ArticlePDF Available

Religion and Psychiatry: Beyond Boundaries

Authors:

Abstract

IntroductionThe Heresy Trial of J. Ernst DaveyProtestants and Partition Politics in IrelandFundamentalist Certainty and Political UncertaintyPsychoanalysis, Faith and ReligionFundamentalism and Holy ScriptureFundamentalism and Group PsychologyRegression and the Loss of Tempero-Spatial Functions‘Violence and the Sacred’Regression and Reconstruction of Large-Group IdentityFundamentalism, Radicalization and ViolenceReferences
Religion and Psychiatry:
Beyond Boundaries
Editors
Peter J. Verhagen
Meerkanten GGZ, Harderwijk, The Netherlands
Herman M. van Praag
University of Maastricht, Maastricht, The Netherlands
Juan J. Lo
´pez-Ibor Jr.
Complutense University, Madrid, Spain
John L. Cox
University of Gloucestershire, United Kingdom
Driss Moussaoui
Ibn Rushd University, Casablanca, Morocco
Contents
List of Contributors ix
Foreword xiii
Preface xv
General Introduction: Religion and Science 1
Peter J. Verhagen
PART 1 PROLEGOMENA (FIRST ISSUES): HISTORY,
PHILOSOPHY, SCIENCE AND CULTURE 11
Introduction 11
1.1 Evil in Historical Perspective: At the Intersection of Religion
and Psychiatry 13
Michael H. Stone
1.2 Linguistic Analysis and Values-Based Practice: One Way of
Getting Started with Some Kinds of Philosophical Problems
at the Interface Between Psychiatry and Religion 39
Bill (K.W.M.) Fulford
1.3 Science and Transcendence in Psychopathology;
Lessons from Existentialism 63
Juan J. Lo
´pez-Ibor Jr. & Marı
´aIn
es Lo
´pez-Ibor Alcocer
1.4 Psychiatry of the Whole Person – Contribution of Spirituality
in form of Mystic (Sufi) Thinking 73
Ahmad Mohit
PART 2 MAIN ISSUES: THE INTERFACE BETWEEN
PSYCHIATRY, MENTAL HEALTH AND MAJOR
RELIGIOUS TRADITIONS 87
Introduction 87
2.1 Judaism and Psychiatry 89
Ayala Uri, Noa Navot & Alan Apter
2.2 Christianity and Psychiatry 105
John R. Peteet
2.3 Religion and Mental Health in Islam 119
Ahmed Okasha
2.4 Psychiatry and African Religion 143
Frank G. Njenga, Anna Nguithi & Sam G. Gatere
2.5 Hinduism and Mental Health 159
R. Srinivasa Murthy
2.6 Buddhism and Psychotherapy in Japan 181
Naotaka Shinfuku & Kenji Kitanishi
2.7 Psychiatry and Theravada Buddhism 193
Pichet Udomratn
PART 3 CORE ISSUES: RELIGION AND PSYCHOPATHOLOGY 209
Introduction 209
3.1 Religious Experience and Psychopathology 211
Juan J. Lo
´pez-Ibor Jr. & Marı
´a Ine
´sLo
´pez-Ibor Alcocer
3.2 God’s Champions and Adversaries: About the Borders
between Normal and Abnormal Religiosity 235
Herman M. van Praag
3.3 Religion and Psychopathology: Psychosis and Depression 253
Andrew C. P. Sims
3.4 Obsessive Compulsive Disorder and Religion: A Reconnaissance 271
Harold J. G. M. van Megen, Dianne A. den Boer-Wolters
& Peter J. Verhagen
3.5 Religion and Psychoanalysis: Past and Present 283
Allan M. Josephson, Armand Nicholi Jr. & Allan Tasman
3.6 On the Psychology of Religious Fundamentalism 305
John, Lord Alderdice
3.7 Measurement at the Interface of Psychiatry and Religion:
Issues and Existing Measures 319
Peter C. Hill & Carissa Dwiwardani
vi CONTENTS
PART 4 RESEARCH ISSUES 341
Introduction 341
4.1 Religion and Mental Health: What Do You Mean When You Say
‘Religion’? What Do You Mean When You Say ‘Mental Health’? 343
Charles H. Hackney
4.2 A Moment of Anger, a Lifetime of Favor: Image
of God, Personality, and Orthodox Religiosity 361
Elisabeth H.M. Eurelings-Bontekoe & Hanneke Schaap-Jonker
4.3 The Relationship Between an Orthodox Protestant Upbringing
and Current Orthodox Protestant Adherence, DSM-IV
Axis II B Cluster Personality Disorders and Structural
Borderline Personality Organization 373
Elisabeth H.M. Eurelings-Bontekoe & Patrick Luyten
4.4 When Religion Goes Awry: Religious Risk Factors for Poorer
Health and Well-Being 389
Hisham Abu Raiya, Kenneth I. Pargament
& Gina Magyar-Russell
4.5 Religious Practice and Mental Health:
a Moroccan Experience 413
Driss Moussaoui & Nadia Kadri
4.6 Religious and Spiritual Considerations in Psychiatric
Diagnosis: Considerations for the DSM-V 423
David Lukoff, C. Robert Cloninger, Marc Galanter,
David M. Gellerman, Linda Glickman, Harold G. Koenig,
Francis G. Lu, William E. Narrow, John R. Peteet,
Samuel B. Thielman & C. Paul Yang
PART 5 INTERDISCIPLINARY ISSUES: PSYCHOTHERAPY,
PASTORAL CARE AND MEANING GIVING 445
Introduction 445
5.1 Gods of the Horizon: The Therapist’s and the Patient’s
Religious Representations and the Inevitability of
Countertransference 447
Moshe Halevi Spero
5.2 Assumptions About Pastoral Care, Spirituality
and Mental Health 479
Peter J. Verhagen & Adamantios G. Avgoustidis
CONTENTS vii
5.3 Coming to Terms with Loss in Schizophrenia – The Search
for Meaning 497
Hanneke (J.K.) Muthert
PART 6 CONTROVERSIAL ISSUES: RELIGION AND THE BRAIN 513
Introduction 513
6.1 The Limits of Scientific Understanding and their Relevance
for the Role of Religion in Psychiatry 515
Robert H. Belmaker
6.2 Seat of the Divine: A Biological ‘Proof of God’s Existence’? 523
Herman M. van Praag
6.3 Neuro-Theology: Demasqu
e of Religions 541
Dick F. Swaab & Wilma T.P. Verweij
PART 7 TRAINING ISSUES: RESIDENCY TRAINING
AND CONTINUOUS EDUCATION 569
Introduction 569
7.1 Religion and the Training of Psychotherapists 571
Allan M. Josephson, John R. Peteet & Allan Tasman
7.2 Multicultural Education and Training in Religion and Spirituality 587
Peter J. Verhagen & John L. Cox
Epilogue: Proposal for a World Psychiatric Association Consensus
or Position Statement on Spirituality and Religion in
Psychiatry 615
Peter J. Verhagen & Christopher C.H. Cook
Notes on Contributors 633
Index of Names 647
Index of Subjects 651
viii CONTENTS
Foreword
Religion is a major activity of human beings including those suffering from a mental
disorder. Psychiatric patients often raise for themselves the kind of questions that everybody
has considered and which religion tries to answer. Where do we come from? Is there life
after death? What is the origin of the universe? Why are we confronted with evil? Are we
free or ruled by our instincts and brain mechanisms?
Religion is an important component of life. Anthropologists have recognized that the
Neanderthals already had some sense of transcendence and of spirituality, a fact that is more
striking in the remnants of archeological excavations of Homo sapiens sapiens settlements.
The history of religions as we know them today begins in the Near East with the invention
of writing about 3000 BCE, with the written record of human religious experiences and
ideas. The middle of the first millennium BCE has been considered by Karl Jaspers, in his
The Origin and Goal of History, as a key Axial Age of thinkers having had a profound
influence on future philosophy and religion. In this context, Rudolf Otto’s famous book, The
Idea of the Holy (1917), defines the essence of religious awareness as awe, a unique blend of
fear and fascination before the divine.
The Encyclopedia of Religion defines religion as a “push, whether ill-defined or conscious,
toward some sort of ultimacy and transcendence that can provide norms and power for the rest
of life. When more or less distinct patterns of behaviour are built around this depth dimension
in a culture, this structure constitutes religion in its historically recognizable form. Religionis
the organization of life around the depth dimensions of experience, varied in form,
completeness, and clarity in accordance with the environing culture.” A religion is an
organized approach to human spirituality which usually encompasses a set of narratives,
symbols, beliefs and practices, often with a supernatural or transcendent quality, that give
meaning to the practitioner’s experiences of life through reference to a higher power or truth.
Religion includes three components: 1) a notion of the transcendent or numinous, often, but
not always, in the form of theism; 2) a cultural or behavioural aspect of ritual, liturgy and
organized worship, often involving priesthood, and societal norms; and 3) a set of myths
(sacred truths) held in reverence or believed by adherents.
Spirituality shares with religion the personal belief in ideas of religious significance,
such as God, the Soul, or Heaven, but rejects the administrative, often bureaucratic and
hierarchical, structure and creeds of a particular organized religion.
Based on census or public opinion data, a person is considered to be of a particular religion if
they say that they are of that faith. According to David Barrett et al, editors of the World Christian
Encyclopedia: A comparative survey of churches and religions - AD 30 to 2200, there are 19 major
world religions which are subdivided into 270 large religious groups, and many smaller ones.
There are about 2.1 billion Christians (32% of the world population); 1.3 billion Muslims (19%);
0.8 billion Hindus (13%); 0.4 billion practise Chinese folk religion (6%) and 0.36 billion are
Buddhist (6%). The remaining religions are practised by the other 10% of the global population.
Another 775 million people (12%) have no religion (they consider themselves agnostics,
freethinkers, humanists, secularists, etc.) and 150 million (2%) are atheists.
Religion plays an important role in the ceremonies attached to the stages of life, such as
birth, becoming adult, marriage and death. It is also important when confronted with illness
and misfortune. The case of mental disorders is special. Severe depression uncovers what
Kurt Schneider called the primordial fears of human beings: the fear of poverty, the fear of
becoming ill and the fear of damnation, which were respectively at the origin of the delusion
of being ruined, the hypochondriacal and the guilt delusions. Delusional patients are
preoccupied with delusions on the origin of the universe, good and evil and so on and
delusions of religious content have been recognized for centuries. In spite of all of this,
psychiatrists have not paid sufficient attention to the examination of religiosity in their
patients. Even fewer include religiosity and spiritualism in psychotherapy, which is strange
as both religion and psychotherapy try to bring meaning to experience. The separation
of religion and science in general parallels the separation of Church and State and this has
been sometimes taken too far. As an example, an English nurse was reprimanded by The
National Health Service for having asked an elderly lady if she would like the nurse to pray
for her.
In Western civilization, there is a division of the world into two comprehensive domains, one
sacred, the other profane. Religion is often described as a communal system for the coherence of
belief focusing on a system of thought, unseen being, person, or object, that is considered to be
supernatural, sacred, divine, or of the highest truth. Moral codes, practices, values, institutions,
traditions, rituals and scriptures are often traditionally associated with the core belief, and these
may have some overlap with concepts in secular philosophy. Religion is also often described as a
“way of life” or a life stance. The scientific method gains knowledge by testing hypotheses to
develop theories through elucidation of facts or evaluation by experiments and thus only answers
cosmological questions about the physical universe. It develops theories of theworld which best
fit physically observed evidence. All scientific knowledge is subject to later refinement in the
face of additional evidence. Modern science and laicism often go together.
Whether religion has a positive or a negative impact on personal growth and mental health
is a controversial issue. It is easy to quote in this respect Sigmund Freud, who wrote that
religion is a “universal obsessional neurosis of humankind”, representing an infantile stage
of mental development which prevents human beings from facing the reality of their life.
Furthermore, it is easy to argue that religion – or an aberrant way to understand religion – has
been a source of conflicts and mass violence in recent years, which have had an enormous
negative impact on the mental health of thousands of people.
However,there is also abundant research evidence that religion, or spirituality (defined as
the individual religious experience as opposed to ritualistic religious practices), is associ-
ated with higher levels of subjective well-being and lower levels of depression, and may
promote both emotional and cognitive growth.
The issue is complex, is made even more complex by problems with definition and
assessment, but is very topical and attractive. The WPA, therefore, welcomes this comprehen-
sive and multifaceted volume, produced by one of its most active Scientific Sections, hoping that
this effort will contribute to clarify the issue and stimulate further reflection and research.
Mario Maj
President, World Psychiatric Association
xiv FOREWORD
Preface
CROSSING BOUNDARIES
The boundary between religious belief and the practice of psychiatry is becoming
increasingly porous. No longer can psychiatrists in a multi-faith, multi-cultural globalized
world hide behind the dismissal of religious belief as pathological, or behind a biomedical
scientism, as they are more frequently confronted by distressed patients for whom religious
belief may determine their choice of symptoms and their compliance with treatment.
There is inevitably a tension in any such boundary crossing. Religious belief, for example,
can be harmful to mental health and be a trigger for mental illness. Spirituality may not have
the safeguards and structures of established Faith Communities; and the political abuse of
religion has left an indelible scar on the world. The destructive manipulation of behaviour
and belief by cult leaders is also well known to be disastrous.
Crossing the boundary, or breaking the psychiatry and religion taboo, may therefore be
complex for an atheist psychiatrist, challenged by a patient with a religious problem, or
when the values espoused by the patient are at variance with their own values and beliefs.
Boundary violations and unrecognized counter transference when treating religious patients
from a similar faith background to the psychiatrist are other pitfalls for the unwary.
Yet, as the authors of this book illustrate, the evidence is cogent that mainstream
religiosity is an enabler of health and a protection against mental illness – through, for
example, the provision of social support, or by enabling contact with a forgiving creator
God.
The religiosity gap, we would maintain, therefore needs to be reduced; and the religious
source of the values that are instrumental to compassion, and which can unleash altruism,
needs to be more fully recognized and utilized.
The World Health Organization (WHO) has rightly regarded spiritual values as a
component of Quality of Life. After the publication of The World Health Report 2001.
Mental Health: New Understanding, New Hope by WHO, the World Council of Churches
showed its partnership and identified mental health as a key issue for the churches’ role in the
mission of the church in the twenty-first century
1
[1, 2]. The World Psychiatric Association
(WPA) was also correct to establish greater links with user organisations and to explore the
provision of a more person-centred psychiatry.
1
The World Council of Churchesformulated its view on mental health in an ambitious Strategic Plan of the Mental
Health & Faith Communities Initiative: “Mental health is a life-long dynamic process which allows the whole
person to develop psychologically, emotionally, and spiritually within society, whilst integrating personal and
interpersonal joy and distress, leading towards the experience of well-being and harmony with oneself, others, the
environment, and God” [3].
FOUR GREAT STREAMS OF RELIGIONS
This volume is about psychiatry and the interface between psychiatry and religion. In other
words, this is not a book on religion(s). However, it is concerned, especially Part 2, with the
views religions have on psychopathology, disordered behaviour and treatment. We are just
at the beginning of exploring, understanding and comparing these views. Although we were
used to the more or less pronounced influence of Judeo-Christian traditions and doctrines in
the Western world, together with Islam, as the Semite, prophetic or Abrahamic religions, the
monotheistic religions do not have exclusive rights. They share prophetic faith, faith in a
transcendent being, consciousness of time and history, and a community based on justice
[4–6]. What do these characteristics mean for an understanding of psychopathology and
disordered behaviour in comparison with the other two main streams of religions?
The mystic religions that emerged out of India have a completely different view on human
nature and the ultimate reality of the universe [5]. It can be expected that these character-
istics mean an original take on psychiatry. The third stream, the wisdom religions, emerged
out of China. Not the prophet, not the mystic, but the sage, the wise man, is honoured as the
ideal human person in his religious context [5]. There is a fourth stream of religions, often
called tribal or indigenous religions [4]. Australian and African religion is typical of this
fourth stream.
It is inevitable that this world seems confused and confusing. But at the same time, despite
this enormous diversity, great questions are universal, such as how to cope with suffering,
serious illness and death. And despite the differences, religions of all times and places offer a
message and a way of salvation. What did and still does that mean for the understanding of
psychopathology, treatment and human welfare?
A LONG AND TENSE HISTORY
For many centuries religiosity and spirituality played a major role in speculations about the
origin of mental disorders. They were thought to be the works of demons, able to penetrate
body and mind of an individual because he had sinned. Exorcism was the treatment of
choice.
In the nineteenth century, demons lost their dominant position. The pioneers of American
moral treatment started to view mental illness as a physical illness. In many cases “moral
treatment”, a child of humanism [7, 8], seemed to be far more appropriate than the dire
treatments that had preceded it.
In the twentieth century, psychoanalysis became the dominant philosophy of psychiatry.
Though sin in a religious sense faded into the background, it returned in a different shape.
Friction between unacceptable strivings (secular “sins”) versus demands of the super ego
played an important role in psychoanalytical theorising. Religiosity proper, however, was
anathema to psychoanalysis. It was considered to be an anachronism, a remnant from an
infantile past; if anything, to be treated rather than to be cherished. The influence of those
ideas has been tremendous, including beyond the boundaries of psychiatry. They probably
have contributed substantially to secularisation of the Western world. They certainly
buttressed the inclination of many, if not most, psychiatrists of the twentieth century to
exclude religiosity from their purview. For biological and social psychiatry – focusing
xvi PREFACE
predominantly on brain functions and living circumstances – religiosity was not a factor
generally to reckon with. Transcultural psychiatry, with its roots in social anthropology, has
always taken the religious beliefs and practices of individuals and their communities more
seriously as they may relate to the understanding of mental disorder.
