ArticlePDF Available

Abstract

I discuss the apparent discrepancy between the qualitative diversity of consciousness and the relative qualitative homogeneity of the brain's basic constituents, a discrepancy that has been raised as a problem for identity theorists by Maxwell and Lockwood (as one element of the ‘grain problem’), and more recently as a problem for panpsychists (under the heading of ‘the palette problem’). The challenge posed to panpsychists by this discrepancy is to make sense of how a relatively small ‘palette’ of basic qualities could give rise to the bewildering diversity of qualities we, and presumably other creatures, experience. I argue that panpsychists can meet this challenge, though it requires taking a contentious stands on certain phenomenological questions, in particular on whether any familiar qualities are actual examples of ‘phenomenal blending’, and whether any other familiar qualities have a positive ‘phenomenologically simple character’. Moreover, it requires accepting an eventual theory most elements of which are in a certain explicable sense unimaginable, though not for that reason inconceivable. Nevertheless, I conclude that there are no conclusive reasons to reject such a theory, and so philosophers whose prior commitments motivate them to adopt it can do so without major theoretical cost.
Thought ISSN 2161-2234
ORIGINAL ARTICLE
Phenomenal Blending and the Palette
Problem
Luke Roelofs
University of Toronto
I discuss the apparent discrepancy between the qualitative diversity of consciousness and the
relative qualitative homogeneity of the brain’s basic constituents, a discrepancy that has been
raised as a problem for identity theorists by Maxwell and Lockwood (as one element of the ‘grain
problem’), and more recently as a problem for panpsychists (under the heading of ‘the palette
problem’). The challenge posed to panpsychists by this discrepancy is to make sense of how a
relatively small ‘palette’ of basic qualities could give rise to the bewildering diversity of qualities
we, and presumably other creatures, experience. I argue that panpsychists can meet this challenge,
though it requires taking contentious stands on certain phenomenological questions, in particular
on whether any familiar qualities are actual examples of ‘phenomenal blending’, and whether
any other familiar qualities have a positive ‘phenomenologically simple character’. Moreover, it
requires accepting an eventual theory most elements of which are in a certain explicable sense
unimaginable, though not for that reason inconceivable. Nevertheless, I conclude that there are
no conclusive reasons to reject such a theory, and so philosophers whose prior commitments
motivate them to adopt it can do so without major theoretical cost.
Keywords philosophy of mind; consciousness; phenomenal qualities; composition;
panpsychism; metaphysics; identity theory
DOI:10.1002/tht3.113
1 The palette problem
Consider the following passage from Michael Lockwood:
There is nothing qualitatively distinctive about a neuron in the auditory cortex, or
the corresponding action potential, to mark it out from a neuron, or the firing of a
neuron, in the visual cortex. So how, on this basis, is one to account, say, for the
fundamental phenomenological difference between a sound and a flash? ...It
seems inconceivable in much the same way, and for much the same reasons, that it
is inconceivable that an artist, however skilled, should conjure the simulacrum of a
Turner sunset from a palette containing only black and white paints.(1992, p. 546)
This passage presents a concern that the structural features of the mind and of
the brain are incompatible: one qualitatively rich, one qualitatively sparse. This is one
Correspondence to: E-mail: luke.roelofs@utoronto.ca
Thought 3(2014) 59– 70 ©2014 Wiley Periodicals, Inc and the Northern Institute of Philosophy 59
Luke Roelofs Phenomenal Blending and the Palette Problem
aspect of a broader discussion Lockwood gives about such structural discrepancies, but
in this paper I am specifically concerned with this problem, which I follow Chalmers
(Forthcoming) in calling ‘the palette problem’.
Who is this a problem for? Lockwood raises it as a problem for mindbrain identity
theories in general, both reductive and non-reductive, which are prima facie committed
to a structural isomorphism between mind and brain. There are various ways for a
defender of such a view to defuse the problem by arguing that we should not expect this
isomorphismfor instance, if strong emergentism is true, then it is only to be expected
that the structure of emergent mentality differs from that of the underlying brain, and
if reductive representationalism is true, the apparent discrepancy might be explained as
arising from a lack of isomorphism between content and vehicle. But in this paper I
am interested in the prospects for views which maintain this isomorphism, and so must
confront the palette problem (cf. Maxwell 1978, Stoljar 2001).
In particular, the palette problem has resurfaced recently in debates over
panpsychism, the view that all of reality has a mental nature, and more precisely
over ‘constitutive panpsychism’, the view that human mentality is constituted by the
mentality of our myriad physical parts. Critics have claimed that lots of micro-minds
are just as unable to explain a single unified mind as the non-mental would be: this has
come to be called ‘the combination problem’, and the palette problem is one strand
of this.1In general, we may say that the palette problem faces views on which the
physical and mental aspects of reality systematically mirror each other, point for point
and part-whole-relation for part-whole-relation.
2 The small-palette hypothesis
Chalmers distinguishes ‘small palette’ and ‘large palette’ approaches to the problem:
small-palette approaches claim ‘‘that all macroqualities can be generated from just a few
microqualities, if we find the right underlying microqualities’’, while on large-palette
approaches, we ‘‘suggest instead that the full range of macroqualities are included
among the microqualities ... [including] colors, sounds, smells, tastes, and so on’’
(Forthcoming, p. 26).
Small-palette approaches, but not large-palette approaches, imply ‘phenomenal
blending’, defined as the instantiation of one phenomenal quality by a subject, as
an automatic consequence of their instantiating two (or more) distinct phenomenal
qualities suitably related.
Call the latter qualities the ‘ingredients’, and the former the ‘resultant’. Their relation is
synchronic, and the ingredients are meant to persist, not to ‘vanish’ into the resultant so as
to no longer be instantiated. But nor is the resultant ‘mere appearance’: within experience,
reality and appearance cannot come apart. This definition is deliberately strongthe
ingredients and the resultant are all really there, being genuinely experienced, even though
experiencing the resultant is simply experiencing all the ingredients rightly related.
When I say that the subject ‘automatically’ instantiates the resultant, I mean with
something stronger than nomological necessity. The link between ingredients and
60 Thought 3(2014) 59– 70 ©2014 Wiley Periodicals, Inc and the Northern Institute of Philosophy
Luke Roelofs Phenomenal Blending and the Palette Problem
resultant must be a transparent one, making the resultant intelligible as ‘nothing over
and above’ the ingredients, with no ‘explanatory gap’ between the ingredients and the
resultant.
