ArticlePDF Available

National self-sufficiency in reproductive resources: An innovative response to transnational reproductive travel

Authors:

Abstract

Transnational reproductive travel is symptomatic of insufficient supplies of reproductive resources, including donor gametes and gestational surrogacy services, and inequities in access to these within domestic health-care jurisdictions. Here, we argue that an innovative approach to domestic policy making using the framework of the National Self-Sufficiency paradigm represents the best solution to domestic challenges and the ethical hazards of the global marketplace in reproductive resources. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.3138/ijfab.7.2.0010
National self-sufficiency in reproductive resources: An innovative response to transnational
reproductive travel
Author(s): Dominique Martin and Stefan Kane
Source:
International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics,
Vol. 7, No. 2, Special Issue
on Transnational Reproductive Travel (Fall 2014), pp. 10-44
Published by: University of Toronto Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.3138/ijfab.7.2.0010 .
Accessed: 22/10/2014 18:06
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
.
University of Toronto Press and Indiana University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve
and extend access to International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
NATIONAL SELF-SUFFICIENCY IN
REPRODUCTIVE RESOURCES:
AN INNOVATIVE RESPONSE TO TRANSNATIONAL
REPRODUCTIVE TRAVEL
DOMINIQUE MARTIN AND STEFAN KANE
Abstract
Transnational reproductive travel is symptomatic of insufcient supplies of
reproductive resources, including donor gametes and gestational surrogacy ser-
vices, and inequities in access to these within domestic health-care jurisdic-
tions. Here, we argue that an innovative approach to domestic policy making
using the framework of the National Self-Sufciency paradigm represents the
best solution to domestic challenges and the ethical hazards of the global mar-
ketplace in reproductive resources.
1. Transnational issues begin at home
Many Australians have traveled overseas to fulll their hopes of parent-
hood by accessing reproductive services in countries such as the United States,
Thailand, and India: more than 269 babies were created for Australian repro-
ductive travelers in 2011 (Whitelaw 2012). Ova provided by third parties
1
and
gestational surrogates
2
are in short supply in Australia, where payment for
THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF FEMINIST APPROACHES TO BIOETHICS Vol. 7, No. 2 (FALL 2014). ©2014
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
providing these reproductive resources is prohibited. In contrast, India has a
thriving legal trade that makes the country a popular, relatively affordable des-
tination for Australian reproductive travelers.
In response to news of changes in Indian policy that may restrict foreign
access to reproductive services (Ministry of Home Affairs 2012), as well as to
reports of ethical concerns about the fertility industry in India and elsewhere
(e.g., Medew 2013), some commentators have called for the introduction of
commercial surrogacy in Australia, arguing that a regulated national market
will protect the interests of surrogates, intending parents,
3
and the children cre-
ated (Haxton 2013;Millibank 2013). Similar arguments have been proposed in
favor of an Australian market in provider gametes as an alternative for the
many Australians who access assisted reproductive technologies (ART) using
ova or sperm purchased in foreign countries (Baker 2012;Nash 2012).
4
There has been little discussion of alternative strategies to encourage or
facilitate unpaid provision of reproductive resources, to promote equity in their
distribution, or to enhance the availability of resources and ART domestically.
In this paper, we hope to open a new dimension of debate and stimulate novel
approaches to policy and practice in this eld. We will argue that transnational
reproductive travel is problematic, not only for its inherent ethical hazards but
also because it is symptomatic of a failure to recognize and address unmet
needs and inequities domestically. We will explore the concept of national self-
sufciency in reproductive resources, a practical goal and social ethos that,
when adopted by policy makers, may encourage strategic innovations to
improve access to these resources, and to enhance equity in their provision
and distribution. The ethical foundations and implications of the self-
sufciency concept have yet to be fully explored, particularly with respect to
reproductive resources, but we provide here a substantial, albeit preliminary,
examination. We suggest that the self-sufciency ethos is more consistent with
a feminist bioethics than with the individualist, libertarian frameworks often
employed to support market-based policies and cross-border solutions pro-
posed in response to the challenge of meeting needs for these resources in the
domestic setting.
a. Why worry about reproductive travel?
The challenges of meeting needs for reproductive resources within coun-
tries and the hazards of the global marketplace reect similar issues that have
arisen in the context of human blood and blood products, and organs for
DOMINIQUE MARTIN AND STEFAN KANE 11
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
transplantation. In particular, reproductive travel mirrors many elements of
transnational travel for organ transplantation, or transplant tourism.Yet, as
Pfeffer (2011) highlights, there has been a marked contrast in the responses of
professional organizations and national and international authorities, such as
the World Health Organization (WHO), to these different practices. Extensive
efforts to discourage and prevent travel for commercial organ transplantation
have been complemented by efforts to achieve self-sufciency in transplanta-
tion at the national or regional level by encouraging donation and facilitating
organ procurement (Delmonico et al. 2011;Noël and Martin 2009).
In contrast, new markets in reproductive resources designed for foreign
consumers are emerging rapidly, often with the support of national authorities
(e.g., Sarojini et al. 2011). Legal conventions governing procurement of gametes
and provision of surrogacy services are usually subnational or national in
scope, reecting a lack of international consensus (Van Hoof and Pennings
2012, 188). Although most jurisdictions nominally reject trade in ova, many
allow for the payment of lump-sum compensationto providers. Studies of
oocyte providersmotivations and recruitment strategies suggest compensation
often serves to incentivize donation(Purewal and van den Akker 2009c, 507;
García-Ruiz and Guerra-Diaz 2012, 123; Levine 2010). Compensation facili-
tates trade and encourages reproductive travel all over the world (Van Hoof
and Pennings 2012;Martin 2010). Many commentators advocate payment as
practically necessary and ethically justiable, if not obligatory (e.g., Steinbock
2004;Ramskold and Posner 2013).
Reproductive travel has been hailed as a moral safety valve enabling indi-
viduals to enjoy procreative liberty (Pennings 2004). Rather than seeking to
reduce travel, many experts from a range of disciplines advocate modication
of current practices and policies so as to maximize the benets and minimize
the harms of cross-border care. Hudson et al. (2011) suggest that most com-
mentators may regard this as the most feasible approach to the issue. Com-
mentators propose strategies to minimize harmful practices (e.g., Ireni-Saban
2013), untangle international legal complexities (e.g., Nelson 2013), and offer
guidelines for health-care professionals involved in transnational reproductive
care (e.g., Sheneld et al. 2011;Blyth et al. 2011;Ethics Committee 2013).
However, the current Australian debate highlights an emerging view that
the ethical issues of reproductive travel should be addressed at the national
level. More locally engaged governance is necessary to protect the providers of
gametes and surrogacy services, to meet the needs of intending parents, and to
12 International Journal OF FEMINIST APPROACHES TO Bioethics 7:2
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
promote the interests of children produced through ART. Reliance on industry
self-regulation within the global market has proven ineffective and sometimes
harmful, exposing children to trafcking and abandonment, surrogates and egg
vendors to exploitation and coercion, and intending parents to devastating loss
as they struggle to bring home children caught in immigration tangles (Storrow
2011). Furthermore, in the absence of national solutions, poorer citizens
who cannot afford to travel remain disenfranchised from ART services. The
self-sufciency paradigm, with its emphasis on national responsibility for meet-
ing needs locally, thus represents an important new approach to the challenges
of transnational reproductive care.
b. Introducing national self-sufciency in reproductive
resources
Broadly speaking, self-sufciency refers to the goal of meeting therapeutic
needs for medical products of human origin within a dened community
usually the nation-stateusing resources derived from within that community.
Thus, self-sufciency in reproductive resources refers to the ability to meet
needs for gametes and surrogacy services within a particular social community,
using resources sourced from providers within that community.
National self-sufciency was rst invoked in the 1970s in response to eth-
ical and safety concerns about international trade in human blood products
(Leikola 1987). Although prevention of harmful cross-border trading was a
major element of the concepts original framework, this was complemented by
efforts to meet needs ethically by promoting blood and plasma donation within
society. Respect for justice appears to have been a key ethical concern of early
self-sufciency advocates, such as the WHO, with exploitation of foreign provi-
ders of biological materials, inequity in access to resources, and inequitable dis-
tributions of the burden of donation identied as issues to be addressed
through policies aimed at self-sufciency (ibid.; Council of Europe 1990).
Similarly, the promotion of self-sufciency in organ transplantation has
been advocated in recent years in response to ongoing global trade in human or-
gans, notably in the Declaration of Istanbul on Organ Trafcking and Transplant
Tourism (Participants 2008, 855). Following the WHOs third Global Consulta-
tion on Organ Donation and Transplantation on the subject of self-sufciency
(WHO 2011), international leaders in transplantation called for governments to
take responsibility for meeting needs for transplantation within their borders, or
in collaboration with regional neighbors (Delmonico et al. 2011).
DOMINIQUE MARTIN AND STEFAN KANE 13
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
The concept of self-sufciency in reproductive resources was recently in-
troduced to the literature by Martin (2010) as a strategic response to reproduc-
tive travel (see also Crozier and Martin 2012). Thorn et al. (2012, 4) also
suggest that pursuit of self-sufciency will reduce reproductive travel. More re-
cently, Downie and Baylis argue that Canadian authorities should promote
national self-sufciency in an effort to contain (if not decrease) the demand for
transnational trade in human eggs(2013, 234).
The concept of national self-sufciency has undergone little critical exam-
ination from an ethical perspective, with the exception of debate regarding
payment for provision of blood and plasma (Keown 1997). The ethical implica-
tions of a societys adoption of responsibility for meeting needs for human
biological materials, the justication of the persisting requirement for non-
remunerated, voluntarydonation that was entrenched in the rst World
Health Assembly (1975) resolution on the development of national blood
donation programs, and the complexities inherent in dening needsare all
overdue for in-depth analysis.
We provide a preliminary discussion of these critical points in the context
of self-sufciency in reproductive resources in the nal section of this paper.
We also explore the additional complexities surrounding the denition of
needs that arise in the context of infertility (e.g., Peterson 2005) and the unique
burdens that may be associated with provision of resources that may engender
desires for relationships on the part of children, intending parents, or providers
(Crozier and Martin 2012, 49). We will argue that within the self-sufciency
ethos, the core themes of social community, shared responsibility for meeting
needs, protection of the vulnerable, and promotion of justice resituate infertility
as a fundamentally social concern, for which effective and ethical solutions
must be shaped through societal mechanisms and strategies. In contrast,
transnational and domestic market mechanismswhether regulated, state-
controlled, or freeperpetuate and exacerbate the social neglect and isolation
of infertile individuals and couples and increase the vulnerability and invisibil-
ity of providers of reproductive resources and potential children created.
