (eBooks@Adelaide: http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/p/plato/p71th/, 2007);
Heidegger, Basic Questions of Philosophy, 135.
366 MIKKO JORONEN
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
from the wondering of beings as beings, which instead of ordering phusis
let it come forth in terms of its own accord.27 For the Greeks wonder left
beings to become opened as beings that they were, thus allowing a ques-
tion concerning their being to arise, even though at the same time the
Greeks approached the question of being in a metaphysical way, as onto-
theologically dened and grounded property.
It was wonder, then, that on the one hand allowed the self-emerging
phusis to command the bringing into appearance of tekhne, although on
the other hand tekhne already had a possibility to “stand against” the phusis,
a seed that later grew to determine beings as orderable reserve set ready for
the use of will. e modern condition of technology rests precisely upon
the fact that tekhne became detached from wonder and hence turned will-
fully towards its own interdependency to phusis. Hence, today tekhne holds
sway as a manipulative power; it orders phusis by constantly demanding
and challenging it to be present as fully accessible and disposable resource.
It was thereby the disconnection of the Greek notion of tekhne from the
wonder, which prepared a way for the calculative process of technologi-
cal manipulation now ordering all things to stand by as makeable reserves
under the orders of the omnipotent power of arbitrary commands.
Due to the danger involved in tekhne – that tekhne could become
detached from wonder and turn into arbitrary ordering of modern Ges-
tell – it could be argued that Gestell is rooted in the rst beginning of the
Greek thinking and its productive way of revealing. Perhaps it is due to
such rootedness (i.e., that tekhne and Gestell are both productive modes
of revealing, yet dierent in their basic dispositions of wonder and calcula-
tion) that Heidegger wrote in Contributions of Philosophy that it is the pro-
ductive imperative of machination, which “dominates the history of being
in Western philosophy up to now, from Plato to Nietzsche”, while specify-
ing that “it seems to be a law of machination […] that more powerfully it
unfolds – for example in the Middle Ages and in modernity – the more
stubbornly and more machinatingly it hides itself as such”, thus darkening
the question of being through constantly growing manipulation of beings.28
As is evident, here Heidegger clearly interprets machination in terms of
not solely referring to the modern epoch, but to the whole history of the
oblivion of be-ing. However, as the former discussions indicate, these pas-
sages should be read in line with the discontinuous preparations through
27. Heidegger, Basic Questions of Philosophy, 153–55; See also Livingston, “inking and Being”,
334–35.
28. M. Heidegger, Contributions to Philosophy (From Enowning), P. Emad and K. Maly (trans.),
88–89 (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press).
HEIDEGGER ON THE HISTORY OF MACHINATION 367
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
which tekhne becomes separated from the wonder through its assimilation
to the calculative ordering of machination. Machination is thus hidden
potential released by the breakdown of the Greek understanding of reveal-
ing. is kind of interpretation, where machination is seen as hidden poten-
tiality released through the breakdown of the Greek notion of wonder,
would be also in line with other passages in Heidegger’s writings such as
the one in Overcoming Metaphysics, where Heidegger argues, seemingly con-
trary to the former passages of Contributions of Philosophy, that machination
“arises from the being of technology”, as well as with Heidegger’s talk about
the modern “epoch of machination” in Mindfulness.29 Accordingly, in as
much as the emergence of Gestell was based on such detachment of wonder
from tekhne that released the hidden potentiality of total producibility (such
producibility not yet manifested in the Greek thinking), machination, the
drive towards total makeability and malleability of all, was a hidden and
unthought potentiality not fully manifested until modern times. is is the
reason why Heidegger writes even on a same page that on the one hand
machination emerges “as what is ownmost to beingness in modern think-
ing”, thus presenting “an essential distancing from phusis”, while on the
other hand holding that machination has dominated the history of being,
even though it did not “become fully manifest in its ownmost” in the rst
beginning of the Greek thinking.30 In short, machination was not ownmost
to the Greek thinking, but unthought potentiality of omnipotent power of
producability, a potentiality hidden within productionist mode of revealing.
Even though Heidegger held that the breakdown of the basic disposition
of wonder could turn tekhne arbitrary in proportion to things, it is curious
that according to Heidegger wonder was also the basic disposition out of
which the mechanism of metaphysical thinking was rst constituted, that
is, the mechanism that became manifested through the history of onto-
theological mutations, the history of the oblivion of be-ing. Regardless of
the circumstance that wondering allowed nature to come forth according
to its own telos, it was precisely “wondrous” thinking that produced the rst
onto-theological beginning, the “metaphysics of presence”. us, in spite
of the dierence between basic dispositions of Greek wonder and modern
calculation, wonder was a primordial preparation of Gestell, even twice
over: its breakdown freed up the possibility for the rise of the willful and
arbitrary power of machination, while it also constituted the rst form of
metaphysical oblivion of be-ing through Aristotle’s onto-theology.
29. Heidegger, e End of Philosophy, 110; M. Heidegger, Mindfulness, 13; See also M. Hei-
degger, Nietzsche, Vol. III, 174–76.
