ArticlePDF Available

Psychology Under Fire: Adversarial Operational Psychology and Psychological Ethics

American Psychological Association
Peace and Conflict: Journal of Peace Psychology
Authors:
  • Independent Researcher

Abstract

The 9/11 attacks on the United States have motivated psychologists to advance counterterrorism and related operations through psychological principles and skills. These operational psychologists seek to legitimize adversarial interventions against targets by prioritizing societal welfare over traditional, individual-focused principles of psychological ethics. In this essay, we distinguish adversarial operational psychology, which facilitates deceptive and coercive operations, from collaborative operational psychology, which optimizes personnel performance in high-risk operations. Our analysis finds that adversarial operational psychology is largely unsupported by the American Psychological Association Ethics Code, that its potential benefits are exceeded by the likelihood of irreversible harms, and that its military necessity is undemonstrated. We offer a three-factor framework for distinguishing between adversarial and collaborative operational psychology, and we recommend institutional separation of these roles so that professional psychologists do not serve in adversarial capacities.
Psychology Under Fire: Adversarial Operational Psychology and
Psychological Ethics
Jean Maria Arrigo
Project on Ethics and Art in Testimony, Irvine,
California
Roy J. Eidelson
Eidelson Consulting, Bala Cynwyd, Pennsylvania
Ray Bennett
Washington, D.C.
The 9/11 attacks on the United States have motivated psychologists to advance
counterterrorism and related operations through psychological principles and skills.
These operational psychologists seek to legitimize adversarial interventions against
targets by prioritizing societal welfare over traditional, individual-focused princi-
ples of psychological ethics. In this essay, we distinguish adversarial operational
psychology, which facilitates deceptive and coercive operations, from collaborative
operational psychology, which optimizes personnel performance in high-risk op-
erations. Our analysis finds that adversarial operational psychology is largely
unsupported by the American Psychological Association Ethics Code, that its
potential benefits are exceeded by the likelihood of irreversible harms, and that its
military necessity is undemonstrated. We offer a three-factor framework for dis-
tinguishing between adversarial and collaborative operational psychology, and we
recommend institutional separation of these roles so that professional psychologists
do not serve in adversarial capacities.
Keywords: operational psychology, psychological ethics, APA Ethics Code, counterterrorism,
psychological torture
For almost a century, American psycholo-
gists have assisted national security opera-
tions, often outside of public awareness or
concern. The progressive social psychologist
Kurt Lewin, for example, applied group dy-
namics to survival training for spies destined
for Occupied Europe in World War II.
Lewin’s role in this training, unknown to two
generations of behavioral scientists (Cooke,
2007), is an example of operational psychol-
Since 1995 social psychologist JEAN MARIA ARRIGO has
given voice to military intelligence professionals of con-
science through oral histories and joint activities with
scholars. She established the Intelligence Ethics Collection
at Hoover Institution Archives, Stanford University, and
the Ethics of Intelligence and Weapons Development Col-
lection at Bancroft Library, University of California,
Berkeley.
ROY J. EIDELSON is a clinical psychologist and the pres-
ident of Eidelson Consulting, where he conducts research,
writes, and consults on the role of psychological issues in
political, organizational, and group conflict settings. He is
a past president of Psychologists for Social Responsibility,
associate director of the Solomon Asch Center for Study of
Ethnopolitical Conflict at Bryn Mawr College, and a mem-
ber of the Coalition for an Ethical Psychology.
RAY BENNETT is a retired military intelligence officer
with more than 20 years of experience in the field of
military and law enforcement interrogation, including ser-
vice in Europe and the Middle East, and conflict deploy-
ments to Bosnia and Iraq.
For consultations on this article we are grateful to Juli-
anne McKinney, Case Officer A, Commander A, David
Debatto, David MacMichael, Grant Marler, Lawrence
Rockwood, and Special Investigator A (military intelli-
gence); David Cooper and Walter Schaller (ethics); Clark
McCauley, Trudy Bond, Steven Reisner, and Stephen
Soldz (psychology); Chuck Ruby (military psychology);
Carolyn Fluehr-Lobban (anthropology); Chaplain A (U.S.
Army chaplaincy); Robert Shabkie (law); John Crigler
(finance); journal editor Susan Opotow, and anonymous
reviewers.
CORRESPONDENCE CONCERNING THIS ARTICLE should be
addressed to Jean Maria Arrigo, 110 Oxford Street, Irvine,
CA 92612. E-mail: peat@peat-intel.org
Peace and Conflict: Journal of Peace Psychology © 2012 American Psychological Association
2012, Vol. 18, No. 4, 384– 400 1078-1919/12/$12.00 DOI: 10.1037/a0030323
384
ogy—the use of psychological principles and
skills to improve the effectiveness of military
and intelligence operations.
The psychological roots of operational psy-
chology in the United States lie in the mobi-
lization of American psychologists in World
War I by Robert Yerkes, then president of the
American Psychological Association (APA)
(Kennedy & Williams, 2011a). When promi-
nent noninterventionists contested U.S. entry
into the war, Yerkes maneuvered a politically
divided APA Council to “throw the machinery
of the Association behind mobilization for na-
tional service” (Camfield, 1992; p. 100). Along
with like-minded colleagues, he then persuaded
reluctant military authorities to embrace psy-
chology because “(a) the human factor was as
important in warfare as the material and (b)
psychologists, as the scientific experts on hu-
man behavior, had vital contributions to make
to the war effort” (Camfield, 1992; p. 102).
The operational roots of operational psy-
chology lie in the World War II Office of
Strategic Services (OSS), precursor to the
Central Intelligence Agency (CIA) (Kennedy
& Williams, 2011a). A 1944 review of the
involvement of social psychologists in the
war effort named 14 OSS psychologists
drawn from the faculties of notable universi-
ties (Marquis, 1944). As one example of their
activities, these psychologists developed effi-
cient methods of selection of agents for high-
risk missions (Office of Strategic Services
Assessment Staff, 1948). The tests predicted
fairly well which recruits would complete the
costly course of training. However, illustrat-
ing the high stakes of selection, “the ability of
the tests to predict stress tolerance under com-
bat, or torture by the Gestapo, could only be
guessed” (Banks, 1995, p. 78).
Williams, Picano, Roland, and Banks (2006)
provide a useful contemporary definition of op-
erational psychology:
Operational psychology is defined as the actions by
military psychologists that support the employment
and/or sustainment of military forces . . . to attain stra-
tegic goals in a theater of war or theater of operations
by leveraging and applying their psychological exper-
tise in helping to identify enemy capabilities, person-
alities, and intentions; facilitating and supporting
intelligence operations; designing and implementing
assessment and selection programs in support of spe-
cial populations and high-risk missions; and providing
an operationally focused level of mental health support
(pp. 194–195).
Although operational research is not specifi-
cally mentioned, it is an inseparable compo-
nent of the actions listed.
After the 9/11 attacks on the United States,
operational psychology gained new prominence
as the particular characteristics of the terrorist
threat—cross-cultural, asymmetric, religiously
and ethnically motivated, inspired by charis-
matic personalities, networked rather than insti-
tutional, and manifested through small-group
dynamics—attracted psychological expertise to
master an unfamiliar enemy. However, opera-
tional psychology also became the center of
intense controversy and debate following media
reports that psychologists were actively in-
volved in the military’s and the CIA’s abusive
interrogations of national security detainees at
various sites including Guantanamo Bay Naval
Base in Cuba and Bagram Airbase in Afghani-
stan (e.g., Lewis, 2004).
Adversarial Versus Collaborative
Operational Psychology
These activities highlight the reinvigoration,
as part of the past decade’s “global war on
terror,” of the ethically fraught category of op-
erational psychology that is the focus of this
article. Within this category we differentiate
between adversarial operational psychology
and collaborative operational psychology.As
we will argue, in most cases specific operational
activities can readily be categorized as predom-
inantly adversarial or collaborative, based on
the relationship between the operational psy-
chologists and the targets of their interventions.
Collaborative Operational Psychology
Collaborative operational psychology (COP)
encompasses the traditional operational psycho-
logical tasks of personnel assessment, selection,
training, evaluation, and overt operations re-
search to maximize personnel performance and
survivability for high-risk military and intelli-
gence operations. It accords with operational
medicine, whose official goal is “to maximize
performance and survivability of the warf-
ighter” (Naval Operational Medicine Institute,
2011). In COP, the targets of psychological
intervention ideally share the psychologist’s
overall mission and are party to employment or
385PSYCHOLOGY UNDER FIRE
social contracts that limit harm and permit legal
representation.
Consider, for example, a clinical psycholo-
gist instructed to evaluate the mental stability of
an employee at a nuclear weapons facility (Pi-
cano, Williams, Roland, & Long, 2011). This
activity fits the profile of COP. Although the
evaluation could possibly have adverse conse-
quences for the employee, it is reasonable to
expect the employee to share the overriding
commitment to the safe operation of the nuclear
facility. In addition, by accepting this position,
the employee has, more or less, agreed to such
evaluations and, in principle, judicial recourse
is available if the employee disputes a negative
assessment. Or consider a clinical psychologist
assigned to a Special Forces sniper team for
mental health care (U.S. Army Medical Depart-
ment, 2010). In this role the psychologist pro-
vides care for the sniper, which is again consid-
ered collaborative, although the sniper is in an
adversarial relationship to his target.
Adversarial Operational Psychology
In contrast with COP, adversarial operational
psychology (AOP) engages psychologists in di-
rect support of deception, coercion, and assault
in military and intelligence operations and in
covert operations research. It encompasses the
tasks of identification and manipulation of ad-
versaries in counterintelligence and counterter-
rorism operations and of covert behavioral and
weapons research on human subjects. The tar-
gets of psychological intervention in AOP op-
pose the psychologist’s mission and/or are sub-
ject to nonstipulated harms. Examples of AOP
would be the clinical evaluation of a national
security detainee in order to uncover psycho-
logical vulnerabilities that will subsequently be
exploited in an interrogation of the prisoner for
intelligence gathering purposes (Frakt, 2009)or
the in-house psychological evaluation to dis-
credit a whistleblower or moral dissident in a
national security setting (Brewer & Arrigo,
2008).
Clarifying the Nature of Operational
Psychology
We emphasize that the COP–AOP categoriza-
tion is not simply a good-bad distinction for two
reasons. First, psychological ethics can be irrec-
oncilable with military ethics. For example, obe-
dience to superiors is a virtue in military ethics but
a source of caution in psychological ethics; phys-
ical courage is central to military ethics but largely
irrelevant to psychological ethics. Second, the
COP–AOP categorization does not precisely
demarcate ethical professional psychology
from unethical professional psychology.
Rather, this distinction is a very close approx-
imation that is comprehensible to agents and ame-
nable to institutional implementation. It thereby
meets the demands of “psychological realism” in
ethics (Flanagan, 1991, p. 32) in a national secu-
rity setting.