Before presenting our account of self-sufciency, we must rst review the
reasons underpinning travel for reproductive resourcesnamely, failure to meet
needs within domestic systemsthe hazards of transnational travel, and pro-
posed responses to the phenomenon, including market regulation (both interna-
tional and domestic), harmonization of laws, and prohibitions on travel or trade
in the absence of efforts to meet needs for reproductive resources domestically.
14 International Journal OF FEMINIST APPROACHES TO Bioethics 7:2
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
2. Travel is symptomatic of domestic problems
a. Insufciency of resources
Demand or needs for reproductive resources are rarely estimated;
5
how-
ever, studies suggest that insufcient supplies of these resources are a major
factor inuencing reproductive travel (Hudson et al. 2011). The relative abun-
dance of these resources in some countries is often associated with payment for
gamete providers and surrogates (Sheneld et al. 2010, 1367), and nancial
compensationis often cited as a secondary, if not primary, motivation for
providers of reproductive resources (Van den Broeck et al. 2013;Purewal and
van den Akker 2009c, 507; Lee 2009, 289). Additional considerations for pro-
spective buyers and providers may include factors such as regulation of pro-
vider anonymity, but resources tend to ow from countries in which trade is
legal to those in which payment is prohibited (e.g., Martin 2010, 382). The posi-
tive association often found between payment and increased supplies has
helped to place markets at the forefront of proposed solutions to the problem
of insufciency in many countries. However, rather than necessarily indicating
superior efcacy, nancial incentives stand out because of a lack of alternative
strategies to increase donation.
Few countries have sought to promote or facilitate donation of gametes or
surrogacy services as part of a societal response to infertility and unmet needs
for these resources. There is little in the way of public education about infertil-
ity, needs for reproductive resources, risks and benets of their provision, and
potential strategies to minimize disincentives for providers. These disincentives
may include immediate costs incurred by providers, such as lost wages; costs of
travel, testing, and insurance; and the discomfort and physical side effects of in-
vasive procedures. Surrogates who carry a baby to term will experience a longer
period of physiological disruption and medical attention compared with single-
cycle oocyte providers. Yet both oocyte providers and surrogates face serious
albeit rarehealth risks, potential legal complications, possible social stigma,
and psychological concerns, some of which may arise years later (Kalfoglou
and Gittelsohn 2000;Maxwell et al. 2008;Bodri 2013;Duffy et al. 2005;Berend
2010;Pande 2009). Concerns about the possible negative impact of removing
gamete provider anonymity on recruitment in the United Kingdom reect
some of the potential long-term psychosocial risks of genetic parenthood, such
as emotional or nancial liability (Frith et al. 2007, 1679).
DOMINIQUE MARTIN AND STEFAN KANE 15
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Many of the potential disincentives to provision of reproductive resources
may be effectively removed, rather than overcome by lump-sum nancial in-
centives: by reimbursement of health-care costs; by provision of health insur-
ance related to the donation or surrogacy; by provision of counselling services
(ibid.); and by providing clarity and transparency of laws governing, for exam-
ple, anonymity, liability (Jayanti 2008), and surrogacy rights.
b. Neglect of inequities
Lack of public efforts to encourage or facilitate altruistic donation may
reect a view that infertility is not an important health and social issue (Jones
and Nisker 2013). Setting aside the problem of insufcient resources, and the
role that markets may play in providing them, many societies are also content
to leave regulation of ART, including allocation of reproductive resources, to
the market sphere. In many countries, most ART is provided in private clinics,
even where care is publicly subsidized (Mladovsky and Sorenson 2010, 122;
Chambers et al. 2013, 1682). Equity in global access to ART remains a major
challenge (Pennings et al. 2008), and one that is particularly neglected where
reproductive resources are concerned.
In countries where ART is available, the costs of accessing services may
exclude many intending parents. Subsidization of costs through public health
funds positively inuences utilization of ART (Chambers et al. 2009); however,
subsidies are usually limited to a xed number of cycles, such that many
patients need to pursue further treatment at their own expense. Financial bar-
riers to ART include additional costs when using third-party reproductive re-
sourcesregardless of whether providers are paid. In addition to direct
nancial barriers, a range of legislative, regulatory, and policy barriers may
impede access to specic procedures or resources. Individuals or couples may
be excluded from or receive lower priority in accessing ART on the grounds of
eligibility criteria that seek to evaluate suitability for parenting (Storrow 2006)
and to rank needsfor ART. Although specic legislation in some countries
may act clearly as a gatekeeper to ARTfor example, by excluding unmarried
heterosexual couples or lesbian, gay, bisexual, transgender, or queer (LGBTQ)
couples or individualsthe criteria or processes used to allocate available re-
sources are rarely transparent.
6
The risk of injustice in allocation is magnied
in the setting of privately run health systems and clinics.
In contrast to relatively transparent systems frequently governing alloca-
tion of organs for transplantation, and vigorous professional and academic
16 International Journal OF FEMINIST APPROACHES TO Bioethics 7:2
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
debates about organ allocation criteria, the allocation of reproductive resources
is rarely discussed. There are no public ova banks or national pools of donated
gametes, nor waiting list reports. Those who lack a friend or relative willing to
provide resources may solicit an unrelated donor, or solicit or select a paid pro-
vider in countries where this legal. Alternatively, they may join the waiting list
of specic clinics or health-care institutions, where provided or shared
7
eggs
are distributed at the discretion of the clinic. Waiting lists and times are fre-
quently invoked, despite lack of transparency regarding the allocation process in
the media, patient websites, industry, and academic forums. The Agence de la
Biomédicine (2012b, 4) publicly warns that average waiting times in French
clinics range from six to sixty months, and notes that times vary according to
the availability of suitably matcheddonors who present to the clinic at which
one is registered. Some clinics boast of no waiting time at all, such as the London
Clinic (2013) in the United Kingdom, which offers free IVF to eligible egg-
sharers.
In a rare article discussing possible criteria for use in an ova allocation sys-
tem, Pennings (2001, 31) suggests that a criterion concerning the degree of phe-
notypic match between prospective recipients and providers should receive little
weight. However, evidence suggests that matching phenotypic and social charac-
teristics of gamete providers and recipients is one of the most important criteria
employed by clinics and used by prospective recipients in selecting from
available providers (Almeling 2007). Those seeking surrogates are also subject
to market vagaries, reliant on paying fees to brokering agencies, soliciting
surrogates through advertisements, or competing with other intending parents
for services advertised by prospective surrogates (e.g., Hibino and Shimazono
2013). The perceived desirability of particular surrogate, gamete provider, or
intending parent attributes plays an important role in advertisements, inuen-
cing both commercial value and the probability of meeting ones needs for
reproductive resources (Almeling 2009;Nowoweiski et al. 2011;Roberts 2009).
While it is difcult to evaluate equity in access to these resources due to lack of
systematic research, current practices appear highly vulnerable to unjust dis-
crimination.
3. An undesirable solution to domestic issues
Opportunities for reproductive travel are often held to improve both
access and equity in access to reproductive resources, at least for some groups
DOMINIQUE MARTIN AND STEFAN KANE 17
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
(Pennings 2002, 338). Additional advantages may include economic benets
for destination countries, their health-care systems, and women who provide
ova or surrogacy services (Crozier and Martin 2012). However, a growing mul-
tidisciplinary body of literature (Hudson et al. 2011;Inhorn and Patrizio 2012)
has identied a range of ethical and practical concerns about reproductive
travel. Many of these concerns are equally relevant to domestic markets, and, in
some contexts, may apply to noncommercial provision or use of gametes or
surrogates. However, the cross-border socioeconomic inequalities that are typi-
cal of many transnational markets for reproductive resources render partici-
pants more vulnerable to these risks than they may be in the setting of
domestic markets, and certainly than they would be in the absence of nancial
incentives for resource provision.
a. Risks for providers of reproductive resources
Relatively wealthy reproductive travelers may pay well above local prices
for reproductive care and resources in less economically developed countries.
The magnitude of nancial incentives available may encourage care providers
to expose donors and surrogates to avoidable risks in the hope of maximizing
prots (Nahman 2011, 631; Deonandan et al. 2012). In turn, the latter may be
willing to incur higher risks in order to obtain signicant nancial incentives
(e.g., Pande 2009, 150). Although laxity of regulation and oversight of repro-
ductive care providers may exist in the absence of reproductive travelers,
foreign customers may play a signicant role in stimulating and sustaining
markets. The relative invisibility of resource providers to those who purchase
gametes or surrogacy services in these markets, due to language and cultural
barriers as well as geographical and social distancing (Vora 2013, S102), may
also diminish concern for provider well-being by customers, thus increasing
their vulnerability.
Physical and psychosocial risks to providers of reproductive resources
may include inadequate medical care leading to ovarian hyperstimulation
syndrome; transfer of multiple embryos; social stigmatization; and impaired
autonomy in decision making about the pregnancy, including choices about
terminations, lifestyle during pregnancy, and interventions during labor (e.g.,
Pande 2009;Bailey 2011;Lundin 2012). Women may be exploited, for example,
where others take advantage of their poverty or lack of education in order to
obtain their agreement to an unfair contract, in which the benets to brokers,
health-care providers, and intending parents are disproportionate to the
18 International Journal OF FEMINIST APPROACHES TO Bioethics 7:2
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
economic gains of donors or surrogates (Ramskold and Posner 2013, 398). In-
creased opportunities to prot from womens reproductive labor may encour-
age coercion by relatives or trafcking (Whittaker 2011) that might not occur
in the absence of a market.
Many of these harms relate to the underlying commodication of wom-
ens labor and bodies and the impact of this on attitudes toward women in
the marketplace for reproductive labor. Anderson (1993) argues that the
contractual nature of surrogacyeven where it is unpaidundermines the
bodily autonomy of women and devalues the emotional labor that surrogates
perform:
Treating womens labor as just another commercial production process vio-
lates the precious emotional ties the mother may rightly and properly estab-
lish with her product,the child, and thereby violates her claims to respect
and consideration. (186)
This concern is reected in ndings from the transnational marketplace, which
Whittaker and Speier describe as disaggregating the work of motherhood
(2010, 377). The intrusion of market norms into the intimate relational sphere
of reproductive labor makes it difcult to avoid objectication of providers of
reproductive resources, or at least obscuration of their subjectivity.
b. Risks for children and intending parents
Children created in the transnational market may risk separation from in-
tending parents due to legal barriers to citizenship; abandonment; trafcking;
and increased barriers to tracing or identication of genetic parents across inter-
national borders (Trimmings and Beaumont 2011;Mohapatra 2012). Research
suggests that maintenance of social relationships between reproductive resource
providers and recipient families or preserving the possibility for future disclo-
sure of identity or personal information may be valuable to children, gamete
providers, and surrogates (Jadva et al. 2010,2011,2012). It is perhaps too soon
to expect research into the long-term outcomes of children produced through
reproductive travel, in particular with respect to the impact of established or
neglected relationships with resource providers. Nevertheless, potential risks
should be considered when seeking care in the transnational market.