That psychiatry in the twentieth century was largely a “Godless” period was not to the
advantage of the psychiatric patient. Religiosity can be considered a normal personality trait
and cannot be disregarded by psychiatrists, whatever their own ideas on religiosity might be.
The entire soul/psyche, after all, belongs to their sphere of work. This point of view is the
raison d’^
etre of the WPA’s section on Religion, Spirituality and Psychiatry, and the main
reason why this book was conceptualised under the section’s auspices. We hope that this
volume will indeed stir up curiosity and interest in the interface between psychiatry and
man’s tendency to provide life with a vertical transcendental dimension.
Peter J. Verhagen
Herman M. van Praag
Juan J. Lo
´pez-Ibor
John L. Cox
Driss Moussaoui
REFERENCES
1. World Health Organization (WHO) (2001) The World Health Report 2001. Mental Health: New
Understanding, New Hope. World Health Organization, Geneva.
2. Tharyan, P, Braganza, D, Jebaraj, P (2006) Mental health as a key issue in the future of global
health developments. International Review of Mission 95, 36–49.
3. World Council of Churches (2008) WCC Strategic Plan Mental Health & Faith Communities
Initiative. Available at: http://www.oikoumene.org/fileadmin/files/wcc-main/documents/p4/
health/WCC_strategic_plan_Mental_health.pdf.
4. K
ung, H (2002) Tracing the Way. Spiritual dimensions of the world religions. Continuum,
London.
5. Kyoung-Jae, K (2007) Christianity and Culture. A hermeneutic of mission theology in an East
Asian context. In: Chung, PS, K
arkk
ainen, VM and Kyoung-Jae, K (eds.) Asian Contextual
Theology for the Third Millennium. Theology of Minjung in fourth-eye formation. Pickwick
Publications, Eugene, OR, pp. 147–163.
6. Pridmore, S, Pasha, MI (2004) Psychiatry and Islam. Australasian Psychiatry 12, 380–385.
7. Taubes, T (1998) “Healthy Avenues of the Mind”: Psychological theory building and the influence
of religion during the ea of moral treatment. American Journal of Psychiatry 155, 1001–1008.
8. Van Praag, HM (2007) Psychiatry and religion: an unconsummated marriage. In: Glas, G, Spero,
MH, Verhagen, PJ and Van Praag, HM (eds.) Hearing Visions and Seeing Voices. Psychological
aspects of biblical concepts and personalities. Springer, Dordrecht, pp. 9–19.
PREFACE xvii
General Introduction: Religion
and Science
Peter J. Verhagen
Psychiatrist and Theologian, The Netherlands
I.1 PSYCHIATRY AND RELIGION
The World Psychiatric Association (WPA) Section on Religion, Spirituality and Psychiatry
(SRSP) took the initiative to start a project that would lead to the publication of a handbook
like volume that would serve several purposes. First of all the editors were convinced, and
still are, (of the fact) that the study of interface between Psychiatry and Religion offers a lot
of helpful and at the same time critical tools for psychiatric thinking and practice. Religion
and spirituality play their role in the lives of many, many people in a personal and/or socially
meaningful, be it salient way. In that sense religiosity and spirituality belong to the domains
of quality of life. In fact it is not imaginable how religion or spirituality could not be of
influence on the way of life, the well being and psychic and social functioning of people in
general, psychiatric patients in particular.
It took psychiatry a lot of time to rediscover this simple and at the same time complicated
fact. For a long time psychiatry had not been aware of the fact that a more or less silent
antipathy against religion influenced her thinking and practice fundamentally, even in her
classificatory systems like the DSM. Although Freud is frequently mentioned as the father of
this anti-religious stance, its roots go further back. Was it not psychiatry, according to the
well-known hagiography, that liberated those poor living creatures who had been captured
for so many years, chained in irons, as a triumph of human care and humanism? The real
story is slightly different. In western society God was replaced by nature and by the end of
the eighteenth century the physician who knew the order of nature, including the structure
of the body, could replace the priest who claimed his authority in the name of God. The start
of psychiatry is an illustration of that development. Religion lost its leading position, and the
physician became the new guide in life with scientific and moral authority. Since then the
relationship between psychiatry and religion has been strained to a greater or lesser extent.
The words ‘mad’ and ‘madness’ are complex terms and, as has been illustrated in several
ways, these and other terms we are used to in (descriptive) psychopathology and the
underlying way of thinking contain these tensions.
Religion and Psychiatry: Beyond Boundaries Edited by Peter J. Verhagen, Herman M. van Praag, Juan J. Lo
´pez-Ibor Jr.,
John L. Cox and Driss Moussaoui
Copyright Ó2010 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd
This book is about the interface between psychiatry and religion and spirituality. It is
a book mainly written by and aimed at psychiatrists all over the world. At the same
time it is a multidisciplinary book and we welcome the contributions of many experts
in the field of inquiry of religion, spirituality, psychiatry and mental health. The
discussion and debates are complex and span a number of disciplines: psychology,
psychology of religion, psychotherapy, psychoanalysis, cognitive sciences, neuros-
ciences, philosophy of mind, of science and of religion, history, and theology. No
single discipline can do full justice to the complexity of the issues at hand. Any
opposed claim would raise troublesome barriers; it is the intention of the editors of this
volume to get beyond such barriers.
I.2 NO APOLOGETICS
In order for progress to occur in this interdisciplinary field of inquiry a minimum
consensus concerning the meaning of core constructs is needed. Now, here the discussion
becomes exciting, because, as one thing is very clear from the perspective of religion and
spirituality, one cannot settle any kind of consensus as intended here on purely objective
grounds. As soon as one starts to discuss such core constructs as disease, mental health,
religiousness and spirituality all kinds of background issues, assumptions and convic-
tions, mindsets come about. One of these assumptions, to name just one, is the rather
typical Western idea that illness is secular [1, p. 271]. Somatic and/or psychic, illnesses
have to do with biomedical, causal-mechanical patterns that are in no way spiritual or
religious. However, Islamic understanding of health and illness cannot be understood
otherwise than in the context of religious conceptualization. Within a totally different
discourse the anti-Semitic image of ‘the dirty Jew’ was repudiated in the nineteenth and
twentieth centuries with the Jewish model of preventive medicine based on the interpre-
tive tradition of Moses and hygiene [2].
Anyhow, it means that from a global perspective it becomes very clear that a discussion
like the one we are thinking of here has much of an interreligious and interspiritual dialogue.
Greater awareness of religious and spiritual plurality has heightened the need for such an
interreligious and interspiritual dialogue, even with regard to psychiatry, or better: from
within the profession itself. In connection with this need, there is overwhelming agreement
that training and permanent education should include instruction and guidance on how to
handle religious and spiritual issues in assessment and therapy. In the meantime such a
dialogue asks for a new kind of spirituality itself in order not to fall back into any form of
outdated exclusivism [3]. Psychiatry is not helped forwards by any form of religious
apologetics or expansionism! That is a very difficult but nevertheless worthwhile task,
beyond usually very tough barriers.
I.3 OVERVIEW
Many colleagues from all around the world, among them many WPA officials, started
working on this project which reflects their commitment to study the interface of
psychiatry and religion. ‘Beyond boundaries’ is felt as a challenging task and formulated
as the general theme.
2 GENERAL INTRODUCTION: RELIGION AND SCIENCE
The central part of the book, Section II, offers a description and analysis of how major
world religions look at psychiatry, its practice and psychiatric disorders. We posed several
questions to the authors. How do the religious and spiritual traditions they represent look at
mental or psychic functioning and how do they evaluate and interpret psychic disorders?
These are rather general formulations and questions. What does it mean in concreto, in daily
practice? Mahayana Buddhism is widely and profoundly immersed in the mental life of East
Asian people. Muslims attribute all events in life to God’s will and thus the concept of
mental illness is influenced by religious aspects. What do these influences mean to
psychiatric thinking and practice and to (the development of) therapy? Table I.1 shows
the top 10 organized world religions.
Necessarily, we had to confine ourselves. The project will cover Christianity, Islam, and
Hinduism, Buddhism in East and South Asia, and Judaism. We are also able to include a
chapter on African Religions. Of course, this is a very ambitious program. The authors have
enough room to elaborate to the best of their knowledge/with their own expertise on
psychiatry and the religious tradition they represent. Statistics of the world’s religions are
only very rough approximations. Aside from Christianity, few religions, if any, attempt to
keep statistical records; and even Protestants and Catholics employ different methods of
counting members.
This central part, including seven chapters, is meant to be the fundamental part of this
book.
It is preceded by what could be called the prolegomena, about issues that have to be
explored first or that cannot be missed without great detriment. When entering an
unfamiliar or unknown field or subject one needs to know (something like) where to
begin. There are so many approaches and confusion is inevitable. Why should we (as
psychiatrists) think and write about religion, spirituality and psychiatry anyway? What
has psychiatry to do with religion or spirituality? Why care? On the one hand, it could be
said that such an idea, prolegomena I mean, is a rather typical Western post-enlightenment
idea. On the other hand, our claim could be that Western psychiatry has omitted an
important realm of human experience [1, p. 182] ‘The constraint of ontological space’). So
in this section it needs to become clear that there are plausible reasons for doing what we
Table I.1 This List Includes Only Organized Religions and Excludes More
Loosely Defined Groups Such as Chinese or African Traditional Religions
Religion Members Percentage
Christianity 2.1 billion 33.0%
Islam 1.3 billion 20.1
Hinduism 851 million 13.3
Buddhism 375 million 5.9
Sikhism 25 million 0.4
Judaism 15 million 0.2%
Baha’ism 7.5 million 0.1
Confucianism 6.4 million 0.1
Jainism 4.5 million 0.1
Shintoism 2.8 million 0.0
Source: Encyclopaedia Britannica [4]
GENERAL INTRODUCTION: RELIGION AND SCIENCE 3
are going to do, and for exploring the hindrances, or for explaining why it should be
evident that we care.
In the twentieth century the encounter and interaction of religion and science took many
forms. New discoveries in science have challenged many classical religious ideas. In
response some people have defended their tradition, others have abandoned their tradition,
and still others have reformulated long-held concepts in the light of science.
This first section contains historical, philosophical, theological and aesthetic viewpoints.
Concepts of evil are dealt with in various religious traditions throughout the ages and also
how these concepts affect(ed) psychiatric thinking from a historical point of view. The
theme will also be approached from a philosophical point of view. This is an important
aspect, because we need a tool to approach the theme. In order to find such a tool,
philosophical fieldwork needs to be done. Chapters are included on science and transcen-
dence, and on religion and spirituality as (not just as) human endeavor, in a very sensitive
and open-minded way. So, this first section is about (world)views, assumptions, concepts
and (ontological) values, and about relevance! Is it still clear that religious believers and
spiritually minded people live by religious and spiritual stories and statements which they
interpret their (even pathological) experiences with accordingly and which enable them to
express meanings of a profound and transcendent kind? Is a human propensity for
transcendence facultative, or is there a fundamental shortfall, and does man need to learn
to cope with emptiness? Do we think exclusively in medical psychiatric categories, hiding or
masking existential layers? After this first part follows the announced central part on
religions and psychiatry; again too ambitious, nevertheless full of starting points for future
discussion and research.
The third section is on religion, spirituality and psychopathology. In this part the core
business of psychiatry, assessment/diagnosis and psychopathology is at stake. Discussions,
explorations, research data and the like will not be restricted wherever possible to Western
thinking or Western populations only, although data from elsewhere might not be available
or insufficient. Since Sigmund Freud published his first article on religion more than a
century ago a number of developments have taken place in psychoanalysis and psychoana-
lytic psychology of religion. A review of these developments is included in this part of the
book. A chapter on the psychology of fundamentalism and religion (‘Violence of the
Sacred’) is necessarily included.
The fourth section is on empirical research, exploring the relation between spirituality/
religion and mental health. These chapters should inform the readers, if possible and
relevant, about phenomenology, epidemiology, research data, explanatory models and
theories, wherever evidence based data are available. It is important to refer to these data
whenever necessary opinion based points of view are presented, explained and discussed,
and that credulity based material should be detected. However, also attention will be paid to
a more conceptual approach. How do these psychopathological phenomena relate to
existential themes? What does that mean? Are we looking at epiphenomena or what else?
In addition, what are the effects of religious practices of fasting and circumcision?
Furthermore it is important to give an account of discussions towards the development
of new classification and diagnostic systems, e.g. DSM-Vand WPA Program on Psychiatry
for the Person [5, 6].
Three other parts are added to the foregoing: one with regard to (psycho) therapy and
pastoral care, one concerning Religion and the Brain and a third one on religion, spirituality,
and training and permanent education.
4 GENERAL INTRODUCTION: RELIGION AND SCIENCE
How to approach the religiously committed patient? This question is thoroughly
discussed and illustrated from both a psychotherapeutic and a spiritual care-giving angle.
A chapter on the relationship between pastoral care an mental health completes the fifth part.
Recent brain research has revealed changes in brain functions concomitant with religious
and spiritual experiences. This is anything but surprising. Experiences of whatever nature
are predicated upon activation of certain brain circuits. Atheists have taken the neuro-
theological data as the ultimate triumph of their viewpoint: religiosity is but a brain state,
nothing more. This is a misconception. Religious needs orginate on a psychological level,
not in the brain. The brain enables one to generate the corresponding religious feelings. As
an analogy: aesthetical feelings are made possible by the brain, they are not caused by the
brain but by external stimuli. Neuro-theological data show that man has the capacity to
conceive of a transcendental realm and communicate with it. These data do not have to mean
the death blow to the deistic idea at all. And although a ‘God spot’, or ‘God gene’ has been
discovered, no conclusions can be drawn whatsoever about the existence of God, or any
supreme being or reality. In the meantime that does not mean, despite the fact that repeated
emperical arguments can not prove the existence or non-existence of God, that the claim that
God exists is meaningless. It just means that we have to argue on anothere level of
knowledge for or against the existence of God. In connection with this type of reasoning
more can be said on brain, soul, self and freedom [7, 8].
With regard to training and education, a curriculum should offer sufficient opportunity for
teaching trainees to address the existential, religious and spiritual needs of our patients, including:
Knowledge: basic knowledge of major belief systems; knowledge about the developmental,
experiential, and mental health; consequences of religious experiences.
Skills: improvement of interviewing skills; improvement of diagnostic skills with respect to
people having all kinds of religious backgrounds; therapeutic skills.
Attitudes: systematic reflection on the professional’s own belief system (atheism included)
and the influence of it on their functioning; analysis of transference and counter-
transference issues; empathy.
All contributors were asked to look at how (if at all) their own faith perspectives influence
the way they think about psychiatry and human nature, about the phenomena they are
writing about and the way they study and write about these phenomena. What are some of
the starting, fundamental premises of their perspective? What are some of their chief
concerns within their religious/cultural perspective that would point the reader to certain
aspects that should have priority? What aspects of religiousness or spirituality are likely to
influence directly the phenomena they are describing for better or for worse?
I.4 RELATION BETWEEN SCIENCE AND RELIGION
Ken Wilber called the relation of science and religion in today’s world ‘a deadly dance’
[9, p. 15]. He warns the reader of several stances toward this relation, that still influence and
even dominate our thinking [9, p. 15–24]:
1. Science denies any validity to religion;
2. Religion denies any validity to science;
GENERAL INTRODUCTION: RELIGION AND SCIENCE 5
3. Science is but one of several valid modes of knowledge, and thus can peacefully coexist
with spiritual modes;
4. Science can offer “plausible arguments” for the existence of Spirit;
5. Science is itself not knowledge of the world but merel y an interpretation of the world, and
therefore it has the same validity – no more, no less – a poetry and the arts.
The author argues that none of these five stances are acceptable. They are not powerful
enough in a way that both parties would find agreeable. I take just one element from his line
of thinking that is worthwhile keeping in mind. The third statement would be properly called
‘epistemological pluralism’. However, what is meant by that? The traditional view on this
pluralism goes back to the Middle Ages: ‘every human being has the eye of flesh, the eye of
mind, and the eye of contemplation’ [9, p. 18]. These three eyes are three eyes of knowledge:
empiricism, rationalism, and mysticism. It would make a great difference with regard to our
view on the relation between science and religion if the existence of this epistemological
pluralism was an accepted fact. However, that is not the case according to modernity.
Science and religion have often been seen as enemies locked in mortal combat. Some
people in both camps are even aggressively continuing the warfare, for instance on the topic of
evolution. But conflict can be avoided if science and religion are seen as strangers, occupying
separate domains at a safe distance from each other. Science and religion, for instance,
represent two kinds of inquiry and so they offer two complementaryperspectives on the world.
However, many people are seeking a more constructive partnership. Science raises
questions it cannot answer itself. So many participants are looking for a constructive
dialogue, because they are aware of the limitations of their own field of inquiry, and because
both partners do not claim to have all the answers. Still other scientists and theologians even
go a step further. They seek a closer integration of science and religion.
We will use a well known influential fourfold typology, originally formulated by Ian
Barbour, who is a pre-eminent figure in the field of science and religion [10, 11]. This
fourfold typology is in fact the standard manner to present the relationship between science
and religion and for that reason it can help us to sort out the great variety of ways in which
people have related science and religion, and neurosciences and theology in particular.
Barbour uses four key words to typify the four relationships: conflict, independence,
dialogue and integration; Table I.2 illustrates the way Barbour relates certain scientific
disciplines and their way of thinking, and religious assertions about human nature.