Thus, three clarifications are important at this
point. First, operational psychology is a special-
ization area within a much broader realm of
psychological knowledge and practice relevant
to military and national security settings. Most
psychologists whose work supports the U.S.
military and other defense-related agencies are
not in operational roles. For example, the many
clinical psychologists routinely providing valu-
able psychological services to soldiers and vet-
erans in VA hospitals and other medical facili-
ties are not engaged in activities characterized
as operational psychology. Nor are those psy-
chologists who teach traditional psychology
courses at any of the military academies. In
contrast, psychologists serving in counterintel-
ligence or counterterrorism roles are working in
the operational psychology arena.
Second, we write here about collaborative
and adversarial operational psychology, not
about collaborative and adversarial operational
psychologists. For us, the key considerations
and concerns revolve around the operational
roles assigned to, or initiated by, psycholo-
gists—not the individual psychologists who
perform them. By this we mean that it is not our
intention to globally categorize people as “eth-
ical professional psychologists” or “unethical
professional psychologists.” Instead, our goal is
to provide a framework for separating specific
operational roles into ethical and unethical cat-
egories. In this regard, both COP and AOP
involve risks to psychological ethics, and COP
activities sometimes transform rapidly into
AOP activities—and vice versa—depending on
the assignment and exigencies. However, the
ethical dilemmas of COP are pliable: they yield
to planning, training, monitoring, and negotia-
tion. AOP, on the other hand, has an obdurate
386 ARRIGO, EIDELSON, AND BENNETT
core of exploitation essential to the operation
and incompatible with independent oversight.
Third, we are strictly focused on issues of
psychological ethics surrounding the use of psy-
chologists for operational roles in military and
other national security settings. We recognize
that a non-psychologist may ethically assume
certain roles that it would be unethical for a
psychologist to assume. However, with U.S.
society under terrorist threat, leading advocates
of AOP (e.g., Ewing & Gelles, 2003) argue that
the traditional psychological ethics of profes-
sional psychology must be adapted to national
security exigencies in order to protect society
and promote the greater good. In a recently
published edited book, Ethical Practice in Op-
erational Psychology (Kennedy & Williams,
2011b), seven chapters champion AOP. The
editors and many chapter authors are them-
selves operational psychologists. Three served
on the controversial 10-member APA Presiden-
tial Task Force on Psychological Ethics and
National Security (PENS), which declared that
psychologists serve to keep interrogations of
national security detainees safe, legal, ethical,
and effective (APA, 2005).
In sum, while recognizing the valuable con-
tributions of military and intelligence psychol-
ogists in COP, our purpose in this essay is to
probe and challenge the ethical underpinnings
and practical consequences of AOP. We will
argue that AOP poses irresolvable ethical con-
flicts for the psychologists involved, APA’s eth-
ics code fails to support the interpretations of
AOP advocates, unintended harmful effects of
AOP are significant, and proponents of AOP
presume its military necessity (e.g., APA, 2005;
Ewing & Gelles, 2003;Johnson, 2008;Ken-
nedy & Williams, 2011b) without providing
evidence. We conclude by offering an ethical
framework for further discussion and by empha-
sizing the urgent and critical need for institu-
tional separation of collaborative operational
roles from adversarial operational roles so that
no psychologists serve in both capacities during
any employment contract period.
In our analysis we include the perspectives of
several veteran military and intelligence profes-
sionals who have worked with military psychol-
ogists. Their interviews and correspondence
with the first author (Arrigo) have been archived
as cited. These individuals offer alternative
viewpoints to the uncritical AOP stance pre-
sented by Kennedy and Williams (2011b) and
related publications (e.g., Department of the
Army, 2010;Ewing & Gelles, 2003;Shumate &
Borum, 2006).
AOP: Questions and Concerns
Which Ethical Codes Apply?
From the start, it is important to recognize
that all active-duty military psychologists are
fully deployable soldiers—soldiers first, psy-
chologists second (Debatto, 2011;Johnson,
2008). According to the Department of the
Army (2010, January 7), U.S. law and military
regulations override the APA Ethics Code:
The [APA] Ethics Code does not supersede applicable
U.S. and international law, regulations, or DoD [De-
partment of Defense] policy . . .. The Ethics Code
pertains only to a psychologist’s activities that are
“part of their scientific, educational or professional
roles” pertaining to the profession of psychology. The
Code does not, therefore, have purview over the psy-
chologist’s role as a Soldier, civilian, or contractor
employee that is unrelated to the practice of psychol-
ogy. For instance, the dictum for beneficence does not
pertain to actions against the enemy in combat (p. 19).
At the same time, the U.S. military requires
its medical corps personnel, including psychol-
ogists, to maintain professional practice licenses
with their state licensing boards. This require-
ment establishes a strong connection between
military psychology and the APA Ethics Code
because this Code is the foundation for most
state licensing board regulations. The U.S.
Army regulations for Behavioral Science Con-
sultation Teams (BSCTs) involved in detention
and interrogation operations, headed by state-
licensed clinical psychologists, foreground the
APA Ethics Code yet ultimately override it. For
operational psychologists there is no official
line where, in principle at least, national secu-
rity missions yield to psychological ethics. The
mission comes first. This is why psychologists
engaged in AOP are essentially military and
intelligence professionals with a specialization
in psychology, obliged to adhere to psycholog-
ical ethics only when compatible with the mis-
sion (e.g., Olson & Davis, 2008), as illustrated
in the Mohammed Jawad case described below.
Operational psychologists who work outside
the Department of Defense (DoD) may not even
be accountable to military regulations and mil-
itary ethics. The Detainee Treatment Act of
387PSYCHOLOGY UNDER FIRE
2005 restricted DoD interrogation techniques to
the Human Intelligence Collector Operations,
Field Manual 2–22.3 (U.S. Army Headquarters,
2006), which respects the Geneva Conven-
tions—apart from the dispensation for isolation
of interrogatees in Appendix M. However, only
the discretion and authority of President George
W. Bush placed limits on CIA interrogations
(Suleman, 2006). Thus, veteran military psy-
chologists under CIA contract were able to ini-
tiate waterboarding of detainees, which military
regulations forbade but the President approved
(Shane, 2009).
Are Psychologists More Ethical Then
Doctors and Anthropologists?
We can look to the operational experience of
sister professions for useful comparisons with
operational psychology. The international his-
tory of operational medicine and psychiatry is
infamous, with the “Nazi doctors” (Lifton,
1986), tactical diagnoses of dissidents by Soviet
psychiatrists to justify forced drugging (Warren,
1975), and persistent, worldwide involvement
in torture (Vesti & Somnier, 1994). In the
United States, adversarial operational medicine
and psychiatry flourished secretly in the Army’s
“man-break” biochemical weapons experiments
in World War II (Pechura & Rall, 1993), post-
war nuclear weapons development programs
(Advisory Committee on Human Radiation Ex-
periments, 2005), and the Cold War CIA behav-
ioral modification project MKULTRA (U.S.
Senate, 1977).
Early revelations of U.S. torture interroga-
tions in the Iraq War pointed to the involvement
of operational physicians (Bloche & Marks,
2005;Miles, 2006) and aroused concern about
the psychiatrists initially assigned to BSCTs
(Department of Defense, 2002, November 11).
In May, 2006 the American Psychiatric Asso-
ciation forbade psychiatrists from “being pres-
ent in the interrogation room, asking or suggest-
ing questions, or advising authorities on the use
of specific techniques of interrogation with par-
ticular detainees” (American Psychiatric Asso-
ciation, 2006). Assistant Secretary of Defense
for Health Affairs William Winkenwerder
(2006) responded that psychiatrists could be
assigned to interrogations if no qualified psy-
chologists were available, and the DoD contin-
ued to train BSCT psychiatrists (Marks &
Bloche, 2008). As is true for psychologists, the
missions and regulations of national security
agencies can override the professional ethics
codes of medical personnel.
Historically, U.S. anthropologists subju-
gated Native Americans for the Bureau of
Indian Affairs and doubled as spies in World
WarI(Fluehr-Lobban, 2009), developed out-
rageous ruses for the OSS in World War II
(Marks, 1979); facilitated the internment of
Japanese Americans (Starn, 1986), planned
counterinsurgency research in South America
under the U.S. Army’s Project Camelot in
1964 (Horowitz, 1974), and advised the
CIA’s Phoenix Program on the capture and
killing of alleged counterinsurgents in the
Vietnam War (Gusterson, 2008).
Post-9/1l, Gusterson (2008) noted that
“The Pentagon seems to have decided that
anthropology is to the war on terror what
physics was to the Cold War.” Secretary of
Defense Robert Gates embedded armed an-
thropologists with “Human Terrain Teams” in
combat brigades in Iraq and Afghanistan. The
goal was to improve cultural sensitivity, col-
lect intelligence from villagers, and serve as
liaisons to local authorities. In 2009, the
American Anthropological Association
(AAA) Ad Hoc Commission on Anthropolo-
gy’s Engagement with the Security and Intel-
ligence Communities emphasized the ideal of
constructive rather than adversarial engage-
ment between anthropology and the military.
The Commission nevertheless attempted to
separate professional from adversarial opera-
tional duties by declaring the Human Terrain
System inconsistent with the AAA Code of
Ethics:
When ethnographic investigation is determined by
military missions, not subject to external review,
where data collection occurs in the context of war,
integrated into the goals of counterinsurgency, and
in a potentially coercive environment . . ., it can no
longer be considered a legitimate professional exer-
cise of anthropology (American Anthropological
Association Commission on the Engagement of An-
thropology with the U.S. Security and Intelligence
Communities, 2009, p. 3).
Advocates for AOP must explain how pro-
fessional psychologists can adhere to psycho-
logical ethics in adversarial operations even
though doctors and anthropologists have been
unable to adhere to the ethics of their profes-
388 ARRIGO, EIDELSON, AND BENNETT
sions in diverse adversarial operations over
decades.
Who Is the Client of AOP?
Like the ethical principles of medicine, psy-
chiatry, anthropology, and law, the principles of
psychological ethics evolved to protect the
weaker from the stronger. They are designed to
protect the patient–client or research subject, as
the relatively unknowledgeable, vulnerable, and
exposed party, from the psychologist, as the
relatively knowledgeable, authoritative, and un-
exposed party. Indeed the APA Ethics Code
largely mandates the psychologist’s responsibil-
ity to individual patient–clients (APA, 2010).
Proponents of AOP though interpret the govern-
ment as an appropriate client and recipient of
the operational psychologist’s protection.
For example, Dunivin, Banks, Staal, and Ste-
phenson (2011) defend the role of BSCT psy-
chologists in detainee interrogations, arguing
that a balance “must be established between
ethical responsibilities to an individual and eth-
ical responsibilities to the larger society” (p.
87). Acknowledging that Principle A of the
APA Ethics Code—Beneficence and Nonma-
leficence—calls upon the psychologist to “do
no harm” to the individual being questioned,
they claim that Principle B—Fidelity and Re-
sponsibility—provides a key counterbalance by
protecting the interests of other individuals and
the general public.
