ArticlePDF Available

Strict finitism as a viable alternative in the foundations of mathematics

Authors:
Logique & Analyse 145 (1994), 23-40
STRICT FINITI S M AS A V I A BLE A L TE RNA TI V E IN THE
FOUNDATIONS O F M A T H E MA TI C S
*
1. Introduction
Jean Paul Va n BENDEGEM
Whether or not one believes tha t G6d el's theorems shattered Hilbe rt ' s
dream o f p ro vin g ma th ema tics ab s o lu t e ly con siste n t , th e t e r m
"f in it ism" i n h is philo sophy a p plie s t o the me t a le ve l o n ly. Ma ny
philosophers s e e Ernst We lt i [1987] fo r an overvie w h a v e been in-
trigued by the possib ility to extend Hilb e rt's f in itis m to the object level.
It seemed and it still seems a neat wa y to escape Goole! a ltoge the r.
Although Gödel h imself had something quite different in min d when he
wrote about " a n extension o f fin itary ma thematics tha t has n o t ye t
been used", the strict finit ist point of view too can be seen as an exten-
sion o f finitary mathematics.
Perhaps one w i l l remark that to con sider strict f in itism as an e xte n -
sion is stretching the meaning o f extension a b it, if not a b it too much.
For i t is a ve ry we ll-k n o wn remark in the literature o f philosophy o f
mathematics that strict f in it is m i s mo st su ita b ly characterized b y the
label " s t rict" . Th e re sultin g mathematics i s so p o or an d weak, th a t
terms such as trivia l, uninteresting and the lik e come t o min d . I t i s
therefore both a philosophically and mathematically interesting question
to ask whether this is necessarily so. The main thesis o f th is paper is
* This paper is essentially an improved version of a paper that was presented at and
published after the First International Symposium on GOdel's Theorems in Paris under a
slightly diff erent title: -
O n a n
e x t e n s i o n
o f
f i n i t a
r y
m a t h e
m a t i c
s
w h
i c
h
h
a
s
m
o
s
t
certainly not yet been used" (see my [1993a1). The meaning of this title is explained in
the paper. More or less the same material has been presented at a lecture at t he
Technical University of Athens, Greece on the invitation of Aristides Eitahas. My thanks
to the audience there, Kostas Gavroglu in particular, f or comments and criticisms. The
same material but in a very early stage of its development, has been presented at the
Ecole Normale Supérieure of Paris in the Séminaire de Philosophie et Mathématiques
organised by Maurice Loi. My thanks to Mauric e Loi and to Yehuda Ray f or the
invitation. Thanks also to Graham Priest for providing me with the material I needed at
precisely the right time and the opportunity to discuss the material at several places in
Australia. Finally, thanks to the "Leuven"-group on philosophy of mathematics, Leon
Horsten in particular. A "popular" version of this material was published in my [1992]
and a discussion of the relevance of this approach to Hilbert's program is to be found in
my [1993b]. Applications to physics have been treated in my [1993c] and [1994].
24 JEAN PAUL VAN BENDEGEM
that the an swe r is (mo st e mp hatically) no. A ctually, a stronge r cla im
wi l l be made. I t is po ssible to formulate a strict f in itis t ve rsion o f a
classical in f inite mathematical theory, such that the fo rmer is a p roper
extension o f the latter (without meaning stretching).
Probably one is tempted to think that this is an impossib ility. I t would
be, i f the additional claim we re th a t st rict f in it ist math e matics must
have the same lo g ical basis as cla ssica l mathe matics. Here, p a raco n-
sistency enters in to the discussion. Separating the notion o f t riv ia lity
from the notion of consistency, classical log ic can be replaced b y a mo re
generous log ic that provides the additional power to turn strict fin it ism
into a n e xtensio n o f cla ssical math e ma tics. Anyon e f a m ilia r wit h
G6del's (neo-)Platonist philosophical ideas will realize that such an ap-
proach was quite simply impossible f o r him, nothing less than a p h ilo-
sophical heresy. Hen ce I mig ht as w e ll talk abou t " a n e xtension o f
fin itary mathematics that Gödel wou ld most d efinitely not have used".
Instead o f presenting the general theory rig h t fro m the start, I will go
through a detailed discussion o f elementary number theory on the se-
mantical le v e l. I n paragraph 2 t h e standard cla ssical mo d e l is p re -
sented. I n paragraph 3 the paraconsistent vie w is introdu ced and in 4
the rich f in itist model is formulated with the follo wing properties:
(i) I f c'/' A then f
. " 1 , I f
A
i s
a
v a l i
d
s t a t
e m e n
t
i
n
c l a
ssi
c a l
e l e
m e
n t a
r y
number theory, then A is valid in rich finit ist elementary number theory.
As said before, the cla im is indeed that rich f initist number the ory is an
extension o f classical number theory.
(ii) There exists at least one non-empty subset Fin o f the set o f all f o r-
mulas F o f the language of elementary number theory, such that for A in
Fin:
Hci A iff r
• A
Furthermore this subset is easy to characterize.
In a single statement th is means that this part o f classical mathematics
can be rewritten in a st rict finit ist fashion wit h o u t the classical mathe -
matician's (qu ite understandable) wo rry th a t a ll kin d s o f nice results
wi ll disappear in the transition. What the platonist does during the day,
the finit ist can rewrite in th e evening. I n paragraph 5 , I p rese n t t h e
general method due to Graham Priest (altho ugh designed fo r d iffe rent
purposes). Finally, in 6 a philosophical discussion concludes the paper.
It mig h t help the reader to b ette r understand the approach outlined
here, i f some history is told. In previous work, I tried to formulate a type
STRICT FINITISM AS AN ALTERNATIVE FOUNDATION 25
of " strict" fin it isml in compatible with classical mathematics. Classical
theorems turned out false ("There is no largest prime nu mb er"), fin itist
theorems we re classica lly speaking false (" There i s number equal t o
its successo r" ). No t altogether satisfied wi t h t h is re s u lt , I t rie d
(though not ve ry successfully) to f in d strong e r models. F a milia r with
the wo rk on relevant and paraeonsistent lo gic, I did not realize the con-
nection there could be between these lo gics and strict finitism. Reading
the papers o f Chris Mortensen, I notice d that paraconsistent and re le-
vant mathematical theorie s t yp ica lly h a ve fin it e mode ls. I t seemed
natural to tu rn the question around: is it possible to f in itize theories b y
going paraconsistent? Unfortunately, the models Mortensen prese nted
in his papers, were not what I needed as a st rict fin it ist and i t wa s not
clear to me at the t ime h o w to generate other models. Thanks to a re-
sult o f Graham P riest (presented in paragraph 5 ), such a meth od i s
available. It is actually extremely powerful. Thus, this paper can also be
seen as a continuation o f the wo rk o f Mortensen and Priest, not f ro m
the relevant-paraconsistent point o f view but from the strict fin itist p e r-
spective. A s must be obvious, th is does n o t imp ly that they share the
latter perspective.
2. The classical case
Let PA b e the theory o f (Peano) arithmetic. Th e language o f PA con-
sists o f the language o f first-order predicate logic in it s standard f o rm
with predicates restricte d to " = " (equ a lity) and fun ctions restricte d to
"S" (su ccessor), " + " (a d d ition ) and " . " (mu ltip lica t ion ). " 0 " is the
only constant of the language.
A mo d el M o f P A i s a t ri p le M = /, v
i
) w h e r e N
i s t h e
(standard) do ma in (o f the n a tural n u m b e rs )
2
, / i s a n
i n t e r p r e t a t i o n
ing conditions:
( / I ) 1 (0 ) = 0 (where O is the number zero in the domain)
(/2) / (S x) = / ( x ) C) 1 (where (D means addition in the model)
( /3) / ( x + y) = / (x) (D 1 (y )
(14) 1 (x . y ) = 1(x) 0 1 (y) (where (g) means multip licatio n in the
1 Se e my [19871
2 No n-s t anda rd models are not c ons idered, alt hough t hey do not c omplic at e matters
in any s erious way . The only reason fo r the restriction to standard models is f o r clarity 's
sake.