Table I.2 Genetics, Neuroscience, and Human Nature [10]
Conflict Independence Dialogue Integration
Reductive
materialism
Body/soul dualism Neuroscience and
the embodied self
Biological organism
and responsible
self
Sociobiology and
human morality
Body and soul:
complementary
perspectives
Anthropology and
the social self
Mind and brain:
Two aspects of one
process
Genetic
determinism and
human freedom
Sin and redemption The computer and
the brain
Process philosophy
6 GENERAL INTRODUCTION: RELIGION AND SCIENCE
I.4.1 Conflict?
Scientific materialism makes two assertions: matter is the fundamental reality in the
universe, and, the scientific method is the only reliable path to knowledge. Religion is not
acceptable because religion lacks public data, lacks experimental testing and so on.
Science is objective, open-minded, and universal; religion is none of these. In neurosci-
ence we can find this same reductionistic materialism. In principle, we are told, we can
account for every mental phenomenon using the same physical laws that suffice to explain
radioactivity, or nutrition, or growth. The same reductive point of view holds true for the
sociobiology: the only demonstrated function of religious beliefs and human morality is to
keep the genes intact. Another illustration of the conflictual relationship between the
neurosciences and theology would certainly be genetic determinism. It has sometimes
been claimed that our fate is determined by our genes. But although nature and nurture
impose severe constraints upon us, we are free selves who envision possibilities and can
decide deliberately and responsibly among alternative actions. So here the conflict is
between determinism and human freedom. Dean Hamer, who is a pre-eminent geneticist,
recognizes the limitations of his scientific treatise and acknowledges that his approach is
not a complete explanation of spirituality; genes exp lain only a relatively small percentage
of variance at best. Hamer shows that new discoveries in genetics and neurobiology might
indicate that humans inherit a set of predispositions that make their brains ready and eager
to embrace a higher power [12]. He calls the specific gene he identified the ‘God gene’ that
appears to influence spirituality. Elaborating on his findings he argues that spiritual belief
may offer an evolutionary advantage by providing us with a sense of meaning and purpose,
and the courage and will to overcome hardshipandloss.InfactinthatwayHamertriedto
bridge the gap between science and religion instead of stirring up the conflict. (For a
critical discussion of religion as ‘adaptation or evolutionary by-product’ and genetics,
see [13]).
I.4.2 Independence?
What is the meaning of independence regarding science and religion? One way to avoid
conflict or any problem is to keep neuroscience and religion separated in watertight
compartments (demarcation theory). One can distinguish the two according to the questions
they ask, the domains to which they refer, the claims they make, and the methods they
employ. Science asks how matters work, and about causal relations. Religion asks why and
asks for meaning and purpose. From another point of view: scientific and religious
languages have distinctive functions and so science and religion offer complementary
perspectives, for instance the complimentary perspectives of brain and mind. Body and soul
used to be two separate compartments. But nowadays it is clear from the neurosciences that
such a dualism can no longer be maintained. The dependence of mental status on
biochemical processes, for instance in moral dilemmas [14, 15] or during religious practices
as meditation or prayer, is clearly shown. So we are getting used to the concept of the
embodied self, that goes beyond the body/soul dualism, and that goes beyond this second
type of relationship between science and religion called independence. Religious concepts
like sin and redemption seem far removed from any scientific data. Even that, however, is
highly questionable from an evolutionary and ethological point of view.
GENERAL INTRODUCTION: RELIGION AND SCIENCE 7
I.4.3 Dialogue?
Contrary to the independency point of view the dialogue looks at the presuppositions and
tries to explore similarities between methods and concepts. Independence emphasizes the
differences. Many theologians today try to reclaim a religious or spiritual view of the self as
a unified activity of thinking, willing and acting. Neuroscience seems to be consistent with
theological affirmations of embodiment. Embodiment is very clear when we look at our
affectivity. When I am moved by an emotion, it is clear that being emotional, for instance
being afraid, is not possible without feeling a bodily tension or beating of the heart. So here
religious thinking and the neurosciences, and also the behavioral sciences join in asserting
the embodied self with special importance of emotions.
I.4.4 Integration?
In integration scientists and theologians go even further. Exponents of dialogue may
sometimes reformulate traditional ideas. Integration is more far-reaching in articulating
theological reconstruction more extensively and systematically. For instance, reconstruc-
tion of a religious concept like original sin as a biologically based disposition from the past
that is not adaptive in the modern world. So according to this approach new knowledge from
the neurosciences will affect religious thinking!
It is up to the reader to look at his or her position, regarding one’s own religious, spiritual
and scientific background. It is one of the aims of the WPA section on Religion, Spirituality
and Psychiatry to help clear up these kinds of important discussions.
I.4.5 Neuro-theology
Neuro-theology is an example of a new emerging scientific discipline, based on neuros-
ciences, that presents strong challenges to traditional religious beliefs concerning human
nature. Neuroscience is the study of the physical structures of and causalinteractions between
neurons and neuronal assemblies [16]. It studies religious and spiritual concepts in relation to
neurological and neuropsychological findings and analyses. There is much to tell about
interesting data and recent discoveries in this particular field regarding religion and spiritual-
ity [12, 17]. Atthe same time, ifone looks carefully, it is not difficult to recognize the fourfold
typology in the way participants in neuro-theology handle and evaluate their findings.
I.5 REFINEMENTS
Barbour’s typology had been the starting point for the study of religion and science
relationships for many years. Stenmark [11] offered a new searching exploration based on
the premise that science and religion are social and dynamic practices and no static entities.
His study offers a refinement of the Barbour typology. How do these relationships between
science and religion evolve? According to Stenmark we need four parameters or dimensions
to take into account in order to understand how and why science and religion relate to each
8 GENERAL INTRODUCTION: RELIGION AND SCIENCE
other as they do. His approach helps us to get a more differentiated picture of the interactions
between science and religion.
Stenmark’s approach is based on the idea that science and religion are both social
practices. He calls it the social level of science and religion, and it is about the social
interactions between practitioners of both science and religion. Such practices can be
distinguished by the aims the practitioners have in mind (teleological dimension) by the
methods that are used (epistemological dimension), and by the subject matter and content of
science and religion (theoretical dimension). The independence view would mean that these
two practices are completely different with regard to these parameters. The conflict view
would mean that the parameters should be the same. The dialogue and integration views
mean that there is a more or less overlap between one or more parameters.
With regard to psychiatry and religion we would have to look at these parameters and to
search for areas of overlap, or areas of total difference. What would be the overlap and the
difference between psychiatry and religion in a teleological sense? If it would be appropriate to
say that both practices aim at ‘healing’ or at helping relationships, there still would be a great
difference between mental health and welfare (salvation) as a goal. However, despite
the difference in ‘healing’ methods (e.g. medication versus prayer) the relationship between
‘the healer’ and ‘the healed’ is fundamental for employing the method. On a theoretical level the
question would be how much overlap or difference there is in theoretical output. Could both
psychiatry and religion offer us explanations of concepts like disease, illness and health, and also
of experiencing illness and health? Would these explanations be complementary or opposite?
However, if we look at the historical development of science and religion as social
practices it is clear that at different times and places human nature has been differently
experienced, behavior has been differently regarded, and claims to knowledge have been
adjudicated in different ways.
I.6 CROSSING BOUNDARIES
The boundary between religion and spirituality and the practice of psychiatry is becoming
increasingly porous, as the contributors to this book amply illustrate. No longer can
psychiatrists in a multi-faith, multi-cultural globalized world hide behind the dismissal
of religious belief as pathological, or behind biomedical scientism. During the last two or
three decades religion and spirituality have become more prominent in mainstream
psychiatry, not least because of the increased migration [18]. Globalization affects
psychiatry, as it affects religion and spirituality. According to Kale [19] globalization
exhibits five main trends in spirituality and religion:
*the use of religion and spirituality in reterritorialization;
*a worldwide quest to integrate spirituality in all aspects of day-to-day life;
*the increasing individualization of spirituality;
*the enhanced manifestation of spirituality in cyberspace;
*the syncretization of spirituality.
Religion and spirituality are on the move, so to say. This asks from psychiatrists to be more
knowledgeable. Religion, spirituality and globalization have a vital impact on wellness and
GENERAL INTRODUCTION: RELIGION AND SCIENCE 9
quality of life for a growing number of people worldwide. The World Health Organization
(WHO) has rightly regarded religious, spiritual and personal beliefs as a component of
quality of life. This growing awareness may enhance the study of religion and spirituality in
psychiatric training, research and practice. In their review Fulford and Sadler stated: ‘There is
a renewed cross-disciplinary contact (between religion and psychiatry, PJV) after nearly a
century of mutual neglect’ [20]. We really hope that this book may stimulate WPA, as a global
organization, to take an active stance in this renewed and promising contact.
REFERENCES
1. Sadler JZ (2005) Values and Psychiatric Diagnosis. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
2. Hart MB (2007) The Healthy Jew. The symbiosis of Judaism and Modern Medicine. Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge.
3. Schmidt-Leukel P (2004) A New Spirituality for a Religiously Plural World. Concilium 40,
62–68.
4. Information Please Almanac: Top Ten Organized Religions of the World. Available at http://
www.infoplease.com/ipa/A0904108.html. Accessed February 21, 2008
5. WPA Report from the London Conference on Person-centered Integrative Diagnosis and
Psychiatry for the Person. Electronic Bulletin. 2008; 59. Available at http://www.wpanet.org/
bulletin/eb59.html. Accessed February 23, 2008.
6. Cox J, Campbell AV, Fulford KWM (2007) Medicine of the person. Faith, Science and Values in
Health Care Provision. Jessica Kingsley Publishers, London.
7. Oomen PMF (2003) On brain, soul, self, and freedom: an essay in bridging neuroscience and faith.
Zygon 38, 377–392.
8. Verhagen PJ Sanctifying Personhood; beyond roles,functions, schemas and traits. Spirituality and
Psychiatry Special Interest Group Newsletter. 2007; 24. Available at http://www.rcpsych.ac.uk/
college/specialinterestgroups/spirituality/publications/newsletter24.aspx. Accessed February 23,
2008.
9. Wilber K (1998) The marriage of sense and soul. Integrating science and religion. Broadway
Books, New York.
10. Barbour IG (2000) When science meets religion. HarperSanFrancisco, New York.
11. Stenmark M (2004) How to relate science and religion. A multidimensional model. Eerdmans
Publishing Co, Grand Rapids.
12. Hamer D (2004) The God gene. How faith is hardwired into our genes. Doubleday, New York.
13. Kirkpatrick LA (2005) Attachment, evolution, and the psychology of religion. The Guilford
Press, New York.
14. Casebeer WD (2003) Moral cognition and its neural constituents. Nature Reviews Neuroscience
4, 840–847.
15. Greene J (2003) From neural ‘is’ to moral ‘ought’: what are the moral implications of
neuroscientific moral psychology? Nature Reviews Neuroscience 4, 847–850.
16. McConnell D, Pickering N (2005) Clinical Practice, Science, and the Unconscious. Editorial.
Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 12, 1–7.
17. Newberg AB, Iversen J (2002) On the “neuro” in neurotheology. In: Joseph R (ed.) NeuroTheol-
ogy. Brain, science, spirituality, religious experience. San University Press, San Jose.
18. Boehnlein JK (2006) Religion and spirituality in psychiatric care: looking back, looking ahead.
Transcultural Psychiatry 43, 634–651.
19. Kale SH (2004) Spirituality, Religion, and Globalization. Journal of Macromarketing 24,
92–107.
20. Fulford KWM, Sadler JZ (2002) Imaging the soul. Current Opinion in Psychiatry 15, 515–518.
10 GENERAL INTRODUCTION: RELIGION AND SCIENCE
CHAPTER 1.1
Evil in Historical Perspective:
At the Intersection of Religion
and Psychiatry
Michael H. Stone
Professor of Clinical Psychiatry, United States of America
1.1.1 INTRODUCTORY REMARKS
Mankind has struggled since remotest antiquity, and presumably long before recorded
history, to comprehend and to deal with – the manifold sources of challenge and threat to our
earthly existence. Precisely because the threats to our survival are so numerous, compared
with the comforting and healing actions that aid our survival, we have evolved over the
millennia with a heightened awareness of the things that can harm or kill us, lower our social
status, adversely affect our loved ones, or otherwise rob us of the necessities of life. This has
led to the broad distinctions in our language between the positive and the (altogether more
numerous) negative influences – captured under the headings Good and Bad, or in a manner
more freighted with religious overtones, Good and Evil.
Originally, the concept of Evil covered a large territory on our mental map: natural
disasters such as droughts, floods, earthquakes, plagues, and extremes of temperature;
animals that could endanger our lives; and finally – the most dangerous of all our enemies:
other humans with hostile intentions. The inescapable death of ourselves and of all living
species was often itself regarded as an evil.
Natural disasters, in particular, could be so overwhelming, wiping out great numbers of
people, even whole populations, at one stroke, that they cried out for explanation and, if
possible, for being brought under our control. But war and violent acts even in peacetime
could also reach devastating proportions. These phenomena also cried out for explanation
and control.
The religious impulse, which has sprung up spontaneously in all cultures from the
beginning of recorded time (if not from the time of our emergence as a separate species), has
acquired pride of place among the attempts our ancestors made to explain evil. Mankind has
found it both comforting and necessary to invoke the concept of the divine, whether
compartmentalized into many deities (as in the pantheons of the ancient Greeks, the Hindus,
Religion and Psychiatry: Beyond Boundaries Edited by Peter J. Verhagen, Herman M. van Praag, Juan J. Lo
´pez-Ibor Jr.,
John L. Cox and Driss Moussaoui
Copyright 2010 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd
the early Egyptians, etc.) or, as in the Abrahamic religions of Judaism, Christianity,
and Islam, manifest in the existence of one God. Many believe that God created us in
His image; others, regarding this as an anthropomorphic conceit, assert that we created (the
concept of) God in our image. Be this as it may, religion assigns to God (whether in the
singular or the plural) supernal powers over our lives and over all Nature. Related ideas
include heavenly reward for doing well; heavenly retribution for doing evil. As we shall see,
in earlier times the natural disasters were themselves understood as punishment writ large –
for violating God’s laws about proper conduct by whole groups of people, even at times
by whole nations.
The belief in life after death, adhered to by religious persons of many faiths, brings with it
the accompanying notions that those whose lives have been (mostly) good will reap the
reward of life-everlasting in Heaven; those whose lives have been (mostly) bad, devoted
repeatedly to acts regarded as evil – will earn only a place in eternal damnation, Hell, or its
equivalent. The appeal of these beliefs is easy to grasp, given the unhappiness endured by
most well-meaning and well-behaved people, and given the outrageous success to the very
day of their death, whether in fame, power, or money, of certain undeserving people who, in
the estimation of society, were evil. One of the functions acquired by religion, in other
words, was the promise of at least belated justice via the punishment of bad people, even if it
could only be carried out in the hereafter – that the good people had been unable to effect
within the lifetime of the offenders.
Looking at the world’s timetable, it is clear that religion antedated philosophy, and that
philosophy came before psychiatry. It is not surprising, then, that in seeking an explanation
as to how the mysterious and embarrassing existence of evil arose amongst their own kind,
men turned first to religion. The first persons to offer explanations about evil were men of
religion: either founders of a new religion, or else men schooled in-, and strongly identified
with, an already developed religion. Many of these men were of what we would now call a
‘philosophical turn of mind’ – in the sense that they grappled with the larger issues of good
and evil, morality, how life should be lived, how death should be confronted, our place in
Nature, and our relation to Deity. The next group of men to ponder these issues and to offer
explanations, steeped as they were in both religion and philosophy – were the religious
philosophers. Only within the past three centuries have we witnessed the emergence of a few
philosophers – often raised in deeply religious families – whose approach to the subject of
evil is nevertheless more secular in construction and less tied to the tenets of this or that
religion.
Until very recently the topic of evil was felt to be the exclusive province of religion, or
perhaps of religious philosophy; explanations of evil partook of the metaphysical or the
supernatural. To that extent, only for religious adepts: priests, ministers, rabbis, imams, was
it permissible to make pronouncements about evil. Philosophers whose thoughts and
writings were imbued with religion might also address the subject. But for the vast majority
of people – to speak about evil, especially to categorize certain others as evil, was felt as an
intrusion on sacred ground, and would often enough invite adverse criticism.
In the twentieth century, however, discussion of evil underwent a sea-change. Many
important philosophers were less attached to conventional religion than heretofore. And in
the last half of the century, particularly following the Holocaust, but also in recognition of
the genocides in Armenia earlier, and in Cambodia, Rwanda, Nigeria, Yugoslavia and
elsewhere, along with the Nanking Massacre of 1937, and the mass murders of its own
citizenry in Russia and China – the topic of evil could no longer be confined to the
14 PROLEGOMENA (FIRST ISSUES)
sanctuaries of religious leaders or to the university halls of the philosophers. Two significant
developments have, in recent years, brought about a reshaping of our attitudes towards evil.
First, we have begun to pay more attention to how the word evil is used by the public and by
the media. There are certain classes of crime, for example, that predictably elicit the word,
whether from people in ordinary life or from writers and journalists. Evil is no longer ‘off-
limits’ except to men of the cloth. Second, evil has become an acceptable subject for study
by the mental health professions, including general psychiatry, forensic psychiatry, and
neuroscience. Rather than relying only on the Bible (of whatever religion) for explanations
about the nature and roots of evil, we now look where we should have been looking all along:
the human brain.