Intending parents who seek reproductive resources abroad may suffer
nancial exploitation; intended genetic relationships may not eventuate, with
DOMINIQUE MARTIN AND STEFAN KANE 19
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
third-party gametes or embryos used to create children instead of those of par-
ents; and parents may be unable to obtain custody or return home with their
children (Medew 2013;Trimmings and Beaumont 2011).
In addition to the direct hazards faced by participants, reproductive travel
may impair access to ART or health-care services for citizens of destination
countries, when resources are diverted to the market for foreign consumers (In-
horn 2012;Donchin 2010). Bailey (2011) also points out that the sale of repro-
ductive resources to foreign patients in countries like India occurs against a
background of gross inequities in access to obstetric care, impaired reproduc-
tive rights, and high rates of infertility and maternal mortality. Reproductive
travel may also exacerbate inequities in access to ART and reproductive re-
sources within the countries from which intending parents travel, as only those
sufciently wealthy are able to circumvent restrictive domestic legislation or
overcome shortages of resources by purchasing care abroad. Finally, reproduc-
tive travel may negatively impact the home country of intending parents, where
costs arising from the creation of children abroad fall upon the domestic
health-care or social welfare systems (McKelvey et al. 2009;Barrington and
Janvier 2013). Where care is provided domestically, easier regulation of policy
and practice may help to minimize health risks to surrogates, gamete providers,
or children createdfor example, by reducing nancial barriers that may
encourage higher-risk practices, such as multiple embryo transfer (Maheshwari
et al. 2011).
4. Responding to reproductive travel
There is consensus that at least some harmful elements of the global mar-
ket can and should be addressed. Three categories of suggested regulatory or
policy responses to concerns about reproductive travel are commonly de-
scribed: prohibition, harmonization, and harm minimization.
Most authors dismiss the idea of prohibiting reproductive travel as un-
feasible or unfair. Nevertheless, Turkey and some Australian states have
introduced legislation with extraterritorial application such that citizens are
considered liable to prosecution on their return home if they engage in activ-
ities such as obtaining gametes or commissioning a surrogate overseas (Cohen
2012, 1325). A number of factors, including respect for liberty, the right to
travel, and patient autonomy and condentiality, may preclude effective
enforcement of prohibitions (Van Hoof and Pennings 2011,2012;Culley et al.
20 International Journal OF FEMINIST APPROACHES TO Bioethics 7:2
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
2013). Furthermore, in the absence of efforts to meet needs within the domestic
setting, prohibitions may increase risks to participants as they seek to conceal
illicit travel abroadfor example, through impaired continuity of care for reci-
pients of ART abroad (Mancini et al. 2011).
Harmonization refers to proposals involving the establishment of interna-
tional consensus on at least some elements of ART regulation. Setting aside the
improbability of achieving this, as even within the European Union this has
proven challenging (Van Hoof and Pennings 2012), harmonization risks
imposing the most restrictive or the most liberal of policies on a global scale.
If the policy is broad in scope and unfair or otherwise unethical, the impact
may be extremely harmful. On the other hand, if harmonization targets specic
issues, it may be possible to achieve consensus on less ethically or politically
contentious issues, such as the setting of minimum standards of care for provi-
ders of reproductive resources (Thorn et al. 2012). Partial harmonization is
unlikely, however, to resolve many of the issues of reproductive travel outlined
earlier.
a. Harm minimization
Most commentators, working from the presumption that reproductive
travel is inevitable and not inherently undesirable, focus on harm minimization
strategies. At one extreme, these include efforts to promote and facilitate repro-
ductive travel with minimal restrictions on trade designed to protect vendor
and purchaser rights, to facilitate citizenship acquisition of created children,
and to establish minimum standards of care (e.g., Chung 2006;Crozier and
Martin 2012). Practical strategies to prevent specic harms include legal mea-
sures, such as international treaties governing the rights of children born
through reproductive travel; fair trade agreements to prevent economic exploi-
tation of resource providers; and accreditation schemes that would help trav-
elers to identify clinics that meet standards of care and ethical practice (e.g.,
Humbyrd 2009;Ramskold and Posner 2013).
The harm minimization approach is imperfect. Successful implementa-
tion requires an ad hoc strategic approach to specic issues, with agreement to
be sought on each of these from a culturally, socioeconomically diverse number
of nation-states. The process of negotiating agreements is likely to be lengthy,
and abstentions by some nations with a large market share may undermine the
impact of partial consensus. Most importantly, harm minimization neglects the
problems within domestic systems that drive the transnational market: many
DOMINIQUE MARTIN AND STEFAN KANE 21
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
people may prefer to access reproductive care in their own country. Although
an understandable strategy at the international level, the harm minimization
approach allows individual nations to avoid responsibility for domestic prac-
tices and for the cross-border impact of domestic policy.
b. Regulated national markets
Regulated markets have long been advocated as a remedy for transplant
tourism(e.g., Matas et al. 2008), and commentators (e.g., Millibank 2013) have
recently proposed introducing payments for ova providers and surrogates par-
tially to discourage harmful reproductive travel. The rationale for regulated mar-
kets is simple: introduction of payments for reproductive resources is expected
to enhance supplies, thus enabling countries to better meet domestic needs
and minimizing demand for travel. The recent increase in compensation
for egg providers in the United Kingdom (Wilkinson 2013) and the introduc-
tion of legislation permitting payment in Israel (Gruenbaum et al. 2011) are
not explicitly designed to discourage reproductive travel, nor are they described
as regulated market systems; however, these changes follow years of national
debate concerning ova shortages and rising numbers of outgoing reproductive
travelers.
There are some intuitively appealing elements of regulated market propo-
sals: in particular, they imply recognition of responsibility for meeting needs
within the domestic setting, and acknowledge the potentially harmful impact of
domestic activities on foreign communities. However, their success depends on
meeting four key requirements. First, market regulation must be sufcient to
prevent at least the major concerns about transnational trade, without being so
restrictive that those with unmet needs will continue to travel abroad in signi-
cant numbers. Second, countries must be capable of enforcing regulation effec-
tively. Third, the nancial incentives offered must sufciently increase supplies
to meet needs. Fourth, payments must not in themselves be sufciently harmful
or unethical to warrant market prohibition.
The challenge of dening standards of care for providers and recipients of
reproductive resources is compounded by such issues as provider anonymity
and eligibility criteria for parenthood. However, these regulatory questions
apply to any system offering ART, regardless of whether providers are paid. Of
note, simply regulating provider care in a national market will not resolve exist-
ing inequities in access to resources, unless allocation and access criteria are re-
vised in the process of market regulation. Although market advocates may
22 International Journal OF FEMINIST APPROACHES TO Bioethics 7:2
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
support the introduction of public subsidies for ART (if these are not already in
place), markets are not renowned for promoting equitable participation. Con-
cerns have recently been expressed about the cost of accessing ART in Austra-
lia, where market norms dominate despite public funding programs (Medew
and Baker 2013). Paying for reproductive resources may well encourage the
adoption or further development of commodicatory attitudes toward prac-
tices surrounding infertility treatment. This could lead to greater economic in-
equities in access to ART through reliance on market mechanisms of exchange.
Determining a fairprice for gametes and surrogacy services that the market
will tolerate may also prove difcult. Should providers of resources be paid
regardless of whether a successful pregnancy results? Will extra incentives be
justiable for providers possessing desirable or rare attributes, such as a specic
ethnic or religious heritage, proven success as a surrogate, and so on?
With respect to the efcacy of hypothetical market regulations, such as
the enforcement of safety standards, transparency in practice, and fair prices
for reproductive resources, there are good reasons to be skeptical. There is
widespread evidence of poor enforcement of regulations in both the market
and nonmarket settings (e.g., Motluk 2010;Gurmankin 2001;Keehn et al.
2012;Janwalkar 2012;Luk and Petrozza 2008;Watson 2011). A major hurdle
to effective regulation will involve the establishment and maintenance of
data collection systems, such as provider and recipient registries, that monitor
practices and outcomes (e.g., Schneider 2008;Cahn 2009). The failure of
many current markets to establish and transparently audit regulations govern-
ing standards of care and data collection, especially concerning the provision
and use of reproductive resources, suggests that the burden of regulation will
fall heavily upon the state.
Given the evidence from existing markets, it is plausible to assume that
the use of nancial incentives may increase supplies of some resources in some
countries, at least temporarily. The efcacy of incentives will depend not only
on the amounts offered but also on the societal extent of economic disadvan-
tage, the availability of alternative employment opportunities for women, and
whether nonnancial disincentives to provide resources are also addressed.
The cost of implementing regulations will likely contribute to higher costs for
those accessing resources within the domestic market. Poorer individuals and
couples may still be priced out of their local systems and driven to seek cheaper
care in foreign markets, as evidenced by outgoing reproductive travel from the
United States to India, and from India to Dubai (Inhorn 2012).
DOMINIQUE MARTIN AND STEFAN KANE 23
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
The fourth and nal claim that advocates must defend is that a regulated
market will eliminate or substantially reduce the ethical concerns raised in
the transnational market setting. Setting aside concerns about physical or psy-
chological harm to vendors of reproductive resources, which regulations gov-
erning standards of care and safety are intended to address, more intangible
but no less signicant concerns about vendor autonomy, exploitation, and
inappropriate commodication may persist in the regulated market setting.
Earlier we discussed these concerns briey, and they have been examined
extensively elsewhere (e.g., Bailey 2011;White 2006;Steinbock 2004;Hol-
land 2001;Tieu 2009). We touch here only on some concerns specicto
autonomy.
Although careful regulation may help to promote vendor autonomy by
ensuring procedures for obtaining informed consent are followed, the existence
of nancial incentives may increase the risk of women being coerced, not by
the incentive offer itself but by others in a position of power over them, where
legal markets provide additional opportunities for prot. Greater transparency
in a regulated market may help to avoid the perils of human trafcking for
reproductive resources; however, expanding the range of earning options avail-
able to the poor is not always desirable, even where such extremes of harm are
preventable (see Rippon 2014). Regulated markets may expose the poor to
additional legal or social pressures to sell reproductive resources, as some ob-
servers have already noted (Palattiyil et al. 2010, 691). At best, regulated
national market proposals offer only limited theoretical advantages in compari-
son to unregulated transnational markets, in the form of more effective harm
minimization.
Donchin argues that commonly proposed solutions to the problem of
reproductive travel are awed due to their shared presumption that injustices
tied to prevailing open market arrangements apply only to individual parties
and do not extend to social institutions(2010, 331). She advocates a social
connection modelof transnational responsibility that would foster a coordi-
nated approach to addressing the issues and would also target the socioeco-
nomic situation of women who have no choice but to sell their reproductive
resources in the transnational market (332). In the next section, we outline the
National Self-Sufciency Model, which more explicitly locates responsibility
within societies, and promotes a holistic response to the multifactorial chal-
lenge of meeting needs for reproductive resources.