26 JEAN PAUL VAN BENDEGEM
model)
(15) / ( = ) = f <n, n> I n E NI
(V I )
( V2)
( V3)
( V4)
I)
/
(
x
=
y
)
=
I
i
f
f
<
/
(
x
)
,
i
(
y
)
>
e
/
(
=
)
(or, equivalently, / (x ) = 1(y))
v l
(
-
A
)
=
1
i
f
f
v
i
(
A
)
=
0
v 1
(A
v
B
)
=
1
i
f
f
v
i
(
A
)
=
1
o
r
v
i
(
B
)
=
1
vja x A (x))= 1 i f f there is an / ' that d iffers f ro m 1 at mo st in
the value of / (x ) such that v
r
( A ( x ) ) = 1 .
A formula A is valid (-c l A ) if f for all models M, v
i
( A ) = 1 .
3. Going paraconsistent
In order to prepare the ground f o r the strict fin itist case, one intermedi-
ate step is necessary. I n the scheme o f paragraph 2, v
i i s a f u n c t i o n
from the formulas of PA to {0 , 1}. Suppose n o w t hat v
i i s a f u n c t i o n
from th e fo rmula s o f P A to the f o ll o win g set: 1{ 0 }, 10, I I , { 1 }1
3
.
Suppose further that the conditions are replaced by:
(11)-(14) as before
(15') 1 + ( = ) = k n , n> I n e 1V)
1 - ( = ) = (IN I )( N)\ 1 +(=)
Instead o f talking o f the extension of a predicate, w e n o w t a lk o f it s
positive and its negative extension. Although not relevant at this stage,
it is a crucial step in the next paragraph.
( V
I
' )
l
e
v
/
(
x
.
y
)
i
f
f
<
1
(
x
)
,
1
(
y
)
>
e
1
+
(
=
)
0 E v 1
(x =
y )
i f
f
<
/
(
x
) ,
/
(
y
)
>
E
I
(
=
)
(V2') l e v
/
( - - A )
i f f
0
e
v
i
( A )
0 e v
i
(-
A
)
i
f
f
I
e
v
/
(
A
)
( V3') l e v
/
( A v
B )
i f f
1
e
v
/
( A )
o
r
1
e
v
i
( B
)
0 e v
t
( A
v
B
)
i
f
f
0
e
v
i
(
A
)
a
n
d
O
e
v
t
(
B
)
3 This type of valuation function has been proposed by Priest in a number of papers
and in his [1987] book (see references there).
( V4') l e v
/
( 3 x A
( x ) )
i f f
t h e
r e
i
s
a
n
/
'
t
h
a
t
d i
f f
e r
s
f
r
o
m
I
a
t
m
o
s
t
i
n
the value of / (x ) such that 1 E 1/
1
, ( A ( X ) ) .
0 E (3 x i i ( x ) ) if f for all .1' that differ fro m I at most i n th e
value of / ( x ) , 0 e v
r ( A ( x ) ) .
A formula A is valid ( p c A) iff l e v
i
( A ) f o r a l l
m o d e l s
M .
It is not that hard to see that the follo win g theorem must hold:
Theo re ml.i=pc B iff B .
Proof. I t is sufficie nt to show that th e truth value o f a formula o f the
form x = y can o n ly be (0 ] o r {
I
}
. I f s o ,
i t i s
o b v i o u s
t h a t
( V 2 ' )
,
( 1 7 3
' )
and ( V4') reduce immediate ly to (V2 ), (V3) and ( V4). Suppose then th a t
v
i
(
x
=
y
)
=
(
0
,
I
)
.
T
h
i
s
i
s
t
h
e
c
a
s
e
i
f
<
/
(
x
)
,
i
(
y
)
>
E
/
4
(
.
)
a
n
d
<1 (x), I(y )> E - (=), which is impossible. QED
Thus, although this formulatio n looks mo re complicated than the p re -
ceeding one, it is e n tirely equivalent to it. I n the next step t he va lu e
{0,1} w il l show its importance.
4. Rich f init ism
STRICT FINITISM AS AN ALTERNATIVE FOUNDATI ON 2 7
Starting with a classical model M < N , I, y> as defined i n 3, a new
model M* = < N*, I *, v * 1
. > , c a l l e d
t h e
m o d e l
d e r i v e
d
f r o
m
M ,
wil
l
b
e
constructed that has the follo wing properties:
(i) N * is finite
(ii) if c 1 B then
M* i s precisely the mo d e l th a t satisfies the first o f the two re q uire -
ments of a rich fin itist model mentioned in the introduction of this paper.
N* is the fo llowin g set: HO], [ I ], [2 ], [ L , L C) 1, .. . ]). Unle ss oth er-
wise indicated , L i s co nsidered to b e a fixe d number. Th e squ are
bracket notation is meant to clarify how the elements o f N* are relate d
to N. The easiest way is to read [n] as an equivalence class under a
(non-stipulated) equivalence relation, o r as a partition o f N in a f in ite
set o f parts.
The interpretation function I * , derived from I, is defined as follows:
28 JEAN PAUL VAN BENDEGEM
I E ( X = y) i f f < 1 * (4 1*(y)>E /*
0 E i t
i
* • (x
=
)
7 )
i
f
f
<
e ( - - A) i f f 0
/* (x),
v
t
*
.
(
A
)
/ * ( y ) > E i
* -
( = )
0 E A ) if f I E ( A )
( / I *) / * ( 0 ) = [01
(12 *) / * ( S x )= [/(Sx)1
( /3*) 1 * ( x + y) = [ 1 (x) 1 ( y ) ]
(14 *) 1 *( x . y ) = [ 1 ( . 0 0 1(y)1
(15 *) < 1 * ( 4 1 *(y)> e /* i f f there is a n E= [/(x)1, and there
i s a m e N y ll, such that < n, m > e 1 +(= )
< 1 * ( ) 1 * ( y ) > E 1* —(=) if f there is a tz E [1(x)1, and there
is a t n E [1(y)], such that < n, in > E 1 —(=).
The valuation function v
i
* . s a t i s f i e s
t h e
f o l l o w i
n g
c o n d i t
i o n s :
( 1
7
1 *
)
( I/2*)
( I/3*) I E v
i
*. ( A
v
B )
i f f
1
e
v
i
* .
( A )
o
r
l
e
v
i
* .
( B )
0 e v
i
* . ( A
v
B
)
i
f
f
0
e
4
.
(
A
)
a
n
d
1
E
4
.
(
B
)
( WO') I e v
t
* . ( 3 x A
( x ) )
i f f
t h e
r e
i s
a
n
/
* '
t h
a t
d i
f f
e r
s
f
r
o
m
/
*
a
t
m
o
s
t
in the value of / *( x ) such that I e v
1 ( A ( x ) ) .
0 e v
i
* .
( 3 x
A
(x))
i
f
f
f
o
r
a
l
l
/
*
'
t
h
a
t
d
i
f
f
e
r
f
r
o
m
/
*
a
t
m
o
s
t
i
n
the value of / *(x), 0 v
/
* . , ( A ( x ) ) .
A formula A is r*-valid ( t
-
* A ) i f f I
e v
i
s
. ( A )
f o r
a l l
m o d e
l s
M *
.
Lemma. Fo r any formula A, f o r any classical model M a nd its d e rived
model M* , we have:
(a) I f I e v
i
( A ) ,
t h e n
I
E v
i
* . ( A )
(b) I f 0 e v
i
( A ) ,
t h e n
0
e v
l
* .
( A ) .
Pro o f (by induction on the length o f the formulas):
(i) B a sis : note f irst th a t if t is a t e rm, t h en i t i s e asy t o s h o w
1*(t )=[1(0 ].
