ArticlePDF AvailableLiterature Review

Abstract

The striking diversity of psychological and neurophysiological models of 'time perception' characterizes the debate on how and where in the brain time is processed. In this review, the most prominent models of time perception will be critically discussed. Some of the variation across the proposed models will be explained, namely (i) different processes and regions of the brain are involved depending on the length of the processed time interval, and (ii) different cognitive processes may be involved that are not necessarily part of a core timekeeping system but, nevertheless, influence the experience of time. These cognitive processes are distributed over the brain and are difficult to discern from timing mechanisms. Recent developments in the research on emotional influences on time perception, which succeed decades of studies on the cognition of temporal processing, will be highlighted. Empirical findings on the relationship between affect and time, together with recent conceptualizations of self- and body processes, are integrated by viewing time perception as entailing emotional and interoceptive (within the body) states. To date, specific neurophysiological mechanisms that would account for the representation of human time have not been identified. It will be argued that neural processes in the insular cortex that are related to body signals and feeling states might constitute such a neurophysiological mechanism for the encoding of duration.
doi: 10.1098/rstb.2009.0003 , 1955-1967364 2009 Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B
Marc Wittmann
The inner experience of time
References http://rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org/content/364/1525/1955.full.html#ref-list-1
This article cites 145 articles, 9 of which can be accessed free
Subject collections
(137 articles)cognition (173 articles)neuroscience
Articles on similar topics can be found in the following collections
Email alerting service hereright-hand corner of the article or click
Receive free email alerts when new articles cite this article - sign up in the box at the top
http://rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org/subscriptions go to: Phil. Trans. R. Soc. BTo subscribe to
This journal is © 2009 The Royal Society
on 31 May 2009rstb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
Review
The inner experience of time
Marc Wittmann*
Department of Psychiatry, University of California San Diego, 9500 Gilman Drive,
La Jolla, CA 92093-9116A, USA
The striking diversity of psychological and neurophysiological models of ‘time perception’
characterizes the debate on how and where in the brain time is processed. In this review, the most
prominent models of time perception will be critically discussed. Some of the variation across the
proposed models will be explained, namely (i) different processes and regions of the brain are
involved depending on the length of the processed time interval, and (ii) different cognitive processes
may be involved that are not necessarily part of a core timekeeping system but, nevertheless, influence
the experience of time. These cognitive processes are distributed over the brain and are difficult to
discern from timing mechanisms. Recent developments in the research on emotional influences on
time perception, which succeed decades of studies on the cognition of temporal processing, will be
highlighted. Empirical findings on the relationship between affect and time, together with recent
conceptualizations of self- and body processes, are integrated by viewing time perception as entailing
emotional and interoceptive (within the body) states. To date, specific neurophysiological
mechanisms that would account for the representation of human time have not been identified. It
will be argued that neural processes in the insular cortex that are related to body signals and feeling
states might constitute such a neurophysiological mechanism for the encoding of duration.
Keywords: time perception; subjective duration; emotion; interoception; insula
1. INTRODUCTION
Throughout history, philosophers have been intrigued
by the nature of time and how we, as humans,
experience its progression. The perception of time is
part of human experience; it is essential for everyday
behaviour and for the survival of the individual
organism (Po¨ppel 1997;Wittmann 1999;Buhusi &
Meck 2005). Yet, and surprisingly enough, its neural
basis is still unknown. Temporal intervals, lasting only
seconds or spanning a lifetime, are judged according to
their perceived duration—often regarded as painfully
long or, the reverse, as lasting too short. Everyday
decisions we make, as simple as either waiting for
the elevator or taking the stairs, are based on the
experienced passage of time and anticipated duration
(Wittmann & Paulus 2008). The importance of our
temporal experiences for daily living is strikingly
documented in individual neurological cases where
patients report of an accelerated progression of time
and, consequently, have troubles in adequately inter-
acting with the environment, i.e. driving a car
(Binkofski & Block 1996). Although we doubtless
have a time sense, our bodies are not equipped with
a sensory organ for the passage of time in the same
way that we have eyes and ears—and the respective
sensory cortices—for detecting light and sound. Time,
ultimately, is not a material object of the world for
which we could have a unique receptor system.
Nevertheless, we speak of the perception of time.
When we talk about time (‘an event lasted long’, ‘time
flew by’), we use linguistic structures that refer to
motion events and to locations and measures in space
(Evans 2004); a further indication that time itself is not
a property in the empirical world.
Despite a growing body of knowledge on the
psychology and on the neural basis of the experience
of time, the riddle for philosophers and scientists alike
is still unsolved: how does the mind (or, for that matter,
the brain) create time? Martin Heidegger’s paraphrase
of St Augustine’s famous quotation
1
‘In you, my spirit,
I measure times; I measure myself, as I measure time’
(Heidegger 1992) reflects a theoretical approach—
founded in western philosophical tradition—which
states that time is a construction of the self. Perceived
time, thereafter, represents the mental status of the
beholder. In terms of a functional equation, one could
state that time tis a function fof the self, where the self
stands for all possible psychological (i.e. empirical
and theoretical) properties of an individual who
perceives time,
tZfðselfÞ:ð1:1Þ
Psychological research has shown that cognitive func-
tions such as attention, working memory as well as long-
term memory determine our temporal judgements
(Brown 1997;Zakay & Block 2004;Ta a t g e n et al.
2007). Moreover, drive states, moods and emotions
(Wittmann et al.2006;Droit-Volet & Meck 2007;
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2009) 364, 1955–1967
doi:10.1098/rstb.2009.0003
One contribution of 14 to a Theme Issue ‘The experience of time:
neural mechanisms and the interplay of emotion, cognition and
embodiment’.
*wittmann@ucsd.edu
1955 This journal is q2009 The Royal Society
on 31 May 2009rstb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
Noulhiane et al. 2007a) as well as factors of personality
(Rammsayer 1997) influence duration estimates. For
example, time intervals are judged to be longer when
we pay more attention to time and when the load of
varying experiences stored in memory is higher. Our
subjective well-being also strongly influences how time
is experienced. Time speeds up when we are involved in
pleasant activities, but it drags during periods of
boredom. Thus, our sense of time is a function of the
intricate interplay between specific cognitive functions
and of our momentary mood states.
The aforementioned psychological factors definitely
influence the processing of duration. However, a specific
neural timing mechanism—influenced by the afore-
mentioned factors—nevertheless, could account for
our ability to accurately process temporal intervals.
Especially for shorter durations up to a few seconds,
humans can accurately synchronize their movements to
regular beats (Mates et al. 1994), discriminate tones
with different durations (Rammsayer & Lima 1991)or
reproduce presented intervals ( Eisler & Eisler 1994).
Yet, there is no consensus as to which temporal
mechanisms account for these temporal-processing
abilities. Over the last decades, the most successful
models for such a mechanism have been variants of a
pacemaker–accumulator clock, where an oscillator
(a pacemaker) produces a series of pulses (analogous
to the ticks of a clock) and the number of pulses
recorded over a given timespan represents experienced
duration (Po¨ ppel 1971;Church 1984;Treisman
et al. 1990;Meck 1996;Zakay & Block 1997).
However, competing models assume neuronal system
properties for encoding duration not related to a simple
pacemaker–accumulator system (Matell & Meck 2004;
Wackermann & Ehm 2006;Karmarkar & Buonomano
2007), or they propose that memory decay processes
are involved in time perception (Staddon 2005;
Wackermann & Ehm 2006). Related to this unsolved
issue, the question of which areas of the brain
process duration has also not yet been answered
definitely. Among other regions, most prominently,
the cerebellum (Ivry & Spencer 2004), the right
posterior parietal cortex (Bueti et al.2008a), the
right prefrontal cortex (Rubia & Smith 2004;
Lewis & Miall 2006) as well as fronto-striatal circuits
(Harrington et al. 2004a;Hinton & Meck 2004)have
been implicated as the neural substrates of a potential
timekeeping mechanism.
In summary, as this brief outline suggests, there is
still considerable uncertainty on how (regarding
psychological and neurophysiological models) and
where in the brain time is processed. This paper has
several goals that are related to the issues raised: (i) to
give an answer to the question of why so many different
brain regions have been assigned to the neural basis for
our experience of time, i.e. to explain some of the
variation found across models, and (ii) to describe
recent developments in the research on time percep-
tion, which are indicative of a strong involvement of
emotions and mood states. These developments could
be described as an ‘emotive turn’ in this area of
research, which might follow decades of focusing on
cognitive aspects of time perception. (iii) Recent
conceptualizations and empirical findings, which have
led to this emotive turn, might develop into a neural
theory of time perception that will encompass sub-
jective feeling and interoceptive (within the body)
states. Specific neurophysiological processes in circum-
scribed regions of the brain, as they are related to these
feeling states, might constitute a mechanism for
encoding duration.
2. COGNITIVE AND NEURAL MODELS OF
TIME PERCEPTION
Investigations in the fields of experimental psychology,
clinical neuropsychology and neuroimaging have
resulted in an extensive literature on the mechanisms
and underlying neural systems of temporal processing.
Over the last decades, certain cognitive and neural
models have dominated time perception research, but
alternative models exist and the number of potential
theories has to date increased considerably. To
summarize the status of the research field in general
terms: there is a lot of conflicting evidence and there are
several competing conceptualizations. In the following,
a short review of (i) predominant cognitive models
of time perception and (ii) related neural theories of
interval timing is provided. These models and theories
will be contrasted with alternative conceptualizations
and empirical evidence in order to provide an overview
of the heterogeneity of ideas concerning mechanisms of
time perception.
Cognitive models distinguish two fundamental
perspectives in time estimation: prospective and retro-
spective time estimation ( James 1890;Zakay & Block
2004).
2
In the former, an observer judges the duration
of an interval that is being presently experienced. In
retrospective time estimation, by contrast, an observer
estimates a timespan that has already been passed and
to which he is only now paying attention. Models of
prospective time estimation assume an ‘internal clock’
with a pacemaker producing a sequence of time units
that are fed into an accumulator (Church 1984;
Treisman et al. 1990). In a variant of these pace-
maker–accumulator models, the attentional-gate
model (Zakay & Block 1997), the time units produced
are only registered when attention is directed to time.
Thus, prospective timing is always a dual task since an
observer has to divide attention between temporal and
non-temporal processes (Grondin & Macar 1992;
Taatgen et al. 2007). The number of units that have
been recorded during a physical time period (being
stored in working memory) is then compared (in a
decision process) with long-term memory of stored
representations of time periods, which can be verbalized
as seconds or minutes (Pouthas & Perbal 2004;Wea r d e n
2004). Thus, in addition to the pacemaker (the actual
clock component), several cognitive processes such as
working memory, long-term memory, attention and
decisions are involved in prospective time perception.
In retrospective time estimation, the duration of a
time interval that has already elapsed has to be judged.
Then, an observer has to estimate a given duration in
retrospect from the amount of processed and stored
memory contents; that is, duration has to be recon-
structed from memory (Ornstein 1970;Flaherty et al.
2005;Noulhiane et al. 2007b). The more changing
1956 M. Wittmann Review. The inner experience of time
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 31 May 2009rstb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
experiences we have during a certain timespan—which
are stored in memory and later retrieved—the longer
the duration is subjectively experienced (Bailey & Areni
2006). In retrospect, routine activity when compared
with novel activity leads to the perception of shorter
time intervals (Avni-Babad & Ritov 2003). Thus, the
subjective impression of a long time interval depends
on the activity of a person with diverse experiences and
recruits the activation of areas such as the medial
temporal cortex, known to be involved in episodic
memory ( Noulhiane et al.2007b). Retrospective
duration judgements are based on temporal intervals
spanning a few seconds (short-term memory) to, in
principle, a whole lifetime (long-term memory)
(Wittmann & Lehnhoff 2005). Pure prospective
duration judgements, by contrast, are only conceivable
over a limited and shorter time range where an observer
attends to time for a period of seconds to minutes.
Prospective timing studies in animals and humans
have yielded the general hypothesis that fronto-striatal
circuits consisting of recurrent loops between frontal
cortex (SMA), caudate–putamen, pallidum and
thalamus, which are modulated by the dopamine
system, are critical for the processing of duration
(Hicks 1992;Harrington et al. 2004a). Support for the
anatomical hypothesis comes from investigations in
patients with brain lesions and from neuroimaging
studies. For example, individuals with structural
damage to the frontal lobes ( Nichelli et al. 1995;
Kagerer et al. 2002) or traumatic brain injury
predominantly affecting frontal areas (Pouthas &
Perbal 2004) show impaired estimates of temporal
intervals. Neuroimaging studies with healthy volun-
teers find that the perception of duration is linked to
activation in right prefrontal and striatal regions
(Ferrandez et al. 2003;Nenadic et al. 2003;Coull
et al. 2004). Regarding the involvement of neurotrans-
mitter systems, D2 dopaminergic antagonists (such as
haloperidol) impair duration discrimination abilities in
healthy subjects (Rammsayer 1999). Moreover, studies
with animals and humans indicate that both dopamin-
ergic agonists, e.g. methamphetamine, and antagonists
influence timing processes, presumably by increasing
and decreasing clock speed, respectively (Mohs et al.
1980;Buhusi & Meck 2002;Cevik 2003). Individuals
dependent on cocaine and methamphetamine, who
have abnormal brain metabolism and structural
changes involving dopaminergic target areas such as
the striatum and the frontal cortex, exhibit impaired
time processing on several timing tasks ( Wittmann
et al. 2007b). Additional evidence for the involvement
of the dopamine system in time perception comes
from patients with Parkinson’s disease who have
decreased dopaminergic function in the basal ganglia
and show deficits discriminating and reproducing
temporal intervals ( Hellstrom et al. 1997;Harrington
et al. 1998). Further evidence comes from a study
in which subthalamic deep brain stimulation in
patients with Parkinson’s disease levelled temporal
reproduction performance to that of control subjects
(Koch et al. 2004). Thus, intact dopamine neurotrans-
mission within striatal and frontal areas of the brain is
an important prerequisite for accurate temporal-
processing abilities.
However, some neuroimaging studies, revealing
areas of activity while subjects estimate durations or
time their movements, suggest that a core temporal-
processing mechanism is located in the right prefrontal
cortex (dorsolateral and ventrolateral areas) for both
sub- and supra-second intervals (Rubia et al. 1998;
Brunia et al. 2000;Lewis & Miall 2003a;Smith et al.
2003). In these (and other) studies, the basal ganglia
did not show activation, thus leading to the conclusion
that dopamine modulation in right prefrontal areas
might be the basis for a primary timekeeping
mechanism (Lewis & Miall 2006). Furthermore, and
pointing to yet another different brain region, since
patients with cerebellar dysfunctions are impaired in
the precise timing of movements (Ivry et al. 1988)as
well as in the sensory discrimination of duration
(Ivry & Keele 1989), the cerebellum seemingly plays
an important role in the processing of time. It has been
speculated that separate, i.e. non-overlapping, neural
elements in the cerebellum that have different delay
properties could potentially encode duration (Ivry &
Spencer 2004). Last but not least, the right posterior–
inferior parietal cortex has been implicated (i) in
integrating duration information as represented in the
sensory modalities and (ii) as an interface between
the perception of duration and timed actions (Bueti
et al. 2008a,c). Repetitive transcranial magnetic
stimulation (rTMS) selectively disrupts duration
discrimination in the visual and auditory modality if
the respective sensory cortices are affected, but
stimulation of the right parietal cortex disrupts timing
in both the visual and auditory domains (Bueti et al.
2008a,b). Bueti and colleagues thus support the idea of
distributed, modality-specific, timekeeping processes
that converge in the parietal cortex. Neurophysiological
studies in monkeys complement these findings by
showing that specific increasing (ramp-like) neuronal
activity in the posterior parietal cortex encodes
duration (Leon & Shadlen 2003). However, similar
neural activity in the monkey brain and related to the
timing of events has been recorded in the premotor and
motor cortex as well (Lebedev et al. 2008).
One difficulty in deciding on which regions are the
primary target areas for a suspected timekeeping
mechanism comes from neuroimaging studies where,
typically, multiple brain regions show activation during
time perception tasks ( Lewis & Miall 2003b). The
involvement of all these brain areas is probably due to
different cognitive processes not subtracted out in the
contrasts between primary time perception and control
tasks, the principal method used in functional
magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI ). Many active
areas are not primarily related to the encoding of
duration (i.e. an internal clock) but, nevertheless, take
part in a complex timing system representing atten-
tion, working memory and decision-making processes
(Rubia & Smith 2004;Livesey et al. 2007).
A consequence of the complex architecture of an
assumed timekeeping system is that disruptions in any
component can result in timing impairments. That
could explain why so many different patient groups
with damage to the brain, i.e. lesions or degenerative
processes in the basal ganglia, cerebellum or right
parietal, as well as frontal cortex, can be impaired
Review. The inner experience of time M. Wittmann 1957
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 31 May 2009rstb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
(Wittmann 1999). Likewise, it cannot be clearly
decided whether experimental disruptions with
rTMS are due to the transient impairment of a neural
clock or of other processing components. For example,
rTMS applied to the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex
reliably impairs temporal reproductions of a few
seconds as well as multiple second intervals, but it is
unclear whether this accounts for the disruption of a
neural clock or of working memory ( Koch et al.
2003,2007;Jones et al. 2004). rTMS applied to
the cerebellum transiently impairs the temporal
reproduction of intervals with durations of approxi-
mately half a second ( but not approx. 2 s), a finding
that could be interpreted by the disruption of either
a millisecond timer or of a motor programme involved
in millisecond timing ( Koch et al. 2007).
Two further complicating factors in this discussion
arise from neuropsychological studies with brain-injured
patients. First, some studies report negative findings in
which patients do not differ in their timing abilities from
control subjects. Second, timing deficits, if registered,
although significant from a statistical point of view, are
not necessarily dramatic. For example, and contrasting
earlier findings, patients with cerebellum lesions
following a stroke were not impaired in a duration
discrimination task and only mildly impaired in a motor-
timing task (Harrington et al. 2004b). Patients with focal
basal ganglia lesions, although impaired in performing
with maximum tapping frequency, were as accurate in
motor timing as were controls (Aparicio et al.2005).
Moreover, although these patient groups, as shown in
several studies, on average, and according to the
inferential statistics, differed from the performance of
control subjects, the deviations were often minimal
(Ivry & Keele 1989;Harrington et al. 1998;Kagerer
et al. 2002;Wittmann et al. 2007b).
One suggested solution to the problem of not being
able to pin down specific regions of the brain as
representing a clock-type timing mechanism is to
assume distributed neural networks where neural
populations within each region would encode duration
(Mauk & Buonomano 2004). If several neural units
would possess intrinsic temporal-processing proper-
ties, many different brain areas could contribute to the
perception of time depending on the modality and
the type of task. These network or state-dependent
models do not incorporate a dedicated timing system
(with a centralized clock) but rather time-dependent
neural changes, such as short-term synaptic plasticity
(Karmarkar & Buonomano 2007). However, such
intrinsic mechanisms would be limited to short time
intervals up to several hundred milliseconds. Time
perception in the range of seconds would still require
additional processes (Ivry & Schlerf 2008). Similarly, it
is conceivable that temporal-processing functions are
embedded in several specialized and interacting neural
circuits, where the timing function would not be the
primary process in those brain regions (through a
dedicated mechanism for temporal processes) but, for
example, motor systems would implicitly be involved in
the temporal processing of intervals ( Nobre & O’Reilly
2004). Alternatively, an idea that has been very recently
stated suggests that the effort made when we perceive
and act might determine experienced duration
(Marchetti 2009). An intuitive example fitting this
idea is the phenomenon that novel experiences seem to
last longer than routine events, which can be explained
by the greater demand of mental activities involved in
performing a task or analysing a situation for the first
time. The idea of mental effort as a determinant of time
experience is compatible with the notion of ‘fluency’,
the subjective experience of ease or difficulty of a
mental task (Oppenheimer 2008). The experience of
time, according to this view, would not rely on clock
processes but would be an epiphenomenon evolving
from cognitive and emotional responses during a time
interval, where a cognitively demanding task (a filled
interval) and doing nothing (an empty interval, i.e.
when sitting in the doctor’s waiting room) would
likewise lead to the impression of a slow passage of time
(the act of waiting without any distraction can be filled
with painful emotions) ( Flaherty 1999).
Further conceptualizations, which argue against the
idea of dedicated timing systems, add to the diversity of
time perception models. Just as is argued for the
retrospective perspective on duration, prospective
timing could be governed by memory processes, where
the decreasing memory strength over time, specifically
modelled using leaky integrators, leads to the
impression of passing time and, eventually, of duration
(Staddon 2005). In a different model, the ‘dual
klepsydra’ model, inflow and outflow processes of a
leaky accumulator form properties of a timekeeping
mechanism (Wackermann & Ehm 2006). Subjective
duration is defined by the state of a leaky integrator
that depends on inflow units (accumulation over time
during the encoding of stimulus duration) and outflow
units (loss over time). Parameters of that model fit
well to individual temporal reproduction responses
as well as to changes in the timing of behaviour
induced by experimental manipulations ( Wackermann
et al. 2008).
In summary, a multitude of incompatible conceptu-
alizations exists on how time is processed. Furthermore,
there is no agreement on which brain areas or brain
systems—dedicated to time or not—might underlie our
perception of duration. The important conclusion so
far is that different processing components are involved
when we perceive duration or time our movements,
which are not related to an internal clock. Nevertheless,
through experimental manipulation or in certain
patient populations, changes in these processes can
affect perception and behaviour related to the time
domain. In the following, one further factor will
be discussed that may explain some of the variation
found in studies on time perception, i.e. why so
many different brain regions have been assigned with
a central timekeeping function. The main point will be
that different neural systems are involved in temporal
processes (and related experiences) depending on the
duration of the processed interval.
3. TIME SCALES IN THE PERCEPTION OF TIME
It is intuitively most unlikely that one mechanism or
one neural system would be responsible for all possible
durations that an organism has to process. Different
temporal processing mechanisms must be involved on
1958 M. Wittmann Review. The inner experience of time
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 31 May 2009rstb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
different time scales ( Trevarthen 1999;Wittmann
1999;Mauk & Buonomano 2004;Buhusi & Meck
2005). Experimental interventions have repeatedly
shown duration-specific effects of psychopharmacolo-
gical agents on interval timing. For example, the
dopamine receptor antagonist haloperidol as well as
the benzodiazepine midazolam impair duration
discrimination of intervals ranging approximately 1 s,
whereas processing of 50 ms intervals is affected by
haloperidol only (Rammsayer 1999). According to
these results, any pharmacological treatment that
affects working memory capacity (e.g. midazolam)
would interfere with temporal processing of intervals
above 1 s. However, intervals with a length of up to a
few hundred milliseconds (such as the 50 ms interval)
are supposed to be processed based on brain
mechanisms outside of motor and cognitive control
and reflect pure timing processes (thus, not being
influenced by midazolam). According to this view,
additional processes such as attention and working
memory, not related to time per se, come into play with
intervals exceeding several hundred milliseconds in
length and complementing dopamine-driven pro-
cesses, which are involved both in shorter and longer
time intervals ( Rammsayer et al. 2001). A similar
theoretical proposal, derived from a meta-analysis on
neuroimaging data, suggests two distinct neural timing
systems: (i) an automatic timing system for shorter
intervals up to approximately 1 s, which recruits motor
systems of the brain (SMA, basal ganglia and
cerebellum) and (ii) a cognitively controlled timing
system for supra-second intervals connected mainly to
right prefrontal and parietal cortical areas (Lewis &
Miall 2003b). This separation of time perception
systems is to some extent mirrored by findings
in motor-timing studies, where qualitative changes in
tapping performance occur with inter-tap intervals of
approximately 1 and 1.5 s duration (Madison 2001).
Time ranges between 0.45 and 1.5 s seem to be
automatically processed, i.e. not strongly affected by
attentional demands, whereas attention and working
memory processes (stimulated by secondary tasks)
affect intervals in the range between 1.8 and 3.6 s
(Miyake et al. 2004).
The notion that perception and motor behaviour are
processed in discrete windows or processing epochs has
been conceptualized for some time ( White 1963;
Po¨ppel 1970;Dehaene 1993;VanRullen & Koch
2003;Fingelkurts & Fingelkurts 2006). These
temporal integration units fuse successive events into
a unitary experience, ‘snapshots of experience’ or
‘psychological presents’ (Blumenthal 1977), which
are characterized by co-temporality, meaning that
events within this time zone have no temporal
relationship (Ruhnau 1995). For example, the percep-
tion of temporal order of short stimuli in different
modalities is only possible if the individual events are
separated by at least 20–60 ms ( Exner 1875;Hirsh &
Sherrick 1961;Kanabus et al. 2002;Fink et al. 2006).
If the two events are separated by smaller intervals, an
observer is not able to tell which of the two appeared
first. Moreover, since stimulus properties of speech
stimuli are perceptually segmented into these
sequential processing units, temporal information
within a segment of a speech sound may not be
relevant for decoding (Kiss et al. 2008). A longer time
frame of approximately 200 ms determines the integra-
tion of auditory–visual input in speech processing
(van Wassenhove et al. 2007). Fusion percepts were
reported if the onset of lip movements and heard
syllables did not exceed this time lag. Threshold values
of approximately 250–300 ms have long been
suggested to represent a specific integration process
in perception (Mu
¨nsterberg 1889;White 1963).
A minimum stimulus duration (or minimum inter-
onset interval) of 200–300 ms is necessary for detecting
the temporal sequence offour acoustic events (Warren &
Obusek 1972;Shrivastav et al. 2008)andforoptimal
effects in an oddball task that leads to the subjective
expansion of duration (Tse et al.2004). Temporal
integration mechanisms in a time frame of approximately
250 ms also seem to be involved in sensorimotor
processing, distinguishing maximum tapping speed
from a personal, controlled motor speed (Peters 1989;
Wittmann et al. 2001).
On a different time scale, a perceptual mechanism
seems to exist that integrates separate successive events
into a unit or perceptual gestalt (see Po¨ ppel 2009). We
do not just perceive individual events in isolation, but
automatically integrate them into perceptual units with
a duration of approximately 2–3 s ( Fraisse 1984;
Po¨ ppel 1997). For example, while listening to a
metronome at a moderate speed, we do not hear
a train of individual beats, but automatically form
perceptual units, such as 1–2–3, 1–2–3, etc. These are
mental constructs—physically speaking, they do not
exist. The duration of this temporal integration
mechanism, referred to as the subjective present,
seems to be limited to 2–3 s (Szelag et al. 1996;
Wittmann & Po¨ppel 2000). Phenomenological
approaches have revealed that temporal intervals
shorter than 2 s are perceived qualitatively as different
from longer intervals (Benussi 1913;Nakajima et al.
1980). Typically, intervals up to 2–3 s are reproduced
accurately, whereas longer intervals tend to be under-
estimated ( Ulbrich et al.2007;Noulhiane et al. 2008). In
one study measuring event-related potentials (ERPs)
during the reproduction of visual stimuli ranging in
duration between 1 and 8 s, accurate reproductions up to
3 s were accompanied bya contingent negative variation-
like slow negative shift in the ERP signal. This shift was
reduced or absent when durations exceeded 3 s (Elbert
et al. 1991). Duration discrimination thresholds with
base durations up to 2 s show constant Weber fractions
(Dt/t, where Dtisthe difference between the base duration
tand the length of the comparison interval at which a
duration difference is just noticeable), but with longer
durations, Weber fractions rise rapidly
3
(Getty 1975).
Subjects can accurately synchronize their motor actions
to a sequence of tones presented with a frequency of
approximately 1–2 Hz. The ability to synchronize these
tones becomes more difficult with increasing inter-tone
intervals and finally breaks down when intervals exceed
durations of approximately 2–3 s (Mates et al.1994;
Miyake et al. 2004). With respect to even longer intervals,
it is also conceivable that distinct processes are involved
for different durations. For example, the estimation of a
1 h interval seems to be related to the duration of wake
Review. The inner experience of time M. Wittmann 1959
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 31 May 2009rstb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
time of an individual, whereas the estimation of seconds
and minutes is related to body temperature (Aschoff
1998).
Experimental interventions selectively affect
intervals of specific time ranges, i.e. the psychopharma-
cological substance psilocybin has an effect on duration
longer than 2 s ( Wittmann et al. 2007a), rTMS of the
cerebellum affects solely millisecond timing and rTMS
of the right dorsolateral frontal cortex only affects
timing in the seconds range ( Jones et al. 2004;Koch
et al. 2007). Nevertheless, a reliable correlation
between time scales and neural systems has not been
accomplished so far. Also, individual neuroimaging
studies often find similar brain areas activated in time
perception tasks employing different durations
(Pouthas et al. 2005;Jahanshahi et al. 2006).
To summarize §§ 2 and 3, several factors contribute
to the diversity of different models on the question of
how (which mechanism) and where (which neural
system) in the brain duration is processed. First, there
are several cognitive processes that are entangled with
our perception of time (independent of a potential
internal clock), which require the integrative proces-
sing of multiple modules distributed across the brain.
Experimental manipulations of task load (in attention
and working memory, for example), clinical studies
with selected patients with dysfunctions in different
brain areas (i.e. cerebellum, basal ganglia, frontal and
parietal cortex) as well as neuroimaging studies show
that many parts of the brain and multiple cognitive
processes contribute to the perception of duration.
Moreover, there is no single area of the brain on which
functioning our temporal experiences would
completely rely on; that is, patients with damage to
the brain may be affected in the processing of duration
but their performance hardly ever breaks down
completely. Second, different neural mechanisms are
most probably responsible for temporal processes and
time experiences depending on the duration involved.
4. THE EMOTIONAL EXPERIENCE OF TIME
Time does not pass with a steady-paced flow.
Perceptual time is not isomorphic to physical time,
meaning that the subjective passage of time and
estimates of duration vary considerably. In uneventful
or unpleasant situations, such as when nervously
waiting for something to happen, we experience a
slower passage of time and overestimate its duration.
By contrast, if we are entertained and focus on
rewarding activities, time seems to pass more quickly
and duration is more likely to be underestimated.
These examples of time judgements are inherently
emotional. They point to an aspect of time perception,
although part of everyday experience, which has been
neglected in research over the past few decades. Only
very recently, a body of evidence has accumulated
which is indicative of the intricate interplay between
mood states and perceived duration. In most cases, the
influence of emotions (often leading to longer time
estimate) is explained by the standard cognitive model of
prospective time perception in which emotions
affect the degree of attention to time or increased physio-
logical arousal levels lead to a higher pacemaker rate
(Droit-Volet & Meck 2007;Wittmann & Paulus 2008).
Both increased attention to time and a higher pace-
maker rate of an assumed internal clock would lead to
the accumulation of more temporal units during a
given timespan.
Regarding durations of multiple seconds to minutes,
it has been shown that patients with depression (Bschor
et al. 2004) and cancer patients with high levels of
anxiety (Wittmann et al. 2006) report a slowing down
of the pace of time and overestimate temporal intervals.
It would appear that the psychological distress these
individuals suffer from directs attention away from
meaningful thoughts and actions to the passage of time.
Also, boredom-prone individuals estimate time inter-
vals to last longer than persons with low levels of
boredom (Danckert & Allman 2005). Similarly,
subjects who were socially rejected in a psychological
experiment overestimated intervals of multiple
seconds, a finding that was interpreted as stemming
from a state of reactive emotional and cognitive
deconstruction, which in turn resulted in a stronger
attentional focus on the present ( Twenge et al. 2003).
Positive correlations of general anxiety levels with
duration estimates of multiple seconds have been
reported in undergraduate students (Siegman 1962)
and in patients with psychiatric diagnoses (Melges &
Fougerousse 1966). Spiderphobics who had to look at
spiders for 45 s also overestimated this exposure time
when compared with controls (Watts & Sharrock
1984). These overestimations were interpreted as
resulting from an arousal-induced increase in an
internal pacemaker. Moreover, emotional stress such
as the anticipation of a mild electric shock ( Falk &
Bindra 1954), when compared with control conditions,
led to an overestimation of duration.
Generally speaking, time distortions are stress
related as they are often experienced during dangerous
or life-threatening situations such as road accidents or
encountered violence (Hancock & Weaver 2005). In
movies, scenes depicting combat are sometimes shown
in slow motion to portray what the involved protagonist
subjectively experiences. To date, two studies
experimentally tested this phenomenon. Novice sky-
divers, for example, who reported a stronger fear
during their first tandem jump, also experienced its
duration (subjective estimates approx. 30 min) as
lasting longer than did less fearful novice skydivers
(Campbell & Bryant 2007). A similar time dilation
effect was also seen on a shorter time scale. Subjects
who experienced a free fall of 31 m before they landed
safely in a net overestimated retrospectively the
duration of that fall when compared with when
watching others fall (Stetson et al. 2007). However, a
slow-motion effect was not detected when probed with
a special chronometer that had to be watched during
the fall. Even in more conventional and less frightening
experimental situations, subjects overestimate the
duration of high arousing pictures with emotional
valence (depicting angry faces or accidents), which
last only several hundred milliseconds to a few seconds
(Angrilli et al. 1997;Droit-Volet et al. 2004;Gil et al.
2007). These effects seem to be strongly tied to the
embodiment of emotions. Participants seem to over-
estimate emotional faces only when they are able to
1960 M. Wittmann Review. The inner experience of time
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 31 May 2009rstb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
spontaneously imitate the perceived emotions on the
faces which they have to judge, thus showing that affect
is embodied (Effron et al. 2006). To be more precise,
however, paradoxical effects can occur in the way that
emotional stimuli can cause over—as well as under-
estimations of time. For example, in one study (Angrilli
et al. 1997), low-arousing and emotionally negative
pictures led to an underestimation of duration (inter-
preted as resulting from the subjects’ distraction from
time and attention to the emotional content of the
stimuli), whereas high-arousing emotional pictures led
to an overestimation of duration (interpreted as
resulting from an increased pacemaker). In another
study (Noulhiane et al. 2007a), unpleasant sounds
(e.g. sobs, a crying women) were judged to last longer
than pleasant (e.g. laughs) or neutral stimuli. This
finding was again interpreted through an increase in
pacemaker rate. Furthermore, and contrasting with the
reported findings above, high-arousing sounds were
judged to be shorter than low-arousing sounds
(interpreted as resulting from the distraction from time).
In summary, increased attention to time (such as in
waiting situations) and an increase in physiological
arousal (such as under stress) can lead to longer time
estimates when judging intervals in the range of
milliseconds to seconds and minutes. However,
paradoxical effects of an underestimation of duration
in emotional situations can occur, which are discussed
as stemming from a distraction from time. It is difficult
to decide which mechanism, attention related or
activation induced, actually affects the sense of time
(and in which direction). Physiological measurements
would have to complement the employed time
perception measures. For example, in one study,
acute marijuana effects in healthy subjects corre-
sponded with underproductions of time intervals
(interpreted as acceleration of a pacemaker) and an
increase in heart rate, indicative of an increase in
physiological arousal (Tinklenberg et al. 1976). The
two proposed mechanisms influencing time experience
are not necessarily exclusive but could contribute in an
additive way (Burle & Casini 2001). For example,
overestimations of time intervals of approximately
1 min in duration as detected in many impulsive
patient groups could be due to an increase in
physiological arousal as well as caused by an increase
in attention to time (Berlin & Rolls 2004;Wittmann
et al. 2007b).
The impact of our emotional states on the
experience of time is usually discussed in the framework
of the standard cognitive model of prospective time
perception, which proposes a pacemaker–accumulator
that is embedded in a system of cognitive components.
However, on reviewing the empirical evidence and as
argued above, the basic questions of how our sense of
time is created are still unresolved. The recent upsurge
in empirical investigations on the relationship between
emotions and time, perhaps signifying an emotive
turn, might result in a new psychological and neural
theory of time perception. So far, emotions and
physiological states, similar to cognitive functions such
as attention and working memory, have been treated as
modulators of an assumed neural clock. What if
mood processes and the representation of body
sensations themselves function as a timekeeper? Since
emotions and physiological states seem so fundamental
to the experience of time, it is tempting to assign a
pivotal role to these processes related to a core time-
keeping system.
Since the late nineteenth century, based on the
theory by James and Lange, it has been argued that
affective states as well as experienced emotions are
inseparable from autonomic responses (e.g. cardiovas-
cular activity, abdominal sensations and breathing
patterns; Saper 2002;Pollatos et al. 2005). According
to this notion, bodily signals, visceral and somatosen-
sory feedback from the peripheral nervous system,
enact emotions (Damasio 1999;Wiens 2005).
For example, people’s heartbeat detection ability is
positively related to subjective ratings of emotional
pictures as more arousing (Pollatos et al. 2007a).
Interoceptive awareness, as tested with heart rate
detection tasks, is predicted (among other regions) by
right anterior insula activity (Critchley et al. 2004;
Pollatos et al. 2007b). The insular cortex of primates,
structurally embedded in the extended limbic system,
is considered as the primary receptive area for visceral
input, i.e. for physiological states of the body (Craig
2002;Saper 2002). The capacity for the awareness of
emotions is probably built on the anatomical organi-
zation and a progressive integration of information in
the insula (Craig 2003). A posterior-to-anterior
progression of representations in the human insular
cortex is the basis for the sequential integration of body
states and internal autonomic responses with cognitive
and motivational conditions, the latter being instan-
tiated by distributed neural processes across the brain.
This progression culminates in the anterior insula and
leads to the conscious awareness of complex feeling
states. A direct link between the perception of time and
physiological processes has been proposed by Craig
(2008), who claims that our experience of time relates
to emotional and visceral processes because they share
a common underlying neural system, the insular cortex
and the interoceptive system. He suggests that the
insula, through the temporal integration of signals from
within the body, produces a series of ‘emotional
moments’ in time. The perception of duration there-
after would be defined by these successive moments of
self-realization, formed by information originating
within the body (see also Craig 2009).
Several attempts have been made to directly relate
rhythms of the body to temporal processes in perception
and action. For example, Mu
¨nsterberg (1889), being his
own subject, reported that when the onset and the offset
of temporal intervals to be reproduced and ranging in
duration between 6 and 60 s coincided with him starting
to inhale, his temporal reproductions were more
accurate than when temporal intervals started at
other points in time not systematically related to his
breathing cycle. Mu
¨nsterberg, who did not count in
his experiments, concluded that the sense of time
relied on the sensation of tension in different organs
which are caused by muscle contractions. Fraisse
(1982) highlights findings showing that the period-
icities of the heart, of walking, of the preferred tapping
tempo as well as of preferred acoustical rates are of
the same order of magnitude of 500–700 ms. However,
Review. The inner experience of time M. Wittmann 1961
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 31 May 2009rstb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
he concludes that ‘we cannot assume that one
phenomenon can be explained by the other. There is
only a narrow range of frequencies of natural or
voluntary rhythms and of preferred tempo’ ( p. 154).
Despite this conclusion, however, one study showed
that participants’ preferred tempo of successive tones
was in a harmonic relation (with a ratio of 1, 1.5 and 2) to
individual heart rates as measured during the presen-
tation of the tone sequences (Iwanaga 1995).
Other studies, which attempted to relate heart rate
(in some cases also breathing rate) to time estimates in
the range of several seconds to minutes, some testing
subjects before and after physical exercise, found no
relationship (Schaefer & Gilliland 1938;Bell & Provins
1963) or associations that were weak or difficult to
interpret (Lediett & Tong 1972;Osato et al. 1995).
One study, nevertheless, employing shorter intervals
with duration up to 4 s, found that drugs, which
either stimulate or inhibit the central or peripheral
sympathetic nerve system, lead to an increase or
decrease in heart rate and breathing rate and an
accompanying relative under- or overproduction of
intervals, respectively ( Hawkes et al. 1962). A relative
underproduction of intervals can be interpreted as
resulting from an increase in clock speed. Although this
latter result points to the role of cardiac and respiratory
cycle rates in the judgement of duration, one has to
keep in mind that proponents of the standard cognitive
models of time perception could still argue that it is not
the heart rate per se that functions as an internal clock
but that generally increased arousal levels affect
the pacemaker of an internal clock in the brain
(Wittmann & Paulus 2008). Especially regarding the
short durations tested in the study by Hawkes et al.
(1962) of just a few seconds, a heart rate cycle of
typically approximately 700 ms could not accurately
represent different temporal intervals.
Although hardly any convincing evidence exists that
would show how specific physiological cycles function
as an internal clock for judging time, body states as a
whole could, nevertheless, form the building blocks of a
timekeeping mechanism. Ultimately, interoceptive
processes as registered in the insula encompass the
physiological status of all body tissues and organs such
as the skin, muscles and the viscera (Craig 2008). It has
beenshownthattheself-regulationofemotions
(Vohs & Schmeichel 2003) and of autonomic para-
meters in biofeedback procedures (Cohen 1981) lead
to longer time percepts. One attempt to explain these
and other findings is that the insular cortex, which
integrates body signals, is the anatomical basis for the
creation of emotions and the sense of time (Craig
2008). Being more strongly aware of one’s own
emotions and body processes would, at the same
time, lead to a prolongation of subjective duration.
When individuals are experimentally deprived of
sensory stimuli (auditory–tactual–visual) their overall
sense of duration over several days gets strongly
impaired. However, these subjects, who have to rely
solely on their inner sense, report that time passes
painfully slowly (Schulman et al. 1967). Experienced
practitioners of mindfulness meditation who concen-
trated ‘on the self across time and the present moment’
in an fMRI study showed stronger activity in a
right lateralized network including the insula and
somatosensory cortex (Farb et al. 2007).
An explicit assignment to a functional role for the
insula in temporal processing was made by Ackermann
et al. (2001), who showed in an fMRI study that a linear
increase in left anterior insula activity was a function of
presented click train rates (increasing up to 6 Hz). By
contrast, a linear increase in right anterior insula
activity was recorded when click rates slowed down to
2 Hz. This and other findings have led to the idea that
the insula is an essential component in the sequencing
of sounds and the perception of rhythm in music
(Bamiou et al. 2003). Moreover, an involvement of the
insular cortex has repeatedly been shown in neuroima-
ging studies on duration processing with different
timing tasks (Brunia et al. 2000;Rao et al. 2001;
Lewis & Miall 2003b;Pouthas et al. 2005;Livesey et al.
2007;Stevens et al. 2007); however, the significance of
insula activation in the context of time perception is
seldom discussed. Recently, however, evidence of
neurophysiological activity in the posterior insula
of the human brain has shown to be involved in the
encoding of multiple-second durations. Time–activity
curves of neural activation derived from event-related
fMRI during a time reproduction task showed acti-
vation in bilateral posterior insula that linearly built up
when subjects were presented with 9 and 18 s tone
intervals ( Wittmann et al. 2008). This build-up of
neuronal activation peaked at the end of the respective
intervals. Related to the functional role of the dorsal
posterior insula, this finding of accumulator-type
activity was, therefore, interpreted as representing the
registration of physiological changes over time that
eventually leads to the representation of duration. The
flow of time, thereafter, corresponds to the flow of
interoceptive signalling from the body as sensed in the
dorsal posterior insula.
A shift in attention to emotional processes and
insular cortex activity in the search for the underlying
mechanisms of time perception has only recently
started. The greatest obstacle to a sound theory on
the neural bases of time perception has been the lack of
evidence for a neurobiological mechanism. The finding
on accumulator-type activity during the processing of
multiple second intervals represents such a potential
mechanism. This finding is also compatible with the
pacemaker–accumulator model of time perception
where pulses emitted by a pacemaker are transiently
stored in an accumulator and the number of pulses
defines duration (Pfeuty et al. 2005). In line with this
conceptualization, it is conceivable that the number
and rate of body signals accumulated in the posterior
insula over a given timespan creates our perception of
duration. To disclose mechanisms on different time
scales, i.e. milliseconds and a few seconds, will be the
challenge for future research. Interval processing over
different time ranges may be controlled by different
neurobiological mechanisms.
5. CONCLUSION
Despite the fact that time is an essential factor for
understanding complex behaviour, the processes
underlying the experience of time and the timing of
1962 M. Wittmann Review. The inner experience of time
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 31 May 2009rstb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
action are incompletely understood. Too many contra-
dictory theories exist—in psychology and neuroscience
alike—that aim at explaining how we judge duration.
One could argue that the conceptualization presented
here of relating body processes to the experience of
time represents yet another alternative approach
among so many others. Only future empirical evidence,
based on strong theoretical grounds, will tell whether
a dedicated neural system actually exists for the
representation of time and which neurobiological
mechanism causes the experience of time.
One argument of plausibility as to why our inner
sense, our body awareness, might be related to
the sense of time should be mentioned here. The
recent proposal of an intimate relationship between
time and the awareness of an emotional and visceral self
(see Craig 2008 2009) seems to be in line with a
western philosophical tradition proposing that time is a
creation of the self. ‘Inner time or duration is virtually
indistinguishable from the awareness of the self, the
experience of the self as an enduring, unitary entity that
is constantly becoming’ (Hartocollis 1983, p. 17).
Thereafter, the experience of our self is only possible as
an entity across time. One attribute of the self is time,
or differently expressed, the self is defined by its
extension over time, a succession of moments that
constitutes duration.
4
This idea is probably most
explicitly expressed by Henri Bergson who noted that
‘psychic states [.] unfold in time and constitute
duration’(Bergson 1913). According to his view, the
phenomenal self creates the sense of duration.
In neurobiological terms, we perceive signals from
the body which create a ‘material me’ that has
subjective feelings and is self-aware (‘I feel it’s me!’;
Craig 2002). Since the ascending pathways to the
insular cortex inform us about the ongoing status of
the body, a pacemaker-type signal (accumulating
successive states of the material self) would be continu-
ously present that could be employed in a timekeeping
system. An accumulation of physiological states
over time would be registered in the insula. This sketch
of a processing model is, of course, borrowed from
the cognitive models with a pacemaker–accumulator unit
and is, to date, speculative. To summarize the main lines
of argument put forward in this review:
(i) Although the perception of time is an essential and
inextricable component of everyday experience,
no conclusive answers to the questions of which
neural substrates and what kind of neurophysio-
logical processes could account for the experience
of duration have been established. That is, several
areas of the brain have been identified as potential
contributors to timekeeping (e.g. cerebellum,
frontal cortices and basal ganglia), but none
have been specifically implicated for this process
and there is no consensus as to the precise neural
mechanisms accounting for our sense of time.
(ii) Philosophical wisdom beginning in antiquity has
related the experience of time to the feeling of a
self. The body self and emotional self in modern
biological terms is based on insular cortex activity.
The signalling of body states, which define the
material me and contribute to the ‘feeling me’, is a
permanent and ongoing process over time and,
thus, could function as an inner measure of
duration by matching external temporal intervals
with the duration of physiological changes.
(iii) The strong relationship between effect and time is
not only an everyday experience of everyone but it
is also well documented by many empirical
studies. Since affective states are entangled with
body states, insular cortex activity (the primary
sensory area for visceral signals) may, therefore,
cause the experience of the passage of time.
ENDNOTES
1
Book 11 of St Augustine’s Confessions: In te, animus meus, tempora
metior [.]ipsam metior, cum tempora metior (electronic edition: http://
ccat.sas.upenn.edu/jod/augustine/).
2
A vivid description of our experience of time from the prospective and
retrospective perspectives can be found in Thomas Mann’s novel The
magic mountain. In his chapter entitled Excursus on the sense of time,
Thomas Mann narrates some of the basic mechanisms of time
perception as described in the psychological sciences of today.
3
From the beginning of psychophysical investigations following
Fechner’s pioneering work, it has been know that, across the time
range between milliseconds and several seconds, the auditory
time sense does not follow the Weber–Fechner law, i.e. Dt/tis not a
constant (Mach 1865). Mach discovered that, in auditory duration,
discrimination, the highest acuity is achieved with base durations
approximately 300–400 ms.
4
In this context,Borges (1999), hintingat the existential aspectof time,
formulated: ‘Time is the substance of which I am made. Time is a river
that sweeps me along, butI am the river; it is a tiger thatmangles me, but
I am the tiger; it is a fire that consumes me, but I am the fire’ (p. 332).
REFERENCES
Ackermann, H., Riecker, A., Mathiak, K., Erb, M., Grodd, W.
& Wildgruber, D. 2001 Rate-dependent activation of
a prefrontal–insular–cerebellar network during passive
listening to trains of click stimuli: an fMRI study.
Neuroreport 12, 4087–4092. (doi:10.1097/00001756-
200112210-00045)
Angrilli, A., Cherubini, P., Pavese, A. & Manfredini, S. 1997
The influence of affective factors on time perception.
Percept. Psychophys. 59, 972–982.
Aparicio, P., Diedrichsen, J. & Ivry, R. B. 2005 Effects of focal
basal ganglia lesions on timing and force control. Brain
Cogn. 58,6274.(doi:10.1016/j.bandc.2004.09.009)
Aschoff, J. 1998 Human perception of short and long time
intervals: its correlation with body temperature and the
duration of wake time. J. Biol. Rhythms 13, 437–442.
(doi:10.1177/074873098129000264)
Avni-Babad, D. & Ritov, I. 2003 Routine and the perception of
time. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen. 132,543550.(doi:10.1037/
0096-3445.132.4.543)
Bailey, N. & Areni, C. S. 2006 Background music as a quasi
clock in retrospective duration judgments. Percept. Mot.
Skills 102,435444.(doi:10.2466/PMS.102.2.435-444)
Bamiou, D. E., Musiek, F. E. & Luxon, L. M. 2003 The insula
(Island of Reil) and its role in auditory processing.
Literature review. Brain Res. Rev. 42,143154.(doi:10.
1016/S0165-0173(03)00172-3)
Bell, C. R. & Provins, K. A. 1963 Relation between
physiological responses to environmental heat and time
judgments. J. Exp. Psychol. 66,572579.(doi:10.1037/
h0048993)
Benussi, V. 1913 Psychologie der Zeitauffassung. Heidelberg,
Germany: Carl Winters Universita¨tsbuchhandlung.
Review. The inner experience of time M. Wittmann 1963
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 31 May 2009rstb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
Bergson, H. 1913 Time and free will.London,UK:George
Allen, Company, Ltd.
Berlin, H. A. & Rolls, E. T. 2004 Time perception, impulsivity,
emotionality, and personality in self-harming borderline
personality disorder patients. J. Per s. D isord . 18, 358–378.
(doi:10.1521/pedi.2004.18.4.358)
Binkofski, F. & Block, R. A. 1996 Accelerated time experience
after left frontal cortex lesion. Neurocase 2, 485–493.
(doi:10.1080/13554799608402424)
Blumenthal, A. L. 1977 The process of cognition. Englewood
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Borges,J.L.1999InSelected non-fictions (ed. E. Weinberger),
New York, NY: Viking.
Brown, S. W. 1997 Attentional resources in timing:
interference effects in concurrent temporal and nontem-
poral working memory tasks. Percept. Psychophys. 59,
1118–1140.
Brunia, C. H. M., de Jong, B. M., van den Berg-Lenssen, M. &
Paans, A. M. J. 2000 Visual feedback about time estimation
is related to a right hemisphere activation measured by
PET. Exp. Brain Res. 130,328337.(doi:10.1007/
s002219900293)
Bschor, T., Ising, M., Bauer, M., Lewitzka, U., Skerstupeit, M.,
Muller-Oerlinghausen, B. & Baethge, C. 2004 Time
experience and time judgment in major depression, mania
and healthy subjects. A controlled study of 93 subjects. Acta
Psychiatr. Scand. 109,222229.(doi:10.1046/j.0001-690X.
2003.00244.x)
Bueti, D., Bahrami, B. & Walsh, V. 2008aThe sensory and
association cortex in time perception. J. Cogn . Ne urosc i. 20,
1054–1062. (doi:10.1162/jocn.2008.20060)
Bueti, D., van Dongen, E. V. & Walsh, V. 2008bThe role of
superior temporal cortex in auditory timing. PLoS ONE 3,
e2481. (doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0002481)
Bueti, D., Walsh, V., Frith,C. & Rees, G. 2008cDifferent brain
circuits underlie motor and perceptual representations of
temporal intervals. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 20, 204–214. (doi:10.
1162/jocn.2008.20017)
Buhusi, C. V. & Meck, W. H. 2002 Differential effects of
methamphetamine and haloperidol on the control of an
internal clock. Behav. Neurosci. 116,291297.(doi:10.
1037/0735-7044.116.2.291)
Buhusi, C. V. & Meck, W. H. 2005 What makes us tick?
Functional and neural mechanisms of interval timing. Nat.
Rev. Neurosci. 6,755765.(doi:10.1038/nrn1764)
Burle, B. & Casini, L. 2001 Dissociation between activation
and attention effects in time estimation: implications for
internal clock models. J. Exp. Psychol. Hum. Percept.
Perform. 27,195205.(doi:10.1037/0096-1523.27.1.195)
Campbell, L. A. & Bryant, R. A. 2007 How time flies: a study
of novice skydivers. Behav. Res. Ther. 45, 1389–1392.
(doi:10.1016/j.brat.2006.05.011)
Cevik, M. O. 2003 Effects of methamphetamine on duration
discrimination. Behav. Neurosci. 117, 774–784. (doi:10.
1037/0735-7044.117.4.774)
Church, R. M. 1984 Properties of the internal clock.
In Timing and time perception, vol. 423 (eds J. Gibbon &
L. Allan), pp. 566–582. New York, NY: New York
Academy of Sciences.
Cohen, J. 1981 A preliminary investigation on time perception
and autonomic self-regulation. Biofeedback Self Regul. 6,
289–293. (doi:10.1007/BF01000654)
Coull, J. T., Vidal, F., Nazarian, B. & Macar, F. 2004
Functional anatomy of the attentional modulation of time
estimation. Science 303, 1506–1508. (doi:10.1126/science.
1091573)
Craig, A. D. 2002 How do you feel? Interoception: the sense of
the physiological condition of the body. Nat. Rev. Neurosci.
3, 655–666.
Craig, A. D. 2003 Interoception: the sense of the physiological
condition of the body. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 13, 500–505.
(doi:10.1016/S0959-4388(03)00090-4)
Craig, A. D. 2008 Interoception and emotion: a neuroanato-
mical perspective. In Handbook of emotion (eds M. Lewis,
J. M. Haviland-Jones & L. F. Barrett), pp. 272–288.
3rd edn. New York, NY: Guilford.
Craig, A. D. (Bud) 2009 Emotional moments across time: a
possible neural basis for time perception in the anterior
insula. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 364, 1933–1942. (doi:10.1098/
rstb.2009.0008)
Critchley, H. D., Wiens, S., Rotshtein, P., O
¨hman, A. & Dolan,
R. J. 2004 Neural systems supporting interoceptive aware-
ness. Nat. Neurosci. 7,189195.(doi:10.1038/nn1176)
Damasio, A. 1999 The feeling of what happens: body and emotion
in the making of consciousness. San Diego, CA: Harcourt, Inc.
Danckert, J. A. & Allman, A. A. A. 2005 Time flies when
you’re having fun: temporal estimation and the experience
of boredom. Brain Cogn. 59,236245.(doi:10.1016/
j.bandc.2005.07.002)
Dehaene, S. 1993 Temporal oscillations in human perception.
Psychol. Sci. 4,264270.(doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.1993.
tb00273.x)
Droit-Volet, S. & Meck, W. H. 2007 How emotions colour our
perception of time. Trends Cogn. Sci. 11,504513.(doi:10.
1016/j.tics.2007.09.008)
Droit-Volet, S., Brunot, S. & Niedenthal, P. M. 2004
Perception of the duration of emotional events. Cogn.
Emot. 18,849858.(doi:10.1080/02699930341000194)
Effron, D. A., Niedenthal, P. M., Gil, S. & Droit-Volet, S. 2006
Embodied temporal perception of emotion. Emotion 6,19.
(doi:10.1037/1528-3542.6.1.1)
Eisler, A. D. & Eisler, H. 1994 Subjective time scaling:
influence of age, gender, and type A and type B behavior.
Chronobiologia 21, 185–200.
Elbert, T., Ulrich, R., Rockstroh, B. & Lutzenberger, W. 1991
The processing of temporal intervals reflected by CNV-like
brain potentials. Psychophysiology 28,648655.(doi:10.
1111/j.1469-8986.1991.tb01009.x)
Evans, V. 2004 The structure of time. Amsterdam,
The Netherlands; Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.
Exner, S. 1875 Experimentelle Untersuchung der einfachsten
psychischen Processe. III. Abhandlung. Pflugers Arch.
Gesamte Physiol. 11,403432.(doi:10.1007/BF01659311)
Falk, J. L. & Bindra, D. 1954 Judgment of time as a function of
serial position and stress. J. Exp. Psychol. 47, 279–282.
(doi:10.1037/h0061946)
Farb, N. A. S., Segal, Z. V., Mayberg, H., Bean, J., McKeon,
D., Fatima, Z. & Anderson, A. K. 2007 Attending to the
present: mindfulness meditation reveals distinct neural
modes of self-reference. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 2,
313–322. (doi:10.1093/scan/nsm030)
Ferrandez, A. M., Hugueville, L., Lehericy, S., Poline, J. B.,
Marsault, C. & Pouthas, V. 2003 Basal ganglia and
supplementary motor area subtend duration perception:
an fMRI study. Neuroimage 19,15321544.(doi:10.1016/
S1053-8119(03)00159-9)
Fingelkurts, A. A. & Fingelkurts, A. A. 2006 Timing in
cognition and EEG brain dynamics: discreteness versus
continuity. Cogn. Process. 7,135162.(doi:10.1007/s1033
9-006-0035-0)
Fink, M., Ulbrich, P., Churan, J. & Wittmann, M. 2006
Stimulus-dependent processing of temporal order. Behav.
Process. 71,344352.(doi:10.1016/j.beproc.2005.12.007)
Flaherty, M. G. 1999 A watched pot: how we experience time.
New York, NY: New York University Press.
Flaherty, M. G., Freidin, B. & Sautu, R. 2005 Variation in the
perceived passage of time: a cross-national study. Soc.
Psychol. Q. 68, 400–410.
1964 M. Wittmann Review. The inner experience of time
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 31 May 2009rstb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
Fraisse, P. 1982 Rhythm and tempo. In The psychology of
music (ed. D. Deutsch), pp. 149–180. New York, NY:
Academic Press.
Fraisse, P. 1984 Perception and estimation of time. Annu. Rev.
Psychol. 35, 1–36. (doi:10.1146/annurev.ps.35.020184.
000245)
Getty, D. J. 1975 Discrimination of short temporal intervals:
a comparison of two models. Percept. Psychophys. 18,18.
Gil, S., Niedenthal, P. M. & Droit-Volet, S. 2007 Anger and
time perception in children. Emotion 7, 219–225. (doi:10.
1037/1528-3542.7.1.219)
Grondin, S. & Macar, F. 1992 Dividing attention between
temporal and nontemporal tasks: a performance
operating characteristics—POC—analysis. In Time, action
and cognition. Towards bridging the gap (eds F. Macar,
V. Pouthas & W. J. Friedman), pp. 119–128. Dordrecht,
The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Hancock, P. A. & Weaver, J. L. 2005 On time distortion under
stress. Theor. Issues Ergon. Sci. 6,193211.(doi:10.1080/
14639220512331325747)
Harrington, D. L., Haaland, K. Y. & Hermanowicz, N. 1998
Temporal processing in the basal ganglia. Neuropsychology
12,312.(doi:10.1037/0894-4105.12.1.3)
Harrington, D. L., Boyd, L. A., Mayer, A. R., Sheltraw, D. M.,
Lee, R. R., Huang, M. & Rao, S. M. 2004aNeural
representation of interval encoding and decision making.
Brain Res. Cogn. Brain Res. 21,193205.(doi:10.1016/
j.cogbrainres.2004.01.010)
Harrington, D. L., Lee, R. R., Boyd, L. A., Rapcsak, S. Z. &
Knight, R. T. 2004bDoes the representation of time
depend on the cerebellum? Effect of cerebellar stroke. Brain
127,561574.(doi:10.1093/brain/awh065)
Hartocollis, P. 1983 Time and timelessness or the varieties of
temporal experience. New York, NY: International
Universities Press.
Hawkes, G., Joy, R. & Evan, W. O. 1962 Autonomic effects on
estimates of time: evidence for a physiological correlate of
temporal experience. J. Psychol. 53, 183–191.
Heidegger, M. 1992 The concept of time. Oxford, UK;
Cambridge, UK: Blackwell Publishers.
Hellstrom, A., Lang, H., Portin, R. & Rinne, J. 1997
Tone duration discrimination in Parkinson’s disease.
Neuropsychologia 35, 737–740. (doi:10.1016/S0028-3932
(96)00122-4)
Hicks, R. E. 1992 Prospective and retrospective judgments of
time: a neurobehavioural analysis. In Time, action and
cognition. Towards bridging the gap (eds F. Macar,
V. Pouthas & W. J. Friedman), pp. 97–108. Dordrecht,
The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Hinton, S. C. & Meck, W. H. 2004 Frontal–striatal circuitry
activated by human peak-interval timing in the supra-
seconds range. Brain Res. Cogn. Brain Res. 21, 171–182.
(doi:10.1016/j.cogbrainres.2004.08.005)
Hirsh, I. J. & Sherrick, C. E. 1961 Perceived order in different
sense modalities. J. Exp. Psychol. 62,423432.(doi:10.
1037/h0045283)
Ivry, R. B. & Keele, S. W. 1989 Timing functions of the
cerebellum. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 1,136152.(doi:10.1162/
jocn.1989.1.2.136)
Ivry, R. B. & Schlerf, J. E. 2008 Dedicated and intrinsic models
of time perception. Trends Cogn. Sci. 12,273280.(doi:10.
1016/j.tics.2008.04.002)
Ivry, R. B. & Spencer, R. M. 2004 The neural representation of
time. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 14,225232.(doi:10.1016/
j.conb.2004.03.013)
Ivry, R. B., Keele, S. W. & Diener, H. C. 1988 Dissociation of
the lateral and medial cerebellum in movement timing and
movement execution. Exp. Brain Res. 73,167180.(doi:10.
1007/BF00279670)
Iwanaga, M. 1995 Harmonic relationship between preferred
tempi and heart rate. Percept. Mot. Skills 81, 67–71.
Jahanshahi, M., Jones, C. R. G., Dirnberger, G. & Frith, C. D.
2006 The substantia nigra pars compacta and temporal
processing. J. Neurosci. 26,1226612273.(doi:10.1523/
JNEUROSCI.2540-06.2006)
James, W. 1890 The principles of psychology. London, UK:
MacMillan.
Jones, C. R. G., Rosenkranz, K., Rothwell, J. C. & Jahanshahi,
M. 2004 The right dorsolateral prefrontalcortex is essential
in time reproduction: an investigation with repetitive
transcranial magnetic stimulation. Exp. Brain Res. 158,
366–372. (doi:10.1007/s00221-004-1912-3)
Kagerer, F. A., Wittmann, M., Szelag, E. &
von Steinbu
¨chel, N. 2002 Cortical involvement in
temporal reproduction: evidence for differential roles
of the hemispheres. Neuropsychologia 40, 357–366.
(doi:10.1016/S0028-3932(01)00111-7)
Kanabus, M., Szelag, E., Rojek, E. & Po¨ ppel, E. 2002
Temporal order judgement for auditory and visual stimuli.
Acta Neurobiol. Exp. 62,263270.
Karmarkar,U.R.&Buonomano,D.V.2007Timinginthe
absence of clocks: encoding time in neural network states.
Neuron 53,427438.(doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2007.01.006)
Kiss, M., Cristescu, T., Fink, M. & Wittmann, M. 2008
Auditory language comprehension of temporally reversed
speech signals in native and non-native speakers. Acta
Neurobiol. Exp. 68, 204–213.
Koch, G., Oliveri, M., Torriero, S. & Caltagirone, C. 2003
Underestimation of time perception after repetitive tran-
scranial magnetic stimulation. Neurology 60, 1844–1846.
Koch, G., Brusa, L., Caltagirone, C., Oliveri, M., Peppe, A.,
Tiraboschi, P. & Stanzione, P. 2004 Subthalamic deep
brain stimulation improves time perception in Parkinson’s
disease. Neuroreport 15, 1071–1073. (doi:10.1097/0000
1756-200404290-00028)
Koch, G., Oliveri, M., Torriero, S., Salerno, S., Gerfo, E. L. &
Caltagirone, C. 2007 Repetitive TMS of cerebellum
interferes with millisecond time processing. Exp. Brain
Res. 179,291299.(doi:10.1007/s00221-006-0791-1)
Lebedev, M. A., O’Doherty, J. E. & Nicolelis, M. A. L. 2008
Decoding of temporal intervals from cortical ensemble
activity. J. Neurophysiol. 99,166186.(doi:10.1152/jn.
00734.2007)
Lediett, V. & Tong, J. E. 1972 Effects of heart-rate increase on
temporal discrimination and time judgment by two groups
of delinquents. Percept. Mot. Skills 34, 759–764.
Leon, M. I. & Shadlen, M. N. 2003 Representation of time
byneuronsintheposteriorparietalcortexofthe
macaque. Neuron 38, 317–327. (doi:10.1016/S0896-
6273(03)00185-5)
Lewis, P. A. & Miall, R. C. 2003aBrain activation patterns
during measurement of sub- and supra-second intervals.
Neuropsychologia 41, 1583–1592. (doi:10.1016/S0028-
3932(03)00118-0)
Lewis, P. A. & Miall, R. C. 2003bDistinct systems for
automatic and cognitively controlled time measurement:
evidence from neuroimaging. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 13,
250–255. (doi:10.1016/S0959-4388(03)00036-9)
Lewis, P. A. & Miall, R. C. 2006 A right hemispheric prefrontal
system for cognitive time measurement. Behav. Process. 71,
226–234. (doi:10.1016/j.beproc.2005.12.009)
Livesey, A. C., Wall, M. B. & Smith, A. T.2007 Time perception:
manipulation of task difficulty dissociates clock functions
from other cognitive demand s. Neuropsychologia 45,321331.
(doi:10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2006.06.033)
Mach, E. 1865 Untersuchungen u
¨ber den Zeitsinn des Ohres.
Sitzungsberichte der kaiserlichen Akademie der Wissenschaften
Wien 51,133150.
Review. The inner experience of time M. Wittmann 1965
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 31 May 2009rstb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
Madison, G. 2001 Variability in isochronous tapping: higher
order dependencies as a function of intertap interval. J. Exp.
Psychol. Hum. Percept. Perform. 27,411422.(doi:10.1037/
0096-1523.27.2.411)
Marchetti, G. 2009 Studies on time: a proposal on how to get
out of circularity. Cog. Process. 10, 7–40. (doi:10.1007/
s10339-008-0215-1)
Matell, M. S. & Meck, W. H. 2004 Cortico-striatal circuits and
interval timing: coincidence detection of oscillatory
processes. Brain Res. Cogn. Brain Res. 21, 139–170.
(doi:10.1016/j.cogbrainres.2004.06.012)
Mates, J., Muller, U., Radil, T. & Po¨ppel, E. 1994 Temporal
integration in sensorimotor synchronization. J. Cogn.
Neurosci. 6,332340.(doi:10.1162/jocn.1994.6.4.332)
Mauk, M. D. & Buonomano, D. V. 2004 The neural basis of
temporal processing. Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 27, 307–340.
(doi:10.1146/annurev.neuro.27.070203.144247)
Meck, W. H. 1996 Neuropharmacology of timing and time
perception. Brain Res. Cogn. Brain Res. 3,227242.(doi:10.
1016/0926-6410(96)00009-2)
Melges, F. T. & Fougerousse, C. E. 1966 Time sense,
emotions, and acute mental illness. J. Psychiatr. Res. 4,
127–139. (doi:10.1016/0022-3956(66)90025-2)
Miyake, Y., Onishi, Y. & Po¨ppel, E. 2004 Two types of
anticipation in synchronization tapping. Acta Neurobiol.
Exp. 64, 415–426.
Mohs, R. C., Tinklenberg, J. R., Roth, W. T. & Kopell, B. S. 1980
Sensitivity of some human cognitive functions to effects
of methamphetamine and secobarbital. Drug Alcohol Depend.
5,145150.(doi:10.1016/0376-8716(80)90191-X)
Mu
¨nsterberg, H. 1889 Beitra
¨ge zur experimentellen Psychologie,
Heft 1. Freiburg, Germany: J. C. B. Mohr.
Nakajima, Y., Shimojo, S. & Sugita, Y. 1980 On the perception
of two successive sound bursts. Psychol. Res. 41, 335–344.
(doi:10.1007/BF00308878)
Nenadic, I., Gaser,C., Volz, H. P., Rammsayer, T., Ha¨ger,F.&
Sauer, H. 2003 Processing of temporal information and the
basal ganglia: new evidence from fMRI. Exp. Brain Res. 148,
238–246.
Nichelli, P., Clark, K., Hollnagel, C. & Grafman, J. 1995
Duration processing after frontal lobe lesions. Ann. NY
Acad. Sci. 769, 183–190. (doi:10.1111/j.1749-6632.1995.
tb38139.x)
Nobre, A. C. & O’Reilly, J. 2004 Time is of the essence. Trends
Cogn. Sci. 8,387389.(doi:10.1016/j.tics.2004.07.005)
Noulhiane, M., Mella, N., Samson, S., Ragot, R. & Pouthas, V.
2007aHow emotional auditory stimuli modulate time
perception. Emotion 7,697704.(doi:10.1037/1528-3542.
7.4.697)
Noulhiane, M., Pouthas, V., Hasboun, D., Baulac, M. &
Samson, S. 2007bRole of the medial temporal lobe in time
estimation in the range of minutes. Neuroreport 18,
1035–1038. (doi:10.1097/WNR.0b013e3281668be1)
Noulhiane, M., Pouthas, V. & Samson, S. 2008 Is time
reproduction sensitive to sensory modalities? Eur. J. Cogn.
Psychol. 21,1834.(doi:10.1080/09541440701825981)
Oppenheimer, D. M. 2008 The secret life of fluency. Trends
Cogn. Sci. 12,237241.(doi:10.1016/j.tics.2008.02.014)
Ornstein, R. E. 1970 On the experience of time.Baltimore,MD:
Penguin Books.
Osato, E., Ogawa, N. & Takaoka, N. 1995 Relations among
heart rate, immediate memory, and time estimation under
two different instructions. Percept. Mot. Skills 80, 831–842.
Peters, M. 1989 The relationship between variability of
intertap intervals and interval duration. Psychol. Res. 51,
38–42. (doi:10.1007/BF00309274)
Pfeuty, M., Ragot, R. & Pouthas, V. 2005 Relationship
between CNV and timing of an upcoming event. Neurosci.
Lett. 382,106111.(doi:10.1016/j.neulet.2005.02.067)
Pollatos, O., Kirsch, W. & Schandry, R. 2005 On the
relationship between interoceptive awareness, emotional
experience, and brain processes. Brain Res. Cogn. Brain Res.
25,948962.(doi:10.1016/j.cogbrainres.2005.09.019)
Pollatos, O., Herbert, B. M., Matthias, E. & Schandry, R.
2007aHeart rate response after emotional picture presen-
tation is modulated by interoceptive awareness. Int.
J. Psychophys. 63,117124.(doi:10.1016/j.ijpsycho.2006.
09.003)
Pollatos, O., Schandry, R., Auer, D. P. & Kaufmann, C. 2007b
Brain structures mediating cardiovascular arousal and
interoceptive awareness. Brain Res. 1141, 178–187.
(doi:10.1016/j.brainres.2007.01.026)
Po¨ ppel, E. 1970 Excitability cycles in central intermittency.
Psychol. Res. 34,19.(doi:10.1007/BF00422860)
Po¨ ppel, E. 1971 Oscillations as possible basis for time
perception. Stud. Gen. 24,85107.
Po¨ ppel, E. 1997 A hierarchical model of temporal perception.
Trends Cogn. Sci. 1,5661.(doi:10.1016/S1364-6613(97)
01008-5)
Po¨ ppel, E. 2009 Pre-semantically defined temporal windows
for cognitive processing. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 364,
1887–1896. (doi:10.1098/rstb.2009.0015)
Pouthas, V. & Perbal, S. 2004 Time perception does not only
depend on accurate clock mechanisms but also on unim-
paired attention and memory processes. Acta Neurobiol.
Exp. 64, 367–385.
Pouthas, V. et al. 2005 Neural network involved in time
perception: an fMRI study comparing long and short
interval estimation. Hum. Brain Mapp. 25, 433–441.
(doi:10.1002/hbm.20126)
Rammsayer, T. H. 1997 On the relationship between
personality and time estimation. Pers. Individ. Dif. 23,
739–744. (doi:10.1016/S0191-8869(97)00117-7)
Rammsayer, T. H. 1999 Neuropharmacological evidence for
different timing mechanisms in humans. Q. J. Exp. Psychol.
B52,273286.(doi:10.1080/027249899391070)
Rammsayer, T. H. & Lima, S. D. 1991 Duration discrimi-
nation of filled and empty auditory intervals: cognitive and
perceptual factors. Percept. Psychophys. 50, 565–574.
Rammsayer, T. H., Hennig, J., Haag, A. & Lange, N. 2001
Effects of noradrenergic activity on temporal information
processing in humans. Q. J. Exp. Psychol. B 54, 247–258.
(doi:10.1080/02724990143000036)
Rao, S. M., Mayer, A. R. & Harrington, D. L. 2001 The
evolution of brain activation during temporal processing.
Nat. Neurosci. 4,317323.(doi:10.1038/85191)
Rubia, K. & Smith, A. 2004 The neural correlates of cognitive
time management: a review. Acta Neurobiol. Exp. 64,
329–340.
Rubia, K., Overmeyer, S., Taylor, E., Brammer, M., Williams,
S., Simmons, A., Andrew, C. & Bullmore, E. 1998
Prefrontal involvement in temporal bridging and timing
movement. Neuropsychologia 36, 1283–1293. (doi:10.1016/
S0028-3932(98)00038-4)
Ruhnau, E. 1995 Time-gestalt and the observer. In Conscious
experience (ed. T. Metzinger), pp. 165–184. Paderborn,
Germany: Ferdinand Scho¨ningh.
Saper, C. B. 2002 The central autonomic nervous system:
conscious visceral perception and autonomic pattern
generation. Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 25, 433–469. (doi:10.
1146/annurev.neuro.25.032502.111311)
Schaefer, V. G. & Gilliland, A. R. 1938 The relation of time
estimation to certain physiological changes. J. Exp. Psychol.
23, 545–552. (doi:10.1037/h0061414)
Schulman, C. A., Richlin, M. & Weinstein, S. 1967
Hallucinations and disturbances of affect, cognition, and
physical state as a function of sensory deprivation. Perc ept.
Mot. Skills 25, 1001–1024.
1966 M. Wittmann Review. The inner experience of time
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 31 May 2009rstb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
Shrivastav, M. N., Humes, L. E. & Aylsworth, L. 2008
Temporal order discrimination of tonal sequences by
younger and older adults: the role of duration and rate.
J. Acoust. Soc. Am. 124,462471.(doi:10.1121/1.2932089)
Siegman, A. W. 1962 Anxiety, impulse control, intelligence,
and the estimation of time. J. Clin. Psychol. 18, 103–105.
(doi:10.1002/1097-4679(196201)18:1!103::AID-JCLP
2270180134O3.0.CO;2-K)
Smith, A., Taylor, E., Lidzba, K. & Rubia, K. 2003 A right
hemispheric frontocerebellar network for time discrimi-
nation of several hundreds of milliseconds. Neuroimage 20,
344–350. (doi:10.1016/S1053-8119(03)00337-9)
Staddon, J. E. R. 2005 Interval timing: memory, not a clock.
Trends Cogn. Sci. 9,312314.(doi:10.1016/j.tics.2005.
05.013)
Stetson, C., Fiesta, M. P. & Eagleman, D. M. 2007 Does time
really slow down during a frightening event. PLoS ONE 2,
e1295. (doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0001295)
Stevens, M. C., Kiehl, K. A., Pearlson, G. & Calhoun, V. D.
2007 Functional neural circuits for mental timekeeping.
Hum. Brain Mapp. 28,394408.(doi:10.1002/hbm.20285)
Szelag, E.,von Steinbuchel,N., Reiser, M.,Gilles de Langen,E.
&Po¨ ppel, E. 1996 Temporal constraints in processing of
nonverbal rhythmic patterns. Acta Neurobiol. Exp. 56,
215–225.
Taatgen, N. A., van Rijn, H. & Anderson, J. R. 2007 An
integrated theory of prospective time interval estimation:
the role of cognition, attention and learning. Psychol. Rev.
114,577598.(doi:10.1037/0033-295X.114.3.577)
Tinklenberg, J. R., Roth, W. T. & Kopell, B. S. 1976 Marijuana
and ethanol: differential effects on time perception, heart
rate, and subjective response. Psychopharmacology 49,
275–279. (doi:10.1007/BF00426830)
Treisman, M., Faulkner, A., Naish, P. L. N. & Brogan, D.
1990 The internal clock: evidence for a temporal oscillator
underlying time perception with some estimates of its
characteristic frequency. Percepti on 19,705743.(doi:10.
1068/p190705)
Trevarthen, C. 1999 Musicality and the intrinsic motive
pulse: evidence from human psychobiology and infant
communication. Musicae Scientiae 1999–2000 (Special Issue),
155–215.
Tse, P. U., Intriligator, J., Rivest, J. & Cavanagh, P. 2004
Attention and the subjective expansion of time. Percept.
Psychophys. 66, 1171–1189.
Twenge, J. M., Catanese, K. R. & Baumeister, R. F. 2003
Social exclusion and the deconstructed state: time percep-
tion, meaninglessness, lethargy, lack of emotion, and self-
awareness. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 85, 409–423. (doi:10.1037/
0022-3514.85.3.409)
Ulbrich, P., Churan, J., Fink, M. & Wittmann, M. 2007
Temporal reproduction: further evidence for two processes.
Acta Psychol. 125,5165.(doi:10.1016/j.actpsy.2006.
06.004)
VanRullen, R. & Koch, C. 2003 Is perception discrete or
continuous? Trends Cogn. Sci. 7,207213.(doi:10.1016/
S1364-6613(03)00095-0)
van Wassenhove, V., Grant, K. W. & Poeppel, D. 2007
Temporal window of integration in auditory–visual speech
perception. Neuropsychologia 45,598607.(doi:10.1016/
j.neuropsychologia.2006.01.001)
Vohs, K. D. & Schmeichel, B. J. 2003 Self-regulation and the
extended now: controlling the self alters the subjective
experience of time. J.Pers.Soc.Psychol.85, 217–230.
(doi:10.1037/0022-3514.85.2.217)
Wackermann, J. & Ehm, W. 2006 The dual klepsydra model of
internal timerepresentation and timereproduction. J. Theor.
Biol. 239,482493.(doi:10.1016/j.jtbi.2005.08.024)
Wackermann, J., Wittmann, M., Hasler, F. & Vollenweider,
F. X. 2008 Effects of varied doses of psilocybin on time
interval reproduction in human subjects. Neurosci. Lett.
435,5155.(doi:10.1016/j.neulet.2008.02.006)
Warren, R. M. & Obusek, C. J. 1972 Identification of temporal
order within auditory sequences. Percept. Psychophys. 12,
86–90.
Watts, F. N. & Sharrock, R. 1984 Fear and time estimation.
Percept. Mot. Skills 59, 597–598.
Wearden, J. H. 2004 Decision processes in models of timing.
Acta Neurobiol. Exp. 64,303317.
White, C. T. 1963 Temporal numerosity and the psychological
unit of duration. Psychol. Monogr. 77,137.
Wiens, S. 2005 Interoception in emotional experience. Curr.
Opin. Neurol. 18,442447.(doi:10.1097/01.wco.0000168
079.92106.99)
Wittmann, M. 1999 Time perception and temporal processing
levels of the brain. Chronobiol. Int. 16,1732.(doi:10.3109/
07420529908998709)
Wittmann, M. & Lehnhoff, S. 2005 Age effects in perception
of time. Psychol. Rep. 97, 921–935. (doi:10.2466/PR0.97.7.
921-935)
Wittmann, M. & Paulus, M. P. 2008 Decision making,
impulsivity and time perception. Trends Cogn. Sci. 12,
7–12. (doi:10.1016/j.tics.2007.10.004)
Wittmann, M. & Po¨ppel, E. 2000 Temporal mechanisms of
the brain as fundamentals of communication—with special
reference to music perception and performance. Musicae
Scientiae 1999–2000 (Special Issue), 13–28.
Wittmann, M., von Steinbu
¨chel, N. & Szelag, E. 2001
Hemispheric specialisation for self-paced motor sequences.
Brain Res. Cogn. Brain Res. 10,341344.(doi:10.1016/
S0926-6410(00)00052-5)
Wittmann, M., Vollmer, T., Schweiger, C. & Hiddemann, W.
2006 The relation between the experience of time and
psychological distress in patients with hematological
malignancies. Palliat. Support. Care 4,357363.(doi:10.
1017/S1478951506060469)
Wittmann, M., Carter, O., Hasler, F., Cahn, B. R.,
Grimberg, U., Spring, P., Hell, D., Flohr, H. &
Vollenweider, F. X. 2007aEffects of psilocybin on time
perception and temporal control of behaviour in humans.
J. Psychopharmacol. 21,5064.(doi:10.1177/02698811
06065859)
Wittmann, M., Leland, D. S., Churan, J. & Paulus, M. P.
2007bImpaired time perception and motor timing in
stimulant-dependent subjects. Drug Alcohol Depend. 90,
183–192. (doi:10.1016/j.drugalcdep.2007.03.005)
Wittmann, M., Simmons, A. N., Aron, J. L. & Paulus, M. P.
2008 Accumulation of neural activity in the posterior insula
encodes the passage of time. Nature Precedings.Seehttp://
hdl.handle.net/10101/npre.2008.2062.1.
Zakay, D. & Block, R. A. 1997 Temporal cognition. Curr.
Dir. Psychol. Sci. 6,1216.(doi:10.1111/1467-8721.
ep11512604)
Zakay,D.&Block,R.A.2004Prospectiveandretrospective
duration judgments: an executive-control perspective. Acta
Neurobiol. Exp. 64, 319–328.
Review. The inner experience of time M. Wittmann 1967
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 31 May 2009rstb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
... So erzeugen Herzschlag und Atembewegung, auch wenn sie meist nicht bewusst wahrgenommen werden, doch eine ständige unterschwellige Rhythmisierung des Bewusstseinsstroms. Neuere Forschungen sprechen dafür, dass die zentrale Integration von solchen rhythmischen Körpersignalen insbesondere in der Insel-Region des Gehirns unserem Sinn für zeitliche Dauer zugrunde liegt (Craig 2009;Wittmann 2009)einem Zeitsinn, der bekanntlich kein eigenes Sinnesorgan aufweist. So kann man experimentell alle exterozeptive Sinneswahrnehmung ausschalten, etwa durch vollständigen Reizentzug in Isolationstanks; doch bleibt selbst unter diesen Umständen der unmittelbare Zeitsinn intakt, denn das Leibempfinden lässt sich dabei nicht aufheben (Kjellgren et al. 2008). ...
Chapter
Full-text available
... T IME perception, or the subjective experience of time in humans, has been extensively studied from both psychological and neuroscientific standpoints [1]. This research has been able to offer scientific explanations to common phrases like "time flies when we are having fun" or "a watched pot never boils" [2]. ...
Preprint
Time perception research has advanced significantly over the years. However, some areas remain largely unexplored. This study addresses two such under-explored areas in timing research: (1) A quantitative analysis of time perception at an individual level, and (2) Time perception in an ecological setting. In this context, we trained a machine learning model to predict the direction of change in an individual's time production. The model's training data was collected using an ecologically valid setup. We moved closer to an ecological setting by conducting an online experiment with 995 participants performing a time production task that used naturalistic videos (no audio) as stimuli. The model achieved an accuracy of 61%. This was 10 percentage points higher than the baseline models derived from cognitive theories of timing. The model performed equally well on new data from a second experiment, providing evidence of its generalization capabilities. The model's output analysis revealed that it also contained information about the magnitude of change in time production. The predictions were further analysed at both population and individual level. It was found that a participant's previous timing performance played a significant role in determining the direction of change in time production. By integrating attentional-gate theories from timing research with feature importance techniques from machine learning, we explained model predictions using cognitive theories of timing. The model and findings from this study have potential applications in systems involving human-computer interactions where understanding and predicting changes in user's time perception can enable better user experience and task performance.
... I suggest the dimension of Passage of Time to properly capture the diversity of the experience of the flow of time or lack thereof instantiated in these experiences (see Figure 3). This dimension allows us to better distinguish between two features of the subjective experience of the passage of time identified in the literature: the feeling of nowness, also known as the specious present (James, 1980;Varela, 1999) and the experience of duration, or flow of time (Wittmann, 2009;Wittmann and Schmidt, 2014). In most cases, these experiences might seem to lack "time" as in the case of "timeless" ones, yet they might still involve a sense of "nowness" or present. ...
Article
Full-text available
I introduce a novel multidimensional framework tailored to investigate a set of phenomena that might appear intractable and render them amenable to scientific inquiry. In particular, I focus on examining altered states of consciousness that appear to the experiencing subject as “contentless” or “objectless” states in some form, either by having disrupted or reduced content of awareness, or content that appears as missing altogether. By drawing on empirical research, I propose a cluster of phenomenological dimensions aimed at enhancing our understanding of this group of experiences of minimal awareness, including Richness of the Content, Bodily-Awareness, Passage of Time, Attentional Focus, and Self-Revelation. The result is a robust framework that provides precise scientific terminology, facilitating its operationalisation and adaptability for future empirical work. I show the explanatory power of this framework through a case study of the state of clear light sleep—a state widely reported by Indo-Tibetan Buddhist traditions as an instance of pure awareness during sleep, a state of consciousness-as-such. This rare phenomenon has gained increasing attention in contemporary analytic philosophy of mind for the study of the nature of consciousness. However, we still lack consensus on its characterisation and potential identity with other associated states. I end the paper by illustrating how the state of clear light sleep can be situated in relation to other associated states and more ordinary ones as regions of a multidimensional state space.
... Our subjective well-being also strongly affects how we perceive time. Time seems to speed up during pleasurable activities but drags on during periods of boredom (Wittmann, 2009). Social isolation, and stress can slow the perception of time, while high levels of social satisfaction and low levels of stress can, conversely, speed up its passage (Droit-Volet et al., 2020; Martinelli et al., 2020). ...
Preprint
Full-text available
This study explores the relationship between emotions, physiological responses, interoception, and time perception. We also aimed to understand how body dissatisfaction influences this interplay. Participants (N = 40) watched videos designed to evoke positive, neutral, and negative emotions while their heart rate was monitored via electrocardiography. Our findings indicate that video duration perception varied depending on emotional content. Negative and neutral videos were perceived as shorter, while positive videos were estimated more accurately. Negative emotions were linked to a decrease in heart rate, suggesting a "freeze response," while positive and neutral content did not significantly affect heart rate. A significant correlation between heart rate and time perception was observed in participants with a normal body image, indicating that heart rate might serve as an internal clock. However, this correlation was absent in those with body image dissatisfaction, implying a weakened link between physiological states and time perception. Additionally, a strong negative correlation between heart rate and interoceptive accuracy was found in participants with body image dissatisfaction. The results suggest that body image dissatisfaction disrupts the integration of emotional and physiological signals, affecting how we perceive and understand our internal bodily sensations and emotions.
... D. Craig 2015, p. 188;see A. D. Craig 2003). The multimodal integration in the insular cortex does not only facilitate efficiency and emotional processing, but has also been linked to awareness and sense of time (Fermin et al. 2023;Wittmann 2009). All of them are vital for engaging with music. ...
Chapter
Performing and perceiving music requires the integration of multimodal information, including sensations of one’s own body. Research on musical engagement investigated emotional responses and the peripheral physiological activations involved, as well as bodily action tendencies, effects on time perception, and the role of awareness and focus of attention. The concept of interoception dedicates a central role to the insular cortex, as suggested by Craig and others, and offers a unifying framework for studying music as an activity that has always had a key role for individuals, groups, societies, with a strong bodily component. Chances and challenges of an interoceptive perspective on music are discussed.
... Neural circuits adjust their processing and computation of temporal information depending on the nature of the task (4,7,8). While recent research has examined how humans, primates and rodents categorize the duration of stimuli (9)(10)(11), there remains significant uncertainty about where and how the perception and memory of time are processed in the brain, and how this information is used for comparison and decision-making (12). ...
Preprint
Full-text available
Understanding how time perception adapts to cognitive demands remains a significant challenge. In some contexts, the brain encodes time categorically (as “long” or “short”), while in others, it encodes precise time intervals on a continuous scale. Although the ventral premotor cortex (VPC) is known for its role in complex temporal processes, such as speech, its specific involvement in time estimation remains underexplored. In this study, we investigated how the VPC processes temporal information during a time interval comparison task (TICT) and a time interval categorization task (TCT) in primates. We found a notable heterogeneity in neuronal responses associated with time perception across both tasks. While most neurons responded during time interval presentation, a smaller subset retained this information during the working memory periods. Population-level analysis revealed distinct dynamics between tasks: in TICT, population activity exhibited a linear and parametric relationship with interval duration, whereas in TCT, neuronal activity diverged into two distinct dynamics corresponding to the interval categories. During delay periods, these categorical or parametric representations remained consistent within each task context. This contextual shift underscores the VPC’s adaptive role in interval estimation and highlights how temporal representations are modulated by cognitive demands. Significance Statement The neural representation of time has long intrigued neuroscientists, particularly how it adapts to cognitive demands. Depending on the task, the brain encodes time either categorically (“long” or “short”) or as precise intervals. While the ventral premotor cortex (VPC) is known for its role in temporal processes, its role in time estimation remains underexplored. Here, we examined how the VPC processes temporal information in primates during a time interval comparison task (TICT) and a categorization task (TCT). The VPC exhibited heterogeneous neuronal responses with distinct dynamics: a linear, parametric relationship in TICT and bifurcated dynamics in TCT. These representations remained consistent during delay periods, underscoring the VPC’s adaptive role in time interval estimation.
... Time perception, fundamental to human experience, has traditionally been explained by appealing to inner 'clocks' that attempt to track physical, objective time [73][74][75][76]. More recently, an alternative proposal has emerged, which argues that subjective duration can be accounted for by accumulated salient change in perceptual processing [77]. ...
Preprint
In the context of consciousness studies, a key challenge is how to rigorously conceptualise first-person phenomenological descriptions of lived experience and their relation to third-person empirical measurements of the activity or dynamics of the brain and body. Since the 1990s, there has been a coordinated effort to explicitly combine first-person phenomenological methods, generating qualitative data, with neuroscientific techniques used to describe and quantify brain activity under the banner of "neurophenomenology". Here, we take on this challenge and develop an approach to neurophenomenology from a mathematical perspective. We harness recent advances in theoretical neuroscience and the physics of cognitive systems to mathematically conceptualise first-person experience and its correspondence with neural and behavioural dynamics. Throughout, we make the operating assumption that the content of first-person experience can be formalised as (or related to) a belief (i.e. a probability distribution) that encodes an organism's best guesses about the state of its external and internal world (e.g. body or brain) as well as its uncertainty. We mathematically characterise phenomenology, bringing to light a tool-set to quantify individual phenomenological differences and develop several hypotheses including on the metabolic cost of phenomenology and on the subjective experience of time. We conceptualise the form of the generative passages between first- and third-person descriptions, and the mathematical apparatus that mutually constrains them, as well as future research directions. In summary, we formalise and characterise first-person subjective experience and its correspondence with third-person empirical measurements of brain and body, offering hypotheses for quantifying various aspects of phenomenology to be tested in future work.
Thesis
Full-text available
Mindfulness and flow are two optimal, therapeutic and productive states of consciousness that have recently gained a lot of attention in various fields such as clinical, cognitive science, psychology, sports, music, human-computer interaction, etc. There is an ongoing discussion about the similarities and differences between these two states, and numerous studies have appeared comparing the two based on various parameters such as present awareness and the type of self that both seek to promote. Research on integrating mindfulness to influence the flow phenomenon has proven to be a promising field, but there is little knowledge about the relationship between these two states in general and in a musical context in particular. The aim of this study was to investigate the relationship between the constructs of mindfulness and the dimensions of flow during the process of playing a musical instrument. Playing a musical instrument is one of the most important areas for entering the flow state, and research on the relevance of mindfulness during the flow phenomenon in a musical context is still in its infancy. This work is divided into two main studies. The first study aims to investigate whether the dispositional trait of mindfulness has a predictive relationship with different dimensions of flow. Such an investigation should understand the nature of optimal experiences of mindfulness and flow and try to elucidate the issues related to their coexistence and interdependence. The second study was a qualitative study aimed at observing the changes in the lived experience of flow by changing mindfulness levels in musicians. A one-month musical induction program was planned with two music students and two musicians. Mindfulness and flow are two optimal, therapeutic and productive states of consciousness that have recently gained a great deal of attention in various fields such as clinical, cognitive science, psychology, sports, music, human-computer interaction, etc. There is an ongoing discussion about the similarities and differences between these two states, and numerous studies have appeared comparing the two based on various parameters such as present awareness and the type of self that both seek to promote. Research on integrating mindfulness to influence the flow phenomenon has proven to be a promising field, but there is little knowledge about the relationship between these two states in general and in a musical context in particular. The aim of this study was to investigate the relationship between the constructs of mindfulness and the dimensions of flow during the process of playing a musical instrument. Playing a musical instrument is one of the most important areas for entering the flow state, and research on the relevance of mindfulness during the flow phenomenon in a musical context is still in its infancy. This work is divided into two main studies. The first study aims to investigate whether the dispositional trait of mindfulness has a predictive relationship with different dimensions of flow. Such an investigation should understand the nature of optimal experiences of mindfulness and flow and try to elucidate the issues related to their coexistence and interdependence. The second study was a qualitative study aimed at observing the changes in the lived experience of flow by changing mindfulness levels in musicians. A one-month musical induction program was planned with two music students and two musicians. In summary, the results of the experiments presented in this thesis provide a preliminary understanding of how mindfulness is related to various dimensions of flow and how a mindfulness training program has an ability to influence flow in musical instrument playing context. This thesis contributes to the literature at a conceptual level by identifying which constructs of mindfulness that have a greater influence on different dimensions of flow as well as outlining relevant mindfulness-based intervention techniques.
Article
Full-text available
The experience of time, i.e. the estimation of duration, is fundamental for perception and behavior and, therefore, essential for the survival of the individual organism. Over the last decades, neuroimaging, neurophysiological and clinical neuropsychological studies have pointed to many different brain areas involved in the processing of time. However, the core neural substrates and the processes accounting for the encoding of duration, which could form a timekeeping mechanism (essentially, a neural clock), are still unknown. Here we present evidence of neurophysiological activity in circumscribed areas of the human brain that is involved in the encoding of duration. Time-activity curves of neural activation derived from event-related functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) during a time estimation task show that bilateral posterior insula as well as superior temporal and inferior parietal cortices build up activation when individuals are presented with 9 or 18 seconds tone intervals. Since the build up of neuronal activation peaks at the end of the interval, it appears that this accumulator-type activity encodes duration. Because of the close connection between posterior insula and ascending internal body signals, the accumulation of physiological changes in body states might constitute our experience of time. These results could be the starting point for a neural model of human time perception in the multiple-seconds range in which specific brain regions accumulate brain activity for the representation of duration.
Chapter
Full-text available
In order to study the influence of attention on time perception, a strategy is proposed that is a combination of two methods. One method is the sharing of attention between temporal and nontemporal information. The other method is that used to trace a Performance Operating Characteristics (POC) curve; the POC curve serves to investigate the relative cost of concurrent tasks when the subject is asked to allocate different amounts of attention to each of two tasks. The tasks are (1) duration discrimination between two confusable time intervals and (2) loudness discrimination between two confusable auditory intensities. Five different conditions of allocation are manipulated, and two durations are investigated: 500 and 1500 ms. The results suggest: (1) that both the temporal and the nontemporal performances suffer from attention sharing, which decreases the amount of attention to a given task and thus increases the number of discrimination errors; and (2) that when less attention is allocated to the passage of time, the perceived duration seems shorter at 500 ms but not at 1500 ms.
Article
We report a patient, BW, with an accelerated time experience as a result of a glioblastoma in his left superior prefrontal cortex. He experienced external events as seeming to occur at a much faster rate than before the lesion, but he showed normal awareness of time, place, and identity. He displayed behavioral slowness, some aphasia, right hemispatial neglect, and other neuropsychological problems typical of left frontal damage. When asked to produce 60 s durations, BW's mean production was extremely long (286.0 s). This finding is consistent with the notion that subjective duration had decreased relative to objective duration. Several explanations for the findings are discussed, including the possibility that the rate of an internal pacemaker was greatly slowed.
Article
To investigate how time perception may contribute to the symptoms of self-harming Borderline Personality Disorder (BPD) patients, 19 self-harming BPD inpatients and 39 normal controls were given measures of time perception, impulsivity, personality, emotion, and BPD characteristics. A test sensitive to orbitofrontal cortex (OFC) function ("Frontal" Behavior Questionnaire) was also administered, as the OFC has been associated with impulsivity and time perception. BPD patients produced less time than controls, and this correlated with impulsiveness and other characteristics commonly associated with BPD. BPD patients were also less conscientious, extraverted, and open to experience, as well as more impulsive (self-report and behaviorally), emotional, neurotic, and reported more BPD characteristics, compared to controls. The results suggest that some of these core characteristics of BPD may be on a continuum with the normal population and, impulsivity in particular, may be related to time perception deficits (i.e., a faster subjective sense of time). Finally, BPD patients scored higher on the Frontal Behavior Questionnaire, suggesting that some symptoms of the BPD syndrome may be related to problems associated with the OFC. A control spatial working memory task (SWM) revealed that SWM deficits could not explain any of the BPD patients' poor performance. While impulsivity was correlated with time perception across all participants, emotionality, introversion, and lack of openness to experience were not. This suggests that different symptoms of the borderline personality syndrome may be separable, and therefore, related to different cognitive deficits, and potentially to different brain systems. This may have important implications for treatment strategies for BPD.
Chapter
Several psychopharmacological experiments on prospective judgments and one experiment on retrospective judgments of time are described briefly. Literature is reviewed supporting a relationship between prospective timing and contingent negative variation. Both these phenomena are hypothesized to result from dopaminergic neuronal activity in the prefrontal cortex, and to reflect activity of a more general behavioral regulation system. Retrospective judgments of time are hypothesized to reflect activity in some aspect of neuronal activity involved with long-term memory.
Article
Anticipation in timing control is one of the important human's ability to cooperate with dynamic environment. In this research, we studied synchronization tapping as an example of timing control and Negative Asynchrony phenomenon in which the tap onset precedes to the onset of tone was observed. To clarify the mechanism of this anticipatory response from the viewpoint of time perception, effect of subject's attention was investigated. In order to control the attention, we used the silent reading as a secondary task of dual task method. In this condition, we measured the range of the period of tonal stimuli (Inter Stimulus Interval; ISI) which may be affected by the subject's attention using synchronization tapping task on ISI range of 450 to 6000ms. Consequently, it was revealed that the mechanism of this timing control depending on a subject's attentional resources works on ISI for about 1800ms or more. This result suggests that there are two modes of anticipatory timing control, an automatic one and an intentional one.