30. Heidegger, Contributions to Philosophy (From Enowning), 88–89.
368 MIKKO JORONEN
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
is all comes back to the circumstance that the basic disposition
of the ancient Greek thinking, the wonder, found the usual itself to be
extraordinary. In wonder it was the most usual that turned into most
unusual.31 Unlike in calculative ordering, in wonder one was simply sur-
prised that things were as they were. Wonder then did not set the unusual
against the usual; wonder rather set human beings before the unsualness
of everything in their usualness. In wonder one was not surprised of the
extraordinary that happened, but of the usual, of the fact that things were
as they were. e wonder of the early Greeks, thereby, opened up the gap
between beings (the usual) and their way of beingness (their unusual-
ness). Instead of the usual and given sense of beings, wonder pointed
out the unsual sense of beings as beings. However, even though wonder
opened up the question concerning beings as beings and thus of their
mode of being (as beingness), it equally precluded the direct inquiry to
the unfolding. In wonder beings were seen as beings, as something that
are, which according to Heidegger opened up “beings as a whole, that
they are and what they are” – i.e. the basic schema of onto-theology –
thus enabling the grounding question of Greek metaphysics.32 For the
Greeks wonder was simply an acknowledgement of beings as beings, and
hence it questioned what beings were in their beingness without exploring
their mode of unfolding in itself; that is, the happening of be-ing (Seyn)
as a nite Event of unfolding.
As is evident, even though the basic disposition of wonder prevented
Greek tekhne from turning into manipulative ordering of phusis, wonder
also presented the basic onto-theological mechanism of metaphysical think-
ing. Wonder opened up the as-structure of beings (i.e. question concerning
their “beingness”), thus abandoning the direct inquiry into the happening
of unfolding through the ontological grounding of entities by virtue of
the highest theological principle behind their presence. Wonder, then, did
not only make the Greek notion of tekhne dierent from the challenging
revealing of Gestell; it also put forward the historical beginning of the basic
metaphysical schema, the mechanism of onto-theology, behind the entire
legacy of Western thinking. In fact, this is one of the basic reasons behind
Heidegger’s understanding of history of being in terms of growing obliv-
ion of be-ing: for the Greeks being of beings (as beingness) was the most
wondrous thing, when the contemporary technological thinking merely
31. Heidegger, Basic Questions of Philosophy, 144; See also B. E. Stone, “Curiosity as the ief
of Wonder: An Essay on Heidegger’s Critique of the Ordinary Conception of Time”, Krono-
Scope 6, no. 2 (2006), 211.
32. Heidegger, Basic Questions of Philosophy, 146, see also 115, 149, 150.
HEIDEGGER ON THE HISTORY OF MACHINATION 369
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
recognizes the question.33 us, for the Greeks being was a question about
the beingness of beings, when in contemporary technological “enframing”
only beings are worthy of thinking. While in the former disposition the
nature of beings “as beings” was wondered, the latter disposition merely
orders them. In this respect it was (literally) “no wonder” that Nietzsche,
as the one who released the hidden powers of technological ordering, abol-
ished being by recognizing only the will to power of beings. It was through
the discussion concerning Nietzsche’s understanding of “will to power”
that Heidegger showed how Nietzsche’s notion of “will to power” sus-
tained and empowered all beings according to its manipulative imperative,
and thereby, in spite of Nietzsche’s own certainty, did not propose a non-
metaphysical stance, but on the contrary, still operated within the tradition
of metaphysical oblivion of be-ing.34 But Heidegger went even further by
claiming that the “will to power” was an essential stage of what consti-
tutes the completion of the history of metaphysics: under the unfolding
of being as power, beings are revealed as makeable, as something dragged
under the power of human will and machination.35 Power of ordering and
33. With this Heidegger also reminds us from the fact that although he is trying to dene the
Greek attunement of wonder, we contemporaries are already devolved from it. e aim here
is not to restore us back to the wonder, but to point out the limits of the Greek sense of won-
dering as a basic attunement that gave birth to an entire era of the “rst beginning”. Hei-
degger, Basic Questions of Philosophy, 159.
34. With such “active nihilism”, which accepts the situation of a demise of old values – the
death of god and thus the disappearance of the transcendental sources of value – but inter-
prets power of beings as sustaining new values and the “superman” as the highest form who
goes beyond the present by following the way power always surpasses itself, Nietzsche iden-
ties only beings and their increasing and circular becoming as will to power. Even though
Nietzsche does not seek the essence of permanent being, but better, thinks of being as “empty
vapour”, he thinks of the nature of beings as such and hence as a whole. Heidegger, Nietzsche,
Vol. III, 163, 189; cf. Schatzki, Martin Heidegger: eorist of Space, 26–27.
35. See Heidegger, Nietzsche, Vol. III, 161, 171, M. Heidegger, Nietzsche. Vol. IV, F. A. Capuzzi
(trans.), D. F. Krell (ed.) (New York: HarperCollins, 1991d), 199–201; J. P. Lawrence,
“Nietzsche and Heidegger”, History of European Ideas 11 (1989), 716–17; M. Joronen, “e
Technological Metaphysics of Planetary Space: Being in the Age of Globalization”, Envi-
ronment and Planning D: Society and Space 26, no. 4 (2008): 602–604. Heidegger’s read-
ing of Nietzsche is of course a matter of controversy, telling perhaps more about Heidegger’s
than Nietzsche’s philosophy (see for instance, L. Lambert, “Heidegger’s Nietzsche Interpre-
tation”, Man and World 7, no. 4 [1974], 353–76, and L. P. iele, “Twilight of Modernity:
Nietzsche, Heidegger, and Politics”, Political eory 22, no. 3 [1994], 468–90). As Gadamer
points out, it is almost as though Heidegger does nothing but rediscovers himself and his
thoughts throughout the history of Western thinking. In some ways Gadamer’s claim is ade-
quate, since Heidegger attempts to read the history of forgotten unfolding of be-ing. Never-
theless, it is precisely for this reason Heidegger’s reading of Nietzsche is also adequate: rather
than corresponding Nietzsche’s thoughts merely for their own sake, Heidegger attempts
to uncover what remains hidden and unthought in Nietzsche’s thinking, the “will to will”.