(a) Suppose now that A is x = y and that 1 v
i
( x = y ) . B y
O M ,
I e 1 )
1
(x
=
y )
i f
f
<
/
(
x
)
,
1
(
y
)
>
E
1
+
(
=
)
.
T
h
u
s
,
b
y
(
/
5
*
)
,
t
h
e
r
e
is a n ( = 1(.0)E11(x)1 and a t n (= / 3 1
) )
E [ I
M ] , s u c h
t h a t
<n , m> E + ( = ). Hence, < /* (x), r ( y ) > E /
* -
1
-
( = ) , i . e . l e
STRICT FINITISM AS AN ALTERNATIVE FOUNDATION 29
v 1
*.
(x
y
)
(b) proceeds along precisely the same lines.
(ii) Indu ction step: three cases have to be distinguished: negation, dis-
junction and the existential q uantifier. The three proofs are id e nti-
cal, I therefore restrict myself to negation. Le t A be o f the fo rm
then:
(a) I e v
1
(
C )
i f
0
E
V
/
(
C
)
then 0 e v
i
* . ( C )
b y
i n d
u c t i
o n
i f 1 e v
i
%
(
C )
,
hence if l e (— C) then J e v
i
% ( C ) .
(b) proceeds along precisely the same lines. Q E D
The central theorem is, o f course, the fact that:
Theorem 2. if 1c1 B then l= r* B.
Proof. Because of theorem I , it is sufficien t to show that if H
p c B t h e n
Hr* B. Now, if l=pc B then for all y I e ( B ) and, by the lemma, f o r all
derived models M*, for all v
i
* . , l E
( B ) ,
hence
B .
Q E
D
As said in the introduction, there is a ra t h e r easy wa y t o strengthen
theorem 2 to an equivalence. Let Fin be the subset of all formulas o f the
language of PA such that:
A E Fin if f there is no term t occurring in A such that
/ * (t ) = [L, L E K ... ]
Theorem 3. I f B E Fin then 1=cIB i f Wrf B.
Proof. I t is easy to see that f o r i, w it h the exception o f [L , L e i ,
[ i] , i . It then f o llo ws that / * reduces to I and hence 4 . to v
i
T h u s , i f
l=t-* B then B . Together with theorem 2, this shows the equivalence.
QED
Remark 1. Fin is not necessarily the o n ly set that satisfies the equiva-
lence. Fo r it is very w e ll possib le t hat a statement A does turn out
uniquely true, even though there is a te rm t occurring in it, such that
/ * (t )= [L, L e i , ...1. Example: if S(L)0 stands f o r SS S O , wit h L oc-
currences o f S, then the statement 0 < S(L)0 (wit h the standard in t e r-
pretation f o r <), is un iquely true. / * ( 0 ) = [0] = 0 and / * ( S(L)0) =
[L, L EH, . . .]. Therefore, given the classical interpretation function I , no
matter what element k we pick from [ L, LED1, ...1, we w i ll have that 0
30 JEAN PAUL VAN BENDEGEM
< k. Hence 1/;. (0 < S(LO) =111
Remark 2. I t seems quite natural to ask the question whether the above
result extends to the notion o f semantical consequence. In other words,
is it possible to extend theorem 2 to:
If A
I
,
A
2
,
A
n
1
c
l
B
t
h
e
n
A
I
,
A
2
,
A
H
r
B
?
The answer is no, as the followin g simple counterexample shows:
S ( +
1
)
0 =
S M
O
r t
S
(
L
)
0
=
S
q
L
-
0
0
.
In the classical model this holds, because both premise and conclusion
are false. Yet, in a fin ite model with domain N t [ 0 1 , [11 , [ L a i l
[ L L l
, . .
. ] 1 ,
w
e
h
a
v
e
v ;
.
( S
(
1
) 0
=
S
(
L
-
1
)
0
)
=
t
0
1
,
a
s
r
(
S
(
L
)
0
)
=
[L, Lei, ...] a nd 1*(s(L-00).[Le1[=Lel, b ut
v2.(S(L+00 = S(L)0)= to , l b as / * ( S ( L
4 - 1
) 0 ) = P ( S ( L ) 0 ) =
[ L ,
L E N , .
. . [ .
If we take L e / *( S ( L +
1
)0 ) b o t h
f o r
n
a n d
m ,
t h e
n
< n
,
m
>
=
< L
,
L
>
E I + (=), hence l e v
i
* . ( S ( L +
0
0
,
- -
- S ( L )
0 ) .
B u t
i f
w e
t a
k e
L
e
1 * ( S (
1
+
1
) 0 )
for n and L EDle / * ( S (
1
) 0 ) f o r
m
then
< n ,
m >
=
< L
,
L E D
1 >
c
h en ce 0 E 1);• ( S
( L + 1 )
0 = S
( L
) 0 ) .
Note, however, that the fo llo wing does hold:
r
(
s
(
L
+
)
0
,
s
(
'
4
0
)
(
s
(
L
)
0
,
s
(
L
-
1
)
0
)
where A D B stands for - A y B.. Furthermore, if all A, and B belong to
Fin , then the extension o f theorem 3 holds:
If A
I
,
A
2
,
A
n
1
c
1
B
t
h
e
n
A
l
,
A
2
,
r
*
B
.
5. Beyond elementary number theory?
The natural question to ask is whether this method wi l l wo rk fo r other
mathematical theories? There are two answers t o th is question. T h e
first is quite simp ly to observe that it has been done. In fact, Mortensen
in his papers [1988] and [1990] has done precisely that. I repeat that in
this sense, fro m the technical po int o f view, not much new is offered in
this paper. Wh y then did I not simp ly state Mortensen's results? B e -
cause, and this is th e second re ply, I have f o llowe d a diffe re n t route
STRICT FINIT1SM AS AN ALTERNATIVE FOUNDATION 31
leading to the same results. As a matter o f fact, wha t I have done i n
this paper is to apply a method of Priest that is fa r more general. With
just on e rest rictio n , i t i s po ssib le t o fin it iz e a lmo s t a n y the o ry.
Stepswise, with out presenting a ll the details, it goes like this:
(i) Take any first-order theory T satisfying the o n ly restriction that
the number of predicates of T is finite. Let M be a model o f T.
(ii) Re formulate T in a paraconsistent fashion, e xtending th e truth
values to (101, {0 ,1}, 1 I I instead o f (0,11.
(iii) I f the models of M are infin ite, define an equivalence relation R
over the domain D o f M, such th a t DI R is finite. O r, equiva -
lently, define a partition in a finite set of parts of the domain D
of M. Let the resulting model be MIR or M*.
(iv ) The model M I R o r M* is a finite paraconsistent model o f the
given first-order theory T such th at va lid it y is extended. Thus
MIR is a strict and rich fin it ist extension of M.
The mo st importa n t th in g t o note is th a t any equivalence rela tio n o r
partition will do. This leaves room fo r an almost unlimited n umber o f
possibilities. Indeed, Mortensen instead o f using N* , preferred to wo rk
with Mmo d n. Howeve r, f o r the st rict f in itist, the n on-trivia l p ro b le m
that remains, is to fin d an R such that the resultin g model deserves to
be called a " n a tural" mode l. Th at a model i s " n a t u ra l" is indicated,
e.g., b y the existence o f theorems such as theorem 3. Mo re ge n erally,
borrowing some terminology o f the structuralist school in philosophy o f
science, i f there is a set o f intended applications of a mathematical th e-
ory, say i n p hysics, then both the orig ina l infin ite theory and its rich
finitist extension should agree on this set. In mo re mundane language
and for the case of PA, this means that if we count with small, accessi-
ble (n o t in the set-theoretic sense o f the term, o f cou rse) o r fea sible
numbers, then both theories should agree. I f , e.g. the truth-value o f 1 ,
8 were 0 , 1 1 , the n I wo u ld not co nsid er th is a " n a tu ra l" model. A s
shown in th is paper, f o r PA such models exist.