There has been an inchoate recognition for a long time that evil is a purely human
phenomenon. For an action on the part of one creature toward another creature to be
considered evil, there must be consciousness and also an awareness of death. The con-
sciousness, in this case, would involve the awareness of the suffering that one is inflicting
upon another. Awareness of death is a special case of consciousness, the implication being
that an aggressor realizes consciously (a) that the death of the victim may be the result of
aggressive action, and (b) that the victim would have beenvehemently opposed to this result.
There is also the matter of attitude. Acts that we regard as evil are often preceded by
powerful emotions of hatred (whether in the form of contempt, envy, jealousy, outrage over
being humiliated, and the like). Born of such hatred are such acts as murder, rape, grievous
assault, public humiliation, the depletion or ruin of another’s possessions, etc. All these
manifestations are unique to our human species (with perhaps a few analogous acts among
some of the higher apes). The cat bears no malice toward the mouse, nor the walrus to the fish
it devours for its sustenance. For all intents and purposes we are the only members of the
animal kingdom of whom it is meaningful to apply the word evil.
In reviewing how the concept of evil has evolvedover the centuries, we turn our attention
first to the men of religion in ancient times, some of whom also became the founders of new
religions. We then see how the concept was reworked and understood by men who were at
once professional philosophers and deeply religious persons. In the more recent centuries
the main commentators on evil were philosophers, often with a strongly religious back-
ground and upbringing, but who were not also clergymen. Still more recently, we confront
professors of philosophy of a more secular orientation. Finally, commentary on evil is
divided between philosophers who are less strongly identified with a particular religion –
and persons in the disciplines of psychology and psychiatry.
1.1.2 EVIL AS VIEWED BY MEN OF RELIGION IN ANTIQUITY
One of the earliest ideas about evil is to be found in the writings of Yajnavalkya, a Hindu
religious adept and ascetic of the eighth century BCE. He spoke of an ‘inner person’ who
existed in two states: one of this world, one in the Other. When we are born and acquire a
body, we are joined with evils; when we die, we abandon evils. In the intermediate situation
of the dream state we see both the evils of this world and the joys of the Other world – an idea
that is incorporated in a religious text: the Brhadaranyaka Upanishad [1]. As for ‘evils,’
Indian and Buddhist countries believe in the notion of karma, according to which all our
deeds, whether good or evil, are rewarded or punished; our ultimate fate is determined by the
accumulation of our deeds, extending over our lifetime ([1], p. 40).
1.1 EVIL IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE 15
A near-contemporary of Yajnavalkya, the Old Testament prophet Isaiah spoke in the
tradition of Jewish monotheism, referring to the fallen angel Lucifer (lit.: the bearer of light)
as one who had claimed that he would ascend into Heaven and exalt his throne above the
stars of God...I will be like the Most High [Isaiah 14:12–15]. The prophet asserts that no,
Lucifer (called also Satan: Hebr. for ‘adversary’) will be brought down to Hell. Lucifer’s
sins were those of pride and covetousness – akin to our modern concept of narcissism. But
there is a hint in Isaiah’s remarks that the good and evil observed among men is related in
some way to the supernatural, celestial battle waged between God and His adversary –
Lucifer/Satan.
Prince Gautama Siddharta (623–543 BCE) as he neared 30 gave up a life of riches,
wandering in northern India as a poor man, and developing a philosophy that emphasized the
renunciation of earthly desires and the state of non-attachment. Having achieved enlight-
enment, he became known as the Buddha (from the Sanskrit verb to awaken). Though he
never claimed divine status, rather that of a teacher and guide, he has now become the object
of veneration by those who claim Buddhism (and its offshoots) as their religion. Buddha
taught that to escape suffering one needed to eliminate desire and to follow the noble Eightfold
Path (right view, right speech, right thought, etc). To be avoided were the chief sins – all
related to lust or desire; namely, anger, greed, and foolishness. These constitute the same
triad of sins embodied in Japanese Zen-Buddhism: ikari (anger), musabori (greed) and
orokasa (foolishness).
The religious teacher and prophet of ancient Persia, Zoroaster, was probably a contem-
porary of the Buddha, though some have suggested he may have lived much earlier, even
before 1000 BCE [2]. The religion he founded – Zoroastrianism – postulated the twin
brother-Gods, Ahura-Mazda (the God of Light and Good), and Ahriman (the God of
Darkness and Evil). There is a close parallel here to the Old Testament story of the
twin brothers, the virtuous Abel and the murderous Cain. Ahriman is said to have chosen of
his free will to behave in an evil way, creating in the process the phenomena of sin, death,
and evil.
The Jewish prophet of the Old Testament, Ezekiel (622–570 BCE), a contemporary of
the Buddha, wrote of Lucifer in this way: ‘Thou wast perfect in thy ways from the day
that thou wast created, till iniquity was found in thee.... Thou hast sinned: therefore... I
will destroy thee, o coveting cherub... and never shalt thou be anymore’ [28:12–19].
Centuries later, Christian theology could not accept that God created Lucifer/Satan as a
wicked creature, since this would amount to God creating an evil. Instead, St.
Augustine’s idea (built upon Ezekiel’s understanding) found preference, according to
which God had not created Lucifer as evil. Rather: Lucifer, now as Ha-Satan [the
adversary] via an exercise of his own free will – chose an evil path, and was cast out of
Heaven (cf. [3]).
1.1.3 EARLY PHILOSOPHERS
Kong Fu-zi [Kong, the Master], whom we know as Confucius [551–479 BCE], albeit a
religious man, rarely discussed supernatural phenomena, emphasizing instead a humanistic
approach – one that recognized the free will of all people [4].
Confucius taught that the superior man is one who has learned to overcome his innately
evil nature, through the practice of jen [acknowledgment, knowledge]. He also advocated
16 PROLEGOMENA (FIRST ISSUES)
moderation as a transcendent virtue, akin to the emphasis on the ‘middle way’ in the
philosophy of Aristotle. Evil, for Confucius, was not seen as a supernatural force implanted
in us, and against which we must constantly struggle, but as an inborn human tendency –
against which we must constantly struggle.
Mencius [372–289 BCE], who may have been taught by Confucius’ grandson, Zi Si, was
an idealist after the manner of Plato, in agreement with the latter that he believed in man’s
innate moral goodness, in contradistinction to Confucius’ belief in man’s originally evil
nature.
The comments of Plato [427-347 BCE] on evil have a resonance with those ofConfucius.
For Plato, God was not the cause of evil; instead, God guarantees the inevitable decree of
Fate; namely, that the man who will make the wrong or immoral decision will pay for it,
becoming tormented, perverted, and unhappy. God is without blame (an
aitio&). The ‘evil
soul,’ meanwhile, is that part of the soul where evil naturally resides; that is, the irrational
part of the soul which is receptive to evil and to ‘unmeasuredness’ – i.e., excess and defect,
the sources of unrestrained wickedness and cowardice. One effect of this irrational soul is to
make the soul think that whatever it avoids or shuns is ‘evil,’ and whatever it seeks is ‘good’
([5], Phaedrus 256B 2–3).
Plato’s pupil, Aristotle (384–322 BCE), expressed similar views concerning evil: evil was
a form of the ‘unlimited’; good, of the limited. Excess and deficiency are failings; virtue lies
in the (golden) mean. As Aristotle mentioned: Men are bad in countless ways; good, only in
one ([6], II vi). The mark of virtue was to have the right feelings at the right times on the right
grounds toward the right people for the right motive and in the right way. In this regard,
Aristotle’s ideas harmonize with those of the Buddha’s Eightfold Path.
Epicurus, a Greek philosopher [341–270 BCE] from the generation after Aristotle, held
that the purpose of philosophy was to attain a happy, tranquil life, adding that pleasure is
the measure of what is good; pain, of what is bad. He held that the gods neither reward
nor punish people, but also counseled against hedonism – remarking that restraint and
temperance were prime virtues, much as was emphasized by Plato and Aristotle ([3],
1:20). The philosophical school he founded (Epicureanism) was one of the three then
dominant schools of thought, alongside Stoicism and Skepticism. Epicurus is noted for
his effort to explain the world without recourse to myth or religion, but through reference
to material principles – testable in what we would call a scientific way via direct
observation. Moral reasoning for Epicurus involved a cost/benefit analysis of pleasure
versus pain (the latter included both physical and mental suffering). Mirrored in his
philosophy is the Jeffersonian credo, embedded in the American Declaration of Inde-
pendence, asserting that human beings have the inalienable rights to life, liberty, and the
pursuit of happiness. In one of his writings, preserved by the early Christian rhetorician,
Lactantius [240-ca. 320 CE], Epicurus casts doubt on God’s responsibility for evil via a
method of careful reasoning that we will confront only much later in the works of Pierre
Bayle. As Epicurus phrased it: God either wishes to take away evils, and is unable, or He
is able and unwilling, or He is neither willing nor able – or He is both willing and able. If
He is willing but unable, He is feeble, but this is not in accord with the character of God.
If He is able and unwilling, He is envious, which is equally at variance with God. If He is
neither willing nor able, He is both envious and feeble – and therefore not God. If He is
both willing and able (which alone is suitable of God), where then does evil arise? And
why does God not remove evils? It will be many centuries before this dilemma is resolved
satisfactorily.
1.1 EVIL IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE 17
1.1.4 COMMENTARY ON EVIL IN THE 1ST MILLENIUM
OF THE COMMON ERA
The word evil, once the New Testament was organized in its final form by Bishop Irenaeus in
the late second century CE, occurs some 106 times (as against 446 times in the Old
Testament). The Greek word kako
´nis used much as was the Hebrew [ra] of the OT– in a
variety of ways: wickedness, hurt, mischief, bad, affliction, adversity, harm, wrong, etc: that
is, both to designate the deed and also its consequence. There is not so much comment on the
primal source of evil (as in Zoroaster’s Ahriman), as there is an implicit recognition that men
are strongly inclined to commit acts which others define as evil – particularly if there is a
weakness in their link to God. In this sense, God plays a role more in the center stage of
human conflict than is apparent in the philosophy of Plato, where God (or the ‘gods’) are at a
greater remove from human affairs, operating more as observer or final judge. Thus the New
Testament speaks of the ungodly man: one whose life-course is an injury to himself and to
everyone around him; he is morally evil and hurtful. Saul of Tarsus [? to ca. 67 CE], who
became St. Paul, famously wrote in the first epistle to Timothy: ‘the love of money
[jilargura] is the root of all evil’ – referring especially to ‘...they that will be rich fallinto
temptation and a snare, and into many foolish [lit. ano
´hto&’mindless’] and hurtful lusts,
which drown men in destruction and perdition’ [1 Tim. 6:9 & 10]. Paul here inveighs against
the same evils of greed and foolishness that the Buddha underscored. Elsewhere, Paul gives
us a brief catalog of evils: adultery, fornication, uncleanness, lasciviousness, idolatry [lit.:
heresy], witchcraft, hatred, strife, envy, drunkenness, revellings, and such like’ [Paul’s
Epistle to the Galatians 5: 16–24]. Oddly, the King James version also mentions ‘murder’
[Gal. 5:21] – which would be jo
´no&/phonos, whereas the original Greek of the Septuagint
only reads jqo
´no&/phthonos – which signifies envy or malice. Paul does not present these
evils in a hierarchical manner; certain ones nevertheless appear to us more malign (such as
ecqra: hatred, enmity) than others (such as drunkenness).
Plotinus [205–270 CE] is believed to have been a Hellenized Egyptian, the developer of
neo-Platonic philosophy. He himself was not Christian nor did he refer to Christianity in his
works. Plotinus’ cosmology influenced subsequent philosophers from many backgrounds,
including Jewish, Christian, and Muslim. One aspect of his cosmology centers around his
belief that the soul is composed of a higher and a lower part: the higher part – divine, and
imparting life to the lower part, which in turn is the seat of the personality with its passions
and vices. Evil is linked with matter, in contrast to the Intellect, which is always pure – and
which turns away from matter. For Plotinus evil was not irremediable, since it came about
through privation: through the soul becoming disconnected from the higher part because of
forgetfulness. In this latter state, the soul loses its ability to rule over its inferior part and
comes under the influence of matter. The remedy for the soul, by which it can free itself from
evil – is through the experience of love.
In contrast to the mind-set of Plato or Mencius, the early Christian philosophers tended
toward a pessimistic view of humanity, picturing man as sinful, evil as inescapable,
salvation as difficult to achieve. This gloomy view was not universal among them, but
was characteristic of the most influential thinkers. Consider, for example, the ideas of St.
Augustine as contrasted with those of Pelagius. Both were born in the same year [354 CE]:
Pelagius in Britain; St. Augustine, in North Africa. St. Augustine, before his conversion to
Christianity at age 31, struggled with sexual feelings that overwhelmed him and which he
strove to ‘conquer’ after coming under the influence of St. Ambrose in Milan. In his effort to
18 PROLEGOMENA (FIRST ISSUES)
understand evil, St. Augustine argued that God was good and the things He made were good.
Evil, not being attributable to God, came from the sin committed by Adam and Eve in
violating God’s prohibition against eating the forbidden fruit (which conferred knowledge,
including, by the way, knowledge about sex and procreation). Because of this hubris, we
became corrupted by our own free will – the Original Sin of these first two humans being
passed down the generations. For St. Augustine this vitium (flaw) lay in our passions and
desires of the flesh, summed up under the heading of concupiscentia (which includes all
desires – for wealth, admiration, power, not just for sex), the root being Pride (the craving for
self-exaltation). In one of his more dour comments, he wrote Sub Deo justo, nemo miser nisi
mereatur: Under a just God, no one is miserable who has not deserved misery. Yet St.
Augustine disagreed with Plotinus, claiming instead that whatever exists on earth (including
matter) is good, because it came from God. The one curative that could free our will from its
inherited and otherwise irremediable predisposition to sin – was the elusive (and for St.
Augustine, not very liberally dispensed) force of God’s grace [7].
Pelagius’ views were diametrically opposed to those of St. Augustine, rejecting the
latter’s fatalistic and rigid conceptions. Opposing the doctrine of Original Sin, Pelagius
proposed instead that Adam was created susceptible of death – whether or not he had sinned;
his sin was his alone and not that of all mankind; infants are in the same state as Adam before
the Fall; and even before Christ there were some men who were sinless. Each person,
furthermore, was free to choose between good and evil. Though Pelagius regarded his
contemporary as nearly Manichaean (and thus heretical) in his picture of Good and Evil as
akin to two separate forces, it was St. Augustine who won the day and set the tone for much
of Christian philosophy in the years to come. Pelagius emerged, despite his (as we would see
it) humanistic philosophy, as the ‘heretic.’ In fairness to his rival, St. Augustine did
recognize (in a manner at variance with Manichaeism) that ’... I once thought that it is
not we who sin but some other nature that sins within us (mihi videbatur non esse nos qui
peccamus, sed nescio quam aliam in nobis peccare naturam)... The truth, of course, was
that it was all within my own self, and that my own impiety had divided me against myself’
([8], V, 10).
1.1.5 ARABIC PHILOSOPHERS IN THE TIME
OF THE FIRST MILLENNIUM
A number of important Arabic philosophers bookended the first millennium, having
flourished in the century-and-a-half just before, or just after 1000 CE.
The first philosopher of major significance during this era was Ab
uY
usuf al-Kind
ı(ca.
801–873), who was born into an aristocratic family in Kufa (in what is now Iraq). A
polymath learned in many academic subjects, Al-Kind
ıis credited with having introduced
Indian numerals (that we now refer to as Arabic numerals) into the Islamic and Christian
worlds. In the field of psychology he wrote a treatise on sleep and dream interpretation. As
to his philosophic thought, he was influenced by Aristotle and by such neo-Platonic writers
as Plotinus and Proclus. In his treatise The Eradication of Sorrow, Al-Kind
ıtouches on the
broad topic of good and evil, insofar as he speaks of grief as related either to the loss of
loved ones or to the loss of personal possessions. Yet one cannot live without sustaining the
loss of loved ones nor can one acquire all he may desire. As Butterworth [9] mentions, ‘the
only way to escape sorrow is to be free from these attachments’ (p. 269). In this sense
1.1 EVIL IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE 19
Al-Kind
ıargues for the kind of asceticism urged by the Buddha long before him, and by
the neo-Platonic philosophers as well – who equated evil with the material world – and
with the inordinate quest for material wealth; good – with philosophic contemplation and
the pursuit of virtue. Implicit in his recommendation for the virtuous life is something akin
to life according to an Aristotelian Golden Mean – where, regarding possessions, one
strives to get along with the low side of average; to be satisfied, that is, with ‘just enough.’
This would be the optimal antidote to greed (recall the Buddha’s triune conception of
evil: anger, greed, and foolishness) – that was still compatible with a tolerable human
existence.
The philosopher/polymath whom we know as Rhazes was born in Persia, in the city of
Rayy (whence his name: ‘from the city of Rayy’) in about 854. He became physician in
charge of the Royal Hospital in Rayy, eventually moving to a similar post in Baghdad.
Among his medical accomplishments were the discovery of sulfuric acid and the medical
use of alcohol. Though a prolific writer (one year he is said to have written 20,000 pages, or
55 a day), little has come down to us of his original works. A freethinker whose philosophic
ideas were more in keeping with Platonic than with Aristotelian thought, Rhazes did not see
creation as a gift or an act of grace bestowed on us by a benevolent deity. Rather, he felt
that ‘... in this life, evils outweigh goods,’ in sympathy with the Epicurean view, and
also with his physicianly observation that there was a ‘prevalence of pain and suffering
over peace and pleasure in all sensate beings’ [10]. Akin to the Judaeo-Christian notion of
expulsion from the Garden of Eden because of sin, Rhazes pictured our bodily existence
as representing a fall from the life-giving principle of the Soul – a fall that can be broken by
the gift of intelligence. The fall was not so much imposed on us by God as permitted by a
tolerant and all-seeing Wisdom [10]. There is a hint here of man having free will,
despite the omnipotence of an all-knowing God – leaving us free to pursue good or to
descend into evil.