24 International Journal OF FEMINIST APPROACHES TO Bioethics 7:2
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
5. National self-sufciency in reproductive resources
The self-sufciency model aims to establish (usually national) governance
of efforts to meet needs for particular human biological materials or medical
products of human origin, and is motivated by practical and ethical concerns.
First and foremost, it situates the challenge of meeting needs within the scope
of societal responsibility, and in the global context. The goal of meeting needs
for resources domestically is framed in contrast, if not in opposition, to the al-
ternatives of outsourcing donations or creating national markets. Given genu-
ine commitment to this goal, efforts will be made to meet needs, and to prevent
them where possible, not merely to discourage or prevent outgoing travel or
cross-border trade in human biological materials.
a. The ethical framework of the self-sufciency model
Although policies governing the procurement, use, and distribution of
human biological materials in various countries are often supported by ethical
declarations or guidelines, these are rarely tied explicitly to the goal of self-
sufciency. The role that ethical principles may play in informing strategic
efforts is neglected: ethics seemingly constrains, through prohibitions and
warnings, rather than facilitates progress toward self-sufciency. Unsurpris-
ingly, practical strategies to increase supplies of resources may be detached
from the moorings of morality, with developed policies checked against ethical
frameworks to ensure compliance, rather than being inspired by and intimately
connected with them. To pursue self-sufciency successfully, this approach to
policy making must be inverted. As the Aristotelian roots of the term would
suggest,
8
self-sufciency must begin with a community of individuals uniting
in pursuit of a common goal, recognizing that its achievement depends on
shared commitment to securing the requirements for human ourishing.
b. Social solidarity as an ethical foundation for self-sufciency
The concept of self-sufciency is reected in contemporary accounts of
solidarity, referred to as shared practices reecting a collective commitment to
carry costs(nancial, social, emotional, or otherwise) to assist others(Prainsack
and Buyx 2012, 346; emphasis in the original). The value of framing blood and
organ donation as societal concerns requiring collective efforts is increasingly
recognized (e.g., Martin 2013, 52). Gestational surrogacy and gamete provision
are practices that may involve a variety of complex, novel, and peculiarly
DOMINIQUE MARTIN AND STEFAN KANE 25
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
intimate relationships, all of which engage with a fundamental social bond of
human lives: that of parent and child. Yet these practices are customarily treated
as private, individual concerns, in which observation or intervention by society
or the state is often considered inappropriate. Resituating infertility, and the use
of reproductive resources, within a framework of community and solidarity will
require a signicant paradigm shift. However, such a move will enable policy
makers to better address not only the social and ethical concerns we emphasize
in this paper, but also the more practical concerns that clearly fall within the
scope of public governance, such as issues of public funding for ART, vigilance
and surveillance of safety and quality of reproductive resources, and legislation
governing parental and child rights in the context of gestational surrogacy and
third-party gamete conception.
The exclusion of society from reproductive concerns may be motivated
by the desire to protect reproductive privacy, but the transnational marketplace
appears to facilitate disconnection rather than fostering intimacy in reproduc-
tive relationships. The relationships formed between intending parents and the
gamete providers or surrogates who enable the creation of their children are
often tenuous or contested (e.g., Vora 2009, 27072; Pande 2011). Indeed,
such are the anxieties surrounding parental rights and the risk that donors or
surrogates may undermine those of intending parents that payment for surro-
gates is even advocated on the grounds it will help to disrupt any maternal
feelings on the part of the surrogate (Ramskold and Posner 2013, 399).
The transnational care setting is especially conducive to relationship disrup-
tion, with language and cultural barriers, geographical distance, and, often,
donor anonymity combiningor conspiringto prevent, weaken, and eventu-
ally disrupt any connections between participants (Vora 2013, S102; Saravanan
2013).
Negotiating the challenges of parental, genetic, and gestational relation-
ships in ART is necessary if societies are to progress toward self-sufciency.
Establishing relationships in the immediate term and facilitating future relation-
ships if and when they become desirable or necessary is likely to be benecial for
all participants, if these relationships are formed within the context of a legal,
medical, and social system that provides appropriate psychosocial support and
clarity on legal obligations and rights, which help to foster trust (e.g., Golombok
et al. 2013). The promotion of solidarity, at both the personal and societal levels,
will encourage recognition of the vulnerability of all participants in ART
through enhanced understanding of their varied experiences, facilitating the
26 International Journal OF FEMINIST APPROACHES TO Bioethics 7:2
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
adoption of protective measures. Promoting solidarity will also help to encour-
age participation in opportunities to help meet needsfor example, through
donation of resources.
The self-sufciency model resituates reproductive resources in a frame-
work of mutual care and relatedness consistent with feminist bioethics. In
transnational reproductive travel, efforts to establish or sustain a relational
account of surrogacy, for example, struggle to compete with neoliberal dis-
course (e.g., Kroløkke and Pant 2012). Within the self-sufciency model, the
social context of procurement and use of reproductive resources is recognized,
and relationships in the personal and public spheres are nurtured, consistent
with an ethics of care (e.g., Parks 2010) and a relational understanding of
bioethics. Baylis et al. (2008, 205), for example, argue that
[the] pursuit of public goods for health, for the benet of us all requires
trust, collective responsibility and accountability. As such, concrete expres-
sions of relational solidarity in the context of public health ethics are to be
found in our accepting of responsibility for ourselves and our actions, in
our willingness to be held accountable for others (especially the weakest and
most disadvantaged in society), and in our awareness of mutual vulnerabil-
ity and interdependence.
c. Justice, reciprocity, and efforts to meet needs
A society that adopts the goal of self-sufciency must begin by acknowl-
edging the extent and diversity of needs for reproductive resources. Infertility is
rarely spoken of as a public health issue, despite the fact it affects roughly 9 per-
cent of heterosexual couples of procreative age seeking to create children (Boi-
vin et al. 2007, 1506), and an untold number of singles and LGBTQ couples for
whom structuralinfertility (Daar 2008, 24) impedes the achievement of pro-
creative goals. The extent of needs for reproductive resources in any country,
represented by individuals or couples for whom the timely receipt of donor
gamete(s) and/or gestational surrogacy services represents the best method of
creating a child, is unknown.
This denition of needs is arguably problematic, in that its scope is
extremely broad, and it allows for a subjective interpretation of the optimal
method for achieving ones procreative desires. In contrast, although rationing
considerations continue to inuence the denition of needs for organ trans-
plantation, quantication of true needs for organs is estimable through
DOMINIQUE MARTIN AND STEFAN KANE 27
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
epidemiological assessments of end-stage organ failure within populations
(e.g., Gilbertson et al. 2005). We believe a broad denition of needs for repro-
ductive resources is necessary to allow all members of society to engage in
meaningful dialogue regarding procreative goals, and strategies that will help to
achieve them. Such a denition respects the fulllment of procreative or par-
enting goals as a fundamental capability of human lives, and enables a more
transparent examination of resource allocation practices and policies and ef-
forts to prioritize or discriminate between needs more equitably.
Recognition of needs is not synonymous with recognition of procreative
rights. The implications of a hypothetical procreative right have been debated
elsewhere (e.g., Dillard 2007); sufce to say that few societies are likely to
endorse an unlimited claim upon the resources that may be required to secure
a child for all those with infertilityeven in cases of medicalinfertility. As
noted earlier, there is considerable work to be done on the issue of just alloca-
tion of reproductive resources, and allocation criteria may vary among commu-
nities. The unique burdens and benets that may arise from creation of kinship
bonds through provision of gametes or surrogacy services may justify greater
partiality in allocation criteria in some societies than would be considered
acceptable in allocation of other biological materialsfor example, through di-
rected donations aiming to support the maintenance of relationships between
donors and recipient families.
Efforts to meet needs for reproductive resources equitably should be mir-
rored by efforts to achieve equity in donation of resources within society.
Equity in the distribution of donations is sometimes implicit in documents
contrasting self-sufciency in biological materials with cross-border trade. If
the burdens of donation are to fall within the responsibility of a community, in
order to avoid the injustice associated with foreign outsourcing, surely that
community must seek to share the burdens fairly among its members. The
removal of barriers to donation within the community assists in promoting
equity and may also enhance access to scarce resources for particular groups
within society who might otherwise be disadvantaged through lower represen-
tation among the donor population. This is particularly relevant if directed
donation of reproductive resources is heavily inuenced by sociocultural or
ethnic factors, as evidence from the marketplace suggests (e.g., Almeling 2007).
Preserving the prohibition of payment for provision of biological materi-
als, which has historically been tied to the pursuit of self-sufciency (Keown
1997), is also necessary if equity in donation is to be achieved. Although the
28 International Journal OF FEMINIST APPROACHES TO Bioethics 7:2
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
requirement for voluntary, nonremunerated donation of blood or organs
is usually linked to concerns about recipient safety and exploitation of donors,
or the concerns of commodication discussed earlier, the Council of Europe
(1990) explicitly tied the prohibition to concerns about equity in its early advo-
cacy of self-sufciency in plasma. The Council cited as one reason for the pro-
hibition social justice reasons, in order to ensure participation in donation by
all social strata of the population, irrespective of economic status(2).
The removal of disincentives, including nancial barriers, regarding
donation of reproductive resources will foster social justice and equity in dona-
tion, and, we repeat, should not be confused with nancial incentives. Simply
removing disincentives may increase the availability of reproductive resources
in some societies. Motivation of donation is nevertheless an important concern
for communities pursuing self-sufciency. If meeting needs is a shared goal
and responsibility, to what extent should community members be expected to
contribute the resources required to achieve this?
d. Donation expectations
Obligations to donate reproductive resources are likely to be more limited
than those arguably associated with donation of blood or organs (e.g., Snelling
2012;Hester 2006). The latter needs are more prevalent than those for reproduc-
tive resources, with the possible exception of specic social communities suffer-
ing high rates of infertility. The statistic promoted by the Australian Red Cross
Blood Service (2012), for example, which notes that one in three Australians will
have need of a therapeutic blood product yet only one in thirty donates blood, is
less readily translatable to donation and use of reproductive resources.
Appeals to reciprocity may be more easily made within some social com-
munities. For example, individuals and couples suffering structural infertility
may engage in a mutual exchange of resources, so that structural barriers to
procreationfor example, the absence of a sexual partner of the opposite sex
may be overcome. Penningss (2007) proposed gamete mirror exchange, in
which partners or even relatives of individuals in need of gametes could donate
their own gametes in exchange for a third partys gametes, may replicate the
success of domino chains and paired exchanges used to facilitate donation and
transplantation of kidneys.