The extension to the integers is a rather du ll exercise. Apart f ro m e x-
isting proposals, it is obvious that the most " natura l" partition o f Z, is:
Z* - ( L + 1 ) , [ - 2 ] , [ -I ] , [0 ] , [1 ] , [2 ] , [ L , LE1311, ...][.
However, entering the domain of the rationals, things become different.
One possible finite partition of Q that leads to a "natural" mo del is this
(here the square brackets refer to open or closed intervals):
(a) Q
L
=
f x
I
X
E
Q
&
X
L
J
,
Q
_
L
=
r
x
I
x
E
Q
8
c
.
x
-
1
,
1
(b) Q
d
=
{ {
,
o
/
q
l
p
i
g
Q
&
-
-
L
<
p
,
<
#
0
}
,
32 JEAN PAUL VAN BENDEGEM
(c)
a
n
d
=
{
l
x
,
y
[
x
,
y
E
Q
&
(
x
,
y
E
Q
d
o
r
x
=
-
L
o
r
y
=
L
)
& - (az)(x < z < Yckz e Qd)/•
A simp le example may illustra t e th is rath e r complicated description.
Take L = 3. Then Q is split up in:
(a) a ll fractions large r than o r equal to 3 (Q , ) a n d a ll fractions
smaller than or equal to -3 ( Q _
3
),
(b) t h e set o f determined fractions:
Qd = t
-
2 ,
- 1
,
- 1
/
2 ,
0
,
1
/
2
,
1
,
2
1
,
(c) a ll in-between in tervals, i.e. 0 -1,-1/2[,
]-1/2,0[, ] 0 ,I / 2 [ , ]1/2,1[, 11,21, 12,3[I.
There are two senses in wh ich this partition can be considered natural.
First, n ote that, i f a ll t e rms are inte rpreted in Q
d
, w e d o h a v e
t h a t
4. ((3 y )(x . y =1 )) =111. Fo r, i f r ( x ) = [ p i g ] e Q
d
, t h e n 1 * ( y ) =
E q l p l ,
but that i s an element o f Q
d a s w e l l ,
t h u s
t h e
t e r m
( p l q ) .
( q /
p )
i
s
uniquely determined, namely 1. Thus if, say, L > 10, then (1/7).7 = I
holds in t h e strict fin it ist th e o ry. No t e that this approach avoids a l l
mention of rounding-off criteria, approximate results, and the like. The
second sense is related to N and Z. I f A and B are two partitions then B
is an extension o f A (A ext B) if f f or every element a E A , there is an
element b e B such that a c b. Clearly, we have N* ext Z*. Somewhat
less cle a rly (bu t immedia te ly cle a r f ro m the e xamp le ): Z * e x t
However, it is ce rta inly (and unfortunately) not the case that th is Q * is
the on ly partitio n that satisfies Z * ext Q * . A d d itional crite ria are re -
quired. A good reason to reject a partition proposal is i f it turns out that
too many statements are true-false. Thu s, wh at might appear to be the
most "natural" pa rtition o f Q, namely
Q"=I[x , y [lx =k .3 &y =( k+ 1 ) .8 8 c -L k <L - 1 1 u
1
1
-
0
o
,
-
L
.
5
[
1
u
t
[
L
c
5
,
+
.
[
1
,
w
h
e
r
e
8
i
s
a
n
u
m
b
e
r
c
l
o
s
e
t
o
0
,
actually is not. Usin g this mode l, f o r every x, v ; • (x . x
-1 = 1 ) = 1 0 , 1 1 .
Likewise f o r every choice of x, v;.(x + 0 = x)= 1 0 , 11 including the in te-
ger values o f x. In Z* (and in N * ) these statements we re exclusive ly
true. Hence, the f irs t mode l presented i s a b e tter candidate than the
second one.
Although the full details w ill be presented in papers to follo w, inclu d -
ing strict and rich finitist geometry - see my [1987a] f or an in tuitive ap-
STRICT FINITISM AS AN ALTERNATIVE FOUNDATION 33
proach - let me ju st mention that introducing (some) irrationals is quite
easily achieved.
Suppose one would like to have A ri . Replace the interval I x , E Qind
that has A f f as a member by ]x, AU,[ and 1V2, y[ and add [ -N/] as a
member to a I I t is easy to sh o w that 1/1.((ax)(x = A ff ))
-
= P l . T o c a p -
ture in a strict fin itist theory the notion o f an irrational is not excluded,
strange though it may appear at first sight (fro m the fin itist vie wp o in t,
that is). The next step is the development o f analysis. Mortensen in his
[1990] has already developed a paraconsistent diffe rential ca lculus thus
showing, once again, that for the st rict finitist, the prob lem reduces to
find " natura l" models.
6. At what p rice rich finitism?
6.1. Fro m the classical point o f vie w, the most obviou s and "heaviest"
price to pay is to give up consistency. Perhaps one is impressed by the
idea that n o n-t rivia l strict fin it ist math ematics exists, bu t one is no t
willin g to give up consistency.
A general argument to the contrary, is this: the wh o le idea o f con sis-
tency proofs started with Hilbert's problem how to control the in troduc-
tion o f ideal elements in a mathematical theory. Typica lly, these id e a l
elements had to do with infinity. A s long as everything was finite, there
was no problem. Hence, as all models are all fin ite to start wit h , co n sis-
tency is not o f prime importance any more. Rather trivia lit y is the key
issue. We do no t want t rivia l models, say mod els with a ll state me n ts
true-false. Thus, it seems obvious that consistency and trivia lit y should
be co nsidered separate concep ts. T h in kin g w i t h in a paraco nsistent
framework does precisely that. B y dropping the ex falso, a th eory does
not become t rivia l then inconsistent. B u t classica l log ic is to a large
extent ide ntified b y the ex falso. It the refore seems unavoidable th a t
strict f init ism should go hand in hand wit h paraconsistent logic.
A more specific argument has to do wit h the paradoxical nature of the
very id ea o f a largest numbe r (o r numeral) L . The paradox i s q u ite
familiar, of course: i f L is the largest number, wha t prevents me fro m
writing down the next one, namely L91? Apparently nothing, as I have
just done p recisely that. The strict fin itist's answer is: the re is n o rea l
paradox as LED I = L. In oth e r words, a lthoug h the q uestion can be
asked: " Wh a t is th e re su lt if 1 i s added to L ?" , the a n swe r is q u ite
simply: "The number L". Note that in the question itse lf, only numerals
smaller or equal to L , are mentioned. Pleasing though this solution may
seem, it proba bly w i l l not satisfy the anti-f in itist. He o r she wil l argue
34 JEAN PAUL VAN BENDEGEM
that, perhaps the set o f numbers o r numerals is fin it e , b u t, apparently,
the number o f operations, say additions, I must be able t o t a lk about,
must be larger. Therefore, the cardin ality o f the set o f a ll additions is
larger than L. Hence, L is not the limit, and the paradox is restored.
In my [1987], I opted fo r a conve ntionalist solution: as i t does not
make sense to ta l k a bout the largest numb e r, I accepted in ste ad a
provisional largest number in f u ll knowledge o f the fact that larger finite
numerals a re imagin a b le. I n t h e appro ach o utlin e d here , a n o th er
solution is p ossible: th e large st n u mb e r is an inherently p aradoxical
id ea
4
.
It
i s
e
a
s
y
t
o
s
h
o
w
t
h
a
t
i
f
/
*
(
x
)
=
I
*
(
y
)
=
[
L
,
L
E
)
1
,
.
.
.
]
,
t
h
e
n
b
o
t
h
1 E V
*
( X
=
y
)
a
n
d
0
E
/
*
(
X
=
y
)
,
h
e
n
c
e
t
h
e
t
r
u
t
h
-
v
a
l
u
e
o
f
x
=
y
i
s
{
0
,
1
}
.