To elaborate on the small-palette approach, we can formulate a ‘small-palette
hypothesis’2:
There are a small number of basic qualities, which the simplest conscious parts of
the brain support experience of; larger more complex brain parts support
experience of the resultants of blending these. For each determinate sort of brain
part, up to and including the whole brain, its structure determines a subset of
phenomenal qualities out of all the possible combinations that its components’
could blend into: e.g. the brain’s structure dictates that we can experience redness
and whiteness in the right relation to blend, via the visual field, but cannot
experience loudness and whiteness ‘together’ like that.
This leaves unspecified what the right relation for blending is; the crucial point is
just that the diversity arises from the structure in which basic elements exist, not from a
diversity of basic elements. My final section suggests one way of specifying the relation.
Large-palette solutions avoid the need for phenomenal blending, but at the cost of a
bloated ontology with hundreds of fundamental phenomenal properties3; by contrast,
small-palette approaches give us exactly what parsimony demands: a small set of basic
elements generating a vast diversity of observed forms. Moreover, only small-palette
approaches are compatible with ‘Russellian’ approaches to the problem of mental
causation, given the plausible premise that the fundamental physical causal powers are
few in number (corresponding to the small number of fundamental properties that
physics seems to describe). On the Russellian approach, physical properties are analyzed
as complex dispositional roles, for which phenomenal or proto-phenomenal properties
provide the intrinsic/categorical basis.
Since I am attracted to Russellianism, and to the ideal of parsimony, I am (like
Chalmers) very attracted to the small-palette hypothesis. This faces three potential
objections:
Phenomenal qualities cannot be blended at all (i.e., that the ‘palette’ metaphor is
misleading from the beginning);
Even if some can, many others are knowably basic and unblended;
Even if all our qualities might be blended, there is no suitable set of basic qualities
which all can be blended out of.
Section 3 adduces plausible examples of phenomenal blending in familiar experience,
and Section 4 argues that we have no good reason to limit the possibility to only some
qualities. Section 5 considers and rejects an argument against the possibility of blending.
Section 6 argues that if it blending is possible, we have no good reason to rule out the
systematic and ubiquitous blending involved in the small-palette hypothesis. Finally,
Section 7 discusses a possible specification of the hypothesis. My conclusion is not that
Thought 3(2014) 59– 70 ©2014 Wiley Periodicals, Inc and the Northern Institute of Philosophy 61
Luke Roelofs Phenomenal Blending and the Palette Problem
the small-palette hypothesis is true, but that if one’s background theory motivates it,
then there is no theoretical obstacle to endorsing it.
3 Actual examples of phenomenal blending?
To determine whether phenomenal blending is possible, we should first ask if we know of
some actual cases, where we sometimes experience the ingredients on their own, and can
see that their nature suffices to explain that of the blends we also sometimes experience.
I think a number of examples invite that analysis.
The set of examples most often appealed to is colors. Lewtas suggests that orange
experiences result from blending red-experiences with yellow-experiences (Forthcoming,
p. 54); in a similar vein Chalmers writes that ‘‘If the same entity simultaneously is aware
of a degree of redness and aware of a degree of whiteness (at the same location), it is
plausibly aware of pinkness (at that location).’’(Forthcoming, p. 26). This accords with
the historical popularity of what Mizrahi 2009 calls a ‘‘‘phenomenalist’ view of colour
composition’’ (p. 2), on which ‘binary’ colors like orange and pink appear different to
us from ‘unitary’ colors like red and blue.
Another candidate is flavorsthe flavor of a given food or drink being a blend of
tastes and aromas provided by its ingredients. But here we must be careful. Psychologists,
following McBurney 1986, have distinguished two ways for sensations to combine:
synthesis, when ‘‘when two stimuli that have been mixed in a solution lose their
individual qualities in order to form a new (third) sensation’’ (Auvray and Spence 2008),
and fusion, when ‘‘sensations combined to form a single percept [which] ... remains
analyzable into its constituent elements even when otherwise perceived as a whole.’’
(Prescott 2012).
Since this distinction is usually phrased in terms of combination of stimuli, and since
the authors generally do not take themselves to be committing to any particular view
on the metaphysics of phenomenal qualities, I will not employ this terminology directly,
but will instead distinguish two forms of blending: the stronger form is ‘seamless’, so
that the ingredients cannot be individually attended or otherwise ‘picked out’, while the
weaker form is ‘discernible’, where the ingredients are not individually salient but can
be picked out with sufficient effort and training.
The small-palette hypothesis concerns seamless blending, and so flavor perception
is not a directly supporting example since it is usually described as a case of fusion,
where the flavor ‘‘ha[s] a curiously unitary character ... [but] by directing the attention,
in the light of past experience, first to one and then to another aspect of the given
whole ... we can distinguish the separate components’’(Tichener 1909, §34). Thus
even if flavor perception involves phenomenal blending, it is ‘discernible’ blending, not
‘seamless’ blending. But those cases which psychologists tend to describe as cases of
‘synthesis’, like the combination of colors and odors, are plausible candidates for seamless
blending.
For an example of blending across modalities, we might consider the two components
of pain which neuropsychology has shown to be dissociablethe affective-motivational
62 Thought 3(2014) 59– 70 ©2014 Wiley Periodicals, Inc and the Northern Institute of Philosophy
Luke Roelofs Phenomenal Blending and the Palette Problem
(which makes pain feel bad) and the sensory-discriminative (which lets us distinguish
pain from other bad feelings, and assign it a definite cause and location).4An affect and
a sensation are of distinct sorts, but blend so seamlessly into familiar pain that we find it
hard to imagine them in isolation, and are surprised when we hear of subjects with one
but not the other.
There may well be more examples, but these are enough to make the case; if they do
not, it is unlikely that more would.
4 Phenomenologically simple character
Maybe some qualities can be the resultants of blends, but only because they displayed
a ‘phenomenologically composite’ character all along. Other qualities display a
‘phenomenologically simple’ character, and cannot be blendsfor instance, maybe
pink is visibly a mixture of white and red, but white and red are both positively
experienced as simple, and hence cannot conceivably arise through blending.