However, the additional burdens of female reproductive labor mean that
such reciprocal exchanges may involve inevitable inequalities in the distribution
DOMINIQUE MARTIN AND STEFAN KANE 29
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
of burdens, if not benets of donation. The nature of female reproductive labor
and the incalculable potential costs of genetic or gestational parenthood (Crozier
and Martin 2012, 49) suggest that donation of reproductive resources will
remain an exceptional act, rather than a societal expectation. Rather than limit-
ing the relevance of the self-sufciency concept, with its solidaristic foundations,
we believe this makes it all the more necessary for use in policy making in the
reproductive eld.
e. Meeting needs for reproductive resources
Just as persons with organ failure or anemia might have their therapeutic
needs met using alternatives to transplants or transfusions, intending parents
may achieve their goals of parenting without using reproductive resources:
with options including adoption, fostering, and other informal opportunities
for parenting. Alternatives to creating children through ART may be limited
due to nancial and regulatory barriers (e.g., Kamarck et al. 2012) and lack of
children available for adoption (e.g., Cuthbert et al. 2010). Furthermore, foster-
ing or adoption may not fulll parenting goals for couples or individuals who
wish to create a child using their own genetic material(s), or who wish to carry
a child using provided gametes.
Unfortunately, socially dominant conceptions of traditional families or
parenting may exclude some individuals or couples from accessing these op-
tions, reinforcing the barriers to parenthood associated with structuralinfer-
tility. Such exclusions should be addressed within the self-sufciency
framework as equity in the allocation of reproductive resources and in access to
ART is pursued. Needs for reproductive resources may also be reduced through
strategies to prevent infertility. Strategies may include: public health interven-
tions (Macaluso et al. 2010); improved access to fertility preservation treat-
ments for young people undergoing oncology treatment (Levine et al. 2010), or
women who anticipate delayed reproduction (van Loendersloot et al. 2011);
and social policy interventions to facilitate earlier reproduction and to engage
with socioculturally constructed procreative goals. Education campaigns to
raise awareness of infertility and its varied etiology, and of opportunities for
prevention, will play an important role in minimizing needs (see Hammarberg
et al. 2013;Wyndham et al. 2012;Lemoine and Ravitsky 2013, 67). Recogni-
tion and engagement with social and cultural norms that may play a role
in shaping expectations and desires for children are also critical (Greil et al.
2011).
30 International Journal OF FEMINIST APPROACHES TO Bioethics 7:2
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
6. Achieving self-sufciencya call for innovation
Progress toward self-sufciency will depend on innovation and a coordi-
nated, multifaceted approach to the complex issue of meeting needs for repro-
ductive resources. The practical elements recognized as essential for progress in
meeting needs for blood or organs are equally relevant to reproductive re-
sources. These may be summarized as the POLIS model: public health, for the
prevention and treatment of needs; organization, with a national authority tak-
ing responsibility for oversight and coordination of various strategic elements
and infrastructure; legislation, to protect the interests of intending parents,
donors, and children; information, through the systematic and transparent col-
lection of data to inform policy and practice through quality and safety evalua-
tion; and societal engagement, through debate and education, to encourage
solidarity and enfranchise all members of the community in opportunities to
donate or receive resources when needed.
A paradigm shift is required, which must relocate infertility in the public,
relational sphere, and reconsider the widespread commodication of ART and
reproductive resources. Advocates of regulated markets will likely be skeptical
of our proposals feasibility, yet, despite the obvious inuence of nancial in-
centives on supplies of gametes and surrogacy services, it would be unwise to
conclude that such incentives are necessary, let alone sufcient, to meet societal
needs for these resources. Studies of actual providers and surrogatesboth
paid and unpaidcite various motivating factors, including a strong emphasis
on altruistic or solidaristic motivations (Purewal and van den Akker 2009c;
van den Akker 2003). There have been few studies of general public attitudes
toward donation and surrogacy (e.g., Purewal and van den Akker 2009a,
2009b;Poote and van den Akker 2009), which, compounded by a lack of public
awareness of the extent of infertility and needs for reproductive resources, pre-
sumably contributes to the current poor rates of unpaid provision through lack
of promotional and educational campaigns informed by knowledge of these at-
titudes. Novel strategies to promote donation might include, for example, the
creation of new opportunities to share resources, such as donating surplus
embryos or gametes that have been procured for personal use and would other-
wise be discarded (e.g., Nachtigall et al. 2009;Mertes et al. 2012).
Successfully implementing the self-sufciency framework with respect to
reproductive resources in any society will require a complete overhaul of poli-
cies and practices concerning procurement, use, and distribution of gametes
DOMINIQUE MARTIN AND STEFAN KANE 31
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
and surrogacy services. The process must begin with public debate about issues
surrounding infertility, ART, and the procurement of resources, as well as
transnational reproductive travel. Change, innovation, and successful efforts to
meet needs effectively and ethically within the domestic setting will take con-
siderable time and public investment. Different societies may choose to priori-
tize particular strategies and adopt unique pathways to self-sufciency, taking
into consideration their own resource constraints, current practices, and socio-
cultural values. Regardless of the anticipated diversity in such approaches, the
self-sufciency framework and its central ethos will lay the foundations for a
more responsible, socially integrated approach to the hazards of transnational
trade and the problem of unmet needs for reproductive resources. It represents
a novel approach to issues that have traditionally been fragmented and rele-
gated to the private market sphere, one that offers rich opportunities for explo-
rationfor example, through the lens of feminist bioethics or Aristotelian
ethicsand one that may nally lay the foundations for a united, collaborative
approach to the global and local challenges of meeting needs for all human bio-
logical materials.
Notes
1. We agree with Downie and Baylis (2013, 225) that the term donor is often
misleadingfor example, where providers of gametes or surrogacy services receive
remuneration exceeding the costs they may incur, as such payment (commonly
described as compensation) represents a nancial incentive and commodies the repro-
ductive labor and/or resources in question. Thus, we use the term providerto refer
to men or women from whom gametes are obtained for use by another individual or
couple, regardless of whether they are genuine donors or vendors.
2. For simplicity, we use the term surrogateor surrogacyto refer to both
gestationaland traditionalsurrogacy, and do not engage with issues that may be
specic to traditional or genetic and gestationalsurrogacy.
3. We use the term intending parent(s)to refer to individuals or couples who
plan to create a child using ART and provided oocytes, sperm, and/or surrogacy ser-
vices.
4. We focus primarily on the use of ova and surrogacy services: rst, because the
ease of transferring sperm internationally makes it easier for individuals in some coun-
tries simply to import sperm rather than traveling abroad to obtain it, although donor
sperm are still frequently used by those traveling abroad to access reproductive services
(Pennings 2010;Sheneld et al. 2010); second, because the nature of female reproductive
labor involved in provision of ova or surrogacy services creates additional burdens for
providers, such as increased risks to health.
32 International Journal OF FEMINIST APPROACHES TO Bioethics 7:2
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
5. One exception is France, where national monitoring of ART enables collation
of data. In 2009, the Agence de la Biomédicine reported 1,673 couples were wait-listed at
French clinics for donor eggs, with 328 women undergoing pick-up for egg donation
enabling 641 IVF attempts (Agence de la Biomédicine 2012a, 2).
6. New Zealand is a notable exception (Gillett et al. 2012).
7. In countries such as the United Kingdom, patients may subsidize the costs of ac-
cessing ART by sharingsome of the ova procured during their own treatment with
other patients, in return for discounted treatment fees (Blyth and Golding 2008). Some
gametes may of course be shared without such nancial incentives.
8. Aristotle discusses autarkeia (self-sufciency) in the context of the polis
(city state) at length in The Politics (1996). He describes states as heterogenous commu-
nities in which individuals come together in pursuit of common needs and shared goals:
not a mere aggregate of persons, but, as we say, a union of them sufcing for the pur-
poses of life(177; 1328b).
References
Agence de la Biomédicine. 2012a.Fiche Cinqla situation du don de gametes en France.
http://www.agence-biomedecine.fr/IMG/pdf/che_5_situation_don_gametes_2009.
pdf
——— . 2012b.Fiche Troisle don dovocytes.http://www.agence-biomedecine.fr/IMG/
pdf/che_3_don_dovocytes_mode_demploi.pdf.
Almeling, Rene. 2007.Selling Genes, Selling Gender: Egg Agencies, Sperm Banks, and
the Medical Market in Genetic Material.American Sociological Review 72 (3):
31940. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/000312240707200301.
——— . 2009.Gender and the Value of Bodily Goods: Commodication in Egg and
Sperm Donation.Law and Contemporary Problems 72: 3758.
Anderson, Elizabeth. 1993.Value in Ethics and Economics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Aristotle. 1996. The Politics and the Constitution of Athens. Ed. Stephen Everson. Cam-
bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Australian Red Cross Blood Service. 2012.Why Donate?http://www.donateblood.
com.au/why-donate/faq#faq_314.
Bailey, Alison. 2011.Reconceiving Surrogacy: Toward a Reproductive Justice Account
of Indian Surrogacy.Hypatia 26 (4): 71541. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1527-
2001.2011.01168.x
Baker, Jordan. 2012.Australians Fly Overseas to Find Egg Donors and Surrogate
Mothers.Daily Telegraph, September 30. http://www.dailytelegraph.com.au/news/
opinion/australians-y-overseas-to-nd-egg-donors-and-surrogate-mothers-but-
what-happens-when-the-children-grow-up/story-e6frezz0-1226484016257.
Barrington, Keith J., and Annie Janvier. 2013.The Paediatric Consequences of Assisted
Reproductive Technologies, with Special Emphasis on Multiple Pregnancies.Acta
Paediatrica (Oslo, Norway) 102 (4): 34048. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/apa.12145.
Medline:23278110
DOMINIQUE MARTIN AND STEFAN KANE 33
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Baylis, Françoise, N. P. Kenny, and Susan Sherwin. 2008.A Relational Account of Pub-
lic Health Ethics.Public Health Ethics 1 (3): 196209. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/
phe/phn025
Berend, Zsuzsa. 2010.Surrogate Losses: Understandings of Pregnancy Loss and Assisted
Reproduction among Surrogate Mothers.Medical Anthropology Quarterly 24 (2):
24062. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1548-1387.2010.01099.x. Medline:20550095
Blyth, Eric, and Berenice Golding. 2008.Egg Sharing: A Practical and Ethical Option in
IVF?Expert Review of Obstetrics & Gynecology 3 (4): 46573. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1586/17474108.3.4.465
Blyth, Eric, Petra Thorn, and Tewes Wischmann. 2011.CBRC and Psychosocial Coun-
selling: Assessing Needs and Developing an Ethical Framework for Practice.