A full reading of Principle B, however, belies
this narrow interpretation. Principle B refers not
only to psychologists’ being “aware of their
professional and scientific responsibilities to so-
ciety,” but also emphasizes that psychologists
“establish relationships of trust with those with
whom they work,” “uphold professional stan-
dards of conduct,” “accept appropriate respon-
sibility for their behavior,” “seek to manage
conflicts of interest that could lead to exploita-
tion or harm,” and are “concerned about the
ethical compliance of their colleagues’ scien-
tific and professional conduct.” Standard 3.08
of the APA Ethics Code on Exploitative Rela-
tionships is especially germane here as well
(APA, 2010). It states specifically, “Psycholo-
gists do not exploit persons over whom they
have supervisory, evaluative, or other authority
such as clients/patients, students, supervisees,
research participants, and employees.”
Although disarming, the government-as-
client analogy is spurious. The reversal of
power relations whereby the psychologist
serves to protect the collective, stronger party
at the expense of the individual, weaker party
is a profound alteration—not merely an ex-
tension—of traditional ethical practice in
psychology.
The government-as-client analogy also fails
as a practical matter when conflict emerges be-
tween government authorities. Consider an ex-
ample from military court records. In 2003,
BCST psychologist “X” advised on the interro-
gation of the teenager Mohammed Jawad at
Guantanamo Bay Detention Center. Jawad’s de-
fense attorney, Maj. David Frakt, subsequently
subpoenaed Dr. X for the 2008 trial of Jawad by
the Guantanamo Military Commission. Frakt
(2009, p. 22) later wrote:
I also was provided records showing that Mr. Jawad
was placed in isolation for two 30-day periods . . .. The
[second] period of isolation was ordered by intelli-
gence officials upon the recommendation of the Be-
havioral Science Consultation Team psychologist [X]
to socially, physically and linguistically isolate this
teenage boy in order to create complete dependence on
his interrogator . . . and to break Mr. Jawad and to
devastate him emotionally.
At the time, Frakt and the psychologist for
the defense reported that Dr. X refused to tes-
tify, invoking the right to remain silent to avoid
self-incrimination by Section 831, Article 31, of
the Uniform Code of Military Justice (Soldz,
2008; S. Soldz, personal communication, May
11, 2011). The government-as-client analogy
offers no ethical remedy in this case of conflict-
ing obligations to different government clients
such as the local commander and the military
court.
Veteran U.S. Army case officer Julianne
McKinney (2011, July 9) raised an additional
point: “Dr. X worked ‘against’ U.S. service
members as much as he or she worked against
Jawad” through “the lowering of standards and
ethical compromises inflicted on inexperienced
interrogators who complied with Dr. X’s ad-
vice.” This case may represent rarer abuses of
AOP, but proponents need to address the lack of
a systematic means of addressing excessive
zeal. Williams and Kennedy (2011) seem to
incorporate this fervor into the AOP program
with alarmist exaggerations such as this: “If
psychologists view [the extremists] as individ-
389PSYCHOLOGY UNDER FIRE
uals, they are terrorists, but if psychologists
view their larger true intent, they are genoci-
dists” (p. 137).
Can Current APA Ethical Guidelines
Regulate AOP?
Even without the extrapolation of the APA
Ethics Code to the government as client, AOP
exacerbates current vulnerabilities of the Ethics
Code to government discretion. APA Ethics
Code Standard 8.05, as adopted in 2002, trans-
fers the “informed consent” obligations of re-
search scientists to government discretion. It
states: “Psychologists may dispense with in-
formed consent only (1) where research would
not reasonably be assumed to create distress or
harm . . . or (2) where otherwise permitted by
law or federal or institutional regulations”
(APA, 2010). Case Officer A (2011, July 4)
remarked: “Government agencies will pass
whatever institutional regulation needed to ac-
complish the mission.”
Historically, routine clinical and research ac-
tivities have provided opportunities and cover
for adversarial operations research. For exam-
ple, clinical psychologist Mitchell Berkun,
known for his psychological stress experiments
on soldiers in maneuvers at the Nevada Test
Site (Berkun, Timiras, & Pace, 1958) and Pre-
sidio of Monterey (Berkun, Bialek, Kern, &
Yagi, 1962), also secretly conducted a medical
mock-death experiment on untrained Army
recruits in the course of apparently routine
inoculations (Secord, Backman, & Arrigo,
1997–1998). Military experts consulted on this
experiment deemed the experiment operation-
ally useless and ethically dubious (e.g., Rood,
2008). For a more current illustration, the Air
Force Research Laboratory, Sandia National
Laboratories, and Raytheon Company have de-
veloped an electronic-beam weapon that causes
the skin of human targets to feel unbearably hot,
yet purportedly inflicts no injury if the person
runs away promptly. One purpose of this Active
Denial System—crowd control, as in repelling
intruders at nuclear energy facilities (Sandia
National Laboratories, 2005)—would seem to
encourage AOP involvement. However, the se-
cretive nature of the project precludes inquiry
into the identities and techniques of researchers.
As the acknowledged experts on mind and
behavior, psychologists can stretch the range of
acceptable conduct in field situations where in-
dependent monitors are forbidden access and
evidence. An army commander described his
harrowing experience of Survival, Evasion, Re-
sistance, and Escape (SERE) training in the
mid-1970s, where trainers convincingly feigned
the death of a disobedient trainee. Afterward the
commander set up a SERE training program in
his own division, noting, “[i]t was easygoing
compared to that [training] because we didn’t
have the psychologists and physicians . . .” to
cover the program risk of staging extreme pun-
ishments (Commander A, 2008). That is, the
absence of health professionals led the com-
mander to reduce—not increase—the harshness
of the exercises.
AOP advocates underestimate the extent to
which adversarial operations can draw the psy-
chologist into ethical entanglements that can be
difficult to escape. Consider the law enforce-
ment hostage negotiation scenario presented by
Gelles and Palarea (2011). To minimize ethical
quandaries posed by dual relationships, differ-
ent operational psychologists take on separate
responsibilities. As multiphased operations
move from one phase to the next, these respon-
sibilities can include the selection and training
of negotiators, stress management for the nego-
tiators, assessment of the hostage taker’s course
toward violence, and debriefing and counseling
of crisis team members. However, such parti-
tioning is impractical or impossible in many
military settings because multiple operational
psychologists with the requisite clearances and
competencies are typically unavailable on ships,
at outposts, in high-risk and secret facilities
requiring special clearances, or at similar sites
(Johnson, 2008).
In reviewing Gelles and Palarea’s (2011)
seemingly straightforward, win–win, crisis ne-
gotiation scenario—the hostages will be res-
cued and the hostage-taker will survive–Case
Officer A (2011, April 19) identified a potential
ethical problem:
So the hostage negotiator going to violence probably
wants to enable a kill shot for his SWAT team. And
how is he going to get the terrorist—let’s say it’s a
terrorist—over to a window? He can ask the psychol-
ogist to help him cause that guy to come to the win-
dow. Now does the psychologist do that or not? Is he
just helping to get someone to the window, or does he
get someone to the window to have him killed? I
believe the psychologist would be fully engaged be-
cause that’s his job.
390 ARRIGO, EIDELSON, AND BENNETT
This scenario shifts the focus from the poten-
tially manageable issue of multiple relation-
ships to the deeper moral question of when
“enabling” becomes “doing.” It is also impor-
tant to recognize that even if there is consensus
that drawing the hostage taker to the window for
a “kill shot” is desirable, it is a separate matter
as to whether a licensed clinical psychologist—
committed to a code of professional ethics—
should be permitted this responsibility.
Can AOP Be Monitored and Deterred?
The ethical risks associated with AOP are
further magnified by the absence of a reliable
system for monitoring and deterring wrongful
behavior. AOP advocates themselves have
noted, “there must also be established proce-
dures for monitoring and observing the actions
of those within the profession along with the
sanctioning mechanisms for those who deviate
from the accepted standards” (Williams & Ken-
nedy, 2011, p. 132). However, there is no pro-
vision in military regulations for the indepen-
dent monitoring of BSCT psychologists in
regard to psychological ethics (Department of
the Army, 2010), no recommendation for inde-
pendent monitoring in the APA PENS Report
(APA, 2005), and no advocacy for independent
monitoring of which we are aware from any of
the proponents of AOP we have cited.
State licensing boards in Alabama, Louisi-
ana, Ohio, and New York have declined to
adjudicate well-documented complaints submit-
ted against operational psychologists purport-
edly involved in abusive interrogations of
national security detainees (Eligon, 2011). In
particular, the Alabama Board of Examiners did
not accept jurisdiction of the 2008 complaint
against Dr. X, the BSCT psychologist whom
Maj. Frakt implicated in the torture of Jawad at
Guantanamo Bay (Lodge, 2009). David Debatto
(2011, April 6), a retired police investigator and
counterintelligence operative who had worked
with psychologists, remarked that if state licens-
ing boards tried to investigate, “The military
would throw up as many roadblocks as it
could.”
Case Officer A (2011, April 19), himself
trained in psychology, pointed to another obsta-
cle to monitoring: the potential use of subordi-
nates as proxies for psychological interventions.
He said: “In the military, you have many people
with psychological training at the masters level.
They have in essence the training that is neces-
sary [for adversarial psychological operations].
I don’t see how you can monitor them.” In fact,
the 2010 BSCT instructions call for an enlisted
Behavioral Science Technician team member
with at least 10 years of experience to serve
under direct supervision of a clinical psycholo-
gist (Department of the Army, 2010). Any re-
alistic monitoring procedures, therefore,
would have to link state licensing boards to
judicial procedures in the security sector, pen-
etrating as far as mental health personnel su-
pervised by operational psychologists. This
would be an unprecedented incursion of mi-
nor civilian authorities into critical operations
of the security sector.
Some AOP advocates assert that operational
psychologists simply cannot be bound by un-
derstandings of psychological ethics that they
now consider outdated. Ewing and Gelles
(2003) argue, “we cannot continue to place [op-
erational psychologists] in situations where the
ethics of their conduct will be judged, post hoc,
either by rules ‘irrelevant’ to their vital govern-
mental functions or by professional organiza-
tions or licensing authorities” (p. 106). Morgan
et al. (2006) further warn: “Efforts to prohibit
these professionals from engaging in their work
are more likely to alienate them from existing
professional organizations rather than influence
them to seek new professional roles” (p. 27).
Does Military Necessity Justify AOP?
Proponents of AOP hold that societal welfare
must often take priority over the welfare of the
individuals with whom the operational psychol-
ogist engages. The crux of this utilitarian ethical
argument is military necessity, the principle that
a nation at war may use any means permitted
under the laws of war that are indispensable to
a military operation (Forrest, 2007). But estab-
lishing military necessity requires advocates to
demonstrate that the use of psychologists sub-
stantially improves the success of operations in
comparison to the use of other military and
intelligence specialists. After all, military ne-
cessity is the justification for the unique ethical
risks associated with AOP. Two examples are
instructive.
In the realm of counterterrorism and counter-
intelligence, Kennedy, Borum, and Fein (2011)
391PSYCHOLOGY UNDER FIRE
describe an ethical dilemma in recruiting a U.S.
service member to collect intelligence from a
childhood friend who is part of a possible ter-
rorist cell. An operational psychologist is en-
gaged to assess the soldier’s suitability for the
assignment, provide behavioral information
useful in managing him, and monitor his man-
agement. Two former case officers consulted
for this essay were skeptical of the operational
value and ethical standing of the operational
psychologist.
Presented with this scenario, Case Officer A
(2011, April 19), who ran agents in the Middle
East in the 1980s, posed an irresolvable conflict
with psychological ethics: “but suppose the per-
son [the soldier] has decided his loyalty is really
with his friend. And now he starts working
against you in the operation . . . . You’ll set traps
for him. The psychologist could be involved
laying the traps.” As a functional objection to
AOP involvement, Case Officer A (2011, July
4) also observed that, in contrast with AOP
practitioners, the case officer’s skills involve
interpersonal communications, persuasion, and
operational planning. Moreover, these skills are
employed in the field, at risk, not in the con-
trolled environments of professional psychol-
ogy. A talented psychologist might be ade-
quately trained, but then he or she would essen-
tially be a case officer, bound by the national
security agency’s mission, regulations, and eth-
ics, not primarily by psychological ethics.
Case officer McKinney (2011, April 11), who
ran agents against the Soviet Bloc in the 1980s,
regarded all of the psychologist’s actions—
from the initial test of the service member’s
cooperation to the amelioration of con-
science—to be elementary moves for highly
trained case officers. McKinney acknowledged
that a battery of remotely evaluated psycholog-
ical tests could be helpful in the initial profiling
effort, but she noted that trained case officers
are as capable as psychologists of determining
whether the potential asset’s aberrations can be
exploited for operational purposes—and such
exploitation could generate irresolvable prob-
lems in psychological ethics. She particularly
objected to Kennedy et al.’s (2011) successful
manipulation of the service member as the mea-
sure of AOP value, whereas she regarded ac-
quisition of useful intelligence as the only rel-
evant measure of value.
Evidence of military necessity is similarly
lacking in regard to the involvement of opera-
tional psychologists in the interrogations of na-
tional security detainees. This controversial
topic has risen to the level of national debate
(e.g., Physicians for Human Rights, 2010) be-
cause some of the psychological techniques
used are tantamount to torture. The third author,
a retired senior interrogator, attested that even
though Guantanamo Bay Detention Center was
(incorrectly) said to hold the “worst of the
worst” terrorists, the Army nevertheless relied
on inexperienced interrogators. At a minimum,
the BSCT psychologists involved should
have—and may have—insisted on well-trained,
mentored, experienced interrogators as critical
to the operation (Arrigo & Bennett, 2007). The
participating psychologists’ inability to accom-
plish this obvious and essential improvement
over the course of years begs explanation.
Bennett also points to the institutional capac-
ity of staff officers, such as BSCT psycholo-
gists, to override the expertise of the lower-
ranking military specialists who opposed
interrogation techniques of the Bush Adminis-
tration (Arrigo & Bennett, 2007). At the very
least, within their utilitarian framework, advo-
cates for AOP need to provide evidence that the
contributions of psychologists actually produce
incremental value in operations in which they
compete for resources, influence, and prestige
with established military specialists. Beyond
that, military necessity must be of sufficient
magnitude to compensate for the harmful unin-
tended consequences of AOP that we discuss
next, because the ethics of military necessity
requires minimization of harms (Forrest, 2007).
What Are Unintended Harmful
Consequences of AOP?
Among those unintended harmful conse-
quences of AOP to psychology as an interna-
tional profession and as a science are the mili-
tarization of psychology, degradation of the sci-
entific method, jeopardy of the public trust, and
damage to COP. We briefly consider each here.
Militarization of psychology. Significant,
and potentially irreversible, unintended adverse
consequences present another troubling dimen-
sion of the legitimization of AOP. As the largest
and most influential psychological association,
APA’s support for AOP would tend to encour-
392 ARRIGO, EIDELSON, AND BENNETT
age the nationalization and militarization of
psychology around the world (Moghaddam,
2007). This is especially evident with the visible
deployment of U.S. operational psychologists to
Afghanistan, Guantanamo Bay, and Iraq and
with retirees hiring out as contractors. Indeed,
this was one of the concerns that led the Puerto
Rican Psychological Association—upon the
initiative of a member who had served in the
Iraq War—to reject a planned visit in 2010 from
the Director of the APA Ethics Office, a notable
public advocate for psychologist-assisted inter-
rogations (Rivera-Santana, 2010).
Any militarization of psychology is likely to
have domestic consequences as well because
defense against foreign enemies is not well dis-
tinguished from state control of internal dissi-
dents. This reality was highlighted by news of
the detention conditions of U.S. Army Pfc.
Bradley Manning, alleged leaker of U.S. intel-
ligence data, which pervaded the media in late
2010 and early 2011. At Marine Corps Base
Quantico, Manning reportedly endured domes-
tic application of abusive AOP techniques of
detention developed for terrorist suspects in
Guantanamo (Pilkington, 2011). David MacMi-
chael, a former commander of the Marine head-
quarters unit at Quantico, wrote a personal letter
to the current Quantico commander recom-
mending court martial of Manning, if merited,
but deploring Manning’s “invidious” illegal
confinement (MacMichael, 2011).
Degradation of scientific method. A fur-
ther consequence of psychology’s militarization
is the politicization and degradation of scientific
method. Transparency, data sharing, peer re-
view, and independent monitoring all drop
away under military necessity. Former APA
President Martin Seligman, a proponent of
AOP, took this position in 2003:
The civilized world is at war with Jihad Islamic ter-
rorism. It takes a bomb in the office of some academics
to make them realize that their most basic values are
now threatened . . .. If we lose the war . . ., fighting
fatwahs and no education for women will displace
grousing about random assignment of schoolchildren
to study education. If we win this war, we can go on to
pursue the normal goals of science (Seligman, 2003).
Seligman’s argument assumes cessation of
AOP violations of scientific method after defeat
of Jihad Islamic terrorism and a subsequent
reversal of the degradation of psychological sci-
ence. Social science historian Ellen Herman ar-
gues to the contrary that, since World War II,
those who interpret war as a psychological con-
flict have “bonded psychological knowledge to
political power,” in “peacefare” as well as war-
fare (Herman, 1995, pp. 306–307).
Jeopardy of the public trust. Taking an
historical perspective, Walsh (2012) ventured
that “American intelligence work can taint an
entire profession . . ..” and noted that CIA spies
are forbidden to pose as Peace Corps volun-
teers, Fulbright Fellows, or accredited Ameri-
can journalists. A Special Operations chaplain,
pressed for collection of intelligence on Muslim
religious authorities, objected: “We are there to
hold to a higher moral ground. You take off
your cross and you step down” (Chaplain A,
2010). An author of the American Psychiatric
Association’s 2006 Position Statement on Psy-
chiatric Participation in Interrogation of De-
tainees said, “The whole issue of psychiatrists
getting into deceptive positions with people was
unacceptable to most of us” (Zonana, 2009).
The legitimization of AOP also crucially risks
jeopardizing the public trust in the clinical
work, human subjects research, and leadership
roles of psychologists.
For good reason, judicial codes of ethics typ-
ically caution against even the appearance of
impropriety. Impropriety can be understood as
“whether a person aware of the facts might
reasonably entertain a doubt that the judge
would be able to act with integrity, impartiality,
and competence” (California Supreme Court,
2009, p. 7). For decades, appearances of impro-
priety have cost U.S. anthropologists the trust of
indigenous peoples. A member of the American
Anthropological Association’s Commission on
Engagement of Anthropology with the Military
and National Security Agencies, 2006–2010,
Carolyn Fluehr-Lobban (2009) complained:
“Most people think I’m a CIA agent anyway.
What else would I be doing coming into the
Sudan and learning Arabic and hanging
around?”
Appearances of impropriety are easily found
in the AOP realm. For instance, Seligman re-
sponded to the 9/11 terrorist attacks by conven-
ing a counterterrorism and psychology meeting
in his home. The psychologist who subse-
quently created the CIA waterboarding program
attended with the CIA Director of Behavioral
Sciences Research. In 2002, Seligman lectured
CIA interrogators and psychologists on his
393PSYCHOLOGY UNDER FIRE
technique of inducing “learned helplessness” in
dogs, a technique subsequently applied to “en-
hanced interrogations” of detainees and desig-
nated a required core competency of the BSCTs
(Department of the Army, 2006). In February
2010, the Army awarded Seligman’s research
group a no-bid contract of $31 million for pos-
itive psychology-based resilience training of
soldiers (Benjamin, 2010). Critics might rea-
sonably entertain a doubt about the impartiality
of the contract. Because of secrecy and the
deliberate strategic dissemination of false or
inaccurate information (i.e., disinformation) in
the security sector, there is no way to resolve
appearances of impropriety in AOP.
Potential damage to COP. According to
military-intelligence sources interviewed by the
first author (Arrigo), concealed AOP tactics can
interfere with and override more appropriate
COP approaches in some situations. These tac-
tics can threaten morale and good order in the
military, which depend on commanders’ fair
and impartial treatment of subordinates (Rock-
wood, 2011). For example, commanders use of
psychological evaluations to control dissident
or disliked subordinates is widely rumored, de-
spite regulations forbidding inappropriate refer-
rals for evaluation (Lauretano, 1998). A veteran
of the Air Force Office of Special Investigations
stated that investigators are often rewarded for
convictions rather than for comprehensive and
impartial investigations—and an unfavorable
psychological diagnosis of the suspect is a
shortcut to a conviction (Special Investigator A,
2010).
Mission goals can therefore sometimes moti-
vate invalid evaluations by operational psychol-
ogists, a looming threat that alone can damage
performance and morale. A former counterin-
telligence officer similarly warned, “the military
has always used the nut ward as a hanging
sword over each agent” (Brewer & Arrigo,
2008, p. 15). Legitimization of clinical psy-
chologists in deceptive and manipulative
AOP tactics would further erode trust in COP
evaluations of personnel, where high stakes
and secrecy can amplify the role of trust.
Relevant here as well are reports of psychol-
ogists diagnosing veterans as having person-
ality disorders in order to avoid the more
costly disability payments associated with the
diagnosis of posttraumatic stress disorder (e.
g., Union of Concerned Scientists, 2009).
As we have indicated, our concerns about the
professional ethics of AOP are deep and multi-
faceted. To be clear, our discussion of the AOP–
COP divide has explicitly focused on whether
professional psychologists should engage in
particular operational activities. By professional
psychologists, we mean individuals who hold
recognized professional degrees in psychology
as clinicians, researchers, teachers, trainers,
consultants, administrators, or other specialists.
We do not address broader questions of whether
certain operational activities should or should
not be undertaken regardless of who is in-
volved, nor do we question the uses of psycho-
logical science in national security arenas. Here
we question only the extension of professional
psychology to include AOP.
A Framework for AOP
The negative consequences of psychologists’
participation in AOP activities highlights the
need for greater clarity in distinguishing be-
tween AOP and COP. With this goal in mind,
we have developed a three-factor framework for
judging whether a particular activity should be
categorized as AOP or COP, recognizing that
we have oversimplified matters by imposing
dichotomous distinctions onto factors that are
sometimes more nuanced than this representa-
tion allows. Nevetheless, we believe our frame-
work establishes grounds for constructive dis-
cussion and debate. The three key questions are
as follows:
1. Is there a sufficient measure of voluntary
informed consent from the target of inter-
vention, including specific contracts or
broader agreements in regard to potential
harms (i.e., stipulated harms)?