I cannot directly refute this claim, but I think it is at least as plausible that
‘phenomenologically simple’ character is simply our having no idea of, or a confused
idea of, the ingredients in a blend. Often a quality initially seems simple and
unanalysable —until further experience lets us discern the components within it. Dennett
describes an auditory example of this phenomenon, in which the sound of a chord played
on a guitar appears simple and pure to the untrained ear, but comes to seem composed
of distinct notes when one is familiar enough with the notes individually to recognize
them in the mixture (1991, pp. 7374). In a similar vein, wine tasters often say that
with practice, one learns to discriminate the different components of a wine’s taste. And
of course the above example of pain is also pertinent. And research showing that, e.g.,
untrained subjects frequently construe certain odors as increasing the sweetness of a
taste, while trained subjects do not (Bingham et al. 1990), reinforces the point that we
are often fallible in distinguishing different sensations.
Perhaps in all these cases, there was no real ‘phenomenologically simple’ character
to begin with; but then how sure can we be that there is such a character in the case
of, say, redness? It seems to me equally reasonable to think that all qualities seem
phenomenologically simple until we can discern their ingredientsso that the apparent
simplicity of a given quality does not warrant us in denying that it has ingredients.
5Aprioriarguments against blending
It is sometimes claimed that blending can be conclusively ruled out a priori.Hereisa
representative passage from James:
‘‘I find in my students an almost irresistible tendency to think that we can
immediately perceive that feelings do combine. ‘‘What!’’ they say, ‘‘is not the taste of
lemonade compounded of that of lemon plus that of sugar?’’ This is taking the
combining of objects for that of feelings. The physical lemonade contains both the
Thought 3(2014) 59– 70 ©2014 Wiley Periodicals, Inc and the Northern Institute of Philosophy 63
Luke Roelofs Phenomenal Blending and the Palette Problem
lemon and the sugar, but its taste does not contain their tastes, for if there are any
two things which are certainly not present in the taste of lemonade, those are the
lemon-sour on the one hand and the sugar-sweet on the other. These tastes are
absent utterly.’’(1890, p. 158)
What is James’s reasoning here? If he is simply asserting that blending never happens,
that should not convince us. Perhaps he is relying on his general compositional nihilism,
on which phenomenal qualities don’t combine because nothing does. But then it should
not convince us if we are unconvinced by that general view about composition.
Thirdly, James might be saying that because the sourness of lemon is subtly
intrinsically changed by being mixed with the sweetness of sugar, it is not present in the
complex. In most contexts this would be fallacious, since part-whole relations typically
involve the parts affecting each other. But there may be a special reason for objecting
to such mutual adjustment in the phenomenal case, a reason articulated and attributed
to James in a recent paper by Pierfrancesco Basile.5Since how a quality is experienced
is essential to it, if it is experienced differently in different contexts, it is numerically
distinct in those different contexts. Hence though parts are often changed by being in a
certain whole, phenomenal qualities cannot be, because any phenomenal change makes
them a different quality.
If we grant this argument from phenomenal essentialism, and suppose that in tasting
lemonade the sweetness and sourness are phenomenally altered in some subtle fashion,
then the taste of lemonade cannot be a blend of the very same qualities as are experienced
in other circumstances. But the taste of lemonade may still be a blend; its ingredients
may be the subtly-different ‘counterparts’ of the sweetness and sourness experienced
in other circumstances.6No plausible holistic view can deny that we often experience
phenomenal qualities, in different contexts, which are at least similar enough to warrant
us calling them ‘the same’. And this same near-identity can be used to make sense of what
James’s students thought: that ‘the same’ qualities are present in the lemonade-blend
and in isolated experiences. Thus even if this argument succeeds, it merely constraints
which blending claims we can make, without ruling out blending in general.
A final reading is that James offers the following argument:
(a) I am not experiencing the sourness of lemon
(b) Therefore, the sourness of lemon is absent from my experience
Hence blending is incoherent, simply because what it is like to experience the whole
(the taste of lemonade) is not the same as what it is like to experience a part (sourness).
I believe this argument equivocates between two senses of ‘is experiencing the
sourness of lemon’. On the first reading, this means ‘has an experience of lemony-
sourness as their sole taste experience’, while on the second, it means ‘has a taste
experience of lemony-sourness, perhaps among others’. Compare two readings of ‘‘fills
this cup’’, either as ‘‘fills this cup exactly’’ (which tells us the thing’s volume) or as ‘‘fills
this cup and possibly more’’ (which tells us only a lower bound on its volume).
64 Thought 3(2014) 59– 70 ©2014 Wiley Periodicals, Inc and the Northern Institute of Philosophy
Luke Roelofs Phenomenal Blending and the Palette Problem
In the first sense of ‘experiencing the sourness of lemon’, claim ais true, but does
not imply claim b. In the second sense, claim ais question-begging, for if the taste of
lemonade is a blend then the subject is experiencing lemony-sourness (blended with
something else). Hence there is no sound argument from ato b.7
I see no compelling reason to think blending impossible. That does not mean that
blending is possible (or actual): one might insist while the lemonade-experiences arise
from the cooccurrence of the processes that independently produce sweet-experiences
and sour-experiences, they are not literally composed of those two. Sweet-experience,
sour-experience, and lemonade-experience might be mutually irreducible. But while
I cannot demonstrate that these examples either do or do not involve phenomenal
blending, it is enough that it be epistemically possible that phenomenal blending is
metaphysically possible.
6 From limited blending to ubiquitous blending
There remains only the problem that there do not appear to be any known qualities
that could plausibly serve as ingredients for all our qualities in the way that, say, redness
and whiteness serve as ingredients for pinkness. McGinn expresses this concern when he
writes that:
We cannot [ ...] envisage a small number of experiential primitives yielding a rich
variety of phenomenologies ... [for] you cannot derive one sort of experience form
another: you cannot get pains from experiences of colours, or emotions from
thoughts, or thoughts from acts of will. (McGinn 2006, p. 96)
McGinn is right that we cannot reasonably hope to get all qualities from any small set
of known qualities, but the defender of blending need not think that the basic ingredients
are known to us. Instead, the basic ingredients may be ‘alien’, unimaginable but not
inconceivable. It is commonplace that there are such qualities: just as a human born
anosmic cannot imagine olfactory qualities, we are all similarly limited regarding the
qualities of the many sensory modalities that humans lack. We can accept the existence
of such qualities, but we cannot ‘know what they are like’.