Thus, i f [L, L e 1, ...] is identified as the largest element of N * (a qu ite
natural suggestion), then the rich fin itis t mode l te lls us that it i s both
true and false that the largest natural number is equal to itself.
Another objection mig h t be raised. If one cla ims th at L = LED 1 is
true-false, wh y then does it n o t f o l lo w th at 0 S 0 (o r 0 = 1 ) i s
true-false? Wha t is wrong wit h the f o llo wing argument? Finit istica lly
speaking, as the st rict fin itis t th eory extends the classical th e o ry, th e
well-known P A-axiom must hold:
(V x)(Vy)((Sx = Sy) D (x = y))
Instantiate x by S(L)0 and y by S ( L
- 1
) 0 , a n d ( * )
b e c o m e s :
(*
)
(SS MO SS(L-00)D (smo = s(L-00) (**)
(or, if a slight abuse of language is allowed for,
(L +1 = L )D(i . , = L -1 ). )
Repeat the argument, and 0 = SO) is derivable. The answer is: because,
as we already indicated, th e strict f in it ist th e o ry does n ot extend th e
notion of semantical consequence. I t is sufficien t to explicate the phrase
"repeat the argument" in the reasoning above. To arrive at the conclu-
sion 0 = SO, one needs modus ponens. Thus, the first step wil l be:
SS(L)0 = S S (
1
-
1
) 0 , ( S S
( L ) 0
=
s s
( L - 0
0 )
D
( s
( L
) 0
=
s
( L
- 1
)
0 )
S(L)0 = S (L
-1
)0
r
The first premise is true-false as has been shown. Likewise, the second
premise is tru e-f a lse. I t i s s u ff i c i e n t t o n o t e t h a t v
i
* . ( S S ( L ) 0 =
4 I n Priest's terminology , the largest finite numb er wo uld qualify as a dialetheia (see
Priest [19871, pp. 3-9).
STRICT FINITISM AS AN ALTERNATIVE FOUNDATION 35
S S ( L
-
) 0 1
= 1
0 ,
1
1
a
n
d
v
; .
(
S
( '
4
0
=
S
(
L
-
0
0
)
=
1
0
1
.
H
o
w
e
v
e
r
,
t
h
e
c
o
n
c
l
u
-
sion S(L)0 = S ( L
- 1
) 0 i s
e x c l u s i
v e l y
f a l s
e .
H e n
c e ,
t h
e r
e
i
s
a
c
a
s
e
s
u
c
h
that the premises are true and the conclusion false. Thu s the conclusion
is not a semantical consequence o f the p remises, and th e repetition
breaks down.
6.2. One mig h t object that the use o f the truth-value {0 , 1 } is a t ric k
needed to prove the richness o f the fin it ist theory. Suppose that instead
of the set o f truth-values I {0 }, {0 , 1 }, ( I I ) we had used the set {0, 1/2,
1}, thu s o b t a in ing a f a mi lia r three -value d l o g ic . Sta tements wi t h
truth-value {0 , 1}, now have truth-value 1/2. Instead o f true-false, the y
are n ow undecided. Does not this reflect more closely the finitist's atti-
tude? A ctu ally, as has been shown b y Priest, the three-valued lo g ic is
equivalent to the paraconsistent lo g ic, i f valid ity is extended to 1 /2. A
formula A is valid if f for all models M, v(A ) = 1 o r 1/2. Thus, the problem
really comes down to this: are there any arguments fo r the fin itist to ac-
cept a statement that is undecided, in some cases as valid? Formulated
thus, the answer is yes. The undecided cases are precisely those cases
that a re n o t acce ssible t o the s t rict f in it i st (sema n t ica lly speaking),
thus they should not p la y any part in the determination whether a sen -
tence is valid o r not. In a way, the choice o f {0,1} is much clearer than
1/2. " Un decided" does n ot preclude that at a la t er stage, i t e ith er be -
comes " t ru e" o r "false". The value {0 , 1 } , however, i s a determined
value.
6.3. Let me try ye t another argument to defend the use of paraconsis-
tent logic as the underlying logic o f strict fin itism. Th ere is something
paradoxical about the fact that, on the one hand, sema n tically, e very-
thing is stric tly fin ite , wh ile, on the other hand, syn tactically, the strict
finitist and the cla ssica l mathe matician are speaking t h e same la n -
guage. Thu s, both are ab le t o asse rt t he sta tement S (L )0 = S(L+1)0.
They will , however, speak about diffe rent models, as f o r the infin itist,
the statement is false, whereas f o r the st rict finit ist i t is true-false.
These considerations - as Priest remarks in h is [1991 ] paper - mu st
remind one o f the Lfte n h eim-S ko lem t h eo rems
5
. A c t u a l l y , t h e
c o r r e -
spondence is qu ite strong. A s an example, think about the notion o f a
largest p rime number. Although on the syntactical level, there will be a
proof of the statement th at th ere is n o largest p rime number, in th e
model there def in itely is. B u t this semantical fa ct is no t expressible in
the the ory itse lf. It is reflected howeve r in th e f a ct that the theo rem
5 Dav id Isles has developed a s im ila r idea (though not in a paraconsistent f ra mework )
in his [1994] . Hi s w ork is closer to t he origina l work of Ye s s enin-Volpin , on e of the
founding fathers of modern strict f initis m. See \Mein [1987] f or details.
36 JEAN PAUL VAN BENDEGEM
"There is no largest prime number" w ill turn out to be true-false in any
particular model M. Th is can b e seen a s f o llo ws. Co n sid er the t w o
statements
(Vx)(S (L )0+ x +SO= S (40 + x) and
(Vx)(S (L )0+ x +SO S( L )0 + x).
Both are true-false. In the f irst case, a ll numerals above L collapse, and
thus all prime numbers among them collapse as well, hence there is a
largest p rime numbe r. Th e theorem is false. B u t in th e second case,
everything looks q uite classical - a ll numbers la rger than o r equal to L
are d istin ct -thus th e th eorem is true . Give n Priest's ge neral me thod
outlined i n pa ragraph 5 o f t h is p a p er, t h e f in it is t a n a lo g u e o f
L6wenheim-Skolem theorem is: Given a paraconsistent first-ord e r the -
ory T with a fin it e n u mber o f predicates, i f the t h e o ry h as mo d e ls
(countable or uncountable), it has finite models.
7. Strict fin itism witho u t cla ssical mathematics in the background.
The strongest criticism imaginable is no doubt this: granted that a form
of strict fin i t is m i s possib le , i t i s s t i l l t h e case t h a t t o b e a ble t o
formulate i t , yo u ne e d cla s sic a l stan d a rd ma th e ma tic s i n t h e
background. To be more precise, the domain N* o f the strict fin ite model
M* is a partition of a classical domain N of a classical model M. What i f
these are not available? Or, if you like , should strict finitism not have its
own proper foundations? The answer is yes.
Suppose that a strict finitist starts with a limit e d domain NJ of natural
numbers (o r numerals), Nf = 10, 1, 2, L ) . Let us, f or the moment, ig-
nore the problem o f there being a largest number o r numeral L and h o w
the strict finitist is supposed to find it
6
. S u p p o s e
f u r t h e r
t h a t
t h e
f i n i t i s t
wants to do mathematics over NJ. He or she defines a successor fu nc -
lion, addition and mu ltiplica tion over NJ, (possib ly, though n o t neces-
sarily) in the follo win g way:
(D I ) Succ: N f —NJ, such that: i f n < L, then Succ(n) = m
(whatever m is) and if n = L, then Succ(n) = L.
(D2) Eli: N J x Nf N J , such that: n EDO n
6 My [1987] focuses mainly on this type of problem, especially the first chapters where
an art if ic ial mathematician, the sheet-mathematician, is introduced (or shemath f or
short).