In a manner analogous to Pelagius’ departure from orthodox Christian belief, the Persian-
born Islamic philosopher, Ab
u Nas¸r al-F
ar
abi [870–950], the founder of Islamic Neo-
Platonism, questioned the authority of the Qur’an and rejected the notion of predestination.
He felt reason was superior to revelation – a heretical idea for a Muslim [11]. Al-F
ar
abi may
have been influenced in this direction by his (heretical) teacher ‘
Isa al-Warr
aq (died 909
CE). Dividing the cosmos into three worlds: the First (independent of matter; the realm of
intelligible forms and higher spirits); the Second (the heavenly spheres); and the Third
(material entities), F
ar
abi posited that evil was excluded from the first two, and could exist
only in the third realm. Even there, in the domain of willful action, good and evil can be
found, and depend on either the proper use, or else the misuse, of material means. Voluntary
evil is associated with wrong choice, as when, for example, the rational faculty is oblivious
to the supreme good and is directed instead toward an inferior good such as pleasure or profit
([11], p. 97). There is no simple correspondence, in other words, between Pleasure and
Good versus Pain and Evil, since certain pleasures are obviously associated with vice and
with harm to others. Rhazes before him had cautioned that pleasure is to be pursued only in a
manner that brings on no greater pain or harm ([9], p 271). As with Pelagius, and in opposition
to St. Augustine, God and the supernatural are no longer primary elements in Al F
ar
abi’s
conceptualization of evil and its origins. Even though he invokes God as the ‘Lord of the
Worlds,’ God, in Al F
ar
abi’s view, does not act directly on the sublunary world (Rhazes
would agree with this postulate), and is thus more remote than the God of St. Augustine.
20 PROLEGOMENA (FIRST ISSUES)
Ab
u ’Ali al-Husayn ibn Sina, whom we know as Avicenna, was born near Bukhara (in
Central Asia) in 980. He died in 1037 CE. A polymath like the previously mentioned Islamic
philosophers, Avicenna is better known today for his voluminous medical writings than for
his essays on other topics. In his philosophical work, he was interested primarily in creating
a coherent system that dealt with man’s place in the world in a way harmonious with Islamic
religious doctrine. His earliest works were influenced by Al-F
ar
abi, and include his Maqala
fi’l Nafs (Compendium on the Soul) in which he argues for the incorporeality of the soul,
though without adopting the Neo-Platonic notion of its pre-existence [12]. As with medieval
philosophers in general, Avicenna used the philosophical mind-set in the service of religion,
positing that God, as one pure Good could produce only a cosmos that was orderly and good.
But this raises the vexatious question: if God is pure Good, whence Evil? Avicenna’s answer
was that there was no Pure Evil (like the Zoroastrian Ahriman) on the other side of the
balance. Rather: in our world there are particular evils, best understood as ‘accidental
consequences of good’ ([12], section 5). Still to be explained: moral evils among human
beings, as opposed to natural evils such as earthquakes and floods. Here Avicenna posited
that God knows the things that exist, but not individuals. This drew fire from a later Islamic
philosopher, Al Ghazali (1058–1111 CE), for whom Avicenna’s denial that God had
knowledge of particulars, as well, was heretical. In the area of psychology Avicenna’s
religion-inspired views existed side by side with his practical medical knowledge. In a
prelibation of Descartes’ seventeenth-century theory, he believed that the soul is indepen-
dent of the body, even going so far as to enunciate an argument, similar to Descartes’ cogito
ergo sum, that a blind man, were he suspended in the air, would be unaware of his body, yet
still possessed of self-awareness – because he could still think ([12], section 7). But in his
great compendium, the Canons of Medicine, Avicenna described various ‘down-to-earth’
psychological (we would say psychiatric) conditions, such as melancholy and mania – along
with recommendations for their treatment. Avicenna’s views on the temperaments (San-
guineous, Phlegmatic, Bilious, Melancholic or ‘Atrabilious’), and their connections to the
four elements: air, water, fire, and earth, respectively, derive from ancient Greek sources
(particularly, Galen). We still use the corresponding temperament terms manic, phlegmatic,
melancholic//depressive, and irritable even today, as did Kraepelin in the early 1900s. But
Avicenna hardly confined himself to psychological issues, and though he touched on
psychiatric conditions, he cannot in any meaningful sense be called a psychiatrist.
The most prominent successor to Avicenna, Ab
u’l Wal
ıd ibn Rushd (our Averrho
es), born
in Islam’s western-most area, in Cordoba (1126–1198), is famous for his commentaries on
Aristotle. Ibn Rushd was in touch with Christian and Jewish philosophers in Islamic Spain,
including Maimonides (also from Cordoba), who greatly admired him. As with many
philosophers, from the Greeks to the time of ibn Rushd, the attainment of intellectual
excellence was considered a ’prerogative of the privileged few’ ([13], p. 301). The masses,
in contrast, could aspire at best to a level of moral excellence through leading a life of virtue
(according to the wisdom and recommendations of the philosophers). Moral uprightness
was a potential for them, even though a comprehension of the essential truth lay beyond their
grasp. A philosophical posture vis-
a-vis good and evil is implicit in this view, though ibn
Rushd focuses less on the topic of evil than did some of his Islamic predecessors. Dante
knew of both Avicenna and ibn Rushd, whom he situated in the limbo of Inferno – where lay
the unbaptized and the virtuous pagans (whereas another prominent Aristotelian, St.
Thomas Aquinas, was in Paradiso). Toward the end of Canto IV (ll. 142–144) of the
1.1 EVIL IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE 21
Inferno, Dante wrote:
Euclide geom
etra e Tolomeo, Euclid the geometer and Ptolemy,
Ipocr
ate, Avicenna e Gali
eno, Avicenna and Galen,
Averoı
`s che ’l gran comento feo. Averro
es who made the great Commentary. [14]
1.1.6 RELIGIOUS PHILOSOPHERS OF THE MEDIEVAL PERIOD
The humanist Jewish philosopher Maimonides [1135–1204] transmitted Aristotelian
rationalism, which had been kept alive through the Arabic sources of the previous four
centuries, to later Christian theologians like Albertus Magnus and St. Thomas Aquinas.
Maimonides accepted the Platonic view that earthly matter was the source of evil and saw
the Imitatio Dei of St. Augustine as a way of freeing oneself from the ties of matter [15].
He also saw the imagination as tied to material things, one manifestation of which was the
anthropomorphism and belief in a corporeal, as opposed to an abstract, God [16]. He
advocated, in a manner akin to asceticism, minimizing one’s attention to bodily functions
and impulses (food, drink, sex...), recognizing how they underlay the ‘evil impulse’
[yetzer ha-ra]. Yet his realism was such that he understood that the evil impulse
was not irredeemably evil: later rabbis would argue, in fact, that without a measure of the
impulse, one would not marry, have children, build a house, or engage in business. What was
crucial in Maimonides’ argument was that the impulses that govern sex and the desire for
mastery can gooverboard (beyond, in effect, the Aristotelian mean) and end up as evil actions.
For St. Thomas Aquinas [1225–1274?] the main theological struggle was that of
theodicy: how to explain the existence of evil, given an omnipotent God who was thoroughly
benign and good – an echo here of the earlier lament of Bo
ethius: ‘If there be a God, from
whence so many evils?’ ([17], xix). The resolutionlay for him in the concept of free will. Only
God had a free will that was at the same time incapable of sin. But St. Thomas considered it
impossible for God to create human beings having both a rational nature and free will – who
would always choosewhat was right and never commit a fault or a sin. As towhy it should be
that God could not have gone the extra distance and engineered our freewill in such a way that
we too could not commit sins – St. Thomas does not hazard an explanation. He does conclude,
however, that the root of all vices lay in the inordinate love of self [Question VIII, art. 2, reply
19] – a comment in linewith our modern conception of narcissism (Aquinas St. Thomas [71].
For further explication of the views of St. Augustine and St. Thomas, the reader should
consult the excellent summary of Carlos Steel [72].
Count Giovanni Pico della Mirandola [1463–94] hoped to put to rest, as had Pelagius
before him, the belief still held by some – that evil was born of two distinct sources, one
representing the Good; the other, Evil, as posited by Zoroaster and the similar-minded third-
century prophet, Mani – from whose name the Manichaean heresy derives.
Writing in the early Renaissance period, St. Ignatius Loyola [1491–1556], the founder of
the Jesuit order, expressed a mixture of views: some that pay homage to traditional Christian
theology; others that have a more modern ring. He mentions (in the traditional vein) that the
Devil, studying the nature and traits of each man, suggests splendor to the ambitious, gain to
the covetous, delight to the sensuous, etc. But he avoids the trap of theodicy in stating that
one cannot define Good and Evil in absolute terms, and that evil is an emergent property that
grows out of a particular context, dependent also on the mind-state of the person(s) in
question [18]. Stressing the important role played by our free will – by which we may choose
to turn away from God’s loving desire (and thus commit evil acts), Loyola lays less emphasis
22 PROLEGOMENA (FIRST ISSUES)
on God as omnipotent and all-good, which so bedeviled, or rather confounded, those who
grappled with theodicy. Similar views were expressed by Loyola’s contemporary, Juan Luis
Vives [19]. As a Jew who converted to Catholicism under the impact of the Spanish
Inquisition, Vives was perhaps more ready to think along less conventional paths, con-
tending that the Will is essentially spontaneous (and not always subject to Reason), and is at
liberty to choose to do evil things as well as good things, God notwithstanding.
1.1.7 THEOLOGIANS AND PHILOSOPHERS OF THE
RENAISSANCE AND ENLIGHTENMENT
Among the prominent theologians and philosophers of the sixteenth through the nineteenth
centuries, the subject of evil is treated more and more as a human affair, with God or the
Devil playing less active roles from the standpoint of causation. There is an increasing
tendency to picture God in a more abstract, less anthropomorphic, manner. Most of the
philosophers are believers; many come from families where the father was a clergyman. But
the dominant explanation concerning the origin of evil relies on concept of free will, albeit a
free will that was granted us by the deity.
The German Protestant religious mystic, Jacob Boehme [1575–1624] argued, in a
way that would have been considered quite heretical earlier, that God was ‘underneath’
rather than ‘above.’ In what amounts to a prelibation of Spinoza’s philosophy, Boehme
stated that Nature rises out of God, and that we ‘sink into him’ [20]. He also posited two
triads of forces, one of which was composed of the elements: Soul, Body & Spirit –
corresponding to which are Good, Evil, and Free Will. In his later writings Boehme
envisioned evil as the direct outcome of the wrathful side of God, adding that the object
of the world’s life and history was to exhibit the eternal victory of Good over Evil; Love
over Wrath.
For Thomas Hobbes [1588–1679], the son of a Protestant vicar, God was one Substance,
of which there could be more than one Persons (or Representatives), such as Moses, or later,
His own Son, Christ ([21], p. 520). But Hobbes’ comments on Good and Evil reflect his
sociological/political understanding of these attributes. Portraying human life as involving a
universal desire for self-preservation, Hobbes argued that because Man is in the state of
nature anarchic and greedy, a social or civil order soon evolves – as a means of avoiding a
war of all against all. In his famous comment about our life as ‘solitary, poore, nasty, brutish
and short’ ([21], p. 186), Hobbes states that the remedy for this is the appointment of a
sovereign, who saw to it that men exchanged a degree of personal freedom in return for
personal safety. Good, Evil, and Justice had no meaning, in Hobbes’ schema, until men
curbed their desires and entered into a social pact ([21], Ch. XIII).
The comments on evil of Descartes [1596–1650] resemble those of Vives: in his De
Passionibus he asserted that ‘All good and evil in this life depend on the Passions alone’
[CCXII] . For Descartes the passions (we would call them the emotions) are the products of
Nature; their use is to contribute to actions that preserve or improve the body. Yet the Will
must at times oppose the Passions with ‘...firm and determined judgments touching the
knowledge of Good and Evil, according to which the Soul has resolved to conduct its
actions’ [CXXXVII]. What Descartes does not make clear is how we know what is Good and
what is Evil to begin with.
Sometimes called the last of the medievalists, Baruch Spinoza [1632–77] had a
conception of evil as identified, in neo-Platonic language, with privation or ‘absences
1.1 EVIL IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE 23
which express no essence.’ He also thought of God in a way reminiscent of Boehme: God is
‘immanent in the world’ and individual things are themselves modes or modifications of
God. The one reality is ‘God or Nature’ [23, 24]. This equation of God with Nature earned
for Spinoza an excommunication from his Jewish coreligionists, but also later even from the
Calvinists – both groups regarding such an unexalted view of God as heretical. Spinoza
argued, in regard to evil, that there is no evil in the nature of things: the same object may be
good in one set of circumstances and evil in another. Whatever advances man toward a more
perfect nature is a true good; evil could be seen as a criticism of God’s goodness. A
`propos
free will, we may know a thing to be (good or) bad, yet not find in ourselves thepower either
to do the good or to abstain from the bad.
In the same way that Spinoza’s family fled to Holland to avoid religious persecution,
Pierre Bayle [1647–1706], the son of an impoverished Calvinist minister in southern
France, fled to Holland – because of his unconventional ideas that ran counter to the
Catholicism of Louis XIV. Picking up where Epicurus left off two millennia before, Bayle
contended that it cannot be the case that Evil exists and that God is both omnipotent and
benevolent [25], for if God were both willing and able to remove Evil, then where does
Evil come from? To strengthen his point (meanwhile alienating the religious orthodoxy of
his day), Bayle challenged the accepted wisdom that belief in divine reward promotes
morality – given that many religious believers are not deterred from evil acts, including
cruel and destructive behaviors, whereas many atheists are not immoral, even though they
standinnofearofdivineretributionfortheir non-belief. Instead, as Bayle emphasized,
people’s conduct is determined primarily by secular sanction and by character structure:
those who are cruel will act cruelly, whether or not they believe in God or the Hereafter.
People who are kind will distance themselves from cruelty, even if they do not believe in
divine punishment [26].
Bayle’s contemporary, the Baron Gottfried von Leibniz [1646–1716] is known more for his
co-invention of the calculus than for his theodicy [27]. Bayle, the incurable pessimist, viewed a
God who could have made a world where therewere fewer crimes and sufferings – yet chose not
to do so – as something of a criminal on a grand scale. Leibniz, the incurable optimist, argued
that, au contraire, this was the best world that could have been created; any alternative world
would have been worse – a view savaged by Voltaire in his famous parody, Candide. Leibniz
did define three categories of Evil; namely, the metaphysical, the physical, and the moral. The
‘metaphysical’ related to the degeneration inherent in the substance of which the world was
made (since only God is perfect). The ‘physical’ concerned the pain and suffering we experience
in the world, whilst ‘moral’ evil amounts to the crime – for which physical (or ‘natural’) evil is
the punishment. It was this latter notion that came in for Voltaire’s ridicule: how, for example,
were the 60,000 victims in Lisbon on that fateful day in November, 1755 – any more ‘deserving’
of the earthquake than were the citizens of some other city? The Lisbon earthquake was in fact a
turning point, much as the Holocaust or 9/11 in our day, that forced men to rethink the concept of
evil, and to rid themselves of the idea that natural disasters were somehow or another ’God’s
punishment’ for our sins. As Voltaire wrote, with timeless eloquence:
What crime, what sin, had those young hearts conceived
That lie, bleeding and torn, on mother’s breast?
Did fallen Lisbon deeper drink of vice
Than London, Paris, or sunlit Madrid?
—(from Poem on the Lisbon Disaster [28])
24 PROLEGOMENA (FIRST ISSUES)
In Bayle and Leibniz we have the paradox of two men, both Protestant, both born within a
year of each other: one still wedded (though not exclusively) to the metaphysical view of
evil; the other, rejecting the metaphysical in favor of a more down-to-earth (and down to the
individual person) conception. Perhaps the answer lay in the fact that Bayle was poor and
was exiled; Leibniz was rich and honored in his own country.
The empiricist Scottish philosopher, David Hume [1711–76], though raised in a Calvinist
background, removed God from the equation concerning good and evil, claiming that what
ought, and what ought not, to be the case cannot legitimately be derived from the ideas of a
deity. He argued against the notion that Reason alone enables us to make moral distinctions.
Rather: morality is concerned with such non-ideational entities as Passions, Volitions, and
Actions. It is only when we are able to attend to our own feelings that we are able to
distinguish Virtue and Vice; between moral good and evil [29].
In the same way that Bayle and Leibniz emerge at the conceptual antipodes regarding the
origins of evil, the postulates of Jean-Jacques Rousseau [1712–88] are diametrically
opposite, regarding the original state of man, to those of Thomas Hobbes. In his Second
Discourse (1762) Rousseau claimed that the human condition derives from society, whereas
in the ‘state of Nature’ Man was free and independent, healthy, happy, and innocent. Once a
social condition develops, there was, Rousseau supposed, a fall from Nature, and with it a
corruption of the once ‘noble savage.’ Here Rousseau was mistaken, for there is not a shred
of anthropological evidence to support his claim. But there was certain grandeur to his error:
scientifically mistaken, but politically correct – for his time. It was not hard to see evils
(social evils, in this case) in Rousseau’s France, on the cusp of the up-coming revolution – if
one contrasted the lot of the common man with that of the aristocracy. Hobbes may have
been right about society in general, but Rousseau was right about the society in particular
with which he was familiar. At all events, Rousseau deserved great credit, as Susan Neiman
pointed out ([30], p. 41), for being the first to treat the problem of evil as a philosophical (one
might even say, sociological), as opposed to a theological problem. Rousseau took the
problem out of God’s hands and ‘put it squarely in ours’ ([30], p. 43). Evil did not require
reference to supernatural forces, which meant in effect that evil is not a metaphysical
problem; it is a human problem.