370 MIKKO JORONEN
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
production, thus, becomes the very thing, which on the one hand positions
us as willful commanders, but on the other hand orders beings through us
under the rule of arbitrary positioning of goals.
Altogether, it was the basic disposition of wonder that made Greek think-
ing in general as well as their notion of tekhne and phusis in particular dif-
ferent from the modern understandings, while at the same time wonder
presented an initiation of machination by establishing the onto-theological
schema of production. Moreover, through the displacement of wonder
metaphysical thinking eventually incubated into challenging revealing and
technological machination of things and thus to the further darkening and
oblivion of be-ing. In order to explicitly understand how the planetary spread
of machination was destined by the early Greek notion of tekhne, we must
thereby understand the succession out of which the power of willful com-
manding, the arbitrary machination, rises to the heart of tekhne and thus how
the emergence of tekhne as willful ordering brought together what seems at
rst perhaps furthest from each other: the manipulative power of calculative
machination and lived-experience (Erlebnis).
In Contributions to Philosophy Heidegger points out this unity between
machination and lived-experience quite straightforwardly: machination
means “Poiesis-tekhne”, denoting the victory of productive mode of unfold-
ing, but equally leads to anthropomorphist disposition of “lived-experience”.
Due to the promotion of “lived-experience” (Erlebnis), the coercive and
calculative forces of machination do not just produce and order beings, but
also integrate themselves to the subject. As lived-experience, machination
positions subjects to represent and manage beings under their will: “what is
lived through lived-experience and is so liveable” means equally that “only
what man is able to bring to and before him, [only that] can count as ‘a
being’”.36 Lived-experience shows itself in terms of the authorization of the
experience, and thus as a particular subject position, which turns beings into
useable reserves for the generation of lived-experiences.37 Lived-experience
hence poses a framework under which all beings are understood as experi-
enceable material under the order of subject’s will. Lived-experience thus
pre-structures the totality of beings in order to safeguard their represent-
ability as reserves useable for the lived-experiences.
H-G. Gadamer, Heidegger’s Ways, J. W. Stanley (trans.) (New York: State University of New
York Press, 1994), 165.
36. Heidegger, Contributions to Philosophy (From Enowning), 90.
37. See M. Heidegger, “e Age of the World Picture”, in e Question Concerning Technology
and Other Essays, W. Lovitt (trans.), 115–54 (New York: Harper & Row, 1977c), 132; Hei-
degger, Nietzsche, Vol. III, 175: See also Livingston, “inking and Being”, 331.
HEIDEGGER ON THE HISTORY OF MACHINATION 371
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
e historical emergence of the basic disposition of lived-experience
shows above all how the productive unfolding of machination sets up a
peculiar subject position, where human beings are set to produce and order
beings. As Heidegger held in a lecture course Traditional Language and Tech-
nological Language given as late as 1962, “what is most peculiar to modern
technology is no mere human amassed to power. Today’s humans are them-
selves challenged forth by the demand to challenge nature forth into arrange-
ment. Humans themselves are set up (gestellt); they are thereby demanded
to correspond to the aforementioned demand [my emphasis]”.38 As lived-
experience, power of machination becomes able to hide itself within the
guise of subjective willing. Underlying such hiding – although machina-
tion does not mean a conspiracy of being, but names pure accessibility to
beings by a way of calculation – the manipulative power of machination
apparently starts to look like “scheming”. e world becomes a picture,
a structured Gebild, represented and produced as a one coherent reserve
under the ordering power of the will.39 Machination simply poses a com-
positioning “Framework” under which beings as a whole are understood as
experienceable material for the heroic will. Under the contemporary rule of
machination the most fundamental domain of “control” is evidently found
at the level that is not usually considered as mastery at all: the coercive force
of machination does not dene our relation to things from the outside, but
ows through all relations between us and other beings by unfolding them
in terms of being set ready for the omnipotent orderings of machination.40
e belonging-togetherness of machination and lived-experience is pre-
cisely the technological gure Heidegger found within Nietzsches notion of
will to power. Under the “will to power” beings share the organized impera-
tive of machine: the eternal production of the ordered selfsame, where will
is ordered to stretch out to things only to level them to more of the same,
that is, as a set of arrangements for the use of the will. Nevertheless, the will
to power does not just lead to the “eternal recurrence of the same”, to the
innite circulation and becoming of all beings. Out of the commanding
of all beings to stand as reserves for the arbitrary means of the will, beings
become equally subjected under the growing power of the will.41 Under the
38. M. Heidegger, “Traditional Language and Technological Language”, Journal of Philosophical
Research 23 (1998d), 138.
39. Heidegger, “e Age of the World Picture”, 128, 134; Heidegger, Nietzsche (Vol. IV), 149.
40. K. Ziarek, “Art, Power and Politics: Heidegger on Machenschaft and Poiesis”, Contretemps
3 (2002), 177; B. Davis, Heidegger and the Will. On the Way to Gelassenheit (Evanston, IL:
Northwestern University Press, 2007), 179.