(D3) 0 :
Note that in (D2) and (D3), it is unnecessary to add the limi t L. Th is is
taken care of by (DI ). Example: suppose that N f = {0, I , 2 }, i.e. L = 2,
and that the result o f 2 (134 2 is asked for. Th e n 2 e 2 = 2 ED Succ(1) =
Succ(2 G) I ) = S u c c (2 e su cc ( 0 )) , S u cc(S u cc(2 e o ) ) .
Succ(Succ(2)) = Succ(2) = 2.
Given su ch a set N f with the appropriate functio ns, the language o f
classical mathematics can be interpreted as follows:
M f = <Nf, I f v f If > i s a strict f in itist model, such that:
(11f) lf (0 ) = 0
(12f) I f (S x) = Succ(if(x)) if ! fix) is defined
= L, in all other cases
(13f) I f (x + y) = I f (x) C)f (y ), if If (x) and I f (y) are defined
= L, in a ll other cases
(14f) I f (x.y) = I f(x) 0 I f(y ), if I f(x) and I f (y ) are defined
= L, in all other cases
(15l) I f -FM = f <If (x), I f (y)> I I f (x) = I f ( y))
I f -(=) = ( (Nf x N f ) \ I » - (=)) L.) t<L , L >)
The valuation function v f
i f ( w i t h
r a n g e 1
{ 0 ) ,
( 0 , 1
} ,
(
I
)
1 )
s a t i s
f i e s
t h
e
following conditions:
(V1D
(V21)
(V3f)
(V4f)
STRICT FINITISM AS AN ALTERNATIVE FOUNDATION 37
n eSucc(m) = Succ(n e m)
Nf x N f —› Nf such that: n 0 0 = 0
n 0 Succ(m) = (n 0 m) G34 n
1 e v f
if
( x
=
y
)
i
f
f
<
I
f
(
x
)
,
I
f
(
y
)
>
e
I
f
+
(
=
)
0 E y i
e
lf
(
X
=
y
)
i
f
f
<
I
f
(
x
)
,
I
f
(
y
)
>
E
I
f
-
(
=
-
)
I E l l it
(-
A )
i f f
-
0
e
v f
/f
(
A
)
0 e i f
f f
(-
A )
i f
f
-
1
e
v
f
I
f
(
A
)
l e v f
/ f
( A
v
B
)
i
f
f
I
E
V
f
i
f
(
A
)
o
r
1
E
V
f
i
f
(
B
)
0 E vf if (A v B) if f 0 e vf
if ( A ) a n d
0 e
v f
i f
( B )
1 e vf
/ f
( a v
A
( x )
)
i
f
f
t
h
e
r
e
i
s
a
n
I
f
'
t
h
a
t
d
i
f
f
e
r
s
f
r
o
m
I
f
a
t
most in the value of I f (x) such that I e v f
/ f
, ( A ( x ) ) .
0 e vf if (axA (x)) if f for all If ' that diffe r from I f at mo st in
38 JEAN PAUL VAN BENDEGEM
the value of 1f(x), 0 E 1 1
4
-
,
( A ( X ) ) .
A formula A is rf-valid l f A ) i f f 1 e i l
i f
( A ) f o r a l l
m o d e l s
M f .
Note that in the d efinitio n above, there is no need to re fer to classica l
mathematics a t all. Hen ce, i t is p e rfectly possible to formulate stric t
finitist mathematics on its o wn (a t le a st f o r ele mentary a rithme t ic).
But, it is not hard to see that the fo llowing theorem can be proved:
Theorem 4. r f A if f r * A
Proof L et Nf and N* be the domains o f resp. M f and M* . De f ine the
function N f —› N* , such th a t J (i ) = [i ] , f o r i < L , a nd I ( L ) =
[L,L 0 1,...]. Note th at J is a bijection . I t is n o w a rou tine ma tter t o
show tha t ( h p correspon ds e xa ctly t o (
J i * ) a n d v i c e
v e r s a .
T h e
conditions on the valuation function are identical in both cases, s o w e
need not bother about this. A s an example, I will take (13*):
/*(x + y)= [1(x )C) 1(y)1 (wh ere I i s th e classica l in t e rp retatio n
function wherefrom / * is derived)
Now, e ither 1f(x) and I f(y) are defined or not. In the f irst case, it fol-
lows that both / (x ) = l f (x ) and 1 (y) = If (y) (or, i f necessary, a p e rmu -
tation can be found). I t then follo ws that:
1*(x + y)= [1 (x) 0 1(y )]= J (1(x)C) 1 (y)) =-
I (I f (x ) C) 1 f(y)) = .1(1f(x + y)).
In the second case, one o r both o f /(x ) and 1(y) are not defined. I t then
follows that / (x ) > L and 1(y) > L and, certainly, / ( x + y) L. Thus:
/ * ( x + y) = [L, 1,01, „ J . J(L )=. 1 (If (x + y)).
Summarizing, we find that for all x and y:
I l f ( x + y) 1 * ( x + y)
Finally, note the necessity in (15f) to include <L, L > in the negative e x-
tension o f T h i s is necessary to obtain the translation. QED
Corollary: c l A then t f A
One might st ill object that, on the synta ctical le vel, the strict f init ist is
STRICT FINITISM AS AN ALTERNATIVE FOUNDATION 3 9
still using the complete vocabulary o f classical mathematics. Th is is in -
deed the case, but so lely f or the purpose o f setting up a translation. I f
the strict finit ist is, in any reasonable sense o f the word, strict, then he
or she will allow only a finite number of names for numbers. I f we accept
L-F1 or L.L as names, then, ob viously, one cannot avo id a (pote n tially)
infinite number o f names. Thus, an additional restriction must be made,
to the effect that, e.g., on ly terms o f a limite d co mp lexity are allowed,
where the limitations refer to the number o f operations (additions a nd
multiplications) mentioned in the t e rm. I t therefore f o llo ws tha t, syn -
tactically, the language o f the theory o ve r Nf is le ss exp re ssive than
the language o f P A, hence it cannot be an extension. Wh a t remains,
however, is that it is still the case that, i f A i s a statement that is f i n i-
tistica lly expressible, then i f A holds cla ssically, it holds fin itistica lly.
Thus, we remain as close as possible to classical mathematics.
REFE RENCES
Vrife Un iversiteit Brussel
Kurt GODEL: "On an extension o f fin ita ry mathematics which has not
yet been used", I n Solomon FE FE RMA N e t a l. (eds. ): Co llecte d
Works, Vo lu me I I , P ublicatio ns 1 938-1974, Oxfo rd Un ive rsit y
Press, Oxfo rd, 1990, pp. 271-280.
David ISLES: " Wh a t Evidence is There Th a t 2A65536 i s a Natura l
Number?", Notre Dame Jo u rn a l o f Formal Lo g ic, V o l. 33, n r. 4,
1992, pp. 465 -480.
David ISL ES: " A Finite Analog to the lA we n h eim-Sko le m Th e o rem"
Studio Logica, Vol. 53, 1994, pp. 503-532.
Robert K . MEY E R and Ch ris MORTE NS E N: "Inco nsistent Models fo r
Relevant Arithmetics", Jou rn a l of Symbolic Logic, 49, 3, 1984, pp.
917-929.
Chris MORTE NSEN: " Inco nsiste nt Nonstandard Arit h metic", Jo urn a l
of Symbolic Logic, 52, 2, 1987, pp. 512-518.
Chris MO RTENS EN: "Inconsiste n t Nu mbe r Systems", No t re Dame
Journal of Formal Logic, 29, 1, 1988, pp. 45-60.
Chris MO R T E N S E N: " Mo de ls f o r I n con siste nt a n d In co mp le t e
Differe ntial Calcu lus", No tre Dame Journal o f Formal Log ic, 31, 2,
1990, pp. 274-285.
Graham PRIEST: I n Contra d ictio n : A Stu d y o f the Transconsistent,
Martinus Nijhoff, Dordrecht, 1987.
Graham P RIES T, Ric h a rd RO U TL E Y & Jean N O RM A N (e d s. ):
Paracon sistent L og ic. E ssa y s o n t h e I n consist e n t . Mt in ch e n,
Philosophia Verlag, 1989.
Graham PRIEST: " Min ima lly Inconsistent LP", Studia L ogica, Vol. L,
40 JEAN PAUL VAN BENDEGEM
n. 2, 1991, pp. 321-331.
Graham PRIEST, " I s A rithme t ic Consistent?", Mi n d , Vo l. 103, 1994,
pp. 337-349.
Jean Paul V A N BENDEGEM: Finite, Emp iric a l Mathematics: Outline
of a Mo d e l. We rke n uitgegeven d o o r de Fa cu lte it L e ttere n en
Wijsbegeerte, R.I.J.Gent, volume 174, Gent, 1987.
Jean Pau l V A N B E NDE G E M: "Zeno 's Paradoxes and th e We y l T il e
Argument", Philosop hy o f Science, 54, 2, 1987a, pp. 295- 302.
Jean Paul V A N B E NDEGE M: " St rict Fin itis m Meant t o Please the
An ti-Fin it ist". In: ANP A West, vol. 3, no. 1, 1992, pp. 6-17.
Jean Paul V A N B E NDEGE M: " Strict, Ye t R ich Finitism", I n : Z . W.
Wo lko wski (e d .): Fi r s t Inte rn a tio n a l S ymp o siu m o n Gôd e l' s
Theorems, Wo rld Scientific, Singapore, 1993a, pp. 61-79.
Jean Paul VA N BENDE G E M: " Th e Strong Hilb e rt P rogram", Re vu e
Internation ale de Philosophie, Volume 47, no. 186, 4, 1993b, pp.
343-353.
Jean P a u l V A N B E NDE G E M: " Ho w I n fin ities Cause P roble ms in
Classical Physical Theories",. Philosophica 50, 1993c, pp. 33-54.
Jean P aul V A N B E N DE GE M: " R o ss' Pa ra d ox i s a n Imp o s s ib le
Super-Task% Th e B rit ish Journ a l fo r the Ph ilosophy o f Science,
Vol. 45, 1994, pp. 743-748.
Ernst WE L TI , D i e Philo so p h ie d e s s t rik t e n Fi n itismus. E n t wic k-
lungstheoretische u n d math e matis ch e Un t e rsuchu n ge n i , ib e r
Un e n dlich ke itsbe g riffe i n I d e e n g e sch ich t e u n d h e u t i g e r
Mathematik, Bern, Peter Lang, 1987.
... The maximally inconsistent set G is remarkable. The abstracting terms that are PFS-provably identical to G, 22 are the only terms that are clean in all nontrivial models as well as, contingent on D, invariant over all models. As an effect, PFS ∀x(∀y(y ∈ x ∧ y / ∈ x) ≡ x = G). ...
... Moreover, it is a collapsed model of Fregean set theory. The term is taken from collapsed models of arithmetic [5,14,15,16,21,22]. However, arithmetic is presumed to be consistently given by the Peano axioms, whereas the adaptive Fregean set theory is inconsistent as well as under construction. ...
... by positing Ω i+1 = Ξ i . Let AFS 1 be the sequential superposition (22), each CLuNs m i being defined by the lower limit logic CLuNs, the set of these Ω i and the Minimal Abnormality strategy. ...
Preprint
This paper defines provably non-trivial theories that characterize Frege's notion of a set, taking into account that the notion is inconsistent. By choosing an adaptive underlying logic, consistent sets behave classically notwithstanding the presence of inconsistent sets. Some of the theories have a full-blown presumably consistent set theory T as a subtheory, provided T is indeed consistent. An unexpected feature is the presence of classical negation within the language.
... The most striking one was ultraintuitionism, developed by Yesenin-Volpin in [3], that asserted that only a finite quantity of natural numbers exists. Other authors suggested that numbers are finite (see, e.g., [4,5]), while different scholars adopted a more moderate approach. The inconsistency of these alternative arithmetics lies in the fact that they are all grounded in the ordinary Diophantine arithmetic. ...
... In [5], Van Bendegem developed an inconsistent axiomatic arithmetic similar to the "machine" one described in [4]. He changed the Peano axioms so that a number that is the successor of itself exists. ...
Conference Paper
Full-text available
We present two classes of abstract prearithmetics, {AM}M≥1 and {BM}M>0. The first one is weakly projective with respect to the nonnegative real Diophantine arithmetic R+=(R+,+,×,≤R+), and the second one is projective with respect to the extended real Diophantine arithmetic R¯=(R¯,+,×,≤R¯). In addition, we have that every AM and every BM is a complete totally ordered semiring. We show that the projection of any series of elements of R+ converges in AM, for any M≥1, and that the projection of any non-indeterminate series of elements of R converges in BM, for all M>0. We also prove that working in AM, for any M≥1, and in BM, for all M>0, allows to overcome a version of the paradox of the heap.
... Other authors suggested that numbers are finite (see e.g. [2] and [4]), while different scholars adopted a more moderate approach. The inconsistency of these alternative arithmetics lies in the fact that they are all grounded in the ordinary Diophantine arithmetic. ...
... In [4], Van Bendegem developed an inconsistent axiomatic arithmetic similar to the "machine" one described in [2]. He changed the Peano axioms so that a number that is the successor of itself exists. ...
Preprint
Full-text available
We present three classes of abstract prearithmetics, $\{\mathbf{A}_M\}_{M \geq 1}$, $\{\mathbf{A}_{-M,M}\}_{M \geq 1}$, and $\{\mathbf{B}_M\}_{M > 0}$. The first one is weakly projective with respect to the nonnegative real Diophantine arithmetic $\mathbf{R_+}=(\mathbb{R}_+,+,\times,\leq_{\mathbb{R}_+})$, the second one is weakly projective with respect to the real Diophantine arithmetic $\mathbf{R}=(\mathbb{R},+,\times,\leq_{\mathbb{R}})$, while the third one is projective with respect to the extended real Diophantine arithmetic $\overline{\mathbf{R}}=(\overline{\mathbb{R}},+,\times,\leq_{\overline{\mathbb{R}}})$. In addition, we have that every $\mathbf{A}_M$ and every $\mathbf{B}_M$ are a complete totally ordered semiring, while every $\mathbf{A}_{-M,M}$ is not. We show that the projection of any series of elements of $\mathbb{R}_+$ converges in $\mathbf{A}_M$, for any $M \geq 1$, and that the projection of any non-oscillating series series of elements of $\mathbb{R}$ converges in $\mathbf{A}_{-M,M}$, for any $M \geq 1$, and in $\mathbf{B}_M$, for all $M > 0$. We also prove that working in $\mathbf{A}_M$ and in $\mathbf{A}_{-M,M}$, for any $M \geq 1$, and in $\mathbf{B}_M$, for all $M>0$, allows to overcome a version of the paradox of the heap.
... We also do not use paraconsistent logics to cope with the challenges of a finitistic view (cf. Van Bendegem, 1994, Bremer, 2007, Priest, 2013. Ideas based on "feasibility" are not relevant for our approach, an idea formulated e.g. by Parikh (1971). ...
Preprint
Full-text available
We present a dynamic model theory that avoids the paradoxes stemming from completed infinities, but does not require any translation of formulae. The main adoption is the replacement of an actual infinite carrier set by a potential infinite one, and by a finitistic interpretation of the universal quantifier.
... The second kind of context is one in which we hold fixed the kind of army Caesar had at his disposal. 24 As in van Bendegem [45]. 25 For examples of contexts like the latter, see Baron et al. [2]. ...
Article
Full-text available
A counterpossible conditional is a counterfactual with an impossible antecedent. Common sense delivers the view that some such conditionals are true, and some are false. In recent publications, Timothy Williamson has defended the view that all are true. In this paper we defend the common sense view against Williamson’s objections.