Presumably, if familiar qualities can blend, so can alien ones. But can they blend
into familiar qualities? For instance, might the familiar phenomenal quality of redness
be a blend of two alien phenomenal qualities (call them AQ1 and AQ2)? If so, maybe
all our phenomenal qualities result from blending, even when we cannot identify their
ingredients.
However, AQ1 and AQ2 cannot be unimaginable in exactly the same way as
standard examples, involving, say, tetrachromatic vision, or bat sonar. Our inability to
imagine the latter corresponds to our inability to experience them. We lack something,
phenomenologically speaking. But we do experience AQ1 and AQ2, whenever we have
experiences of red: we lack nothing. How, then, can they be unimaginable?
In one sense, we can imagine AQ1 and AQ2, just by imagining redness. But when
we do so, we cannot separate AQ1 from AQ2. They are imaginable together, but not
Thought 3(2014) 59– 70 ©2014 Wiley Periodicals, Inc and the Northern Institute of Philosophy 65
Luke Roelofs Phenomenal Blending and the Palette Problem
distinctly imaginable. We do not know what they feel like on their ownnot because
we lack necessary resources, but because we cannot deploy one resource without also
deploying another. Call this ‘unimaginability by surplus’; it contrasts with the standard
examples of ‘unimaginability by lack’.
For a more mundane example of unimaginability by surplus, consider an
arachnophobe trying to imagine how their friend, who finds large furry spider adorable,
perceives a tarantula. This imaginative task may be impossible for them, but not because
they lack anything. They can imagine spiders, they can imagine finding something cute,
and they can connect these imaginings together. The problem is that they cannot generate
an image of a spider without also generating a feeling of intense fear and revulsion, which
would constitute failure to imagine their friend’s experience.8
Even accepting the possibility of both phenomenal blending and unimaginability
by surplus, it may still seem that the different qualities we experience are too radically
heterogeneous to be blends of the same ingredients.9But our ability to recognize two
things as akin to one another often depends on our ability to recognize and attend to the
features they share, and if we cannot pick out their shared features we may wrongly feel
that they are entirely unlike; musical and taste training provide many examples. Hence
if we cannot distinctly experience the basic ingredients, we may consequently be unable
to recognize or attend to them, and thus get a false impression of radical heterogeneity.
Inability to pick out shared features does not always stop us registering similarities.
Sometimes we feel that two things ‘seem alike’ in some way, without being able to say how;
whether a particular shared feature generates such an intuition may depend on subtle
details of our information processing. And this kind of inarticulate resemblance is very
commonly encountered among experiential qualities: we frequently describe qualities
of one modality using terms drawn from another (warm, harsh, sweet, soft, loud, etc.),
or use sensory terminology to describe emotional or cognitive phenomenology. The
defender of the small-palette hypothesis can say that the resemblances among qualities
fall into three types: those we can articulate by identifying the common element (e.g.,
the negative valence in a pain and an itch, or the redness in orange and purple), those
we cannot articulate but nevertheless vaguely intuit (e.g., between redness and warmth),
and those we do not register as similarities at all because we cannot imagine the shared
ingredients distinctly.10
I conclude that there remains no principled objection to the small-palette
hypothesis.11
7 What is the right relation?
The small-palette hypothesis mentions ‘the right relation to blend’; while defending
the hypothesis does not required specifying this relation, such an absence makes it less
satisfying, so I will briefly suggest a candidate specification. First note that phenomenal
unity definitely seems like a pre-requisite; it would be hard to experience two qualities as
a single quality, if they were not ‘experienced together’. But clearly more is required.
66 Thought 3(2014) 59– 70 ©2014 Wiley Periodicals, Inc and the Northern Institute of Philosophy
Luke Roelofs Phenomenal Blending and the Palette Problem
Consider colors. If redness and whiteness are experienced at two different points
in the visual field, there is no experience of pinkness. To blend they must stand
in the relation ‘experienced-in-the-same-location-as’. We might try to generalize this
relation beyond the visual case, by saying that blending occurs when the same object
is being representedthe same part of the visual field, the same point on the skin’s
surface, etc.
Blending also seems to occur in those aspects of experience which do not distinguish
multiple objects: sense-modalities like smell which encode very little spatial information,
and affective phenomena like mood. It seems characteristic of odors and moods to merge
and interpenetrate rather than being compartmentalized. In fact, this follows from the
definition of ‘seamless’ blending: if we experienced the qualities as qualifying different
objects, we could distinguish them by focusing on one object or the other.
Thus I would suggest that blending is the default: it occurs whenever two qualities
are unified, but not positively separable. What is hard is not to blend two qualities
but to simultaneously instantiate them without them blending: this requires the mental
infrastructure to ascribe the qualities to specific objects, and then distinguish those
objects.
To provide a non-representational characterization, we might speak of causal
‘quarantining’ processes to prevent two mental elements from interacting as fully as
they might, as is often thought to occur when we imagine another person’s mental
state without allowing it to infect, or be infected by, our own mental state.12 Structures
like the visual field might be partly constituted by systematic relations of mutual
quarantining.
Call this the ‘Blending-As-Default’ extension of the small-palette hypothesis. It claims
that the negative part of the definition of seamless blending (inability to distinguish),
together with phenomenal unity, is sufficient for the positive phenomenology of two
qualities forming a third. It need not be adopted, but it has some plausibility, and is
attractively straightforward.
8 Conclusions
Once we recognize that the basic shades on our palette need not be (distinctly) imaginable
by us, and see that James’s argument against phenomenal blending is either fallacious
or does not preclude blending in general, small-palette solutions to the palette problem
become perfectly reasonable options. There may be other reasons to reject panpsychism
or other forms of identity theory, but this particular one should not move us.
Acknowledgements
Aaron Henry, Mark Fortney, an audience at the APA central division meeting 2014, and
an anonymous referee for Thought all have my gratitude for their feedback on various
drafts of this paper.
Thought 3(2014) 59– 70 ©2014 Wiley Periodicals, Inc and the Northern Institute of Philosophy 67
Luke Roelofs Phenomenal Blending and the Palette Problem
Notes
1 For discussion of the palette problem (also sometimes referred to as the blending problem or
the derivation problem), see Chalmers 1996, p. 306, Chalmers Forthcoming, Goff 2006, p. 57,
Coleman 2012, p. 144 and Forthcoming pp. 40–51, Alter and Nagasawa 2012, p. 5, Dainton
2011, p. 246, Lewtas Forthcoming, pp. 54–55.
2 For examples of philosophers endorsing something like what I call the small-palette
hypothesis, see Peirce 1998, pp. 35–36 and Spencer 1899, §60, inter alia.
3 How objectionable this ‘bloating’ is may depend on whether it is seen as a matter of
quantitative parsimony (number of existents) or qualitative parsimony (number of basic
types). Basic phenomenal qualities are mutually irreducible properties (and thus
multiply-instantiable universals, rather than particulars), but might be thought sufficiently
akin to one another that they form a single basic type. In the latter case they would offend
only against quantitative parsimony, which many consider less important.
4 Schilder and Stengel 1931, Ploner et al. 1999, Grahek 2007.
5 Basile’s central concern is whether it is coherent for a single quality to be experienced
simultaneously by two different subjects, one a part of the other. I address this question
directly in other work, but it is separate from the question of blending, which involves only a
single subject.
6 Does this threaten mind-brain isomorphism? No, if these changes to phenomenal character
mirror the physical changes one neurone causes electrically in another. Is it problematic that
this replaces one quality with another, but does not replace a neurone with another? No;
isomorphism demands merely that some fine-grained physical property or event be replaced
with another.
7 Similar remarks apply to the apparent truism that nothing can display two colors at once to
the same observer—nothing could both look red and look white at once. In one sense of
‘look red’ and ‘look white’, nothing can do both, but this is because to ‘look red’ in this sense
definitionally precludes displaying any other visual qualities. But in another sense, looking
both red and white might just be ‘looking pink’. Pink things look red, but unlike the things
we tend to call ‘red-looking’ (in the holistic sense), they also look white.
8 The arachnophobe’s imaginative inability is ‘shallow’, i.e., the right sequence of experiences
could let them imagine a spider without feeling fear. By contrast, alien qualities are ‘robustly’
unimaginable: only a profound transformation, possibly requiring gross physiological
reorganization, would let human distinctly imagine AQ1 or AQ2.
9 I thank an anonymous referee for pressing me on this point.
10 For an extensive discussion of the kinships we can recognize between qualities in different
modalities, see Coleman Forthcoming, pp. 43–47, drawing on Hartshorne 1934, pp. 35ff. Cf.
Pierce 1998, p. 35.
11 Is this hypothesis now objectionably ‘mysterious’, in postulating that the qualities we can
(distinctly) imagine are minority of the experiences we actually have? Certainly, without
further detail it is less an explanatory achievement than a postulate that things are in principle
explainable. But it is acceptable for a theory of consciousness to postulate many unimaginable
things. Inconceivable postulates are objectionable, since they undermine the theory as an idea.
But unimaginable postulates only undermine the theory as an image, and theories need not
be images. Those who accept the irreducibility of subjective experience to the objective and
public should already be committed to a vast range of unimaginable experiences.
12 Cf. Goldman 2008, Gallese et al. 2004.
68 Thought 3(2014) 59– 70 ©2014 Wiley Periodicals, Inc and the Northern Institute of Philosophy
Luke Roelofs Phenomenal Blending and the Palette Problem
References
Alter, T. and Y. Nagasawa. ‘‘What is Russellian Monism?’’ Journal of Consciousness Studies 19
(2012): 67–95.
Auvray, M. and C. Spence. ‘‘The Multisensory Perception of Flavour.’’ Consciousness and
Cognition V17 (2008): 1016–31.
Basile, P. ‘‘It Must be True – But How Can it Be? Some Remarks on Panpsychism and Mental
Composition.’’ Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 67 (2010): 93 –112.
Bingham, A., G. Birch, C. De Graaf, J. Behan, and K. Perring. ‘‘Sensory Studies with Sucrose-Maltol
Mixtures.’’ Chemical Senses V15.4 (1990): 447–56.
Chalmers, D. The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory.NewYork:Oxford
University Press, 1996.
Chalmers, D. (Forthcoming). ‘‘The Combination Problem for Panpsychism.’’ URL: http://consc.
net/papers/combination.pdf (accessed April 2013)
Coleman, S. ‘‘Mental Chemistry: Combination for Panpsychists.’’ Dialectica V66.1 (2012):
137–66.
Coleman, S. ‘‘Neuro-Cosmology,’’ in Perception and Sensory Consciousness: The Nature of
Phenomenal Qualities, edited by P. Coates & S. Coleman. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, Forthcoming. URL: http://www.academia.edu/4901338/Neuro-Cosmology (accessed
November 2013)
Dainton, B. ‘‘Review of Consciousness and Its Place in Nature.’’ Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research V83.1 (2011): 238–261.
Dennett, D. Consciousness Explained. xxx: Penguin Press, 1991.
Gallese, V., C. Keysers, and G. Rizzolatti. ‘‘A Unifying View of the Basis of Social Cognition.’’
Trends in Cognitive Sciences 8.9 (2004): 396–403.
Goff, P. ‘‘Experiences Don’t Sum.’’ Journal of Consciousness Studies 13.10– 11 (2006): 53– 61.
Goldman, A. Simulating Minds. xxx: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Grahek, N. Feeling Pain and Being in Pain. 2nd ed. xxx: MIT Press, 2007.
Hartshorne, C. The Philosophy and Psychology of Sensation. xxx: Chicago University Press, 1934.
James, W. The Principles of Psychology. xxx: Harvard University Press, 1890.
Lewtas, P. ‘‘What Is It Like to be a Quark?’’ Journal of Consciousness Studies V20.9 (Forthcoming):
39–64.
Lockwood, M. ‘‘The Grain Problem,’’ in Objections to Physicalism, edited by H. Robinson. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1992.
Maxwell, G. ‘‘Rigid Designators and Mind-Brain Identity,’’ in Perception and Cognition. Minnesota
Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 9, edited by C. Savage. Minneapolis, MN: Minnesota
University Press, 1978.
McBurney, D. H. ‘‘Taste, Smell, and Flavor Terminology: Taking the Confusion Out of Fusion,’’
in Clinical Measurement of Taste and Smell, edited by H. L. Meiselman and R. S. Rivkin. New
York, NY: Macmillan, 1986, 117–25.
McGinn, C. ‘‘Hard Questions,’’ in Consciousness and Its Place in Nature: Does Physicalism Entail
Panpsychism?, edited by A. Freeman. Exeter/Charlottesville: Imprint Academic, 2006.
Mizrahi, V. ‘‘Is Colour Composition Phenomenal?,’’ in Color Perception: Physiology, Processes and
Analysis, edited by D. Skusevich and P. Matikas. xxx: Nova Science Publishers, 2009, 185–202.
Peirce, C. S. ‘‘The Law of Thought,’’ in Philosophers of Process, edited by D. Browning and W.
Myers. xxx: Fordham University Press, 1998.
Thought 3(2014) 59– 70 ©2014 Wiley Periodicals, Inc and the Northern Institute of Philosophy 69
Luke Roelofs Phenomenal Blending and the Palette Problem
Ploner, M., H. J. Freund, and A. Schnitzler. ‘‘Pain Affect without Pain Sensation in a Patient with
a Postcentral Lesion.’’ Pain 81 (1999): 211–14.
Prescott, J. ‘‘Multimodal Chemosensory Interactions and Perception of Flavour,’’ in The Neural
Bases of Multisensory Processes, edited by M. M. Murray and M. T. Wallace. Boca Raton, FL:
CRC Press, 2012.
Schilder, P. and E. Stengel. ‘‘Asymbolia for Pain.’’ Archives of Neurology & Psychiatry 25.3 (1931):
598–600.
Spencer, H. Principles of Psychology. xxx: D. Appleton, 1899.
Stoljar, D. ‘‘Two Conceptions of the Physical.’’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research V61.2
(2001): 253–81.
Tichener, E. B. A Textbook of Psychology. New York, NY: Macmillan, 1909. URL: http://archive.
org/stream/textbookofpsycho00edwa/textbookofpsycho00edwa_djvu.txt (accessed August 26
2013).
70 Thought 3(2014) 59– 70 ©2014 Wiley Periodicals, Inc and the Northern Institute of Philosophy
... However, even if we grant that this explanation demonstrates what may occur for many things that we experience (e.g., our phenomenology of colors), the appeal to phenomenal 32 See e.g., Roelofs [2014Roelofs [ , 2019. 33 By 'phenomenology of temporal experience' I am not concerned with our consciousness of time. ...
Article
Full-text available
This paper argues for the claim that the mental ontology required for what has been called the “Phenomenal Intentionality Theory” (PIT) should be understood in terms of mental events or episodes, not mental states that instantiate phenomenal properties because the former but not the latter has a kind of temporal shape. I begin by laying out the basic commitments of PIT. I then introduce the notion of “temporal shape” and defend the following simple but powerful argument: (1) If conscious experiences are phenomenal mental states that instantiate phenomenal properties, then the phenomenal character of these experiences will lack a temporal shape. (2) The phenomenal character of conscious experience typically has a temporal shape. (3) Therefore, conscious experiences are not mental states that instantiate phenomenal properties.
... Others went in the completely opposite direction. Roelofs (2014) argues that there is nothing problematic with the notion of a very small number of basic qualities, while Turausky (manuscript) makes the claim that there might be only one basic phenomenal quality that can account for human-level consciousness. I will not go into further detail since I only want to make the point that monadic panpsychism does not need to accept any special view of fundamental qualities or causality in order to avoid the palette problem, while also avoiding the subject-summing version of the combination problem. ...
Thesis
Full-text available
Panpsychism, the view that consciousness is present everywhere at the fundamental level of reality, has established itself as an increasingly popular option in the philosophy of mind. Situated between substance dualism and reductive physicalism, panpsychism aims to capture the intuitions behind both, integrating consciousness into the physical world without explaining it in terms of purely physical facts. In this thesis, I offer a defence of panpsychism. First, I examine influential arguments against physicalism, such as Thomas Nagel’s (1974, 1979) perspective-based proposal, Frank Jackson’s (1982) knowledge argument, David Chalmers’ (1996, 2010) conceivability argument, as well as vagueness arguments (Antony 2006a; Tye 1996). I argue that none of them offers a knockdown case against physicalism, particularly because of the threat presented by the phenomenal concept strategy (Chalmers 2007; Papineau 2007a), though they suggest panpsychism as a promising alternative that avoids many common objections. Second, I discuss independent arguments for panpsychism, including the Russellian monist view (Goff 2017; Russell 1927/1992), the intrinsic nature argument (Seager 2006; Strawson 2006), recent developments in the literature as presented by Hedda Hassel Mørch (2018, 2020) and Luca Dondoni (2022), Tye’s (2021b) representational panpsychism based on the vagueness argument, as well as cosmopsychism (Nagasawa & Wager 2016; Shani 2015) – an alternative to panpsychism that shares its aims whilst claiming to avoid its shortcomings. Third, I address the most pressing objection to panpsychism: the combination problem or the question of how fundamental consciousness can combine to lead to complex consciousness (James 1890). Focusing especially on the subject-summing version of the combination problem or the issue of how small subjects can combine to form complex subjects, I go over various proposals for either solving or avoiding it, such as Philip Goff’s (2016) phenomenal bonding relation and William Seager’s (2010) combinatorial infusion proposal, arguing against both and agreeing at the end with Sam Coleman (2014), who advocates that subject-summing is demonstrably incoherent. However, as I argue in the fourth and final chapter, the panpsychist still has an option that avoids the subject-summing problem, while also circumventing the objections faced by the alternative view of cosmopsychism. Inspired though not reliant on the philosophy of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1902/2005), I introduce what I call monadic panpsychism, the view that the phenomenal character of any given consciousness-bearing physical ultimate is determined by its relations to other such ultimates featuring in the relevant causal structure. The theory consists of two key claims. The first is that phenomenal qualities are relational rather than intrinsic. This view has precedent in literature on the philosophy of mind, such as in Rudolf Carnap (1928), Gottlob Frege (1956), Moritz Schlick (1959), as well as more recently in David Hilbert and Mark Kalderon (2000) and Austen Clark (2000), though not in the context of panpsychism. The second claim is that physical ultimates only possess a very basic form of consciousness necessary for experiencing as such. There are many ways to conceptualise this basic consciousness: non-relational or intrinsic, rudimentary and non-specific, a point of view without experiences, the minimal subject, a mere conduit for experience, phenomenal space, etc. Russellian panpsychists offer a more detailed proposal in which every physical ultimate has an appropriate associated type of experience. For example, all quarks have the same quark-type of experience, assuming for the sake of discussion that quarks are ultimates. Still, arguing for a more minimal notion, as I do, requires making less claims and should not be controversial to any panpsychist. So, what follows from these two claims? I propose that the relational constitution of phenomenal qualities has its endpoint at the fundamental level rather than at the level of a combined complex or emergent subject. Put simply, physical ultimates guarantee the basic consciousness or the point of view that I occupy, while the relational structure constitutes my rich and full human experience. So to speak, relationally constituted phenomenal qualities ‘anchor’ themselves in physical ultimates. As long as these relations result in a phenomenally unified experience, which is an uncontroversial thesis, then no matter where that process reaches the end of its causal chain, it will necessarily be experienced from a subjective point of view. Since only qualities but not subjects need to combine, my proposal avoids the subject-summing version of the combination problem, which is arguably an insurmountable challenge to other forms of panpsychism. Because of this, I conclude that my theory contributes to the field, serving as a good starting point for further developments of neither combinatory nor emergent panpsychism with regard to subjects.
... Others went in the completely opposite direction. Roelofs (2014) argues that there is nothing problematic with the notion of a very small number of basic qualities, while Turausky (manuscript) makes the claim that there might only be one basic phenomenal quality that can account for human-level consciousness. I will not go into further detail since I only want to make the point that monadic panpsychism does not need to accept any special view of fundamental qualities or causality to avoid the palette problem, while also avoiding the subject-summing version of the combination problem. ...
Article
Full-text available
One of the main obstacles for panpsychism, the view that consciousness is fundamental and ubiquitous, is the difficulty of explaining how simple subjects could combine to form complex subjects. Known as the subject combination problem, it poses a possibly insurmountable challenge to the view. In this paper, I will assume that this challenge cannot be overcome and instead present a version of panpsychism that completely avoids talk of combination. Inspired by Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz’s metaphysics of monads, I will focus on a relational explanation of how simple subjects could constitute complex experiences, without them having to combine in virtue of their subjectivity. I call this view monadic panpsychism. Additionally, my proposal will not rely on emergence and so it will circumvent problems commonly faced by emergentist accounts. As I will argue, monadic panpsychism is preferable to combinatory and emergentist panpsychism because it faces a significantly less worrisome set of objections. Apart from being unaffected by the seemingly insuperable issue of subject combination, I will demonstrate that monadic panpsychism also has tools to address other kinds of the combination problem. That alone justifies the need for a new formulation of panpsychism, one which faces unique difficulties but also offers unique solutions.
... But even if we grant that this explanation demonstrates what may occur for many things that we experience (e.g., our phenomenology of colors), the appeal to phenomenal 15 See e.g., Roelofs (2014Roelofs ( , 2019. 16 It is worth mentioning here that by talking about our phenomenology of temporal experience I am not concerned with our consciousness of time. ...
Thesis
Full-text available
My dissertation puts forward a critique of the phenomenal intentionality theory (PIT). According to standard accounts of PIT, all genuine intentionality is either identical to or partly grounded in phenomenal consciousness. I argue that it is a conceptually significant mistake to construe conscious experiences in terms of token mental states that instantiate phenomenal properties. This mistake is predicated on ignoring an important difference in the temporal character—what I call the “temporal shape”—between states and properties as opposed to conscious experiences. States and properties lack a temporal shape, but conscious experience has a temporal shape. Thus, in order to adequately capture our phenomenology of temporality we need a mental ontology that adequately reflects this distinction. A second aim of this dissertation is to defend a mereological account of phenomenal intentionality, which says that phenomenality and intentionality are related by being proper parts of a first-personal, subjective, mental event. On this approach, the conditions of satisfaction for a subject’s first-personal, subjective, mental event just are the conditions of satisfaction for phenomenal intentionality. I explore the theoretical grounds for a mereological account of phenomenal intentionality and conclude that it does a better job of explaining difficult cases like the problem of unconscious thought (e.g., your belief that “grass is green”). Thus, we have prima facie support for a mereological account of phenomenal intentionality exactly where competing accounts fail.
... • Panpsiquismo constitutivo =df la conciencia de un sujeto de experiencia dependiente está fundada (grounded) en la experiencia de las entidades fundamentales microfísicas (Goff (2017), Roelofs (2014)). 4 • Panpsiquismo emergentista =df la conciencia de un sujeto de experiencia dependiente emerge (débilmente) de la actividad causal de la experiencia de las entidades fundamentales microfísicas (Mørch (2014), Seager (2010)). ...
Article
El principal problema del panpsiquismo es el problema de la combinación. Como solución se distinguen dos tipos de panpsiquismo: el panpsiquismo constitutivo y el panpsiquismo emergentista. Pero esta distinción opera sobre la distinción entre fundación y causalidad. Sin embargo, se verán razones para considerar que causalidad y fundación no son distintos. De modo que la distinción entre los anteriores panpsiquismos colapsa. Posibilitando la postulación de un nuevo tipo de panpsiquismo, el panpsiquismo de construcción. También, se trazará un primer esbozo de solución para el problema de la combinación desde el punto de vista del panpsiquismo de construcción.
... • Panpsiquismo constitutivo =df la conciencia de un sujeto de experiencia dependiente está fundada (grounded) en la experiencia de las entidades fundamentales microfísicas (Goff (2017), Roelofs (2014)). 4 • Panpsiquismo emergentista =df la conciencia de un sujeto de experiencia dependiente emerge (débilmente) de la actividad causal de la experiencia de las entidades fundamentales microfísicas (Mørch (2014), Seager (2010)). ...
Article
Full-text available
A la luz de la propuesta arendtiana de espacio público, en este artículo se analiza uno de los conceptos que más interés está despertando en el contexto de la llamada filosofía política continental: lo común. Desde una revisión comparada con la obra de C. Laval y P. Dardot enfrento los siguientes interrogantes: ¿Qué perspectivas abre la obra arendtiana en la actual reflexión sobre lo común como principio político articulador? ¿Qué nuevas cuestiones suscita la idea de espacio público como comunidad política de Arendt al confrontarla con la propuesta de lo común?
Book
Full-text available
Inclui estudos de Dena Shottenkirk (Brooklyn Colege, NY), Manuel Curado (Uminho) and Steven S. Gouveia (UMinho), “Introduction”, Davide Dalla Rosa (U. Padova) and Federico Sanguinetti (UFRGN Brasil), “Disjunctivism and the Internal: A Problem for McDowell’s Epistemological Disjunctivism?”; Manuel Curado (Uminho), “Xenophanes’ Figs and Honey: An Essay about a Program of Philosophy of Perception”; Steven S. Gouveia (UMinho) and Georg Northoff (U. Ottawa), “A Neurophilosophical Approach to Perception”; Benjamin D. Young (U. Nevada, USA) “Smelling Molecular Structure”; Anatoly Nichvoloda (Brooklyn College, USA), “‘Hierarchical Bokeh’ Theory of Attention”; Aili Bresnahan (U. Dayton, USA), “Perceiving Live Improvisation in the Performing Arts”; Bill Brewer (U. Oxford), “Consciousness and Content in Perception”; Susanna Schellenberg (Rutgers U., USA), “Perceptual Capacities”; Nicholas Georgalis (East Carolina U., USA), “Thinking Differently About Thought”; Angela Mendelovici (U. Western Ontario), “Immediate and Reflective Senses”; Tim Crane (CEU, Budapest), “The Unity of Unconsciousness”; Michelle Liu (U. Oxford), “Phenomenal Experience and the Thesis of Revelation”; Anya Farennikova (City Univ., New York, USA), “Would You Buy Absence Art?”; Jesse Prinz (City U. New York, USA), “Penetrating Beauty: Knowledge, Culture and Context in Aesthetic Perception”; Dena Shottenkirk (Brooklyn College, NY), “Gist Experience”; Romain Bigé (CNRS), “How Do I Know When I Am Dancing?”; Dena Shottenkirk (Brooklyn College, NY), “Interview with James Cohan”; and Steven S. Gouveia, “Interview with Leonel Moura”.
Article
Some have argued that panpsychism offers the most simple view of reality. The most prominent advocate of this argument is Philip Goff. In this paper, I examine Goff’s position and argue that considerations of simplicity and parsimony do not support panpsychism. Quite the reverse: they give us good reason to reject it.
Article
Full-text available
Russellian monism offers a distinctive perspective on the relationship between the physical and the phenomenal. For example, on one version of the view, phenomenal properties are the categorical bases of fundamental physical properties, such as mass and charge, which are dispositional. Russellian monism has prominent supporters, such as Bertrand Russell, Grover Maxwell, Michael Lockwood, and David Chalmers. But its strengths and shortcomings are often misunderstood. In this paper we try to eliminate confusions about the view and defend it from criticisms. We present its core and distinguish different versions of it. We then compare these versions with traditional theories, such as physicalism, dualism, and idealism. We also argue that the knowledge argument and the conceivability argument are consistent with Russellian monism and that existing arguments against the view, such as the argument from weirdness, are not decisive. We conclude that Russellian monism is an attractive view that deserves serious consideration.
Article
Full-text available
Colour composition divides colours into two types: unitary and binary colours. Colours which are not composed are said to be "unique" or "unitary" colours, whereas composed colours are always binary. Colour composition and the distinction between unitary and binary colours have played a major role in colour science and in the philosophy of colours. They have for example been invoked to introduce opponent-processes in the mechanisms underlying colour vision and have been used to criticize philosophers who defend a physicalist view on the nature of colours. Most philosophical or scientific theories suppose that colour composition judgments refer to the way colours appear to us. The dominant view is therefore phenomenalist in the sense that colour composition is phenomenally given to perceivers. This paper argues that there is no evidence for a phenomenalist view of colour composition and that a conventionalist approach should be favoured. We can express a lot of judgments about the colours we perceive. Most observers judge for example that red is more similar to orange than it is to blue; that no shade of yellow is a shade of blue; or that red and green, orange and blue, and yellow and purple are pairs of maximally dissimilar colours. All those judgments express colour structural relations, i.e. relations that colours bear to each other. Among colour structural relations, colour composition has received tremendous attention by philosophers and scientists from fields 1 Thanks to M. Nida-Rümelin, J. Suarez, Y. Jraissati and D. Gross for helpful comments and criticisms. This paper was written with the support of a grant from the SNF (Swiss National Science Foundation).
Book
An examination of the two most radical dissociation syndromes of the human pain experience—pain without painfulness and painfulness without pain—and what they reveal about the complex nature of pain and its sensory, cognitive, and behavioral components. In Feeling Pain and Being in Pain, Nikola Grahek examines two of the most radical dissociation syndromes to be found in human pain experience: pain without painfulness and painfulness without pain. Grahek shows that these two syndromes—the complete dissociation of the sensory dimension of pain from its affective, cognitive, and behavioral components, and its opposite, the dissociation of pain's affective components from its sensory-discriminative components (inconceivable to most of us but documented by ample clinical evidence)—have much to teach us about the true nature and structure of human pain experience. Grahek explains the crucial distinction betweenfeeling pain and being in pain, defending it on both conceptual and empirical grounds. He argues that the two dissociative syndromes reveal the complexity of the human pain experience: its major components, the role they play in overall pain experience, the way they work together, and the basic neural structures and mechanisms that subserve them. Feeling Pain and Being in Pain does not offer another philosophical theory of pain that conclusively supports or definitively refutes either subjectivist or objectivist assumptions in the philosophy of mind. Instead, Grahek calls for a less doctrinaire and more balanced approach to the study of mind–brain phenomena. Bradford Books imprint
Article
Eating and drinking are among life's most pleasurable activities and among the most multisensory as well. However, cognitive neuroscientists have only recently come to realise that their insights, derived from studies of the multisensory integration of auditory, visual and tactile stimuli, can be extended to help explain flavour perception. This approach is already starting to impact upon the design of foods, drinks and dining experiences in locations as diverse as the supermarket and Michelin-starred restaurants. Psychology and cognitive neuroscience can help create novel flavours, taste sensations and dining experiences that can more effectively stimulate the mind, and not just the mouth, of the consumer.
Article
The most plausible type of panpsychism explains high-level consciousness as a compound of basic conscious properties instantiated by basic bottom-level physical objects. Arguments for panpsychism stand little chance in the absence of an account that (1) makes sense of basic bottom-level experience; and (2) explains how basic bottom-level experiences yield high-level experiences. This paper tackles the first task. It develops a method for investigating basic bottom-level experience: it identifies constraints, motivated by scientific and philosophical considerations, that force a unique account. Then it applies this method, using quarks as stand-ins for basic but conscious physical objects. It concludes that quark-consciousness is (1) maximally simple (in ways explained); (2) multiple (the quark has multiple phenomenal fields each with a maximally simple experience and its own subject); and (3) internal (experience is a stable aspect of the quark's intrinsic nature, not a response to or representation of entities external to the quark)