Immanuel Kant [1724–1804] also rejected the notion of Original Sin –as an affront to our
moral freedom [31], but retained a place for religion, given that religion underlines our duty
to uphold moral values as divine commands. Christianity focuses on pride as the primary sin,
which Kant regarded as ineradicable by human means. Kant distinguishes between self-
conceit (Eigendunkel) and Self-Love (Eigenliebe), as the latter can be good insofar as it is
controlled by ‘practical reason.’ He understood the evil that arises in the human heart as
stemming from the subordination of what he called the Objective Law of Duty to (mere)
happiness. Evil becomes one of the choices open to us via our free will. Man has a propensity
[Hang] to evil (akin to Maimonides’ yetzer ha-ra), which must be combated through our
becoming our own ‘moral sentries.’ Kant made a distinction between B
ose [evil] and U
¨bel
[bad, though it is the cognate for the English word evil]: evil actions are those which aim at
the violation of the humanity of another person (such as murder, rape, torture). Whereas bad
actions are those that might be harmful or disagreeable to one’s general well-being (e.g.,
delayed payment of a debt or failure to honor some other type of promise). While neither
Kant nor other philosophers give detailed descriptions of individual case-histories em-
bodying evil actions, he was aware that terrible crimes occurred, and remarked that ’great
crimes are paroxysms, the sight of which makes one whose soul is healthy to shudder’ [32].
1.1 EVIL IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE 25
Here is a comment that presages our contemporary, more emotional, use of the word evil,as
pertaining to acts that are (to those who witness or experience them) breathtakingly
inhuman.
Georg Hegel [1770–1831] became famous for his dialectic triad of thesis, antithesis, and
synthesis – inspired in part by the French Revolution. Hegel felt the latter movement could
be understood as a burst into freedom for the masses (thesis), that then ushered in a reign of
terror (antithesis) that led finally to a better post-revolutionary form of government based on
freedom and equality (synthesis). As for his comments on evil, these are mostly to be found
in his Philosophie des Rechts [33] – the German word conveying the meanings both of
‘right’ and ‘law.’ Hegel sought to establish a groundwork for morality centered on each
person’s free will and humanity – within the context of our life as members, inevitably, of a
social entity. The social entity, in turn, needed to be regulated by a superordinate morality,
which for Kant (more so than for Hegel) necessitated the acceptance of God as the
embodiment of that higher morality. What makes a person evil in Hegel’s view is the
choosing of natural desires in opposition to the good ([33], section 40). Though Hegel does
not give ‘case histories’ of evil, he does assert that there is an important distinction between
crimes that attack the entire manifestation of one’s Will (i.e., of another person’s freedom
and humanity), as in the instance of murder, slavery, or religious compulsion – in contrast to
lesser crimes that invade less of the life-space of another person [34]. As for the matter of
‘free will,’ it is noteworthy that Hegel felt that the success of America (along with England
and France) in the nineteenth century related in large part to the large numbers of Protestant
dissenters who ‘created a tradition for a people who aspired to create libertarian societies’
([35], p. 172). The point here is that the dissenters exercised greater freedom to think for
themselves and to stress their individuality – in contrast to those who adhered to monolithic
systems of thought and belief, like the Catholics and Muslims.
For Arthur Schopenhauer [1788–1860], irritable, embittered, pessimistic, this was, in his
180turn from Leibniz, the worst of all possible worlds – where pleasure was the exception
in human life; pain, the rule. As he concluded in his most important work, Die Welt als Wille
und Vorstellung ([36] The World as Will and Representation), the Will isequated with effort
and desire, which is ultimately painful and ‘evil.’ Pain arises from the desire to have – and
then not having. After a brief satisfaction with one’s desire there is momentary pleasure –
and then the emergence of new desire and new pain. Selfishness or egoism (narcissism, in
our language) was for Schopenhauer, universal: the egoist seeks his own advantage and is
ready to strike down those who oppose him. His Weltanschauung resonates in this way with
Hobbes’ ‘war of all against all.’ Schopenhauer recognized that the attachment to life that
characterizes all living forms makes understandable our horror in reaction to murder – as the
maximal violation of our inherent will-to-live. Toward the end of life Schopenhauer
embraced Buddhism, by virtue of its preaching deliverance from Self – unlike the egoist:
the malicious man who thinks only of himself.
The year before Schopenhauer’s death coincided with the publication of Darwin’s Origin
of Species. Darwin, though of course not a philosopher, gave new meaning to the kind of
existential struggle for survival alluded to by Hobbes and Schopenhauer. Putting this
struggle on a scientific footing for the first time, Darwin drew attention to natural selection.
Herbert Spencer five years later used the term ‘survival of the fittest.’ Some took this to mean
that brute force triumphed over weakness, applying the idea to our species as well as to the
other animals. But Darwin was not arguing that evil won out over the good, particularly as he
held that the ethical life (among men) is different from the life in (the rest of) Nature. It is the
26 PROLEGOMENA (FIRST ISSUES)
ethical life that brings us out of the state of all-against-all warfare and leads us to peace. In
our own generation it has become clear through the work of evolutionary psychiatry – that as
a group species we also harbor genes that promote compassion and altruistic behavior. As
James Wilson has put forward [37], we would not have survived as a species if we did not
possess, alongside our aggressive tendencies, other innate, gene-driven tendencies that
promote moral sentiments: sympathy, fairness, self-control, and (here, James cited Kant)
duty. Viewed in this light, evil can be seen as an exaggeration of our aggressive tendencies;
good – as a manifestation of our adherence to the moral sentiments outlined by Wilson. In
this schema religion no longer has any explanatory value vis-
a-vis evil, though it retains its
value as a promulgator and advocate of the moral sentiments by which our lives should be
guided.
Darwin’s new theory did not sweep away all at once the religion-based explanation for
evil. Søren Kierkegaard [1813–55], for example, though born after Darwin, died before the
Origin was published. Still ensconced within traditional Christianity, he understood sin as
rooted in Willing. Sin (and hence evil) occur when a person refrains from doing what is right
even though he understands what is right [38].
For Friedrich Nietzsche [1844–1900] God played no role in the causation of evil, which,
he argued, was to be understood in purely human terms. ‘Being evil’ was ‘being not moral,’
practicing immorality, resisting tradition – however reasonable or stupid tradition might be.
Nietzsche recognized that ‘harming the neighbor,’ however, was felt to be preeminently
harmful in all the moral laws of different ages ([39], #96). Though Nietzsche endorsed the
idea of the will to power as the basis of human nature (a view in sympathy with that of
Schopenhauer), he also spoke of ‘resentment’ as a key emotion in those whose quest for
power was denied them. This resentment, Nietzsche saw as resulting from the ‘corruption of
human nature’ that was encouraged by religion in general, specifically by Christianity ([40],
p. 262) – a pretty radical departure from beliefs of Nietzsche’s Lutheran father, grand-
fathers, and great-grandfather. His much-misunderstood concept of the U
¨bermensch
[‘Superman,’ or ‘Overman’) was totally unrelated to the notion, as hijacked by the Nazis,
of a superior race. Nietzsche’s U
¨bermensch was the creative artist who lives ‘beyond good
and evil’ (as popularly conceived): the powerful man, that is, who has mastered his passions
and risen above the mediocrity of everyday existence [41]. At all events, Nietzsche took the
concept of evil far away from the religion-based explanations (the theodicies of Leibniz and
others), adopting a much more relativistic notion of what constituted evil. Apart from
harming one’s neighbor, that is, certain acts or tendencies might be regarded as evil in one
culture or one context, but not so in another culture or context.
1.1.8 MODERN CONCEPTIONS OF EVIL. THE INFLUENCE
OF PSYCHIATRY & NEUROSCIENCE
During the last century the ways of defining and understanding evil have been left less in the
hands of theologians and philosophers; much more, in the hands of experts in psychology
and psychiatry, including those in the field of neuroscience. There has been increasing
recognition that evil is a purely human phenomenon, and that the place to look for its site and
origins is not in the heavens but in the human brain. Even the question ‘what is evil?’ is
recognized as an erroneous question, since it presupposes there is some ineffable substance
that corresponds to the substantive [i.e., the noun] ‘evil,’ or that there is some one-size-fits-
1.1 EVIL IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE 27
all definition that is universally acceptable. Instead, a more meaningful approach is to adopt
the standard proposed by the Austrian philosopher Wittgenstein [1889–1951], who took the
position that the meaning of a word is its usage [42]. Viewed in this light, we look to the
way in which people in ordinary life, as well as the ways in which journalists and others in
the media, employ this term. It turns out that we reserve the word ‘evil’ in everyday life
for actions that evoke the emotion of horror: acts that are breathtakingly horrible because
of the intense suffering to which the victims are subjected, the outrageousness of the
acts, their heinousness or depravity – especially if the acts were prompted by scheming
(malice aforethought) of a ‘diabolical’ nature (implying the intention to hurt in a particularly
cruel and sadistic manner). Thus, a man who kidnaps a child, whom he then violates
sexually, and afterwards strangles and dismembers – is readily identified as having
committed an evil act. And if he has committed a string of such acts over time, with every
intention of repeating such behavior if given the opportunity – people will often apply the
word evil to the man himself: he is an evil person. Perhaps the only philosopher to draw
attention to this way of thinking about evil: as that which is breathtakingly awful – is Susan
Neiman [30].
Persons who are apprehended by the authorities for having committed acts of these kinds
will usually be incarcerated in prisons or, if mental illness had been a key factor in the
commission of the act, will be mandated to a forensic hospital for observation and treatment.
In either situation, a forensic psychiatrist may be summoned to evaluate the offender – as to
whether he or she is mentally ill, or is instead in the grips of a personality disorder, such as
antisocial or psychopathic personality. It is uncommon for people to use the word evil in
reference to crimes (such as financial swindles) that do not involve violence or intense
psychological harm (as by extreme humiliation, subjugation, or unlawful imprisonment).
Furthermore, one seldom refers to a person as evil (in contrast to particular acts of violence),
unless the person has engaged habitually and for an extended period of time in acts of
unusual cruelty. Many men committing serial sexual homicide, and some repeat-rapists, fall
into this category, especially where there is an element of torture of the victim(s).
Descriptions of such persons can be found in numerous books and articles by forensic
psychiatrists and psychologists [43–46]. Buss, writing from the perspective of evolutionary
psychiatry, focuses on those brain mechanisms that subserve aggression and defense against
threats to one’s survival: mechanisms that under certain circumstances can operate in a
grossly exaggerated manner – leading to extreme acts of violence of the sort to which the
public will apply the label ‘evil.’ Egger, Stone, and Ward et al. enumerate the background
factors in men committing serial sexual homicide, some of whom subject their victims to
prolonged periods of torture, earning thereby the label of ‘evil person.’ The background
factors conducing to violence in general: genetic predisposition to psychopathy, parental
neglect or cruelty, hormonal factors, head injury with unconsciousness, drug abuse, etc. –
have been discussed in detail by Debra Niehoff [47]. In an outstanding book written by a
survivor of an attempted murder by an axe-wielding psychopath, Terri Jentz [48] defined as
an act of evil: ‘when an act ruptures all categories of comprehension’ (p. 516), elsewhere
describing her ‘belief in the existence of utter evil as a modern revision of Manicheanism,’
based on her study of gratuitous cruelty in the twentieth century (p. 512). Even more
poignantly is her comment about her would-be assassin, whose sadism was in no way
confined just to her and her friend (who was blinded by this axe wielder): ‘I was astonished at
the many searing memories this one man had ignited in so many people...Was this evil’s
strategy, to perform breathtakingly brutal acts that so shocked the nervous system and
28 PROLEGOMENA (FIRST ISSUES)
overwhelmed the brain that these traumatic events were not integrated into consciousness,
but left disturbing, damaged mosaics of unassimilated memories?’ (p. 509).
The inadvertent spokesman for the general public and its use of the word, Jentz has left us
with as accurate a depiction of evil as we are likely to find in the lay literature. In the
psychiatric literature the term evil occurs very seldom. Freud, when writing of his celebrated
case, the Wolf Man [49], mentions the patient’s dissatisfaction with God, leading to his own
strange theodicy, according to which: ’If He were almighty, then it was His fault that men
were evil, wicked and [that they] tormented others... He ought to have made them good;
He was responsible for all the wickedness’ (p. 62). In his Introductory Lectures [50] Freud
speaks of our dream-life – in which the Ego, freed from all ethical bonds, finds itself at one
with all the demands of sexual desire, even those which have been condemned by our ethical
upbringing; lusts we think of as remote from human nature show themselves.... These
censored wishes appear to rise up out of a positive Hell’ (p. 142).
A
`propos Freud, the interconnections between religious thought and the development of
his psychoanalytic theories are discernible, albeit subtle and complex. Among his ancestors
were rabbis and Hasids, but his father, Jakob, broke away from the stricter practices and
traditions of his forebears, while retaining great pride in his Jewish heritage and his
familiarity with Yiddish and Hebrew. Sigmund grew up still less familiar with Jewish
observance, though retaining throughout his life a ‘Judaism without religion’ ([51], p. 6).
Toward the end of his life, Freud wrote his controversial Moses and Monotheism – which
angered both observant Jews and Christians (as Spinoza had managed to do, years before,
with his equation of God with Nature). Freud likened Moses to the first Messiah, and saw
Christ as reborn as a resurrected Moses – transfigured as the Son in the place of his Father
([52], p. 114). Freud’s biographer, Peter Gay, tells us that Freud spoke with his friend, Lou
Andreas Salom
e in 1935, mentioning that ‘The figure of Moses ...had haunted him all his
life,’ adding that Freud had compared Jung to Joshua – ‘who would take possession of the
promised land of psychiatry while he, Freud, the Moses, was destined to glimpse it only
from afar’ ([52], p. 605). So far we have commented on Freud’s complex relationship to his
Jewish origins. But the impact of his religious background upon his practice of psychiatry is
less readily detectable. There is some fairly compelling evidence for a more direct influence,
however, in two related areas. Two of the ’pillars’ of psychoanalysis are free association and
dream analysis, both crystallizing in Freud’s mind in the 1890s. David Bakan [53] makes
the case that Freud’s exposure to the Hasidic and Kabbalistic background of his grand-
parents’ generation set the stage for his discovering the value of ‘free association’ as a
method of gaining access to deeper layers of reality. Freud may well have been aware, for
example, of his thirteenth-century coreligionist – the Spanish-Jewish mystic philosopher
from Saragossa: Abraham Abulafia. As part of his method of achieving a trance-like state in
which he felt in closer touch with God, by unsealing the soul and untying the knots which
bind it (Bakan, p. 76) was through the practice of k’fitsah [] – which meant jumping or
skipping from one thought to another, till he was able to escape the quotidian, and reach ever
more lofty and spiritual levels. Abulafia induced this state in himself in the quest of a
religious goal. Freud appears to have transformed this method in the quest of a psychiatric
goal; namely, that of gaining access to hidden layers in the psyche of his patients, with the
ultimate goal of liberating them from their neurotic conflicts. The second pillar – dream
analysis – represents an interest of long-standing in Jewish tradition, as noted in the Old
Testament story of Joseph (Genesis 41: 1–37), and in the Moreh Nevuchim (Guide to the
Perplexed) of Maimonides. But dream-interpretation before Freud tended, with a few
1.1 EVIL IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE 29
exceptions, to stereotyped and sterile; the results, unconvincing. Dream dictionaries were
popular, in which common dream elements were said to have certain specific meanings.
Aside from the genius of the poet, Pushkin, who gave his heroine, Tatyana, a dream which
had the effect of warning her against marrying the ‘gloomy and dangerous crank,’ Evgeny
Onegin (a full 60 years before Freud’s Traumdeutung/The Interpretation of Dreams) – there
was almost nothing in the earlier dream literature that hit upon the psychological meaning of
the dream, unique to each dreamer. It was Freud’s genius that paved the way to unlock these
highly individual meanings – via his patients’ own free associations to their dreams. Granted
there are culturally determined, rather common symbols: bottles are often female genitals;
snakes are often penises – but not always. In the dreams of one of my analytic patients from
many years ago snakes kept cropping up. From her associations it became clear the snakes
did not represent her boyfriend’s organ; instead, they led her to think about his sister – an
intrusive and highly critical woman who kept trying to interfere in their relationship. None
of the old dream-dictionaries would have led one to this conclusion.
The relationship of Carl Gustav Jung (1875–1961) to religion was quite different from
that of his erstwhile mentor, Freud. Jung’s father was a Swiss pastor; Jung himself
throughout his life was preoccupied with mystical themes, astrology, and spiritism (the
latter prompted by the spiritistic trances he witnessed in his 15-year-old maternal cousin,
Helene, when he was a young man). During his youth, Jung once saw an eighteenth-century
carriage, and imagined that he had a memory of it in a previous life ([54], p. 664). During the
period of the Great War, Jung became intrigued with Gnosticism, not only for its emphasis
on knowing, but on its interest in the problem of evil ([54], p. 719). Equally interested in
dreams as Freud was, Jung, once he became a psychiatrist, developed a different technique.
He took to writing his dreams down, then telling himself stories stimulated by the dream
images, and encouraging fantasies to arise in his mind, as an outgrowth of these mental
pictures. Next, Jung would draw the resulting images on paper. He began this practice in
1913. It was out of these exercises that his theory of archetypes emerged. He believed that
there existed a set of universal, primordial images – the archetypes – embedded in the
unconscious of every person. Various coincidences convinced Jung of this proposition, such
as the similarity of a hallucination (of a phallus suspended from the sun, that produced the
wind) mentioned to him by a schizophrenic patient – to an early Greek text that spoke of a
tube hanging from the sun that set the winds in motion ([54], p. 705). These impressions led
Jung to speak of a ’collective unconscious.’ He later used the terms collective subconscious
and then the objective psyche, by which he referred to what he believed was a reservoir of the
experiences of human beings as a species – by virtue of its being common to everyone.
Practitioners in contemporary psychoanalysis and psychiatry, apart from those who are
adherents to Jung’s psychology, do not accept the notion of a collective unconscious. There
is another concept that Jung developed that relates to the subject of evil. The set of personal
characteristics that a person wishes to conceal from others, even from himself, Jung called
the ‘shadow.’ Jung further postulated that the more someone tried to keep this shadow
hidden, the more the shadow becomes active, predisposing to evil actions. Further, Jung
imagined that the shadow could, especially under the influence of alcohol or other mind-
altering agents, become the predominant force in the individual, leading to hitherto
unsuspected levels of evil. Robert Louis Stevenson’s 1886 classic, Dr. Jekyll and Mr.
Hyde, may be understood as a parallel in novel-form to Jung’s shadow. Consistent with
Jung’s beliefs in archetypes, collective unconscious, shadows, and the like – is his religious
faith. Toward the end of his life, in a 1955 interview with a journalist, Jung stated that ‘God is
30 PROLEGOMENA (FIRST ISSUES)
the voice of conscience speaking within us,’ adding that he had an ‘unshakable conviction of
the existence of God...I do not take His existence on belief – I know that He exists’ ([54], p.
726). It is easy to see why Freud and Jung eventually parted ways, given that the religion-
based views of Jung, expressed rather in poetic than in scientific language, were quite alien
to Freud, who retained his biological foundation and his antipathy to organized religion to
the end, even while pursuing similar psychoanalytic pathways as did his younger counter-
part. Jung’s psychology, in this respect, offers analogies to whatever it is in us that leads to
evil action, but does not have the kind of explanatory value that would give it purchase in the
field of science, including in the domain of forensic psychiatry.
What contemporary psychiatry can now provide by way of explaining the phenomenon of
evil, as defined in popular usage – is the following: (a) commonalities can be discovered
when one looks at a large number of detailed case histories of persons whose acts have been
described as ‘evil,’ (b) study of the brain, via functional magnetic resonance imaging and
other techniques, can reveal differences in the brains of such persons, when compared with
the brains of ordinary persons. I refer here only to evil acts committed in peacetime, since it
is well known that in wartime many ordinary men suddenly find themselves capable of
cruelties which would be most foreign to their lives before and after their participation in
warfare.
As for the commonalities among persons with a penchant for committing evil acts, there
are two in particular that stand out. One group consists of serial killers intent upon torturing
their victims. From a diagnostic standpoint these persons (the vast majority of whom will be
men) exemplify the confluence of psychopathy and sadistic personality. The main person-
ality traits of the psychopath, as defined by Robert Hare and his colleagues [55] are glib
speech (insincerity), grandiosity, lying, manipulativeness, callousness, lack of empathy and
remorse, and inability to take responsibility for one’s actions. The main traits of sadistic
personality as outlined in DSM-III-R [56] consist in the enjoyment of another’s suffering,
humiliation, and subjugation of others [57]. Another group consists of persons, outside the
domain of serial homicide, who scheme (‘with malice aforethought’) to subject another to
extreme pain and/or death – as witnessed in the cases of certain men who stage the death of
their wives in order to make their deaths appear accidental, or who make plans to hide their
bodies in hopes of rendering their death an uncertainty (as in the case of Scott Peterson, who
killed his pregnant wife and threw her body into the ocean [58]).
Neuroscientists do not use the word evil in their reports, but considerable research has
recently been carried out on brain activity in persons whose violent crimes have inspired the
word evil in everyday discourse. Much of this research has been summarized in the book
about psychopathy of James Blair and his colleagues [59]. One common underlying factor
concerns brain-differences in psychopaths that diminish their capacity for empathy;
specifically, for feeling compassion for the suffering of others. Absent this capacity, the
possibility of inflicting torturous suffering on others becomes greatly enhanced. This is
reflected in the commission of acts that the public experiences as ‘evil.’ Specific regions of
the brain that communicate with one another in determining what behaviors emerge in
response to particular urges or stresses have been outlined by Kalivas and Volkow [60] in
their paper on pathways relevant to addiction. Their model is pertinent as well to other
maladaptive behaviors, including those related to violent crime. The key regions in this
schema involve a memory system, subserved by the amygdala, in touch with prior
experiences (including those of harm done to the individual by early caretakers). This
region communicates with another – the dopamine-dependent nucleus accumbens – that
1.1 EVIL IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE 31
weighs the salience (degree of desirability) of various behavioral options. Both these
regions are important parts of what is often called the ‘bottom-up’ brain mechanisms, and
concern our basic drives [61]. Final decisions regarding action (that is, what we actually end
up doing in any given situation) are the function of the ‘top-down’ mechanisms. A control-
mechanism mediated by the anterior cingulate gyrus exerts either a weak or a strong control
upon the various options being considered. Finally the orbitofrontal cortex, integrating all
this information, either allows the most favored option to go forward into actual behavior –
or decides against it, thwarting the behavior. A man struggling with the temptation to kid-
nap and rape a child (which would end up as an evil act, if consummated) may think of
how that child might feel, or might think about the consequences of getting caught and
arrested – and then decide against this ‘desired’ behavior. Or his desire may be so strong as
to override the ’braking’ mechanisms; his impulse-control may be so weak as to fail to
inhibit the behavior. In these scenarios, the crime (the ‘evil’ act) will occur.
As I mentioned at the beginning of the chapter, judgments about which acts are
considered evil are made more easily in peacetime – by individuals and by the public –
than is the case in situations of group conflict (as in riots or between gangs) or of full-scale
war. The witness of inter-group strife, so characteristic of our species, reminds us of our
origins as members of small tribes numbering perhaps 100 or 150 persons. Our brains have
evolved over the approximately four million years since we split off from bonobos and
chimpanzees to become hominids, gradually emerging as what Carl Zimmer has cleverly
called (because we can talk and read) the gossiping ape [62]. To meet the multitudinous
threats to survival in our early days, our brains became ‘wired’ for group affiliation and for
aggressive defense against those who would harm us—whether the predators were saber-
tooth tigers or (more commonly) other people. Religion sprung up in every human society,
presumably answering to vital needs and impulses peculiar to a distinctly social species such
as our own. We cannot do without each other, and (all too often) we cannot get along with
one another – especially when goods necessary to survival are scarce and when the
conditions that make life secure and comfortable are seriously compromised. During times
of adversity religion can play contrary roles: religion unifies and strengthens the bonds
among members of a religious group, offering hope, and emboldening group action that
fosters survival. But therein lay the rub. For at such times, religion may be used by one group
to rally forces against a competing group, fomenting a war that is justified (in the eyes of the
adherents of the warring group) against those who do not believe in the ‘true God’ of the
group that has taken up arms. This conceit – that God stands behind only our group – helps
explain the paradoxical situation in which the monotheistic Abrahamic religions, quickly
separate into tribes (albeit large ones) in times of trouble. The followers of Jehovah, Christ,
and Allah are suddenly at each other’s throats. This phenomenon becomes particularly acute
during times of drastic change or drastic shortage. If the crisis is local, we see the emergence
of religious cults, some of which are led by fanatics of remarkable cruelty. The Reverend Jim
Jones in Guyana, David Koresh in Waco, Texas, and Jeff Lundgren, the breakaway Mormon
leader in Kirtland, Ohio are examples. If the crisis involves whole nations or religious
memberships, we see the emergence of religious armies, with a charismatic leader at the
helm, poised to conquer another group or nation. If the army is strong, there will be war; if it
is too weak to conquer outright, there will be terrorism. The red thread running through all
these religion-inspired actions is fundamentalism. Two chief characteristics of such
fundamentalism, as mentioned by Vamik Volkan in a recent address on psychoanalysis
and religion [63], are a list of unchangeable doctrines adhered to by the believers, and their
32 PROLEGOMENA (FIRST ISSUES)
opposition to non-believers or to ‘lukewarm’ believers. By no means is fundamentalism
regularly associated with violence. But under particular circumstances a group of believers
may be energized by a charismatic and hate-filled leader, such that religious fundamental-
ism becomes the force by which violence is unleashed. Kernberg [64] made the point, in the
immediate aftermath of 9/11, that the internal tensions of the jihadists (bemoaning the
decline of Islam since the defeat in 1683 at the gates of Vienna, and the relative
impoverishment in Dar al-Islam (the countries where Islam is the dominant religion)
compared with the Western industrialist countries – are now displaced toward the outside,
toward, that is, the ‘infidel’ West. Volkan has striven to create a bridge between the
psychology of the individual, as emphasized in traditional psychoanalysis, and the
psychology of the group – stressing how children are raised as fledgling members of a
social group – with which they strongly identify, at the same time they develop, during the
same formative years, a sense of personal identity. The admonitions and information
imparted to children in their first half dozen years, creating both the individual and the group
identities, become ‘hard-wired’ into brain circuitry, fostering automatic, unconscious
responses. In certain groups, these responses may include such convictions as we the
faithful of religion X are better than you people of religion Y and we are thus, through God’s
favor, more deserving of the good things of the world than you...Like all thought-habits of
long standing, these automatic responses are not easily overturned. The topic of religious
fundamentalism and its psychology has been previously explored by Ren
e Girard [65] and
summarized recently in the admirable article by Lord Alderdice of Northern Ireland [66].
Alderdice makes the point that the jihadist terrorists that figure so prominently in the current
geopolitical scene are heavily indoctrinated, but are not mentally ill. The fundamentalist
environment in which they were enveloped was one that predisposed to violent solutions.
Many were educated in madrassas, memorizing the Qur’an, with its many references to the
infidel and to the dire fate that awaited them (as in the long passage in Sura 5: 35–66).
Saturated in a Good/Believer versus Evil/Infidel atmosphere, the step toward violence,
when under the influence of a paranoid leader during socially disruptive times – is not a long
one. One may note in contrast that in the Old Testament ‘infidel’ does not occur; the word is
used in the New Testament just twice (2 Corinthians 6:15, and 1 Timothy 5:8). In neither
reference is the (Christian) believer abjured to harm or to kill the infidel; merely to avoid
association with the infidel.
Psychiatry, as it turns out, has much of value in helping us to understand the mind-set of
fundamentalists, as well as of those who become terrorists. But psychiatrists at the
vanguard in this arena, such as Jerrold Post [67], Vamik Volkan, Otto Kernberg, John
Alderdice, and also the historian-philosopher, Ren
e Girard, convey their excellent points
to like-minded audiences; in effect, they preach to the converted. The fundamentalists, and
the terrorists among them, do not listen. The most militant and disaffected among them
continue to regard those who disagree with them as infidels and evil-doers. We are then apt
to see a perversion of religion: religious leaders sanction actions that, ironically, the rest of
the world regard as evil. Examples are legion: the Protestants and Catholics in Northern
Ireland bombing each other’s houses, the Sunnis and the Shiites in Iraq bombing each
other’s mosques, Hindus and Moslems in India destroying each other’s holy places, the
jihadists bombing the Twin Towers and cafes in Tel-Aviv, or slitting the throat of journalist
Daniel Pearl in Karachi (February 1st, 2002) – because he was a Jew. The date is of interest
to me: I was in Karachi 20 years earlier to the day, living as a Jewish psychiatrist in the
home of Moslem psychiatrist colleagues, lecturing on my topic of ’borderline personality,’
1.1 EVIL IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE 33
and attending many Moslem weddings. It was a different time. When religion is hijacked
and made into a pretext for war and atrocities, we may, as psychiatrists, correctly diagnose
that calamity as a sign that a large group of people has come to feel humiliated,
disenfranchised, dealt out of the chance to have the good things of life: dignity, adequate
food, satisfactory work, the pursuit of happiness. Military action may be necessary as an
unfortunate first step. Ultimately the excesses of fundamentalism, and the terrorism it may
spawn, can be corrected only politically: by helping in whatever way possible to improve
the lives of the group whose cause was spearheaded (literally) in the first place by the
fundamentalists and their terrorist cohorts. In this great task, psychiatry can play only an
advisory role, helping to educate political leaders as to what the social ‘disease’ had been,
and what might be its most likely cure. Equally important as an antidote to religious
fundamentalism, when it has gotten out of hand, is the voice of the ‘lukewarm’ believers,
the moderates, who show, instead of paranoid hatred and fanaticism, tolerance and the
warm acceptance of others. More such voices are beginning to be heard. An outstanding
example is that of the Moslem writer, Irshad Manji. She has shown the courage to criticize
the jihadists within Islam in her widely read The Trouble with Islam Today [68]. And
Salman Rushdie has outlived the fatwa leveled against him by Ayatollah Khomeini. I was
privileged to hear Rushdie address a large audience two years ago, where he could speak
freely, and where it was not even necessary for the public to pass through metal detectors.
There is hope.
In summary, religion and philosophy no longer have a meaningful role in explaining the
causes of evil, though they of course retain an important role in setting forth theguidelines for
appropriate moral values and acceptable behaviors. For clues concerning causation, we must
turn instead to psychiatry, psychology, and neuroscience. Age-old conundrums as to whether
humans are inherently good or inherently evil fall by the wayside, as we become aware that our
genetic givens and our brains are equipped with the mechanisms for both altruistic/
cooperative interactions – and for narcissistic or aggressive interactions. This position was
already championed long ago by the Moslem empiricist historian of culture – ibn Khaldun
[1332–1406]. Unhappy with the abstract and metaphysical arguments of theologians and
philosophers, ibn Khaldun relied on what he could actually observe in societies. He
recognized that ‘evil qualities’ existed in man – such as injustice and aggression, which
were ’natural’ to human beings, yet compassion and affection were also part of our human
nature – in such measure that we were more inclined to the good than to the bad [69, 70].
Which behaviors are favored, as we now realize, are dependent upon a host of factors:
heredity, constitution, gender, early rearing, culture, brain damage, involvement with drugs
that lower impulse-control, etc. When aggressive actions pass a certain socially-acknowl-
edged boundary-line and pass into the grotesque and the heinous, we have entered the realm of
evil. As one of their functions, religion and philosophy deplore such actions. To understand
evil actions – is the domain of sciences that explore the workings of the human brain.
REFERENCES
1. Scharfstein B-A (1998) A Comparative History of World Philosophy. Albany, NY: State
University of New York Press.
2. Boyce M (1984). Textual Sources for the Study of Zoroastrianism. Chicago: Chicago University
Press.
34 PROLEGOMENA (FIRST ISSUES)
3. Forsyth N (2002). The Origin of Evil. Perspectives on Evil 1: 17–52.
4. Williams JN (1988) Confucius, Mencius, and the notion of the true succession. Philosophy East &
West 38, 157.
5. Plato (1973) Phædrus & Letters VII and VIII. Walter Hamilton, tr. London: Penguin Books.
6. Aristotle (1955) Nicomachean Ethics. JAK Thomson, tr. London: Penguin Books.
7. Mendelson M (2000) St. Augustine. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
8. Augustine St Aurelius (2007) Confessions. AC Outler & M Vessey, trs. New York: Barnes &
Noble Classics.
9. Butterworth CE (2007) Ethical and political philosophy. In The Cambridge Companion to Arabic
Philosophy. PAdamson & RC Taylor (editors), 4th edit. New York: Cambridge University Press,
pp. 266–286.
10. Goodman LE www.muslimphilosophy.com/ei2/razi.htm.
11. Fakhry M (2002) Al-F
ar
abi: Founders of Islamic Neoplatonism. Oxford: One World.
12. Rizvi SH (2006) Avicenna/IbnSina. www.iep.utm.edu/a/avicenna.htm.
13. Fakhry M (2004) A History of Islamic Philosophy. 3rd edn. New York: Columbia University
Press.
14. Durling RM Translator & Editor (1996): The Divine Comedy of Dante Alighieri: vol. I:
The Inferno. New York: Oxford University Press.
15. Seeskin K (2000) Searching for a Distant God: The Legacy of Maimonides. New York: Oxford
University Press.
16. Maimonides (1956) A Guide for the Perplexed. M Friedlander, tr. New York: Dover Press.
17. Oesterle JA & JT (1995) On Evil: St. Thomas Aquinas. Notre Dame, Indiana: Univ of Notre Dame
Press.
18. Loyola St. Ignatius (1997) Personal Writings. JA Munitiz, ed. & tr. New York: Penguin Books.
19. Vives JL (1538/1553) De Anima et Vita. Basel: Johann Oporinus.
20. Boehme J (1648) Concerning the Three Principles of the Divine Essence. J Sparrow, tr. London:
H. Blunden [reprinted: KessingerPublishing].
21. Hobbes T (1651/1968) Leviathan. CB Macpherson, editor. London: Penguin Books.
22. Descartes R (1650) De Passionibus. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
23. Spinoza B (1989) Tractatus Theologico-Politicus. S Shirley, tr. Leiden: Brill.
24. Spinoza B (2000) Ethics. G. H. R. Parkinson, ed. & tr. New York: Oxford University Press.
25. Bayle P (1697/1991) Historical and Critical Dictionary. RH Popkin, tr. Indianapolis, Indiana:
Hackett Publishing Company.