... The most extreme assertion that there is only a finite quantity of natural numbers was suggested by Yesenin-Volpin (1960) [2] , who developed a mathematical direction called ultraintuitionism and took this assertion as one of the central postulates of ultraintuitionism. Other authors also considered arithmetics with a finite number of numbers, claiming that these arithmetics are inconsistent (cf., for example Van Bendegem, 1994 [3] and Rosinger, 2008 [4]). Van Danzig had similar ideas but expressed them in a different way. ...
Article
Full-text available
Counting has always been one of the most important operations for human be-ings. Naturally, it is inherent in economics and business. We count with the unique arithmetic, which humans have used for millennia. However, over time, the most inquisitive thinkers have questioned the validity of standard arithmetic in certain settings. It started in ancient Greece with the famous philosopher Zeno of Elea, who elaborated a number of paradoxes questioning popular knowledge. Millennia later, the famous German researcher Herman Helmholtz (1821-1894) [1] expressed reservations about applicability of conventional arithmetic with respect to physical phenomena. In the 20th and 21st century, mathematicians such as Yesenin-Volpin (1960) [2], Van Bendegem (1994) [3], Rosinger (2008) [4] and others articulated similar concerns. In validation, in the 20th century expressions such as 1 + 1 = 3 or 1 + 1 = 1 occurred to reflect important characteristics of economic, business, and social processes. We call these expressions synergy arithmetic. It is common notion that synergy arithmetic has no meaning mathematically. However in this paper we mathematically ground and explicate synergy arithmetic.
Article
This paper defines provably non-trivial theories that characterize Frege’s notion of a set, taking into account that the notion is inconsistent. By choosing an adaptive underlying logic, consistent sets behave classically notwithstanding the presence of inconsistent sets. Some of the theories have a full-blown presumably consistent set theory T as a subtheory, provided T is indeed consistent. An unexpected feature is the presence of classical negation within the language.
Book
Full-text available
The latter half of the twentieth century witnessed an ‘intensional revolution’, a great collective effort to analyse notions which are absolutely fundamental to our understanding of the world and of ourselves—from meaning and information to knowledge, belief, causation, essence, supervenience, conditionality, as well as nomological, metaphysical, and logical necessity—in terms of a single concept. This was the concept of a possible world : a way things could have been. Possible worlds found applications in logic, metaphysics, semantics, game theory, information theory, artificial intelligence, and the philosophy of mind and cognition. However, possible worlds analyses have been facing numerous problems. This book traces them all back to hyperintensionality : the need for distinctions more fine-grained than the possible worlds apparatus can easily represent. It then introduces impossible worlds— ways things could not have been—as a general tool for modelling hyperintensional phenomena. The book discusses the metaphysics of impossible worlds and applies them to a range of central topics and open issues in logic, semantics, and philosophy: from the problem of logical omniscience in epistemic logic, to the semantics of non-classical logics, the modelling of imagination and mental simulation, the analysis of information and informative inference, truth in fiction, and counterpossible reasoning.
Chapter
Full-text available
Imagination seems to have a logic, albeit one which is hyperintensional and sensitive to context. This chapter offers a semantics of imagination, with operators expressing ‘imaginative acts’ of mental simulation. A number of conditions that could be imposed on the semantics are then discussed, in order to validate certain inferences. One important issue is how acts of imagination interact with disjunction: one can imagine some disjunction as obtaining without being imaginatively specific about which disjunction obtains. This chapter subsequently turns to non-monotonicity: how B may follow from imagining that A , but not from imagining that A ∧ C. Finally, the Principle of Imaginative Equivalents is discussed.
Article
A solution of the Zeno paradoxes in terms of a discrete space is usually rejected on the basis of an argument formulated by Hermann Weyl, the so-called tile argument. This note shows that, given a set of reasonable assumptions for a discrete geometry, the Weyl argument does not apply. The crucial step is to stress the importance of the nonzero width of a line. The Pythagorean theorem is shown to hold for arbitrary right triangles.
Article
This book advocates and defends the view that there are true contradictions (dialetheism), a view that has flown in the face of orthodoxy in Western philosophy since Aristotle's time. The book has been at the centre of the controversies surrounding dialetheism ever since the first edition was published in 1987. This text contains the second edition of the book. It expands upon the original in various ways, and also contains the author's reflections on developments over the last two decades.
Article
The traditional model theory of first-order logic assumes that the interpretation of a formula can be given without reference to its deductive context. This paper investigates an interpretation which depends on a formula's location within a derivation. The key step is to drop the assumption that all quantified variables must have the same range and to require only that the ranges of variables in a derivation must be related in such way as to preserve the soundness of the inference rules. With each (consistent) derivation there is associated a “Buridan-Volpin (orBV) structure” [M, {r(x)}] which is simply a Tarski structureM for the language and a map giving the ranger(x) of each variablex in the derivation. IfLK* is (approximately) the classical sequent calculusLK of Gentzen from which the structural contraction rules have been dropped, then our main result reads: If a set of first-ordered formulas Γ has a Tarski modelM, then from any normal derivationD inLK* of Γ ⇒ Δ can be constructed aBV modelM D=[M, {r(x)}] of Γ where each ranger(x) is finite.
Article
This paper continues the investigation of inconsistent arithmetical structures. In §2 the basic notion of a model with identity is defined, and results needed from elsewhere are cited. In §3 several nonisomorphic inconsistent models with identity which extend the (=, <) theory of the usual classical denumerable nonstandard model of arithmetic are exhibited. In §4 inconsistent nonstandard models of the classical theory of finite rings and fields modulo m, i.e. Zm , are briefly considered. In §5 two models modulo an infinite nonstandard number are considered. In the first, it is shown how to model inconsistently the arithmetic of the rationals with all names included, a strengthening of earlier results. In the second, all inconsistency is confined to the nonstandard integers, and the effects on Fermat's Last Theorem are considered. It is concluded that the prospects for a good inconsistent theory of fields may be limited.
Article
This paper develops in certain directions the work of Meyer in [3], [4], [5] and [6] (see also Routley [10] and Asenjo [11]). In those works, Peano's axioms for arithmetic were formulated with a logical base of the relevant logic R , and it was proved finitistically that the resulting arithmetic, called R # , was absolutely consistent. It was pointed out that such a result escapes incautious formulations of Gödel's second incompleteness theorem, and provides a basis for a revived Hilbert programme. The absolute consistency result used as a model arithmetic modulo two. Modulo arithmetics are not ordinarily thought of as an extension of Peano arithmetic, since some of the propositions of the latter, such as that zero is the successor of no number, fail in the former. Consequently a logical base which, unlike classical logic, tolerates contradictory theories was used for the model. The logical base for the model was the three-valued logic RM3 (see e.g. [1] or [8]), which has the advantage that while it is an extension of R , it is finite valued and so easier to handle. The resulting model-theoretic structure (called in this paper RM3 ² ) is interesting in its own right in that the set of sentences true therein constitutes a negation inconsistent but absolutely consistent arithmetic which is an extension of R # . In fact, in the light of the result of [6], it is an extension of Peano arithmetic with a base of a classical logic, P # . A generalisation of the structure is to modulo arithmetics with the same logical base RM3 , but with varying moduli (called RM3 i here).
Mo d e ls f o r Inconsistent a n d In co mp le te Differential Calculus
  • Mo Chris
  • Ns E N
Chris MO RTE NS E N: " Mo d e ls f o r Inconsistent a n d In co mp le te Differential Calculus", Notre Dame Journal o f Formal Logic, 31, 2, 1990, pp. 274-285.
Min ima lly Inconsistent LP
  • Priest L Graham
  • J E A N Paul Van Bendegem N
Graham PRIEST: " Min ima lly Inconsistent LP", Studia Logica, Vol. L, J E A N PAUL VAN BENDEGEM n. 2, 1991, pp. 321-331.