Reproductive Biomedicine Online 23 (5): 64251. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/
j.rbmo. 2011.07.009. Medline:21962772
Bodri, Daniel. 2013.Risk and Complications Associated with Egg Donation.In Princi-
ples of Oocyte and Embryo Donation, ed. Mark V. Sauer, 20519. London:
Springer. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4471-2392-7_16
Boivin, Jackie, Laura Bunting, John A. Collins, and Karl G. Nygren. 2007.International
Estimates of Infertility Prevalence and Treatment-Seeking: Potential Need and
Demand for Infertility Medical Care.Human Reproduction (Oxford, England) 22
(6): 150612. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/humrep/dem046. Medline:17376819
Cahn, Naomi. 2009.Necessary Subjects: The Need for a Mandatory National Donor
Gamete Databank.DePaul Journal of Health Care Law 12 (1): 20324.
Chambers, Georgina M., Elizabeth A. Sullivan, Osamu Ishihara, Michael G. Chapman,
and G. D. Adamson. 2009.The Economic Impact of Assisted Reproductive Tech-
nology: A Review of Selected Developed Countries.Fertility and Sterility 91 (6):
228194. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.fertnstert.2009.04.029. Medline:19481642
Chambers, Georgina M., Yueping A. Wang, Michael G. Chapman, V. P. Hoang, Eliza-
beth A. Sullivan, Hossam I. Abdalla, and William Ledger. 2013.What Can We
Learn from a Decade of Promoting Safe Embryo Transfer Practices? A Compara-
tive Analysis of Policies and Outcomes in the UK and Australia, 20012010.
HumanReproduction(Oxford,England)28 (6): 167986. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1093/humrep/det080. Medline:23548332
Chung, Lisa H. 2006.Free Trade in Human Reproductive Cells: A Solution to Procre-
ative Tourism and the Unregulated Internet.Minnesota Journal of International
Law 15 (1): 26396.
Cohen, I. Glenn. 2012.Circumvention Tourism.Cornell Law Review 97 (6): 130998.
Medline:23072007
Council of Europe. 1990.Recommendation No R(90)9 of the Committee of Ministers
to Member States on Plasma Products and European Self-Sufciency.https://
www.edqm.eu/site/Recommendation_No_R909_of_the_Committee_of_Minis
ters_to_member_states_on_plasma_products_and_European_self_sufciency-
en-7001-2.html.
34 International Journal OF FEMINIST APPROACHES TO Bioethics 7:2
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Crozier, Gillian K. D., and Dominique Martin. 2012.How to Address the Ethics of
Reproductive Travel to Developing Countries: A Comparison of National Self-
Sufciency and Regulated Market Approaches.Developing World Bioethics 12
(1): 4554. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1471-8847.2012.00316.x. Medline:22420451
Culley, Lorraine, Nicky Hudson, Eric Blyth, Wendy Norton, Allan Pacey, and Frances
Rapport. 2013.“‘What Are You Going to Do, Conscate Their Passports?
Professional Perspectives on Cross-Border Reproductive Travel.Journal of
Reproductive and Infant Psychology 31 (1): 4657. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/
02646838.2012.762084
Cuthbert, Denise, Ceridwen Spark, and Kate Murphy. 2010.“‘That Was Then, but This
Is Now: Historical Perspectives on Intercountry Adoption and Domestic Child
Adoption in Australian Public Policy.Journal of Historical Sociology 23 (3): 427
52. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-6443.2010.01376.x. Medline:20845588
Daar, Judith F. 2008.Accessing Reproductive Technologies: Invisible Barriers, Indelible
Harms.Berkeley Journal of Gender Law & Justice 23 (1): 1882.
Delmonico, Francis L., Beatriz Domínguez-Gil, Rafael Matesanz, and Luc Noël. 2011.
A Call for Government Accountability to Achieve National Self-Sufciency in
Organ Donation and Transplantation.Lancet 378 (9800): 141418. http://dx.doi.
org/10.1016/S0140-6736(11)61486-4. Medline:22000137
Deonandan, Raywat, Samantha Green, and Amanda van Beinum. 2012.Ethical Concerns
for Maternal Surrogacy and Reproductive Tourism.Journal of Medical Ethics 38
(12): 74245. http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2012-100551. Medline:23047836
Dillard, Carter. 2007.Rethinking the Procreative Right.Yale Human Rights and Devel-
opment Law Journal 10 (1): 163.
Donchin, Anne. 2010.Reproductive Tourism and the Quest for Global Gender Justice.
Bioethics 24 (7): 32332. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8519.2010.01833.x.
Medline:20690916
Downie, Jocelyn, and Françoise Baylis. 2013.Transnational Trade in Human Eggs:
Law, Policy, and (In)Action in Canada.Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 41 (1):
22439. Medline:23581667
Duffy, Deirdre A., John C. Nulsen, Donald B. Maier, Lawrence Engmann, David
Schmidt, and Claudio A. Benadiva. 2005.Obstetrical Complications in Gesta-
tional Carrier Pregnancies.Fertility and Sterility 83 (3): 74954. http://dx.doi.
org/10.1016/j.fertnstert.2004.08.023. Medline:15749509
Ethics Committee of American Society for Reproductive Medicine. 2013.Cross-Border
Reproductive Care: A Committee Opinion.Fertility and Sterility 100 (3): 64550.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.fertnstert.2013.02.051. Medline:23523262
Frith, Lucy, Eric Blyth, and Abigail Farrand. 2007.UK Gamete DonorsReections on
the Removal of Anonymity: Implications for Recruitment.Human Reproduction
(Oxford, England) 22 (6): 167580. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/humrep/dem061.
Medline:17449513
García-Ruiz, Yolanda, and Diana Guerra-Diaz. 2012.Gamete and Embryo Donation: A
Legal View from Spain.In Reproductive Donation: Practice, Policy and Bioethics,
DOMINIQUE MARTIN AND STEFAN KANE 35
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ed. Martin Richards, Guido Pennings, and John B. Appleby, 11229. New York:
Cambridge University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139026390.007
Gilbertson, David T., Jiannong Liu, Jay L. Xue, Thomas A. Louis, Craig A. Solid, James
P. Ebben, and Allan J. Collins. 2005.Projecting the Number of Patients with
End-Stage Renal Disease in the United States to the Year 2015.Journal of the
American Society of Nephrology 16 (12): 373641. http://dx.doi.org/10.1681/
ASN.2005010112. Medline:16267160
Gillett, Wayne R., John C. Peek, and G. P. Herbison. 2012.Development of Clinical Pri-
ority Access Criteria for Assisted Reproduction and Its Evaluation on 1386 Infer-
tile Couples in New Zealand.Human Reproduction (Oxford, England) 27 (1):
13141. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/humrep/der372. Medline:22081248
Golombok, Susan, Lucy Blake, Polly Casey, Gabriela Roman, and Vasanti Jadva. 2013.
Children Born through Reproductive Donation: A Longitudinal Study of Psycho-
logical Adjustment.Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, and Allied Disci-
plines 54 (6): 65360. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/jcpp.12015. Medline:23176601
Greil, Arthur, Julia McQuillan, and Kathleen SlausonBlevins. 2011.The Social Con-
struction of Infertility.Social Compass 5 (8): 73646. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/
j.1751-9020.2011.00397.x
Gruenbaum, Benjamin F., Zachary S. Pinchover, Eitan Lunenfeld, and Alan Jotkowitz.
2011.Ovum Donation: Examining the New Israeli Law.European Journal of
Obstetrics, Gynecology, and Reproductive Biology 159 (1): 4042. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1016/j.ejogrb.2011.07.011. Medline:21824713
Gurmankin, Andrea D. 2001.Risk Information Provided to Prospective Oocyte Donors
in a Preliminary Phone Call.American Journal of Bioethics 1 (4): 313. http://dx.
doi.org/10.1162/152651601317139207. Medline:11954633
Hammarberg, Karin, Tracey Setter, Robert J. Norman, Carol A. Holden, Janet Michel-
more, and Louise Johnson. 2013. Knowledge about Factors That Inuence Fertil-
ity among Australians of Reproductive Age: A Population-Based Survey.Fertility
and Sterility 99 (2): 5027. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.fertnstert.2012.10.031.
Medline:23158832
Haxton, Nancy. 2013.Indian Surrogacy Change Cuts Off Aussie Parents.ABC News
(Australian Broadcasting Corporation), January 15. http://www.abc.net.au/news/
2013-01-15/india-surrogacy-arrangements/4465198.
Hester, D. Micah. 2006.Why We Must Leave Our Organs to Others.American Jour-
nal of Bioethics 6 (4): W23W28. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/15265160600755839.
Medline:16885086
Hibino, Yuri, and Yosuke Shimazono. 2013.Becoming a Surrogate Online: Message
BoardSurrogacy in Thailand.Asian Bioethics Review 5 (1): 5672. http://dx.doi.
org/10.1353/asb.2013.0004
Holland, Suzanne. 2001.Contested Commodities at Both Ends of Life: Buying and Sell-
ing Gametes, Embryos, and Body Tissues.Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 11
(3): 26384. http://dx.doi.org/10.1353/ken.2001.0025. Medline:11700683
36 International Journal OF FEMINIST APPROACHES TO Bioethics 7:2
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Hudson, Nicky, Lorraine Culley, Eric Blyth, Wendy Norton, Frances Rapport, and Allan
Pacey. 2011. Cross-Border Reproductive Care: A Review of the Literature.
Reproductive Biomedicine Online 22 (7): 67385. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.
rbmo.2011.03.010. Medline:21498121
Humbyrd, Casey. 2009.Fair Trade International Surrogacy.Developing World
Bioethics 9(3):11118. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1471-8847.2009.00257.x.
Medline:19508290
Inhorn, Marcia C. 2012.Reproductive Exile in Global Dubai: South Asian Stories.Cul-
tural Politics 8 (2): 283306. http://dx.doi.org/10.1215/17432197-1575174
Inhorn, Marcia C., and Pasquale Patrizio. 2012.The Global Landscape of Cross-Border
Reproductive Care: Twenty Key Findings for the New Millennium.Current
Opinion in Obstetrics & Gynecology 24 (3): 15863. http://dx.doi.org/10.1097/
GCO.0b013e328352140a. Medline:22366965
Ireni-Saban, Liza. 2013.Give Me Children or Else I Die: The Politics and Policy of
Cross-Border Reproductive Care.Politics & Policy 41 (1): 538.
Jadva, Vasanti, Lucy Blake, Polly Casey, and Susan Golombok. 2012.Surrogacy Fa-
milies 10 Years On: Relationship with the Surrogate, Decisions over Disclosure
and Childrens Understanding of Their Surrogacy Origins.Human Reproduction
(Oxford, England) 27 (10): 300814. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/humrep/des273.
Medline:22814484
Jadva, Vasanti, Tabitha Freeman, Wendy Kramer, and Susan Golombok. 2010.Experi-
ences of Offspring Searching for and Contacting Their Donor Siblings and
Donor.Reproductive Biomedicine Online 20 (4): 52332. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1016/j.rbmo.2010.01.001. Medline:20129827
——— . 2011.Sperm and Oocyte DonorsExperiences of Anonymous Donation and
Subsequent Contact with Their Donor Offspring.Human Reproduction
(Oxford, England) 26 (3): 63845. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/humrep/deq364.