41. M. Heidegger, “Vol I: e Will to Power as Art”, in Nietzsche: Volumes One and Two, D. F.
Krell (trans. and ed.) (New York: HarperCollins, 1991a), 60; M. Heidegger, “Vol II: e
372 MIKKO JORONEN
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
machination, the “will to power” turns into technological “will to will”:
“will wills” itself forevermore and hence is directed towards the strength-
ening and overpowering of its own power. Power, then, is not centred on
subject, but better, power positions subjects to will, value, and command
beings within the structure of continual return and increase of the selfsame,
the will to will more of the power of willing. Accordingly, even though
through the lived-experience the thought of subject may take the form
of re-presenting (Vor-stellen), the ruling sense of “machination” should be
understood in terms of coercive “pro-posing” and “pre-presenting” of things
as reserves set ready for the utilizing drive of self-strengthening power, the
machination.
e Endgame: Emergence of tekhne as Machination
As the paper has argued, Heidegger’s view of history is based on ontologi-
cal ambiguity of the Event: exploration to Ereignis, to the multiplicity of
its unfolding, uncovers the unnecessary oblivion of the necessary conceal-
ment. It is the oblivion that becomes unveiled and remembered through
the recognition of the nite nature of dierent ontological monopoli-
zations of unfolding. However, such recognition of hidden nitude, an
“experience of the limits” as Simon Critchley puts it, also holds chance for
the “other beginning” of post-metaphysical thought, which does not just
bring out the longstanding foundations of metaphysical oblivion (along
with their “rst beginning”), but also prepares an “existential saving” that
escapes the obscuring logic of metaphysical rationality.42 Such “overcoming
of metaphysics”, thus, is not a mere negative destruction of the ontological
bedrocks of Western thinking, where the ossied layers of metaphysical
thought, further and further covering the source of open be-ing under their
sediments, are cleared away, but equally a positive issue, where something
long concealed becomes nally released.
In spite of the evident relevance of Heidegger’s well-known later writ-
ings on technological ordering and manipulation of things through their
“enframing” (Gestell), it was already Heidegger’s earlier, the so called mid-
period work dating back to the late 1930s writings such as Besinnung
Eternal Recurrence of the Same”, in Nietzsche: Volumes One and Two, D. F. Krell (trans. and
ed.) (New York: HarperCollins, 1991b), 109.
42. S. Critchley, “Very Little… Almost Nothing. Death, Philosophy, Literature (London: Rout-
ledge, 1997), 12, See also M. Heidegger, “e Turning”, in e Question Concerning Technol-
ogy and Other Essays, W. Lovitt (trans.), 36–49 (New York: Harper & Row, 1977b), 42–46.
HEIDEGGER ON THE HISTORY OF MACHINATION 373
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
(Mindfulness), Beiträge zur Philosophie (vom Ereignis) (Contributions to Phi-
losophy (From Enowning)) and Die Geschichte des Seyns, that along with the
Nietzsche lectures written between 1936 and 1946, aorded a profound
insight to the ontological scaolding constitutive for the whole history of
Western thinking of being. However, in spite of the similarities the shift
from Heidegger’s discussion of Machenschaft in the 1930s to his writings
about Gestell in the mid- and late-1940s evidently includes substantial
rethinking of some key matters. Heidegger’s early talk on machination in
the 1930s lectures, for instance, seems to emphasize the role of human
beings as the willful masters over beings, when the notion of Gestell refers
also to human beings as useable reserves part of this mastery of calcula-
tive ordering. Nevertheless, already in the last Nietzsche lectures Heidegger
discusses machination in a manner that seems to correspond to the later
notion of enframing.
As Heidegger writes in the fourth volume of Nietzsche lectures, “the age
of the fulllment of metaphysics – which we descry when we think through
the basic features of Nietzsche’s metaphysics – prompts us to consider
[…] the extent to which we must experience history as the release of be-ing
into machination”.43 It is hence possible to understand Heidegger’s dier-
ent readings of machination in proportion to the historical development, so
that eventually in the mature planetary stage of (late) modernity machina-
tion mutates in such a way that “the subject-object relation as pure relation
takes precedence over the object and the subject”, so that also human beings
become secured as standing-reserves.44 Moreover, as Heidegger continues in
the Overcoming Metaphysics, it is Nietzsche’s thinking where the “sphere of
pregured possibilities” of metaphysical thinking has gone through, and thus,
where the “completed metaphysics” as a ground for the “planetary manner of
thinking” gives the scaolding for an order of the earth. Heidegger’s notions
on the historical emergence of the manipulative power of “machination
(Machenschaft) as a possessive and coercive force (Macht) of ordering and
technological “enframing” (Gestell) of things into exibly mouldable reserves,
both then insightfully articulate the moment of completion of the legacy of
Western metaphysical thinking: its outgrowth in terms of globally expand-
ing systems of calculative rationality and willful orderings. ey thus aord
a profound view to the operational logic behind the technological ordering
of planetary space – to an ordering that takes place by framing spatial rela-
tions of things through the self-strengthening systems of coercive orderings
43. Heidegger, Nietzsche Vol III, 196.
44. M. Heidegger “Science and Reection”, in e Question Concerning Technology and Other
Essays, W. Lovitt (trans.), 155–82 (New York: Harper & Row, 1977d), 173.
374 MIKKO JORONEN
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
imposed upon the earth. Today market mechanisms and business rationali-
ties seem to span the whole earth as nothing other than a big market place
subjugated under the domination of the self-intensifying logic of calcula-
tive organization, under the strange aimlessness and homelessness produced
by alienating forces of technological societies against which the critique of
modernity and capitalism, from Marx and Weber to critical theories of the
Frankfurt School thinkers and Zizek, have found their standpoint.
Mikko Joronen is in the Department of Geography and Geology, University of Turku,
Finland. He has published on Heidegger and globalization and his research broadly
focuses on globalization, political geography, Heidegger’s philosophy, history and
ontology of space and place.
References
Backman, J. 2006. “Divine and Mortal Motivation: On the Movement of Life in Aristotle and
Heidegger”. Continental Philosophy Review 38, nos. 3-4: 241–61. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/
s11007-006-9007-4
de Beistegui, M. 2009. Truth & Genesis: Philosophy as Dierential Ontology. Bloomington and
Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press.
Critchley, S. 1997. Very Little … Almost Nothing. Death, Philosophy, Literature. London:
Routledge.
Dallmayr, F. 2001. “Heidegger on Macht and Machenschaft”. Continental Philosophy Review 34,
no. 3: 247–67. http://dx.doi.org/10.1023/A:1012294107879
Davis, B. W. 2007. Heidegger and the Will: On the Way to Gelassenheit. Evanston, IL: Northwestern
University Press.
Elden, S. 2003. “Reading Genealogy as Historical Ontology”. In Foucault and Heidegger: Critical
Encounters, A. Michman and A. Rosenberg (eds), 187–205. Minneapolis, MN: University of
Minneapolis Press.
Feenberg, A. 2005. Heidegger and Marcuse: e Catastrophe and Redemption of History. New York
and London: Routledge.
Fell, J. P. 1979. Heidegger and Sartre: An Essay on Being and Place. New York: Columbia Univer-
sity Press.
Foltz, B. 1995. Inhabitating the Earth: Heidegger, Environmental Ethics and the Metaphysics of
Being. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press International.
Gadamer, H.-G. 1994. Heidegger’s Ways, J. W. Stanley (trans.). New York: State University of
New York Press.
Haar, M. 1993. e Song of the Earth: Heidegger and the Grounds of the History of Being, R. Lilly
(trans.). Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press.
Heidegger, M. 1967. What is a ing?, B. Barton & V. Deutch (trans.). South Bend, IN: Regn-
ery/Gateway.
Heidegger, M. 1968. What is Called inking?, J. G. Gray (trans.). New York: HarperCollins.
Heidegger, M. 1972. On Time and Being, J. Stambaugh (trans.). New York: Harper & Row.
Heidegger, M. 1974. “e Principle of Ground”, K. Hoeller (trans.). Man and World 7, no. 3:
207–22. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF01248755
HEIDEGGER ON THE HISTORY OF MACHINATION 375
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
Heidegger, M. 1977a. “e Question Concerning Technology”. In e Question Concerning Tech-
nology and Other Essays, W. Lovitt (trans.), 3–35. New York: Harper & Row.
Heidegger, M. 1977b. “e Turning”. In e Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays,
W. Lovitt (trans.), 36–49. New York: Harper & Row.
Heidegger, M. 1977c. “e Age of the World Picture”. In e Question Concerning Technology
and Other Essays, W. Lovitt (trans.), 115–54. New York: Harper & Row.
Heidegger, M. 1977d. “Science and Reection”. In e Question Concerning Technology and Other
Essays, W. Lovitt (trans.), 155–82. New York: Harper & Row.
Heidegger, M. 1984. Early Greek inking. San Francisco, CA: Harper & Row.
Heidegger, M. 1991a. “Vol I: e Will to Power as Art”. In Nietzsche: Volumes One and Two,
D. F. Krell (trans. and ed.). New York: HarperCollins.
Heidegger, M. 1991b. “Vol II: e Eternal Recurrence of the Same”. In Nietzsche: Volumes One
and Two, D. F. Krell (trans. and ed.). New York: HarperCollins.
Heidegger, M. 1991c. “Vol III: e Will to Power as Knowledge and as Metaphysics”. In
Nietzsche: Volumes ree and Four, J. Stambaugh, D. F. Krell & F. A. Capuzzi (trans.), D. F.
Krell (ed.). New York: HarperCollins.
Heidegger, M. 1991d. “Vol IV: Nihilism”. In Nietzsche: Volumes ree and Four, F. A. Capuzzi
(trans.), D. F. Krell (ed.). New York: HarperCollins.
Heidegger, M. 1994. Basic Questions of Philosophy: Selected Problems of Logic, R. Rojcewicz and
A. Schuwer (trans.). Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press.
Heidegger, M. 1998a. “On the Essence and Concept of Phusis in Aristotle’s Physics B”. In Path-
marks, T. Sheehan (trans.), 183–230. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Heidegger, M. 1998b. “Kant’s esis about Being”. In Pathmarks, T. E. Klein Jr. & W. E. Pohl
(trans.), 337–63. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Heidegger, M. 1998c. Die Geschichte des Seyns: Gesamtausgabe, Band 69. Frankfurt Am Main:
Vittorio Klostermann.
Heidegger, M. 1998d. “Traditional Language and Technological Language”. Journal of Philo-
sophical Research 23: 129– 46.
Heidegger, M. 2000. Contributions to Philosophy (From Enowning), P. Emad and K. Maly (trans.).
Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
Heidegger, M. 2002. Identity and Dierence. Chicago, IL and London: e University of Chicago
Press.
Heidegger, M. 2003. e End of Philosophy, J. Stanbaugh (trans.). Chicago, IL: University Chi-
cago Press.
Heidegger, M. 2006. Mindfulness, P. Emad and T. Kalary (trans.). New York: Continuum.
Joronen, M. 2008. “e Technological Metaphysics of Planetary Space: Being in the Age of Glo-
balization”. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 26, no. 4: 596–610.
Joronen, M. 2011. “Dwelling in the Sites of Finitude: Resisting the Violence of the Metaphysical
Globe”. Antipode 43, no. 4: 1127–154. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8330.2010.008
50.x
Krell, D. 1992. Daimon Life: Heidegger and Life-Philosophy. Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN:
Indiana University Press.
Lambert, L. 1974. “Heidegger’s Nietzsche Interpretation”. Man and World 7, no. 4: 353–78.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF01246815
Lawrence, J. P. 1989. “Nietzsche and Heidegger”. History of European Ideas 11: 711–17. http://
dx.doi.org/10.1016/0191-6599(89)90259-3
Livingston, P. 2003. “inking and Being: Heidegger and Wittgenstein on Machination and
Lived-Experience”. Inquiry 46, no. 3: 324–45. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/002017403100
02398
Lovitt, W. 1973. “A Gespräch with Heidegger on Technology”. Man and World 6, no. 1: 44–62.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF01252782
376 MIKKO JORONEN
© Equinox Publishing Ltd 2012.
Plato 2007. eaetetus. eBooks@Adelaide: http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/p/plato/p71th/ (accessed
3 January 2009).
Polt, R. 2006. e Emergency of Being: On Heidegger’s Contribution to Philosophy. Ithaca, NY and
London: Cornell University Press.
Sadler, T. 1996. Heidegger and Aristotle: e Question of Being. London: Athlone.
Schatzki, T. 2007. Martin Heidegger: eorist of Space. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag.
Seidel, G. J. 2001. “Musing with Kierkegaard: Heidegger’s Besinnung”. Continental Philosophy
Review 34, no. 4: 403–418. http://dx.doi.org/10.1023/A:1013169623934
Sinnerbrink, R. 2005. “From Machenschaft to Biopolitics: A Genealogical Critique of Biopower”.
Critical Horizons 6, no. 1: 239–65. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/156851605775009447
Stiegler, B. 1994. Technics and Time. I. e Fault of Epimetheus, R. Beardsworth & G. Collins
(trans.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Stone, B. E. 2006. “Curiosity as the ief of Wonder: An Essay on Heidegger’s Critique of the
Ordinary Conception of Time”. KronoScope 6, no. 2: 205–29. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/
156852406779751881
Taminiaux, J. 1982. Recoupements. Bruxelles: Ousia.
iele, L. P. 1994. “Twilight of Modernity: Nietzsche, Heidegger, and Politics”. Political eory
22, no. 3: 468–90. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0090591794022003005
omson, I. D. 2005. Heidegger on Ontotheology: Technology and the Politics of Education. New
York: Cambridge University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511499210
Vallega, A. A. 2003. Heidegger and the Issue of Space: inking on Exilic Grounds. University Park,
PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.
Ziarek, K. 2002. “Art, Power and Politics: Heidegger on Machenschaft and Poiesis”. Contretemps
3: 175–86.
... Heidegger, like many others after him, Derrida in particular, has aptly called this metaphysical ambition to ontological ordering and grounding 'onto-theology' (Heidegger, 2002(Heidegger, , 2003. Onto-theology, in short, is a mode of thinking accompanied by the metaphysical aim to define the ultimate ground, conditions, categories, forces, causes, ideas, forms, permanent structures and/or essences through which the manifold identities, relations and differences of entities (or beings) are constituted (for a more detailed discussion see Thomson, 2005;Joronen, 2012). Against the notion of 'ordered ontology' (or onto-theology) Law and Lien (2012) suggest a way of thinking, inaugurated by Nietzsche and pragmatists, that focuses on the 'empiric ontologies' as they are enacted in practices through which we are connected to things. ...
... However, we consider that Law and Lien (2012) fall short in their critique of ontotheology as being merely about fixing ontological stances even though they direct the inquiry in the right way. On the reverse side of the ontotheological coin lies the obliteration of the question of being, or what Heidegger calls the 'oblivion of being' carried in the tradition of Western thought (Heidegger, 2003(Heidegger, , 2012see Rorty, 1991: 29-31;Joronen, 2012). In Heidegger's (1991) reading, the abandonment of being as a Nietzschean 'empty vapor' in favour of the endless becoming of ontic entities eclipses how the ontological question becomes structured in the process (Heidegger, 1977(Heidegger, , 2001. ...
... The event (Ereignis) hence does not mark another ontological scaffolding -a new 'ontology of the Event' -but something that has been hidden within different ontological comportments all along (Heidegger, 1972(Heidegger, : 6, 8, 24, 2003). Heidegger's discussions of early Greek notions of tekhne, phusis and wonder, or modern 'enframing' (Gestell) and 'machination' (Machenschaft) (Heidegger, 1977(Heidegger, , 2003(Heidegger, , 2012, should be understood as a series of efforts to uncover and 'turn back' (Kehre) to think of this forgotten 'history of be-ing' (Geschichte des Seyns) -the veiled 'structures of revealing' and the legacy of oblivion they produced (see Joronen, 2012). ...
Article
Full-text available
This paper is a response to a growing body of geographical literature exploring the interface between ontology and politics. We develop an understanding that does not start by building ontological bedrocks, to which the question of politics is then rooted. Ontology building, we argue, operates against the essential possibility of the political invested in ontological openness, and thus remains blind to politics inconsistent with, but also practised upon, its own foundations. We propose a relation between the political and the ontological as questioning that grows from the events and situations, which ontologically position us in multiple and unexpected ways.
... It is through the proper response to the ontological question of revealing that ontological politics operates, either by blocking or opening up a space for the coming events of revealing. The response thus has a potentiality to lead to a problematization of the prevailing mode of revealing, which I see parallel to Heidegger's destructive loosening of the ties between the proper response to the 'oblivion of being' and the metaphysical forgetfulness of the 'oblivion of being' (Abbott, 2014, p. 2;Joronen, 2012). The crux is hence the following: the response to the difference in revealing (revealing as giving/revealing as concealed coming event) is what creates the difference within which ontological politics operates. ...
Article
Full-text available
This paper grows from a discontent with the equation of topology to relational thinking in the recent geographical literature operating under the rubric of ‘post-mathematical topology’. In order to find a more subtle way for comprehending topology, the paper shows that there exists an entirely different tradition of topological thought, which is explicitly connected to the problematic around the notion of ontology. An alternative approach is suggested, where not only the relational constitution of topology is properly taken into account, but where an in-depth reading of the ontological aspect is offered. Instead of fabricating another ‘ontology of topology’, the paper argues that it is the ontology itself, which takes place topologically, i.e. it is place-bound. By relying on Heidegger’s insight about the bond between place (topos) and being (ontology), the paper proposes an approach that is concentrated on the manifold modes through which topological relations are ontologically revealed, ordered, and defined. It acknowledges three topological tensions – thing-gathering, gathering-revealing, and concealing-revealing – in order to highlight the structure of the place in which the question of ontology, and ‘ontological politics’ are entwined.
... Texts like Contributions to Philosophy (of the Event) may thus give us a revolutionary angle of what the politics of being could look like, when human beings are not put at the centre of process. But the fact that Heidegger's hopes were grounded on National Socialism makes Heidegger lose what is " own-most " to being and Dasein: the openness of being that Dasein receives, guards and makes a question of (see Imre, 2010; Joronen, 2012; Owen and Imre, 2013). Heidegger not only falls to the robust ethnic characterization, but also establishes a collective portrayal of a metaphysical foundation upon which he bases his thinking of " world Jewry " . ...
Article
Full-text available
http://www.geogr-helv.net/special_issue298.html
Article
This article looks at learning geographically, conceptualizing transformative learning as a site of gathering-revealing—that is, as a fundamentally relational and deeply affectual coming together of ideas, histories, and doings. Rearticulating the stakes of the recent ontological turn in education in terms of encounters of difference put into play by the event, we outline evental learning, which stands in contrast to traditional models of propositional knowledge transmission and subjectification. With attention to spaces of attunement, hesitation, and dwelling as fundamental to transformative learning, we examine the renewed Finnish curriculum for upper secondary education, arguing that evental learning is foreclosed through two seemingly incongruous ontological horizons: (1) from the perspective of being, where technological thinking reveals a world knowable, orderable, and intendable, and with it a wilful subject that itself remains an available resource, and (2) from the perspective of becoming, where the learner is a subject of perpetual emergence and innovation, always moving on the edge of the event. The curriculum presents a valuable case for probing the tension between latent ideations of education as Bildung, or noninstrumental self-cultivation, and the demands of an increasing economization of education; and, further, the means by which the perspectives of being and becoming are woven together to handle such competing aims.
Article
Full-text available
Martin Buber’s writings on technology are scarce and seemingly subordinated to what he described in I and Thou as the “tyranny of the It”. But a closer look at his writings reveals, in fact, a life-long reflection on the dialogical potentiality of things—whether artworks, buildings, or machines—that echoed broader discourses on technology at the time. Beginning with Julius Goldstein’s Die Technik (1912), which Buber edited for his series Die Gesellschaft, and concluding with Buber’s reception and critique of Heidegger, especially during the 1950s, we can see that Buber critically engaged with the question of technology with respect to labor and community, art and artisanship, and the ethics of thinghood. The essay contextualizes Buber’s repeated call to “humanize technology” in early 20th-century debates on technology and in the post-1945 crisis of humanism. What it argues is that Buber framed technology not only through its aesthetic potential, as Werk, but also as another form of solidarity and care without which community and respect for our environment would not be possible.
Article
This article contributes to a growing debate within the field of early childhood education about the concept of ‘belonging’. It continues from earlier discussions that commented on the adoption of Belonging as a key term in the development of a national curriculum for the early years in Australia in 2009, as well as increasingly common references to belonging in various aspects of debate within the field. The article focuses specifically on the idea of belonging as it has emerged within existentialist philosophy in the 20th century, and more recent post-structuralist theories, especially the work of Jacques Derrida. The article ties belonging to language as a means of redefining approaches in early childhood education to the notions of place and context, so as to more rigorously connect ‘belonging’ to the philosophical debates of the 21st century.
Article
The paper lays out an ontological enquiry into the ways of ‘being of equipment’ as analysed by Heidegger and its role in understanding the design process. Equipments are things that make up our world. It is hard to imagine living without things because our existence is thingly textured. Heidegger’s analytics of equipment far exceeds the ontic sense of things. The argument is that there is a danger when designers limit themselves with the ontic understanding of equipment. Such an understanding coaxes us to believe in the half-baked truth about equipment- an isolated instance of a piece of artifact and leave us ignorant of the equipment's character as a part of an equipment structure. An ontological reflection on equipment brings forth its relational nature and can be rewarding in several ways in improving its design process.
Article
As part of a religiously-oriented analysis, Martin Buber associates Martin Heidegger’s later philosophy with magic. The present article is dedicated to explicating and evaluating this association. It does so, first, by fleshing out how Buber comes to depict Heidegger as an advocate of magic. Then, by examining other appearances of the category of magic in the wider context of Buber’s dialogical oeuvre, it demonstrates that what he has in mind when he invokes this category is a specific manner of human appeal to the divine marked by manipulation, utility and control. Finally, it evaluates the affiliation of Heidegger with magic: first, by comparing the metaphysical presuppositions undergirding the logic of magic—specifically the conceptions of, and interrelations between, ‘language’ and ‘being’—with Heidegger’s views, and second, by judging whether the claim that Heidegger promotes manipulative, utilitarian, and power-laden attitudes can be justified in light of his analysis of ‘technology’. The article ultimately argues that Buber misattributes magic to Heidegger, and that this misattribution better reflects the theoretical framework through which Buber justifies his dialogical position than an apt assessment of Heidegger’s thought.
Article
Martin Heidegger describes technology in essence as the late modern Western understanding of Being which is planetary in its reach. Succeeding the long phase of colonialism after World War II, the history of the global spread of this understanding of Being is intertwined with the developmental and globalization eras in the Global South. Techno-capitalist development crowds out alternative forms of economic and social life, which have been meaningfully prevalent in the Global South. The monistic metaphysics that powers developmentalism makes alternatives impossible. However, alternative political possibilities still exist, which are post-metaphysical and post-techno-developmental. Such politics pays attention to the place, things and self that matters to human beings and opens up a space for resisting techno-developmentalism.
Book
The long-awaited English translation of Heidegger’s ground-breaking work of 1936-38, Beiträge zur Philosophie (Vom Ereignis)
Book
The heart of history, for Heidegger, is not a sequence of occurrences but the eruption of significance at critical junctures that bring us into our own by making all being, including our being, into an urgent issue. In emergency, being emerges.”-from The Emergency of Being The esoteric Contributions to Philosophy, often considered Martin Heidegger’s second main work after Being and Time, is crucial to any interpretation of his thought. Here Heidegger proposes that being takes place as “appropriation.” Richard Polt’s independent-minded account of the Contributions interprets appropriation as an event of emergency that demands to be thought in a “future-subjunctive” mode. Polt explores the roots of appropriation in Heidegger’s earlier philosophy; Heidegger’s search for a way of thinking suited to appropriation; and the implications of appropriation for time, space, human existence, and beings as a whole. In his concluding chapter, Polt reflects critically on the difficulties of the radically antirationalist and antimodern thought of the Contributions. Polt’s original reading neither reduces this challenging text to familiar concepts nor refutes it, but engages it in a confrontation-an encounter that respects a way of thinking by struggling with it. He describes this most private work of Heidegger’s philosophy as “a dissonant symphony that imperfectly weaves together its moments into a vast fugue, under the leitmotif of appropriation. This fugue is seeded with possibilities that are waiting for us, its listeners, to develop them. Some are dead ends-viruses that can lead only to a monolithic, monotonous misunderstanding of history. Others are embryonic insights that promise to deepen our thought, and perhaps our lives, if we find the right way to make them our own.
Book
"... an attempt to revive ontology (or metaphysics) -- indeed philosophy itself -- by means of a two-sided conception of being.... This is a remarkable idea which has produced a powerful book." -- Leonard Lawlor. "... a major philosophical study: rich, brilliant... a tour de force, a seminal study that will be a starting-point for future research in this area." -- Robert Bernasconi. In Truth and Genesis, Miguel de Beistegui considers the role and meaning of philosophy today. Calling for a new departure for philosophy, one that brings together philosophy's scattered identities, de Beistegui proposes a robust and unified philosophy that would find itself equally at home in artistic and scientific disciplines. To build this renewed philosophy, de Beistegui turns to Aristotle and the earliest foundations of thought. He traces philosophy's development through the medieval and modern periods before comparing and investigating the work of two of the 20th century's most influential thinkers, Martin Heidegger and Gilles Deleuze. In particular, de Beistegui focuses on Deleuze's Difference and Repetition and Heidegger's Contributions to Philosophy for their handling of the concept of difference. De Beistegui concludes that Deleuze and Heidegger are irreconcilable, but it is in their disagreements that he sees a way to liberate philosophy from its current crisis.
Article
Heidegger is now widely recognized as one of the most influential and controversial philosophers of the twentieth century, yet much of his later philosophy remains shrouded in confusion and controversy. Restoring Heidegger's understanding of metaphysics as ‘ontotheology’ to its rightful place at the center of his later thought, this book demonstrates the depth and significance of his controversial critique of technology, his appalling misadventure with Nazism, his prescient critique of the university, and his important philosophical suggestions for the future of higher education. It will be required reading for those seeking to understand the relationship between Heidegger's philosophy and National Socialism, as well as the continuing relevance of his work.