26. Edwards P (2003) Pierre Bayle: 1647-1706. Free Inquiry 23 (summer issue): 55ff.
27. Leibniz GW (1988). Theodicy. AM Farrar, ed.; EM Huggard, tr. Chicago, Illinois: Open Court
Publishing.
28. Voltaire FMA (1756/1994) Poem on the Lisbon Disaster. In– A Treatise on Toleration and Other
Essays. Amherst, New York: Prometheus Press.
29. Hume D (1740/2000) A Treatise on Human Nature. DF & MJ Norton, eds. Oxford, UK: Oxford
University Press.
30. Neiman S (2002) Evil in Modern Thought. Princeton, New Jersey: University of Princeton Press.
31. Lilla M (1998). Kant’s theological-political revolution. Review of Metaphysics 52: 397ff.
32. Garcis EV (2002). A Kantian theory of evil. The Monist 85: 194ff.
33. Hegel GWF (1821/1952) The Philosophy of Right. TM Knox, tr. New York: Oxford University
Press.
34. Rayburn HA (1921) The Ethical Theory of Hegel: A Study of the Philosophy of Right. Oxford,
UK: Clarendon Press.
35. Harris L (2007) The Suicide of Reason: Radical Islam’s Threat to the West. New York: Basic
Books.
36. Schopenhauer A (1819–1859/1966) The World as Will and Representation. 2 vols. EFJ Payne, tr.
New York: Dover Publications.
1.1 EVIL IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE 35
37. Wilson JQ (1993) The Moral Sense. New York: The Free Press/Macmillan.
38. Kierkegaard S (1849/1980) Sygdommen til Døden (Sickness unto Death). A Hanny, tr. London:
Penguin Books.
39. Nietzsche FW (1878) Human, All Too Human. RJ Hollingdale, tr. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
40. Blackburn S (1994) The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.
41. Nietzsche FW (1887/1966) Jenseits von Gut und B
ose (Beyond Good and Evil). W Kaufman, tr.
New York: Randon House/Vintage Books.
42. Wittgenstein L (1953) Philosophical Investigations. GEM Anscombe, tr. Oxford, UK: Basil
Blackwell.
43. Buss D (2005) The Murderer Next Door: Why the Mind is Designed to Kill. New York: Penguin
Books.
44. Egger SA (2002) The Killers Among Us: An Examination of Serial Murder and its Investigation.
Upper Saddle River, New Jersey: Prentice Hall.
45. Stone MH (2001) Serial sexual homicide: Biological, psychological and sociological aspects.
Journal of Personality Disorders 15, 1–18.
46. Ward T, Polaschek DLL, & Beech AR (2006) Theories of Sexual Offending. Chichester, UK: John
Wiley & Sons.
47. Niehoff D (1998) The Biology of Violence. New York: The Free Press.
48. Jentz T (2006) Strange Piece of Paradise. New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux.
49. Freud S (1918). From the History of an Infantile Neurosis. S. E. XVII, pp. 3–122. London:
The Hogarth Press.
50. Freud S (1916). Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis. S. E. XV. London: Hogarth Press.
51. Gay P (1988) Freud: A Life for Our Time. New York: W.W. Norton.
52. Freud S (1938) Moses and Monotheism. S. E. XXIII, pp. 3–137.
53. Bakan, D. (1990) Sigmund Freud and the Jewish Mystical Tradition. London: Free Association
Books.
54. Ellenberger HF (1970) The Discovery of the Unconscious: The History and Evolution of Dynamic
Psychiatry. New York: Basic Books.
55. Hare RD, Harpur TJ, Hakstian AR, Forth AE & Hart SD (1990). The Revised Psychopathy
Checklist: Reliability and factor structure. Psychol. Assessment 2: 338–341.
56. Diagnostic & Statistical Manual of Psychiatric Disorders, 3rd edn., revised [DSM-III-R] (1987).
Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Press.
57. Stone MH, Butler J & Young K (2009) Sadistic Personality. In: Blaney PH & Millon T (eds.)
Oxford Textbook of Psychopathology, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, New York,
pp. 651–670.
58. Linedecker C (2003) The Murder of Laci Peterson. DesMoines, Iowa: America Media Inc.
59. Blair J, Mitchell D & Blair K (2006). The Psychopath: Emotion and the Brain. Malden,
Massachusetts: Blackwell Publishing.
60. Kalivas PW & Volkow ND (2005). The neural basis of addiction: A pathology of motivation and
choice. Amer J Psychiatry 162: 1403–1413.
61. Siever LJ (2008) Neurobiology of aggression and violence. American Journal of Psychiatry 165,
429–442.
62. Zimmer C (2001) Evolution: The Triumph of an Idea. New York: Harper Collins.
63. Volkan V Psychoanalysis and Religion. (Power-Point presentation: www.acopsa.org/acopsa_
assets/ReligiousFundamentalismandViolenceDD.pdf).
64. Kernberg OF (2001) The psychology of religious fundamentalist ideologies. Presented at the
New York Academy of Medicine, October 30th.
65. Girard R (1972). Violence and the Sacred. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins Press.
66. Alderdice John Lord (2008) On the psychology of religious fundamentalism. www.
medicalnewstoday.com/articles/113876.php.
36 PROLEGOMENA (FIRST ISSUES)
67. Post JM (2007) The Mind of a Terrorist: The Psychology of Terrorism from the IRA to al-Qaeda.
New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
68. Manji I (2005) The Trouble with Islam Today. New York: St. Martin’s Press.
69. Ibn Khaldun (1967) The Muqaddimah: An Introduction to History. F Rosenthal, tr.; NJ Dawood,
ed. Princeton, New Jersey: Bollinger Series/Princeton University Press.
70. Baali F (1988) Society, State, and Urbanism: Ibn Khaldun’s Sociological Thought. Albany,
New York: State University of New York Press.
71. Aquinas St. Thomas (2002) Summa Theloogica [shorter version]. C Vollert, tr. Manchester,
New Hampshire: Sophia Institute Press.
72. Steel C (1994) Does evil have a cause? Augustine’s perplexity and Thomas’s answer. The Review
of Metaphysics 48, 251–273.
1.1 EVIL IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE 37
... Today the situation is entirely different in many settings, transcending the classic Freudian hypothesis that religion is nothing but a neurotic defense mechanism (Freud 1907(Freud /1961; see also Pargament 2002). We have been witnessing the emergence of new bridges between religion and psychiatry, as illustrated in a recent handbook published by the Religion, Spirituality and Psychiatry Section of the World Psychiatric Association (Verhagen et al. 2010). The field of social and clinical psychology has gained a leading role to discover the roots of spirituality and formulate a positive framework even for severe psychological problems (Clark 2010;Gale et al. 2014). ...
Article
Full-text available
This paper explores the relationship among schizophrenia, spirituality, and Christian religiosity. We interviewed 120 patients with schizophrenia and 120 control individuals (74.2 % of individuals with self-reported Christian religions). Patients with schizophrenia showed increases in positive spirituality and decreases in positive congregational support, as measured by the Brief Multidimensional Measure of Religiousness/Spirituality. There was no significant difference in Christian religiosity. Higher positive spirituality was predicted by more severe self-disorder, perceptual disorder, and positive clinical symptoms. Schizophrenia patients with religious delusions did not exhibit enhanced Christian beliefs and rituals. These results do not confirm the hypothesis of general hyper-religiosity in schizophrenia.
... For centuries, the names given to epilepsy in medical terminology by different cultures have been an indication of the believed relationship between the disease and the supernatural. The holy illness, the divine illness, the falling sickness, the disease created by God, the heavenly illness, the shaking punishment from God, the illness passed on through witchcraft and magic, the star illness, morbus lunaticus (the moon-induced illness), among others have been used to designate epilepsy [1]. In Babylonia three millennia ago, the disease was attributed to possession of the sufferer by demons or ghosts [2]. ...
Article
ABSTRACT Despite increasing global awareness of mental health issues, understanding the perception and influences of depression remains limited within specific cultural contexts such as Southeast Nigeria. This study investigates how residents define and perceive depression, exploring socio-cultural, demographic, and religious factors that shape these perceptions. In-depth interviews were conducted with twenty participants (10 males and 10 females) from Anaocha and Idemili South Local Government Areas in Anambra State. Thematic analysis revealed that depression is perceived as a profound emotional and psychological burden, characterized by sadness, hopelessness, and isolation. Influential socio-cultural factors included beliefs in supernatural forces, traditional healing practices, gender norms, educational levels, and religious/spiritual practices. Stigma emerged as a significant barrier to help-seeking, with cultural expectations of resilience and reliance on religious coping mechanisms complicating the mental health landscape. The study proposes resilience-based interventions to enhance help-seeking behavior and support individuals with internalized stigma. These interventions by professional service providers such as social workers will increase mental health literacy, reduce stigma, and promote community resilience. Future research could also prioritize comparative studies across different regions to examine regional variations in depression perceptions and inform tailored interventions in social service delivery that effectively address local socio-cultural contexts, thereby advancing social research.
Thesis
Full-text available
A project based upon an independent investigation. http://hdl.handle.net/11020/24685 The spiritual and religious life of clients is an important clinical factor in therapy; it holds significant meaning and may support therapeutic outcome. This study explored client perceptions of the quality of care they received in therapy when disclosing their spiritual/religious life to their therapists as well as the factors that might contribute to their perceptions of care and disclosure. A total of 75 respondents participated in an online survey tool composed of quantitative and qualitative questions. Qualitative responses were coded and data was analyzed using descriptive statistics. Findings showed that most clients (73%) shared some or all of their beliefs; in contrast only 40% shared their spiritual or religious experiences. Almost all clients (80-90%) have had a significant spiritual/religious experience, most often describing a feeling of interconnection and well-being, a loss, gain, or change of faith, high intuition, and/or a sensory experience (auditory, visual, or tactile.) Fifty percent of clients who shared their beliefs with their therapists were satisfied or very satisfied with the care they received; 23% were somewhat satisfied or unsatisfied. Of clients who shared their experiences 38% were satisfied and less than 10% were somewhat satisfied or unsatisfied. A poor working alliance, misattuned responses, lack of engagement, and the therapist’s lack of knowledge on the subject were reasons for low levels of satisfaction. The study concludes with suggestions on how to improve the therapeutic quality of care for spiritual or religious clients.
Article
Full-text available
What are the therapeutic limitations of systemic psychotherapy when working with families who hold religious fundamentalist beliefs? At a time of debate about religious fundamentalism, terrorism and radicalisation, where do family therapists position themselves when confronted by extreme beliefs in the therapy room? Research suggests that the increase in modernity within our society equates not just with an increase in secularisation, but rather an increase in pluralism. Contemporary models of family therapy pay explicit attention to issues of gender, culture, ethnicity, discrimination and societal contexts. The author, therefore, proposes that family therapists need to examine their position regarding religious fundamentalism in relation to the social constructionist relativist continuum and engage with uncomfortable questions about whether they believe that fundamentalism has essentially pathological roots. This article will explore whether the dualist position within some religious movements set against a more secular psychotherapeutic and psychiatric cultural milieu can invite a fundamentalised response from clinicians. The author draws on her own work with families who hold religious fundamentalist beliefs and enquires about ethics, transparency and collaboration within family therapy practice. This article invites complex ongoing challenging questions and debate.
Article
Full-text available
There is no agreed definition of a mental health crisis; however, a useful one is ‘a situation where mental health has deteriorated to an extent that the user is likely to be at risk of harm to self or others and is in need of urgent intensive specialist support and treatment’ (Minghella et al , 1998). Community-based care is the primary model of specialist mental healthcare in Ireland (Government of Ireland, 2006 a ). When clinically indicated, a patient with mental health crisis is referred to the community mental health team (CMHT) for an urgent assessment.
Conference Paper
Full-text available
OBJECTIVE: Iron deficiency was suggested to play a role in the pathophysiology of attention deficit hyperactivity disorder (ADHD) due to the role of iron in the production of dopamine and noradrenaline. The aim of this study was to assess iron status in a sample of Egyptian children with ADHD. METHODs: Thirty children with ADHD (6-12 years old) and 15 age and sex matched controls were recruited. Subjects were evaluated using the Mini International Neuropsychiatric Interview for kids (mini-kid) and Conner's Parent Rating Scale - Revised (CPRS-R). Laboratory measures were also carried out to investigate iron status in all subjects including: complete blood count, serum iron, total iron binding capacity, and serum ferritin. RESULTS: Children with ADHD showed significantly lower levels of hemoglobin and serum ferritin as compared to control groups. A strong negative correlation was found between serum ferritin and ADHD total score and cognitive subscore but not with hyperactivity subscore. No significant differences were found between the two groups as regards other hematological data. CONCLUSIONS: Iron deficiency, with or without anemia, might play a role in pathogenesis of ADHD. Further work is needed to confirm the clinical utility of iron supplementation in the treatment of ADHD, especially in developing countries.
Book
Monotheism is usually considered Judaism's greatest contribution to world culture, but it is far from clear what monotheism is. This work examines the notion that monotheism is not so much a claim about the number of God as a claim about the nature of God. Seeskin argues that the idea of a God who is separate from his creation and unique is not just an abstraction but a suitable basis for worship. He examines this conclusion in the contexts of prayer, creation, sabbath observance, repentance, religious freedom, and love of God. Maimonides plays a central role in the argument both because of his importance to Jewish self-understanding and because he deals with the question of how philosophic ideas are embodied in religious ritual.
Article
A review of H. F. ELLENBERGER's book, The Discovery of the Unconscious, opens up this section. In this monumental work the author shows how the main schools of dynamic psychiatry over the past two centuries had their roots in the broad cultural movements of their time. A wide perspective of psychotherapeutic approaches ranging from faith healing to psychoanalysis is presented. J. ZUBIN highlights cultural factors regarding etiological models of schizophrenia and regarding the diagnosis of this illness. He comprehensively discusses emerging trends in descriptive psychopathology and cross-cultural studies. E. F. TORREY has provided us with a preview of his book, The Mind Game: Witchdoctors and Psychiatrists. Based on his experiences in several cultures he has identified com monalities in the activities of psychotherapists all over the world. He offers models based on his experiences with different ethnic groups for future mental health services for these groups and others. The last paper in this section concerns itself with the application of verbal psychological tests in translation for cross-cultural psychological or psychiatric purposes. K. GLATT compared differences in the responses to the MMPI in French, Spanish, and German translations (see also R. Prince and W. Mombour, Transcultural Psychiatric Research.
Book
This book’s aim is to enrich and deepen our psychological understanding of biblical concepts and personalities. Such understanding is relevant for theology as well as for psychology and psychiatry. It may help theologians to contextualize their discipline by bringing it into contact with contemporary psychological and existential issues and tensions, both at an individual and a societal level. It also encourages psychologists and psychiatrists to develop and refine their vocabularies when they try to comprehend the existential meaning of what is transmitted to them by their clients. The book highlights the concepts of prophecy, martyrdom, and messianism from Christian and Judaic perspectives. Each concept offers one biblical figure as representative: Jeremiah, Paul, and Jesus, respectively. The sections on these three subjects and personalities are sandwiched between a section on historical and conceptual issues, and a section devoted to select interdisciplinary issues. Biblical images of pain, anguish, suffering, hope, resentment, and awe are part of our cultural background and shape the way we understand our lives and sufferings. Biblical perspectives on human existence, on the other hand, differ in some important respects from modernist conceptions that prevail in psychotherapy and psychiatry. The book investigates the possibility of a theological criticism on common frameworks of psychological and psychiatric understanding of the inner world of the client. It also offers new ways to understand the ‘transformative’ power of religion.
Chapter
Until the late eighteenth century, religions, particularly in the West, were defined by their sacred texts and dogmatic formulations. Friedrich Schleiermacher, in the late eighteenth century, was one of the first scholars that attempted to define “religion” by switching from a doctrinal emphasis to a more cognitive, visceral, or intuitive one. Schleiermacher defined religion as a “feeling of absolute dependence.” Since his day most attempts at a general definition of religion have relied heavily on emphasizing the intuitive, emotional, or visceral elements rather than the doctrinal ones. This shift has important implications for bringing a neuroscientific approach to the study of religion. However, this also results in a neuroscientific approach to both religious and non-religious spirituality and spiritual experiences. In fact, as the definitions have evolved, the distinction between spirituality and religiousness has become much more complicated.
Chapter
Religion is obviously shaped by the social context within which it exists. Hence, one might expect some legitimacy to the concept of rural religion. Furthermore, if there is even partial truth to the claims that, relative to more cosmopolitan cultures, rural cultures are less heterogeneous, less tolerant of divergencies in belief and action, and less abstract in their conceptualizations, then these claims should hold true to the same extent for rural religion as they do for rural culture in general. In this sense, religious fundamentalism is not unanticipated in rural areas. Yet, as we shall see, it is more than just a curiosity that the persistence of the faith of the rural Roman (the paganus) became an English word for unbeliever (pagan) and the religious conservatism of the English heath dwellers became another word for unbeliever, heathen (Smith & Zopf, 1970). Yet these terms conceal a bias that also characterizes the scientific study of religion in general and of religious fundamentalism in particular. The problem of bias, noted through many chapters of this text, is even more apparent when investigators confront not only a rural culture unlikely to be their own, but also a religious fundamentalism dominant in that culture and to which they are unlikely to subscribe.