Medline:21177310
Janwalkar, Mayura. 2012.17-Yr-Old Egg Donor Dead, HC Questions Fertility Centres
Role.Indian Express, July 12. http://www.indianexpress.com/news/17yrold-egg-
donor-dead-hc-questions-fertility-centre-s-role/973327/0.
Jayanti, Suriya E. 2008.Guarantors of Our Genes: Are Egg Donors Liable for Latent Genetic
Disease?American University Law Review 58 (2): 40557. Medline:20222215
Jones, Mavis, and Jeff Nisker. 2013.Health Equity and Access to Oocyte Donation.In
Principles of Oocyte and Embryo Donation, ed. Mark V. Sauer, 37182. London:
Springer. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4471-2392-7_27
Kalfoglou, Andrea L., and Joel Gittelsohn. 2000.A Qualitative Follow-Up Study of Wom-
ens Experiences with Oocyte Donation.Human Reproduction (Oxford, England)
15 (4): 798805. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/humrep/15.4.798. Medline:10739823
Kamarck, E., E. Mary Hansen, Julie B. B. Wilson, and Jeff Katz. 2012.Eliminating Bar-
riers to the Adoption of Children from Foster Care.HKS Faculty Research
Working Paper Series RWP12040, John F. Kennedy School of Government, Har-
vard University. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:9804493.
DOMINIQUE MARTIN AND STEFAN KANE 37
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Keehn, Jason, Eve Holwell, Ruqayyah Abdul-Karim, Lisa J. Chin, Cheng-Shiun Leu,
Mark V. Sauer, and Robert Klitzman. 2012.Recruiting Egg Donors Online: An
Analysis of In Vitro Fertilization Clinic and Agency WebsitesAdherence to Amer-
ican Society for Reproductive Medicine Guidelines.Fertility and Sterility 98 (4):
9951000. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.fertnstert.2012.06.052. Medline:22840240
Keown, John. 1997.The Gift of Blood in Europe: An Ethical Defence of EC Directive
89/381.Journal of Medical Ethics 23 (2): 96100. http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/
jme.23.2.96. Medline:9134490
Kroløkke, Charlotte H., and Saumya Pant. 2012.“‘I Only Need Her Uterus: Neo-Liberal
Discourses on Transnational Surrogacy.NORA 20 (4): 23348. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1080/08038740.2012.729535
Lee, Ruby L. 2009.New Trends in Global Outsourcing of Commercial Surrogacy: A
Call for Regulation.Hastings Womens Law Journal 20: 275300.
Leikola, Juhani. 1987.Self-Sufciency in Blood Products: Background and Overview.
Plasma Therapy & Transfusion Technology 8 (3): 21520. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1016/S0278-6222(87)80056-6
Lemoine, Marie-Eve, and Vardit Ravitsky. 2013.Toward a Public Health Approach to
Infertility: The Ethical Dimensions of Infertility Prevention.Public Health Ethics
6 (3): 287301. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/phe/pht026
Levine, Aaron D. 2010.Self-Regulation, Compensation, and the Ethical Recruitment of
Oocyte Donors.Hastings Center Report 40 (2): 2536. http://dx.doi.org/10.1353/
hcr.0.0245. Medline:20391847
Levine, Jennifer, Andrea Canada, and Catharyn J. Stern. 2010.Fertility Preservation in
Adolescents and Young Adults with Cancer.Journal of Clinical Oncology 28 (32):
483141. http://dx.doi.org/10.1200/JCO.2009.22.8312. Medline:20458029
London Clinic. 2013.http://www.londonwomensclinic.com/.
Luk, Janelle, and John C. Petrozza. 2008.Evaluation of Compliance and Range of Fees
among American Society for Reproductive MedicineListed Egg Donor and
Surrogacy Agencies.Journal of Reproductive Medicine 53 (11): 84752. Med-
line:19097517
Lundin, Susanne. 2012.“‘I Want a Baby; Dont Stop Me from Being a Mother: An Eth-
nographic Study on Fertility Tourism and Egg Trade.Cultural Politics 8 (2): 327
44. http://dx.doi.org/10.1215/17432197-1575192
Macaluso, Maurizio, Tracie J. Wright-Schnapp, Anjani Chandra, Robert Johnson, Ca-
therine L. Satterwhite, Amy Pulver, Stuart Berman, Richard Y. Wang, Sherry Farr,
and Lori A. Pollack. 2010.A Public Health Focus on Infertility Prevention,
Detection, and Management.Fertility and Sterility 93 (1): 16e116e10. http://dx.
doi.org/10.1016/j.fertnstert.2008.09.046. Medline:18992879
Maheshwari, Abha, Siriol Grifths, and Siladitya Bhattacharya. 2011.Global Variations
in the Uptake of Single Embryo Transfer.Human Reproduction Update 17 (1):
10720. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/humupd/dmq028. Medline:20634207
Mancini, Fulvia, Elisabet Clua, Francisca Martínez, Cesare Battaglia, Anna Veiga, and
Pedro N. Barri. 2011.Heterotopic Pregnancy in a Cross Border Oocyte Donation
38 International Journal OF FEMINIST APPROACHES TO Bioethics 7:2
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Patient: The Importance of Cooperation between Centers.Fertility and Sterility
95 (7): 2432e132432e 15. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.fertnstert.2011.03.092.
Medline:21601667
Martin, Dominique. 2010.Medical Travel and the Sale of Human Biological Materials:
Suggestions for Ethical Policy Development.Global Social Policy 10 (3): 37795.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/1468018110379979
——— . 2013.Charitable Incentives for Blood Donation Are Promising, but Require
Careful Consideration.American Journal of Bioethics 13 (6): 5254. http://dx.doi.
org/10.1080/15265161.2013.781706. Medline:23641854
Matas, Arthur J., Benjamin Hippen, and Sally Satel. 2008.In Defense of a Regulated
System of Compensation for Living Donation.Current Opinion in Organ Trans-
plantation 13 (4): 37985. http://dx.doi.org/10.1097/MOT.0b013e328308b2d9.
Medline:18685333
Maxwell, Kara N., Ina S. Cholst, and Zev Rosenwaks. 2008.The Incidence of Both Serious
and Minor Complications in Young Women Undergoing Oocyte Donation.Fertil-
ity and Sterility 90 (6): 216571. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.fertnstert.2007.10.065.
Medline:18249368
McKelvey, Alastair, Anna L. David, Françoise Sheneld, and Eric R. Jauniaux. 2009.
The Impact of Cross-Border Reproductive Care or Fertility Tourismon
NHS Maternity Services.BJOG: An International Journal of Obstetrics & Gynae-
cology 116 (11): 152023. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1471-0528.2009.02294.x.
Medline:19614936
Medew, Julia. 2013.Surrogacys Painful Path to Parenthood.The Age (Melbourne,
Australia), March 23. http://www.theage.com.au/national/surrogacys-painful-
path-to-parenthood-20130322-2glhn.html.
Medew, Julia, and Mark Baker. 2013.Making Babies.Sydney Morning Herald (Sydney,
Australia), October 19. http://www.smh.com.au/national/health/making-babies-
20131014-2vhbk.html.
Mertes, Heidi, Guido Pennings, Wybo Dondorp, and Guido de Wert. 2012.Implica-
tions of Oocyte Cryostorage for the Practice of Oocyte Donation.Human Repro-
duction (Oxford, England) 27 (10): 288693. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/humrep/
des250. Medline:22802093
Millibank, Jenni. 2013.Paying for Birth: The Case for (Cautious) Commercial Surro-
gacy.The Guardian, September 2. http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/
2013/sep/02/australia-commercial-surrogacy.
Ministry of Home Affairs. 2012.Type of Visa for Foreign Nationals Intending to Visit
India for Commissioning Surrogacy and Conditions for Grant Visa for the Purpose.
Government of India. http://mha1.nic.in/pdfs/CS-GrntVISA-291112.pdf.
Mladovsky, Philipa, and Corinna Sorenson. 2010.Public Financing of IVF: A Review of
Policy Rationales.Health Care Analysis 18 (2): 11328. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/
s10728-009-0114-3. Medline:19343499
DOMINIQUE MARTIN AND STEFAN KANE 39
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Mohapatra, Seema. 2012.Stateless Babies and Adoption Scams: A Bioethical Analysis
of International Commercial Surrogacy.Berkeley Journal of International Law
30 (2): 41250.
Motluk, Alison. 2010.The Human Egg Trade.Walrus, April. http://thewalrus.ca/the-
human-egg-trade/.
Nachtigall, Robert D., Kirstin MacDougall, Jennifer Harrington, Julia Duff, Matthew Lee,
and Gay Becker. 2009. How Couples Who Have Undergone In Vitro Fertilization
Decide What to Do with Surplus Frozen Embryos.Fertility and Sterility 92 (6):
209496. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.fertnstert.2009.06.027. Medline:19700150
Nahman, Michal. 2011.Reverse Trafc: Intersecting Inequalities in Human Egg Dona-
tion.Reproductive Biomedicine Online 23 (5): 62633. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/
j.rbmo.2011.08.003. Medline:21945267
Nash, Meredith. 2012.Women Who Donate Their Eggs Deserve Compensation
HeresWhy.The Conversation, November 9. http://theconversation.com/
women-who-donate-their-eggs-deserve-compensation-heres-why-10515.
Nelson, Erin. 2013.Global Trade and Assisted Reproductive Technologies: Regulatory
Challenges in International Surrogacy.Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 41 (1):
24053. Medline:23581668
Noël, Luc, and Dominique Martin. 2009.Progress towards National Self-Sufciency in
Organ Transplants.Bulletin of the World Health Organization 87 (9): 647. http://
dx.doi.org/10.2471/BLT.09.068817. Medline:19784439
Nowoweiski, Sarah, Hayley Matic, and Penelope Foster. 2011.Patient Experiences in
Advertising for an Egg Donor.Reproductive Biomedicine Online 22 (7): 68691.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.rbmo.2011.03.009. Medline:21498120
Palattiyil, George, Eric Blyth, Dina Sidhva, and Geeta Balakrishnan. 2010.Globalization
and Cross-Border Reproductive Services: Ethical Implications of Surrogacy in
India for Social Work.International Social Work 53 (5): 686700. http://dx.doi.
org/10.1177/0020872810372157.
Pande, Amrita. 2009.Not an Angel,Not a Whore: Surrogates as DirtyWorkers in
India.Indian Journal of Gender Studies 16 (2): 14173. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/
097152150901600201
——— .2011.Transnational Commercial Surrogacy in India: Gifts for Global Sisters?
Reproductive Biomedicine Online 23 (5): 61825. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.
rbmo.2011.07.007. Medline:21958916
Parks, Jennifer A. 2010.Care Ethics and the Global Practice of Commercial Surrogacy.