2. Does the action plan of the operation in-
volve either the intent to cause nonstipu-
lated harm, or the expectation of nonstipu-
lated harm greater than any benefit to the
target of intervention?
3. Is the action plan of the operation reason-
ably accessible to the participating psy-
chologist(s) and to ethical oversight and
accountability by institutions, boards, or
groups beyond the purview of the national
security establishment?
394 ARRIGO, EIDELSON, AND BENNETT
In our view a psychological operation is col-
laborative (COP) only if there is voluntary in-
formed consent by the targets of intervention
(Question 1), there is not intended or foresee-
able nonstipulated harm (Question 2), and there
is effective outside ethical oversight and ac-
countability (Question 3). If any of these three
conditions is not met, we categorize the psycho-
logical operation as adversarial (AOP).
Question 1: Is there a sufficient measure of
voluntary informed consent from the target
of intervention? If the intervention target has
not freely agreed to participation in the opera-
tion (directly or through an ongoing contractual
arrangement), then the psychological operation
cannot be considered collaborative. In general,
this means that operational psychology activi-
ties that target individuals designated as “ene-
mies” will be categorized as AOP, because con-
sent is highly improbable in these cases. Issues
of consent are therefore most salient when mak-
ing AOP–COP determinations in situations
where the target of intervention is “one of our
own.”
For example, a disguised or remote psycho-
logical evaluation of an unsuspecting individual
to determine whether he might be an attractive
recruit for a national security assignment would
qualify as an AOP activity because of the lack
of consent. If this target instead agreed to the
evaluation, then it would be accurately viewed
as COP, assuming the other necessary condi-
tions were also met. Freely given informed con-
sent is often the basis for distinguishing be-
tween stipulated harm and nonstipulated harm.
The former refers to those risks the target has
knowingly accepted, such as the dangers of
combat duty for an enlisted soldier; the latter
refers to potential harms of which the target was
unaware, such as torture upon capture.
Question 2: Does the operation involve the
intent or expectation of nonstipulated harm
greater than any benefit to the target of
intervention? The question of whether a psy-
chological operation subjects the target to non-
stipulated harm—intended or merely foresee-
able—is usually a relatively easy determination
to make. If the psychologist is involved in an
activity that runs contrary to the profession’s
guiding ethical principle of “do no harm” to-
ward the target of intervention, then the action
plan is an instance of AOP. One clear example
would be a psychologist’s participation in, or
consultation to, the interrogation of a detainee
that involves exploitation of his psychological
vulnerabilities, intentionally causing him psy-
chological distress and possibly inducing him to
act contrary to his interests. Another would be a
psychologist working to draw a hostage taker to
a window for a kill shot by a sniper. A third
example is a situation where the psychologist
knowingly gives an unwarranted psychiatric di-
agnosis to a whistleblower in order to punish
her and discredit her claims.
In contrast, the psychologist who conducts
personnel evaluations for security clearances at
a nuclear weapons facility is not engaging in an
activity in which his or her intent is to harm the
interviewees, even though some of them may
mistakenly be denied clearance as a result of
these evaluations. It is important to note here
that an action plan designed to subject the in-
tervention target to nonstipulated harm is cate-
gorized as AOP even if the participating psy-
chologist personally has no knowledge of this
intention (e.g., due to lack of requisite clear-
ances or a cover story from superiors). This is
necessary to discourage cover stories in the
tasking of psychologists for adversarial opera-
tions. A psychological operation is AOP if the
participating psychologists are not cleared to
know the full scope of the operation as relates to
nonstipulated harms to the intervention targets.
Consultation to case officers in recruitment of
spies is AOP.
Question 3: Is the action plan of the oper-
ation reasonably accessible to the participat-
ing psychologist(s) and to outside ethical
oversight and accountability? We consider
a psychological operation to be AOP if it does
not readily permit state licensing boards, insti-
tutional review boards, professional association
boards, the U.S. Office of Research Integrity, or
other appropriate professional agencies to over-
see or monitor these activities. The necessary
accountability to a professional code of ethics is
diminished or eliminated when the review of
evidence of possible ethical wrongdoing is
hampered by claims that the work is of a clas-
sified nature or that revelations would pose risks
to national security.
Consider, for example, a psychologist in-
volved in a top-secret military research project
testing an experimental drug judged not to have
adverse effects. Although the “do no harm”
principle is met here, the lack of transparency
395PSYCHOLOGY UNDER FIRE
means that this psychologist could violate other
standards of professional ethics (e.g., acting
outside of areas of competency) without suffi-
cient likelihood of repercussions from civilian
agencies. This case highlights a key point: some
instances of AOP are unethical for psycholo-
gists solely because the actions are taken with
the knowledge that they are beyond ethical
monitoring and scrutiny by the profession. In
short, the presumption that professional over-
sight and accountability are unnecessary is in-
herently objectionable on an ethical basis.
Conclusion: A Proposal for Protecting
Professional Ethics in Operational
Psychology
Our analysis of professional ethics and oper-
ational psychology leads us to a clear conclu-
sion: the ethical practice of psychology requires
institutional separation of COP from AOP in
national security contexts.
Proponents of AOP anticipate that operational
psychology will become an official APA area of
specialization (Estrada, 2012), similar to the status
sought by police and public safety psychology
(Stewart, 2012). If operational psychology attains
this status, then AOP goals, methods, and legiti-
mization would pertain not only to psychologists
employed by the military but equally to clinicians,
applied researchers, and trainers employed by ci-
vilian intelligence agencies and to academic re-
searchers funded under security-sector grants or
contracts. Legitimization of AOP would entitle all
of these full-time, part-time, and occasional oper-
ational psychologists to work in AOP without risk
of stigma and censure—and without oversight by
the profession as a whole. One immediate conse-
quence would be the curtailment of ethics com-
plaints against operational psychologists to state
licensing boards (Eligon, 2011) and the APA Eth-
ics Committee. In addition, some strategic and
financial relationships of the APA with the secu-
rity sector that are now in a gray zone—such as
CIA-funded, invitation-only, APA symposia (e.g.,
Davis, 2008)—would be normalized.
Our study though points to the importance of
excluding AOP from professional psychology.
Acknowledging the subordination of AOP to the
requirements of national security missions and
regulations, we propose that psychologists in-
volved in adversarial operations should serve as
intelligence officers or national security contrac-
tors with special expertise in psychology, not as
professional psychologists. Intelligence officers
regularly specialize in related fields such as cul-
tural anthropology and political science. Although
lesser steps may create fewer immediate chal-
lenges, the third author (Bennett) and military
and intelligence advisors insist that only a firm and
complete institutional divide between COP and
AOP can suffice. If psychologists choose to en-
gage in AOP roles, where professional ethics are
secondary to command orders, they must not hold
state licenses as clinicians committed to a profes-
sional code of ethics. For similar reasons, AOP
psychologists must not work in academic or re-
search settings undercover and must not hold po-
sitions of influence in professional associations
undercover.
We recognize that these proposed changes
carry with them significant unsettling ramifica-
tions. Professional psychology and the security
sector now have a century of institutional and
career entanglements. For the security sector, the
exclusion of AOP from professional psychology
could hinder ease of recruitment of psychologists
and the efficiency of deployment in dual roles. For
individual psychologists, exclusion could limit
funding, research, and career opportunities. For
American psychology in general, and the APA in
particular, exclusion could impede expansion into
the security sector and diminish government fund-
ing. Historians of psychology attribute the rise of
American psychology to World War II and post-
war militarism (e.g., Herman, 1995). The 9/11
attacks created another stimulus for national ser-
vice and entrepreneurial expansion into AOP for
psychologists and others.
The benefits of our proposal should carry
much greater weight when considering the in-
evitable and irreversible trade-offs. Exclusion
of AOP from professional psychology can pre-
vent the disastrous unintended consequences we
have described, including militarization of psy-
chology internationally, degradation of scien-
tific method in psychology, loss of public trust
in psychology, and damage to COP. At the same
time, institutional separation of AOP and COP
can protect psychologists who work in COP
from AOP pressures and preserve their valuable
national security roles as evaluators, trainers,
therapists, and researchers.
A key purpose of this article is to initiate a
fruitful and multidimensional discussion be-
tween advocates and critics of AOP, including
396 ARRIGO, EIDELSON, AND BENNETT
those in the national security system whose
work is affected by the unsubstantiated claim
that AOP is a military necessity. Toward this
end, and prior to this much needed discussion,
we recommend that the APA Commission for
Recognition of Specialties and Proficiencies in
Psychology deny efforts to promote operational
psychology, including AOP, as a recognized
specialty area in psychology (e.g., Kennedy,
2010). We also recommend that practitioners
not be eligible for certification through the
American Board of Professional Psychology
(ABPP) as operational psychologists.
The issues we have explored in this essay are
matters of great consequence, not only for op-
erational psychologists, the APA, the behav-
ioral sciences, and the health professions. They
are also of great consequence for all national
security personnel whose work is directly or
indirectly affected by AOP. Representatives
from the fields of military ethics, civil–military
relations, international law, and international
psychology are crucial voices in this much
needed dialogue about psychological ethics.
References
Advisory Committee on Human Radiation Experi-
ments. (1995, October). Final report. Washington,
DC: U.S. Government Printing Office.
American Anthropological Association Commission
on the Engagement of Anthropology with the U.S.
Security and Intelligence Communities. (2009, Oc-
tober 14). Final report on the Army’s Human Ter-
rain System Proof of Concept Program. Retrieved
from http://www.aaanet.org/cmtes/commissions/
CEAUSSIC/upload/CEAUSSIC_HTS_Final_
Report.pdf
American Psychiatric Association. (2006). Psychiat-
ric Participation in Interrogation of Detainees.
Retrieved from http://www.psychiatry.org/advocacy–
newsroom/position-statements
American Psychological Association. (2005). Report
of the American Psychological Association Presi-
dential Task Force on Psychological Ethics and
National Security. Retrieved from http://www.apa
.org/pubs/info/reports/pens.pdf
American Psychological Association. (2010). Ethical
Principles of Psychologists and Code of Conduct.
Retrieved from http://www.apa.org/ethics/code/
index.aspx
Arrigo, J. M., & Bennett, R. (2007). Organizational
supports for abusive interrogations in “The War on
Terror” [Special issue]. In J. M. Arrigo & R.
Wagner (Eds.), Torture is for amateurs. Peace and
Conflict, 13, 411–421.
Banks, L. M. (1995). The office of strategic services
psychological selection program (Unpublished
masters thesis). U.S. Army Command and General
Staff College, Fort Leavenworth, Kansas. Re-
trieved from http://www.ossreborn.com/files/
OSSPsychologicalSelectionProgram.pdf
Benjamin, M. (2010, October 14). “War on Terror”
psychologist gets Giant No-Bid Contract. Re-
trieved from http://www.salon.com/2010/10/14/
army_contract_seligman/
Berkun, M. M., Bialek, H. M., Kern, R. P., & Yagi,
K. (1962). Experimental studies of psychological
stress in man [Special issue]. Psychological Mono-
graphs: General and Applied, 76, 1–39.
Berkun, M. M., Timiras, P. S., & Pace, N. (1958).
Psychological and physiological responses in ob-
servers of an atomic test shot. Psychological Re-
ports, 4, 679682.
Bloche, M. G., & Marks, J. H. (2005). When doctors
go to war. New England Journal of Medicine, 352,
3–6. doi:10.1056/NEJMp048346
Brewer, S. E., & Arrigo, J. M. (2008). Places that
medical ethics can’t find: Preliminary data on why
health professionals fail to stop torture in overseas
counterterrorism operations. In M. Roseman & R.
Goodman (Eds.), Interrogations, forced feedings,
and the role of health professionals: New perspec-
tives on international human rights, humanitarian
law and ethics (pp. 1–20). Cambridge, MA: Hu-
man Rights Program and Harvard Law School.
California Supreme Court. (2009, April 29). Califor-
nia code of Judicial Ethics. Retrieved from http://
www.courts.ca.gov/supremecourt.htm
Camfield, T. M. (1992). The American Psychological
Association and World War I: 1914 to 1919. In
R. B. Evans, V. S. Sexton, & T. C. Cadwallader
(Eds.), 100 years: The American Psychological
Association, a historical perspective (pp. 91–118).
Washington, DC: American Psychological Associ-
ation.
Case Officer A. (2011, April 19 & July 4). Easy
cases—A critique of Ethical Practice in Opera-
tional Psychology by C. Kennedy and T. Williams
(Eds.) (2011). Interview conducted by J. M. Ar-
rigo. Intelligence Applications. Intelligence Ethics
Collection. Hoover Institution Archives, Stanford
University, Stanford, California. [Restricted until
2020.]
Chaplain A. (2010). Chaplaincy-military relations as
a comparison for psychology-military relations.
Interview conducted by J. M. Arrigo. Intelligence
Ethics Collection. Hoover Institution Archives,
Stanford University, Stanford, California. [Re-
stricted until 2020.]
397PSYCHOLOGY UNDER FIRE
Commander A. (2008, June 29). Prisoner handling
and interrogation in the first Gulf War, Psychology
and military intelligence casebook on ethics of
interrogation meeting. Herndon, Virginia. Intelli-
gence Ethics Collection, Hoover Institution Ar-
chives, Stanford University, Stanford, California.
Retrieved from http://www.pmicasebook.com/
PMI_Casebook/Origins.html. [Name restricted un-
til 2030.]
Cooke, B. (2007). The Kurt Lewin–Goodwin Watson
FBI/CIA files: A sixtieth anniversary of there-and-
then of the here-and-now. Human Relations, 60,
435–462. doi:10.1177/0018726707076686
Davis, M. (2008, October 10). Recruiting research
psychologists for national security applications.
Retrieved from http://www.pmicasebook.com/
PMI_Casebook/Cases.html
Debatto, D. (2011, April 6). Differences between
operational psychology for law enforcement and
for national security. Interview conducted by J. M.
Arrigo. Intelligence Ethics Collection. Hoover In-
stitution Archives, Stanford University, Stanford,
California.
Department of Defense, JTF GTMO-BSCT. (2002,
November 11). Memorandum for Record: BSCT
Standard Operating Procedures. Retrieved from
http://www.americantorture.com/documents/
gitmo/05.pdf
Department of the Army. (2006, October 20). Mem-
orandum for commanders, MEDCOM Major Sub-
ordinate Commands: Behavioral science consulta-
tion policy. Fort Sam Houston, TX: Department of
the Army.
Department of the Army. (2010, January 7). Memo-
randum for commanders, MEDCOM Major Sub-
ordinate Commands: Behavioral science consulta-
tion policy. Fort Sam Houston, TX: Department of
the Army.
Dunivin, D., Banks, L. M., Staal, M. A., & Stephen-
son, J. A. (2011). Behavioral science consultation
to interrogation and debriefing operations: Ethical
considerations. In C. H. Kennedy & T. J. Williams
(Eds.), Ethical practice in operational psychology:
Military and national intelligence applications
(pp. 85–106). Washington, DC: American Psycho-
logical Association. doi:10.1037/12342-005
Eligon, J. (2011, April 27). Advisors on interrogation
face legal action by critics. New York Times. Re-
trieved from http://www.nytimes.com/2011/04/28/
nyregion/psychologist-advisers-on-questioning-
terror-suspects-face-ire.html
Estrada, A. (2012, April 25). Update on ABPP dis-
cussion. APA Division 19 Society of Military Psy-
chology listserv.
Ewing, C. P., & Gelles, M. G. (2003). Ethical con-
cern in forensic consultation regarding national
safety and security. Journal of Threat Assessment,
2, 95–107. doi:10.1300/J177v02n03_05
Flanagan, O. (1991). Varieties of moral personality:
Ethics and psychological realism. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Fluehr-Lobban, C. (2009, July 10). Censure of an-
thropologists by the American Anthropology As-
sociation. Intelligence Ethics Collection, Stanford
University, Stanford, California. Retrieved from
http://www.pmicasebook.com/PMI_Casebook/
Consults.html
Forrest, C. J. S. (2007). The doctrine of military
necessity and the protection of cultural property
during armed conflicts. California Western Inter-
national Law Journal, 37, 177–219.
Frakt, D. J. R. (2009). Closing argument at Guan-
tanamo: The torture of Mohammed Jawad. Har-
vard Human Rights Journal, 22, 1–21.
Gelles, M. G., & Palarea, R. (2011). Ethics in crisis
negotiation: A law enforcement and public safety
perspective. In C. H. Kennedy & T. J. Williams
(Eds.), Ethical practice in operational psychology:
Military and national intelligence applications
(pp. 107–123). Washington, DC: American Psy-
chological Association. doi:10.1037/12342-006
Gusterson, H. (2008, June 20). The U.S. military’s
quest to weaponize culture. Bulletin of the Atomic
Scientists. Retrieved from http://www.thebulletin.
org/web-edition/columnists/hugh-gusterson/the-
us-militarys-quest-to-weaponize-culture
Herman, E. (1995). The romance of American psy-
chology: Political culture in the age of experts.
Berkeley, California: University of California
Press.
Horowitz, I. L. (Ed.). (1974/1967). The rise and fall
of Project Camelot—Revised Edition: Studies in
the relationship between social science and prac-
tical politics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Johnson, W. B. (2008). Top ethical challenges for
military clinical psychologists. In C. H. Kennedy
& B. A. Moore (Eds.), Clinical military psychol-
ogy ethics [Special issue]. Military Psychology,
20, 4662.
Kennedy, C. H., & Williams, T. J. (2011a). Opera-
tional psychology ethics: Addressing evolving di-
lemmas. In C. H. Kennedy & T. J. Williams (Eds.),
Ethical practice in operational psychology: Mili-
tary and national intelligence applications (pp.
3–27). Washington, DC: American Psychological
Association. doi:10.1037/12342-001
Kennedy, C. H., & Williams, T. J. (Eds.). (2011b).
Ethical practice in operational psychology: Mili-
tary and national intelligence applications. Wash-
ington, DC: American Psychological Association.
doi:10.1037/12342-000
Kennedy, K. A. (2010). Transitioning from the clinic
to the field of operations and investigations. The
Forensic Examiner, 19, 52–57.
Kennedy, K., Borum, R., & Fein, R. (2011). Ethical
dilemmas in psychological consultation to coun-
398 ARRIGO, EIDELSON, AND BENNETT
terintelligence and counterterrorism. In C. H. Ken-
nedy & T. J. Williams (Eds.), Ethical practice in
operational psychology: Military and national in-
telligence applications (pp. 6983). Washington,
DC: American Psychological Association. doi:
10.1037/12342-004
Lauretano, D. A. (1998, October). The Military
Whistleblower Protection Act and The Military
Mental Health Evaluation Protection Act. The
Army Lawyer. Retrieved from http://www.loc.gov/
rr/frd/Military_Law/pdf/10–1998.pdf
Lewis, N. A. (2004, November 30). Red Cross finds
detainee abuse at Guantanamo. New York Times.
Retrieved from http://www.nytimes.com/2004/11/
30/politics/30gitmo.html
Lifton, R. J. (1986). The Nazi doctors: Medical kill-
ing and the psychology of genocide. New York,
NY: Basic Books.
Lodge, T. J. (2009, February 17). Letter to Kathy
Cawood, Executive Officer, Alabama Board of
Examiners in Psychology, Re: Complaint vs. Di-
ane Zierhoffer, License No. 934. APA PENS De-
bate Collection, Norlin Library, University of Col-
orado, Boulder, Colorado.
MacMichael, D. (2011, January 14). Letter to Gen.
James F. Amos, Commandant of the Marine
Corps. Retrieved from http://www.bradley
manning.org/activism/former-commander-of-
headquarters-company-at-quantico-objects-to-
treatment-of-bradley-manning
Marks, J. (1979). The search for the “Manchurian
Candidate”—The CIA and mind control. New
York, NY: Times Books.
Marks, J. H., & Bloche, M. G. (2008, September 11).
The ethics of interrogation—The U.S. military’s
ongoing use of psychiatrists. New England Journal
of Medicine, 359, 1090–1092. doi:10.1056/
NEJMp0806689
Marquis, D. G. (1944). Social psychologists in na-
tional war agencies. Psychological Bulletin, 41,
115–126. doi:10.1037/h0056072
McKinney, J. (2011, April 11). “Utter propagan-
da”—A Critique of Ethical Practice in Opera-
tional Psychology by C. Kennedy and T. Williams
(Eds.). (2011). Interview conducted by J. M. Ar-
rigo. Intelligence Ethics Collection. Hoover Insti-
tution Archives, Stanford University, Stanford,
California.
McKinney, J. (2011, July 9). In J. McKinney and J. M.
Arrigo, Selected correspondence concerning opera-
tional psychology, March 26–July 9, 2011. Intelli-
gence Ethics Collection. Hoover Institution Ar-
chives, Stanford University, Stanford, California.
Miles, S. H. (2006). Oath betrayed: Military medi-
cine and the war on terror. New York, NY: Ran-
dom House.
Moghaddam, F. M. (2007). Interrogation policy and
American psychology in global context. In J. M.
Arrigo & R. W. Wagner (Eds.), Torture is for
amateurs: A meeting of psychologists and military
interrogators [Special issue]. Peace and Conflict,
13, 437–444.
Morgan, C. A., Gelles, M. G., Steffian, G., Temporini,
H., Fortunati, F., Southwick, S., Feuerstein, S., &
Coric, V. (2006). Consulting to government agen-
cies: Indirect assessments. Psychiatry, 3, 24–28.
Naval Operational Medicine Institute. (2011). Mis-
sion. Retrieved from http://www.med.navy.mil/
sites/navmedmpte/nomi/Pages/default.aspx
Office of Strategic Services Assessment Staff.
(1948). Assessment of men: Selection of personnel
for the Office of Strategic Services. New York,
NY: Rinehart & Company.
Olson, B., & Davis, M. (2008). APA and the myths
and costs of endorsing psychologist involvement
in detainee interrogations. The National Psycholo-
gist, 17(January-February), 18.
Pechura, C. M., & Rall, D. P. (Eds.). (1993). Veter-
ans at risk: The health effects of mustard gas and
lewisite. Washington, DC: National Academy.
Physicians for Human Rights. (2010, June). Experi-
ments in torture: Evidence of human subject re-
search and experimentation in the “enhanced”
interrogation program. Cambridge, MA: Physi-
cians for Human Rights.
Picano, J., Williams, T. J., Roland, R., & Long, C.
(2011). Operational psychologists in support of as-
sessment and selection: Ethical considerations. In
C. H. Kennedy & T. J. Williams (Eds.), Ethical
practice in operational psychology (pp. 2949).
Washington, DC: American Psychological Associ-
ation.
Pilkington, E. (2011, March 15). Bradley Manning’s
military doctors accused over treatment. Retrieved
from http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2011/mar/
15/bradley-manning-military-doctors-treatment
Rivera-Santana, C. (2010, December 2). Puerto Ri-
can psychologists reject psychologist-assisted in-
terrogations. Interviewed by J. M. Arrigo. APA
PENS Debate Collection, Norlin Library, Univer-
sity of Colorado, Boulder, Colorado.
Rockwood, L. P. (2011, April 11). Operational psy-
chology and command responsibility. Intelligence
Ethics Collection. Hoover Institution Archives,
Stanford University, Stanford, California.
Rood, H. W. (2008, October 1). Military and intel-
ligence consultation on “Psychological Stress Ex-
periments on Soldiers.” Psychology and military/
intelligence casebook on ethics of interrogation,
training, treatment, and research. Psychologists for
Social Responsibility. Intelligence Ethics Collec-
tion. Hoover Institution Archives, Stanford Uni-
versity, Stanford, California. Retrieved from
http://www.pmicasebook.com/PMI_Casebook/
Consult_-_Rood.html
399PSYCHOLOGY UNDER FIRE
Sandia National Laboratories (U.S. Department of
Energy). (2005). Sandia Lab News, June 24, 4.
Secord, P., Backman, C., & Arrigo, J. M. (1997–
1998). Correspondence concerning Mitchell
Berkun’s psychological stress experiments. Intel-
ligence Ethics Collection, Hoover Institution Ar-
chives, Stanford University, Stanford, California.
Summarized at http://www.pmicasebook.com/
PMI_Casebook/Cases.html
Seligman, M. E. P. (2003). On “What are the pressing
scientific issues for the nation and the world. . .?”
Edge: The world question center. Retrieved from
http://www.edge.org/q2003/q03_seligman.html
Shane, S. (2009, August 11). 2 U.S. architects of
harsh tactics in 9/11’s wake. New York Times.
Retrieved from http://www.nytimes.com/2009/08/
12/us/12psychs.html
Shumate, S., & Borum, R. (2006). Psychological
support to defense counterintelligence operations.
Military Psychology, 18, 283–296. doi:10.1207/
s15327876mp1804_3
Soldz, S. (2008, August 15). Military Psychologist
Refuses To Testify about Abusive Treatment of
Detainee at Guantánamo. Retrieved from http://
psychoanalystsopposewar.org/blog/2008/08/15/
press-release-military-psychologist-refuses-to-
testify-about-abusive-treatment-of-detainee-at-
guantanamo
Special Investigator A. (2010, November 7). Oppor-
tunistic use of clinical psychologists in the U.S.
Air Force Office of Special Investigations. Intelli-
gence Ethics Collection. Hoover Institution Ar-
chives, Stanford University, Stanford, California.
[Name restricted until 2013.]
Starn, O. (1986). Engineering internment: Anthropol-
ogists and the War Relocation Authority. Ameri-
can Ethnologist, 13, 700–720. Retrieved from
http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1525/ae
.1986.13.4.02a00070/abstract(abstract only). doi:
10.1525/ae.1986.13.4.02a00070
Stewart, C. O. (2012). Police & Public Safety Sec-
tion. Public Service Psychology Newsletter, 37, 10.
Retrieved from http://www.apadivisions
.org/division-18/publications/newsletters/public-
service/2012/04/issue.pdf
Suleman, A. M. (2006). Detainee Treatment Act of
2005: Recent developments. Harvard Human
Rights Journal, 19, 257–265.
Union of Concerned Scientists (2009, November 9).
Pressure not to diagnose PTSD at the U.S. Army
and Department of Veterans Affairs. Retrieved
from http://www.ucsusa.org/scientific_integrity/
abuses_of_science/pressure-not-to-diagnose-ptsd
.html
U.S. Army Headquarters. (2006, September). Human
Intelligence Collector Operations, Field Manual
2–22.3. Washington, D.C.: Author.
U.S. Army Medical Department. (2010). Womack
Army Medical Center: Clinical and Operational
Psychology Residency Program. Retrieved from
http://www.wamc.amedd.army.mil/res/dbh/coprp/
Pages/default.aspx
U.S. Senate, Select Committee on Intelligence and
Subcommittee on Health and Scientific Research
of the Committee on Human Resources. (1977).
Project MKULTRA: The CIA’s program of re-
search in behavioral modification. Washington,
DC: U.S. Government Printing Office.
Vesti, P., & Somnier, F. E. (1994). Doctor involve-
ment in torture: A historical perspective. Torture,
4, 82–89.
Walsh, D. (2012, May 2). Fallout of Bin Laden raid:
Aid groups in Pakistan are suspect. New York
Times. Retrieved from http://www.nytimes.com/
2012/05/03/world/asia/bin-laden-raid-fallout-aid-
groups-in-pakistan-are-suspect.html
Warren, T. (1975, December 1). Soviet Union: The
prisoners of conscience. Time Magazine. Retrieved
from http://www.time.com/time/magazine/article/
0,9171,913780,00.html
Williams, T. J., & Kennedy, C. H. (2011). Opera-
tional psychology: Proactive ethics in a challeng-
ing world. In C. H. Kennedy & T. J. Williams
(Eds.), Ethical practice in operational psychology:
Military and national intelligence applications
(pp. 125–140). Washington, DC: American Psy-
chological Association. doi:10.1037/12342-007
Williams, T. J., Picano, J. J., Roland, R. R., & Banks,
L. M. (2006). Introduction to operational psychol-
ogy. In C. H. Kennedy & E. A. Zillmer (Eds.),
Military psychology: Clinical and operational ap-
plications (pp. 193–214). New York, NY: Guilford
Press.
Winkenwerder, W. (2006, June 7). Media roundtable
with Assistant Secretary Winkenwerder. U.S. De-
partment of Defense. Retrieved from http://www
.globalsecurity.org/military/library/news/2006/06/
mil-060607-dod03.htm
Zonana, H. (2009, July 22). The development of the
American Psychiatric Association Position State-
ment on Psychiatric Participation in Interrogation
of Detainees. Intelligence Ethics Collection, Hoo-
ver Institution Archives, Stanford University,
Stanford, California. Retrieved from http://www
.pmicasebook.com/PMI_Casebook/Consults.html
400 ARRIGO, EIDELSON, AND BENNETT
... . The American Psychological Association (APA) Ethics Code essentially requires the psychologist's accountability to the individual patient-client and that psychologists should not harm those being questioned (APA 2010). It clearly states that "[p]sychologists do not exploit persons over whom they have supervisory, evaluative, or other authority such as clients/patients, students, supervisees, research participants, and employees" (APA 2010).After the 9/11 attacks,Arrigo et al. (2012) argue that the U.S. psychological operations gained new prominence because of the distinct nature of the terrorist threat. These operations also became the source of intense controversy following media reports that psychologists were actively involved in the military's abusive interrogations of the detainees in Guantanamo Bay and Afghanistan. ...
... These operations also became the source of intense controversy following media reports that psychologists were actively involved in the military's abusive interrogations of the detainees in Guantanamo Bay and Afghanistan. American operational physicians were also engaged in torture interrogations in the Iraq War(Arrigo et al. 2012). Psychologists directly backed deception, coercion, assault in military and intelligence operations and covert operations research. ...
... Psychologists directly backed deception, coercion, assault in military and intelligence operations and covert operations research. They identified and manipulated adversaries in counterterrorism operations, and the targets of their intervention opposed the psychologist's mission and/or were subject to no-stipulated harms(Arrigo et al. 2012). They clinically evaluated convicts to expose their psychological liabilities that will consequently be misused in interrogating the prisoner for intelligence gathering purposes(Frakt 2009).The vulnerabilities of psychology patients were exploited to achieve military goals.Arrigo et al (2012) argue that psychological operations conducted by the U.S. army posed irresolvable ethical conflicts for the psychologists involved. ...
Article
Full-text available
The aim of this article is twofold: to examine how psychological operations function in Phil Klay's Redeployment (2015), namely, the ninth story, "Psychological Operations", and to uncover the moral dimension of these practices in the context of the 2003 Iraq War. Psychological Operations are primarily concerned with influencing target audiences' emotions, motives, objective reasoning, and ultimately the behaviour of adversaries to achieve military goals. Nevertheless, these psychological practices may violate some ethical and moral codes and endanger the well-being of their assumed patients, their enemies. The study makes the argument in two constructs, namely, 'Ethical Implications in "Psychological Operations"', which addresses the ethical dimensions of the psychological operations, and 'Accountability in "Psychological Operations"', which investigates culpability for these unethical practices. It contends that the immoral practices committed by American soldiers are presented as a reaction to the cruelty of the enemy rather than unscrupulous procedures per se.
... It is not an application of health care service provision, rather, it focuses on organizational effectiveness and individual performance. The history of operational psychology has not been without controversy (American Psychological Association [APA], 2015; Arrigo et al., 2012;Staal, 2018;Staal & Harvey, 2019). Emerging from this debate was recognition of the need for an ethical framework to inform the field of operational practitioners. ...
... While supporting organizational clients, operational psychologists may contribute to adverse outcomes for individuals, who may or may not be aware of the operational psychologists' involvement. These situations raise concerns about informed consent and potential harm (Arrigo et al., 2012;Soldz et al., 2016). Usually without the benefit of an interview, operational psychologists review case files and evidence of possible criminal activity, indirectly assess possible suspects, and help investigators plan operations to identify individuals who may pose a grave threat to national security, national defense, or public safety (C. ...
Article
Full-text available
Operational psychologists provide a variety of psychological services in support of national security, national defense, and public safety. Their work may include the assessment of personnel for high-risk positions, consultation to investigations and crisis negotiations, support to military or intelligence training and operations, or other types of psychological and behavioral assessments. The practice of operational psychology differs in important ways from other practice areas and has developed significantly over the past 20 years. Given developments in the field, debate about the proper roles of psychologists in national security settings, and psychologists’ ongoing need for guidance, these Professional Practice Guidelines for Operational Psychology are provided to benefit operational psychologists, the recipients of their services, and other affected parties.
... One of the most common issues raised in opposition to psychologists serving in the military concerns the duty to do no harm (APA, 2017b; Arrigo et al., 2012). The assumption that psychologists "do no harm" is somewhat predicated on the notion that the telos or purpose of psychology is to promote individual health and well-being. ...
... On the one hand, uniformed psychologists supporting high-risk training may determine that their involvement is likely to improve the training environment (e.g., assisting in the employment of sound training methodologies and robust safety protocols) reducing risk and increasingly the likelihood of trainee completion (Staal et al., 2008). On the other hand, critics of such involvement have argued that the mere presence of psychologists during risky training is problematic as it condones a coercive activity that may do psychological harm (Arrigo et al., 2012). If training methods lack empirical support (e.g., water confidence training does not lead to greater mastery or stress inoculation), uniformed psychologists have an ethical obligation to either abstain from their involvement or communicate this limitation and advise their leadership accordingly. ...
Article
Full-text available
Uniformed military psychologists are challenged by the multiple roles they serve simultaneously, as health care professionals, organizational consultants, and commissioned military officers. As such, their leadership approach must accommodate a style consistent with their civilian counterparts as well as other military officers. This additional complexity offers highly specialized leadership opportunities and requires an expanded set of leadership tools. Serving in multiple roles also adds complexity to their ethical challenges. A brief overview of military psychology, common leadership challenges facing uniformed military psychologists, and relevant ethical considerations is provided while the specific leadership experiences and challenges of uniformed military psychologists are also discussed.
... Such activities include personnel suitability assessments for incoming employees, talent management evaluations for personnel advancement and placement (Civiello, 2009;Freedman, 2009), indirect or remote assessments (Neller, 2019), support to counterintelligence operations (Borum, Fein, Vossekuil, Gelles & Shumate, 2004;Kennedy, Borum & Fein, 2011;Shumate & Borum, 2006), and consultation to interrogation and detention operations (Dunivin, Banks, Staal & Stephenson, 2011;Greene III & Banks, 2009) as well as other types of investigations. Psychologists' support to intelligence operations has been the most contentious of operational psychology practices (APA, 2015; Arrigo, Eidelson & Bennett, 2012). This contention reached its zenith following the release of the APA's independent review (the Hoffman report) in 2015. ...
Article
Introduction Establishing competency in new or emerging areas of psychological practice is always difficult. For practitioners of operational psychology, it is even more challenging due to the requirement for highly specialized skills, novel applications, and the fact that many organizations employing operational psychologists operate in classified or sensitive settings. Despite the ethical obligation to do so, operational psychologists may face challenges in establishing and maintaining their credentials and competency. Methods This article outlines the core competencies of operational psychology based on the extant literature, provides case examples illustrating their application, and identifies recommendations for training and consultation necessary for establishing and maintaining competence. Discussion Given the scarcity of current training opportunities, limited mentorship, and the lack of training standards, many operational psychologists may develop only some, but not all, of their specialty's core competencies. Furthermore, establishing and maintaining competency may take years of post‐graduate study and experience for most practitioners. Results To accelerate this process and codify core competencies and training standards, the formation of an operational psychology society or association may be necessary. Such actions could create a collective agency among practitioners, securing advocacy for the needs and equities of this practice community, and advancing its policies, practices, and scholarship.
... The workshop refined a model of ethical and unethical behaviour in Operational Psychology developed by psychologists Jean Maria Arrigo and Roy Eidelson together with retired Army interrogator Ray Bennett (Arrigo et al., 2012). With significant input from the participating military and intelligence professionals, the workshop produced the Brookline Principles on the Ethical Practice of Operational Psychology . ...
Article
Full-text available
The post-9/11 US torture program brought attention to the critical roles of health professionals generally and of psychologists more particularly in the modern administration of torture. Over a decade of controversy in the American Psychological Association (APA) and an independent investigation finding APA collusion with the Bush administration’s torture and coercive interrogation programs led to 2015 policies restricting the activities of psychologists in national security interrogations and illegal detention sites like Guantanamo. This controversy expanded to evaluation of a broader set of issues regarding the ethical roles of psychologists in furthering military and intelligence operations, or what has become known as operational psychology. Controversy over the extent to which operational psychology activities are consistent with psychological ethics has expanded since 2015 with critics calling for policies restraining operational psychologists from involvement in activities that cause greater than trivial unstipulated harm, lack informed consent, or are absent plausible independent ethical monitoring (due, for instance to information classification). Operational psychologists have pushed back against any constraints on their actions other than US law and government regulations. This debate also raises a broader issue, are there limitations on the extent to which we as members of democratic societies can tolerate the use of psychological science and expertise to manipulate unwitting people?
... We think that the hotly-debated issue of psychologists' role in unethical and inhumane interrogations (cf. Arrigo, 2004;Arrigo and Bennett, 2007;Arrigo et al., 2012;Burton and Kagan, 2007) 9 made the distinction even bolder: One can't be both pro-peace and pro-torture. Likewise one can't believe that peace will come by change in cognitions and emotions, and that it will come by change in social and material conditions. ...
Article
Full-text available
Peace psychology, critical peace psychology, critical psychology, organic peace psychologist, medical model of peace, and analogical inference error For correspondence Abstract There may be at least three ways through which psychology and psychologists can contribute to peace processes: 1. Psychological research findings can be usual for peace processes. 2. Psychologists as a professional group can involve in negotiations or other peace-related processes. 3. Applied psychological counseling skills such as active listening, basic empathy, multicultural competency, acceptance, rapport-building etc. can be utilized to train both sides of the conflict for a smooth transition to peace processes. Unfortunately, these three options are rarely taken into consideration. The article discusses various ways through which psychology and psychologists can and can't contribute to peaceprocesses, errors, biases and fallacies typically observed in the relevant research and the applied fields, and the distinction between medical and social models of peace.
... But we feel obligated to respond to Staal's repeated unwarranted ad hominem attacks as well as his failure to acknowledge our direct responses to previous points he has raised. Indeed, Arrigo and colleagues also responded to most of these claims in a previous dialog with Staal and Greene in this same journal (Arrigo, Eidelson, & Bennett, 2012;Arrigo, Eidelson, & Rockwood, 2015). ...
Article
Full-text available
The 2015 Brookline Ethics of Operational Psychology Workshop aimed to advance public and professional deliberation regarding challenges and controversies associated with the ethical practice of operational psychology. In his initial critique, Staal (2018a) criticized our meeting on methodological and ideological grounds and condemned the resulting Brookline Principles (Soldz, Arrigo, & Olson, 2016; Soldz, Olson, & Arrigo, 2017). In an earlier response (Soldz, Arrigo, Frakt, & Olson, 2018), we argued that Staal and his colleagues have failed to adequately address legitimate concerns related to traditional civil-military relations and the social contract of the professions—both essential to broader issues of democratic process. Staal responded by largely ignoring the issues we raised. In this second response, we rebut Staal’s critiques and again call on him and operational psychology colleagues to address central issues regarding the ethics of operational psychology practice.
Preprint
Full-text available
This report presents a methodology for the prognosis of trauma victims' mental health using stress modeling. This is applied to a fictional narrative of an environmental activist, John, who undergoes a series of events impacting his mental well-being over 12 months. In this report we demonstrate the potential for stressful Threat Management Assessments to precipitate the mental breakdown of the subject, or escalate an incipient conflict.
Preprint
Full-text available
Reports are provided with a version number so updates can be tracked. CIA torture program methodology. This work is provided for law enforcement, and medical professionals so they can enhance their understanding of, and improve treatment plans for torture surivors. Current American Medical Guidelines are not effective in diagnosing or treating victims of torture; especially problematic given global refugee crisis.
Chapter
Conflict has been an integral part of collaborative ventures. Educational institutes comprise multiple integrated key activities such as teaching, learning, student management, examination, result declaration along with several administrative tasks. It has also been observed that generally stakeholders do not have formal training to deal with such issues and sometimes lack of knowledge and skills to address the disagreements efficiently adversely affects the overall productivity. Conflicts can occur in various forms starting from verbal dialogue and escalated up to physical confrontations resulting in spoiled relationships. An institutional framework should be designed and must be made transparent, so that all stakeholders understand their roles and responsibilities at the institutions. The obligation and constraint defined clearly can act as an essential tool in de-escalation of conflict. This chapter aims at understanding the modes of conflict, reasons behind conflict, and then designing a framework for conflict management in educational institutes.
Article
WASHINGTON -The International Committee of the Red Cross has charged in confidential reports to the United States government that the American military has intentionally used psychological and sometimes physical coercion "tantamount to torture" on prisoners at Guantánamo Bay, Cuba. The finding that the handling of prisoners detained and interrogated at Guantánamo amounted to torture came after a visit by a Red Cross inspection team that spent most of last June in Guantánamo. The team of humanitarian workers, which included experienced medical personnel, also asserted that some doctors and other medical workers at Guantánamo were participating in planning for interrogations, in what the report called "a flagrant violation of medical ethics." Doctors and medical personnel conveyed information about prisoners' mental health and vulnerabilities to interrogators, the report said, sometimes directly, but usually through a group called the Behavioral Science Consultation Team, or B.S.C.T. The team, known informally as Biscuit, is composed of psychologists and psychological workers who advise the interrogators, the report said. The United States government, which received the report in July, sharply rejected its charges, administration and military officials said. The report was distributed to lawyers at the White House, Pentagon and State Department and to the commander of the detention facility at Guantánamo, Gen. Jay W. Hood. The New York Times recently obtained a memorandum, based on the report, that quotes from it in detail and lists its major findings. It was the first time that the Red Cross, which has been conducting visits to Guantánamo since January 2002, asserted in such strong terms that the treatment of detainees, both physical and psychological, amounted to torture. The report said that another confidential report in January 2003, which has never been disclosed, raised questions of whether "psychological torture" was taking place. The Red Cross said publicly 13 months ago that the system of keeping detainees indefinitely without allowing them to know their fates was unacceptable and would lead to mental health problems.
Article
The Army Lawyer is published monthly by The Judge Advocate General's School for the official use of Army lawyers in the performance of their legal responsibilities. The opinions expressed by the authors in the articles, however, do not necessarily reflect the view of The Judge Advocate General or the Department of the Army. Masculine or feminine pronouns appearing in this pamphlet refer to both genders unless the context indicates another use. The Army Lawyer welcomes articles on topics of interest to military lawyers. Articles should be submitted on 3 1/2" diskettes to Editor, The Army Lawyer, The Judge Advocate General's School, U.S. Army, ATTN: JAGS-ADL-P, Charlottesville, Virginia 22903-1781. Article text and footnotes should be double-spaced in Times New Roman, 10 point font, and Microsoft Word format. Articles should follow A Uniform System of Citation (16th ed. 1996) and Military Citation (TJAGSA, July 1997). Manuscripts will be returned upon specific request. No compensation can be paid for articles. The Army Lawyer articles are indexed in the Index to Legal Periodicals, the Current Law Index, the Legal Resources Index, and the Index to U.S. Government Periodicals.