Bioethics 24 (7): 33340. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8519.2010.01831.x.
Medline:20690917
Participants in the International Summit on Transplant Tourism and Organ Trafcking.
2008.The Declaration of Istanbul on Organ Trafcking and Transplant Tour-
ism.Kidney International 74 (7): 85459. http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/ki.2008.388.
Medline:18810784
40 International Journal OF FEMINIST APPROACHES TO Bioethics 7:2
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Pennings, Guido. 2001.Distributive Justice in the Allocation of Donor Oocytes.Jour-
nal of Assisted Reproduction and Genetics 18 (2): 5663. http://dx.doi.org/10.1023/
A:1026570305919. Medline:11285981
——— . 2002.Reproductive Tourism as Moral Pluralism in Motion.Journal of Medical
Ethics 28 (6): 33741. http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/jme.28.6.337. Medline:12468650
——— . 2004.Legal Harmonization and Reproductive Tourism in Europe.Human
Reproduction (Oxford, England) 19 (12): 268994. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/hum
rep/deh486. Medline:15513984
——— . 2007.Mirror Gametes Donation.Journal of Psychosomatic Obstetrics and Gy-
naecology 28 (4): 18791. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/01674820701656492. Med-
line:17966048
——— . 2010.The Rough Guide to Insemination: Cross-Border Travelling for Donor
Semen Due to Different Regulations.Facts, Views & Vision in ObGyn (Mono-
graph): 5560.
Pennings, Guido, Guido de Wert, Françoise Sheneld, Jacques Cohen, Basil Tarlatzis,
and Paul Devroey, and the ESHRE Task Force on Ethics and Law. 2008.ESHRE
Task Force on Ethics and Law 14: Equity of Access to Assisted Reproductive Tech-
nology.Human Reproduction (Oxford, England) 23 (4): 77274. http://dx.doi.
org/10.1093/humrep/den037. Medline:18321893
Peterson, Madelyn M. 2005.Assisted Reproductive Technologies and Equity of Access
Issues.Journal of Medical Ethics 31 (5): 28085. http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/
jme.2003.007542. Medline:15863687
Pfeffer, Nancy. 2011.Eggs-Ploiting Women: A Critical Feminist Analysis of the Differ-
ent Principles in Transplant and Fertility Tourism.Reproductive Biomedicine
Online 23 (5): 63441. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.rbmo.2011.08.005. Med-
line:21945266
Poote, A. E., and Olga B. A. van den Akker. 2009.British Womens Attitudes to Surro-
gacy.Human Reproduction (Oxford, England) 24 (1): 13945. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1093/humrep/den338. Medline:18794160
Prainsack, Barbara, and Alena Buyx. 2012.Solidarity in Contemporary Bioethics
towards a New Approach.Bioethics 26 (7): 34350. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/
j.1467-8519.2012.01987.x. Medline:22827315
Purewal, Satvinder, and Olga B. A. van den Akker. 2009a.Attitudes and Intentions towards
Volunteer Oocyte Donation.Reproductive Biomedicine Online 19 (Suppl 1): 1926.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/S1472-6483(10)60059-4. Medline:19622246
——— . 2009b.A Study of the Effect of Message Framing on Oocyte Donation.Human
Reproduction (Oxford, England) 24 (12): 313643. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/hum
rep/dep342. Medline:19801573
——— . 2009c.Systematic Review of Oocyte Donation: Investigating Attitudes, Motiva-
tions and Experiences.Human Reproduction Update 15 (5): 499515. http://dx.
doi.org/10.1093/humupd/dmp018. Medline:19443709
Ramskold, Louise A. H., and Marcus P. Posner. 2013.Commercial Surrogacy: How
Provisions of Monetary Remuneration and Powers of International Law Can
DOMINIQUE MARTIN AND STEFAN KANE 41
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Prevent Exploitation of Gestational Surrogates.Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (6):
397402. http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2012-100527. Medline:23443211
Rippon, Simon. 2014.Imposing Options on People in Poverty: The Harm of a Live
Donor Organ Market.Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (3): 14550. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1136/medethics-2011-100318. Medline:22745109
Roberts, Dorothy E. 2009.Race, Gender, and Genetic Technologies: A New Reproductive
Dystopia?Signs (Chicago, Ill.) 34 (4): 783804. http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/597132.
Saravanan, Sheela. 2013.An Ethnomethodological Approach to Examine Exploitation
in the Context of Capacity, Trust and Experience of Commercial Surrogacy in
India.Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine; PEHM 8 (1): 10. http://
dx.doi.org/10.1186/1747-5341-8-10. Medline:23962325
Sarojini, Nandimpally, Vrinda Marwah, and Anjali Shenoi. 2011.Globalisation of
Birth Markets: A Case Study of Assisted Reproductive Technologies in India.
Globalization and Health 7: 27. http://dx.doi.org/10.1186/1744-8603-7-27. Med-
line:21838866
Schneider, Jennifer. 2008.Fatal Colon Cancer in a Young Egg Donor: A Physician
Mothers Call for Follow-Up and Research on the Long-Term Risks of Ovarian
Stimulation.Fertility and Sterility 90 (5): 2016.e12016.e5. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1016/j.fertnstert.2007.12.074. Medline:18314117
Sheneld, Françoise, Jacques de Mouzon, Guido Pennings, Anna-Pia Ferraretti,
A. Nyboe Andersen, Guido de Wert, and V. Goossens; ESHRE Taskforce on
Cross-Border Reproductive Care. 2010.Cross Border Reproductive Care in Six
European Countries.Human Reproduction (Oxford, England) 25 (6): 136168.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/humrep/deq057. Medline:20348165
Sheneld, Françoise, Guido Pennings, Jacques De Mouzon, Anna-Pia Ferraretti, and
V. Goossens; ESHRE Task Force on Cross-Border Reproductive Care. 2011.
ESHREs Good Practice Guide for Cross-Border Reproductive Care for Centers
and Practitioners.Human Reproduction (Oxford, England) 26 (7): 162527.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/humrep/der090. Medline:21505043
Snelling, Paul C. 2012.Challenging the Moral Status of Blood Donation.Health Care
Analysis (September): 126. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10728-012-0221-4.
Steinbock, Bonnie. 2004.Payment for Egg Donation and Surrogacy.Mount Sinai Jour-
nal of Medicine, New York 71 (4): 25565. Medline:15365592
Storrow, Richard F. 2006.The Bioethics of Prospective Parenthood: In Pursuit of the
Proper Standard for Gatekeeping in Infertility Clinics.Cardozo Law Review
28 (5): 2283320.
——— . 2011.Assisted Reproduction on Treacherous Terrain: The Legal Hazards of
Cross-Border Reproductive Travel.Reproductive Biomedicine Online 23 (5):
53845. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.rbmo.2011.07.008. Medline:21962773
Thorn, Petra, Tewes Wischmann, and Eric Blyth. 2012.Cross-Border Reproductive
ServicesSuggestions for Ethically Based Minimum Standards of Care in
Europe.Journal of Psychosomatic Obstetrics and Gynaecology 33 (1): 16. http://
dx.doi.org/10.3109/0167482X.2011.646346. Medline:22272601
42 International Journal OF FEMINIST APPROACHES TO Bioethics 7:2
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Tieu, Matthew M. 2009.Altruistic Surrogacy: The Necessary Objectication of Surro-
gate Mothers.Journal of Medical Ethics 35 (3): 17175. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1136/jme.2008.024679. Medline:19251968
Trimmings, Katarina, and Paul Beaumont. 2011.International Surrogacy Arrange-
ments: An Urgent Need for Legal Regulation at the International Level.Journal
of Private International Law 7 (3): 62747. http://dx.doi.org/10.5235/jpil.v7n3.627
van den Akker, Olga A. B. 2003.Genetic and Gestational Surrogate MothersExperi-
ence of Surrogacy.Journal of Reproductive and Infant Psychology 21 (2): 14561.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0264683031000124091
Van den Broeck, Uschi, M. Vandermeeren, D. Vanderschueren, Paul Enzlin, Koen De-
myttenaere, and Thomas DHooghe. 2013. A Systematic Review of Sperm Do-
nors: Demographic Characteristics, Attitudes, Motives and Experiences of the
Process of Sperm Donation.Human Reproduction Update 19 (1): 3751. http://
dx.doi.org/10.1093/humupd/dms039. Medline:23146866
Van Hoof, Wannes, and Guido Pennings. 2011.Extraterritoriality for Cross-Border
Reproductive Care: Should States Act against Citizens Travelling Abroad for Ille-
gal Infertility Treatment?Reproductive Biomedicine Online 23 (5): 54654.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.rbmo.2011.07.015. Medline:21955486
——— . 2012.Extraterritorial Laws for Cross-Border Reproductive Care: The Issue of
Legal Diversity.European Journal of Health Law 19 (2): 187200. http://dx.doi.
org/10.1163/157180912X628226. Medline:22558659
van Loendersloot, L. L., L. M. Moolenaar, B. W. J. Mol, S. Repping, F. van der Veen, and
M. Goddijn. 2011. Expanding Reproductive Lifespan: A Cost-Effectiveness Study
on Oocyte Freezing.Human Reproduction (Oxford, England) 26 (11): 305460.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/humrep/der284. Medline:21896545
Vora, Kalindi. 2009.Indian Transnational Surrogacy and the Commodication of Vital
Energy.Subjectivity 28 (1): 26678. http://dx.doi.org/10.1057/sub.2009.14
——— . 2013.Potential, Risk, and Return in Transnational Indian Gestational Surro-
gacy.Current Anthropology 54 (S7): S97S106. http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/671018
Watson, Julie. 2011.Surrogacy Scandal Raises Questions about Regulation,Seattle Times,
August 11. http://seattletimes.com/html/health/2015886062_surrogacy12.html.
White, Amy E. 2006.The Morality of an Internet Market in Human Ova.Journal of
Value Inquiry 40 (2): 31121.
Whitelaw, Anna. 2012.Hundreds Pay for Overseas Surrogacy.The Age (Melbourne,
Australia), June 3. http://www.theage.com.au/federal-politics/political-news/hun
dreds-pay-for-overseas-surrogacy-20120602-1zp1u.html.
Whittaker, Andrea. 2011.Cross-Border Assisted Reproduction Care in Asia: Implica-
tions for Access, Equity and Regulations.Reproductive Health Matters 19 (37):
10716. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/S0968-8080(11)37575-1. Medline:21555091
Whittaker, Andrea, and Amy Speier. 2010. “‘Cycling Overseas: Care, Commodication,
and Stratication in Cross-Border Reproductive Travel.Medical Anthropology
29 (4): 36383. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/01459740.2010.501313. Medline:21082483
DOMINIQUE MARTIN AND STEFAN KANE 43
This content downloaded from 128.250.144.144 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 18:06:30 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions