ArticlePDF Available

Abstract and Figures

The idea of a moving present or `now' seems to form part of our most basic beliefs about reality. Such a present, however, is not reflected in any of our theories of the physical world. I show in this article that presentism, the doctrine that only what is present exists, is in conflict with modern relativistic cosmology and recent advances in neurosciences. I argue for a tenseless view of time, where what we call `the present' is just an emergent secondary quality arising from the interaction of perceiving self-conscious individuals with their environment. I maintain that there is no flow of time, but just an ordered system of events.
Content may be subject to copyright.
arXiv:1403.4671v1 [physics.hist-ph] 19 Mar 2014
Noname manuscript No.
(will be inserted by the editor)
Present time
Gustavo E. Romero
Received: date / Accepted: date
Abstract The idea of a moving present or ‘now’ seems to form part of our
most basic beliefs about reality. Such a present, however, is not reflected in any
of our theories of the physical world. I show in this article that presentism, the
doctrine that only what is present exists, is in conflict with modern relativistic
cosmology and recent advances in neurosciences. I argue for a tenseless view
of time, where what we call ‘the present’ is just an emergent secondary quality
arising from the interaction of perceiving self-conscious individuals with their
environment. I maintain that there is no flow of time, but just an ordered
system of events.
Keywords Ontology ·spacetime ·general relativity ·quantum mechanics
Again, the ‘now’ which seems to bound the past and the future –
does it always remain one and the same or is it always other and
other? It is hard to say.
Aristotle.
1 Introduction
Time has always puzzled philosophers and scientists alike. Traditionally, there
are two broad views about the nature of time. These views are usually called
the “tensed” and the “tenseless” views, or, for simplicity, the A and B the-
ories of time. For an A-oriented person, only present things exist. There are
Instituto Argentino de Radioastronom´ıa (IAR, CCT La Plata, CONICET)
C.C. No. 5, 1894, Villa Elisa, Buenos Aires, Argentina.
Tel.: +54-221-482-4903
Fax: +54-221-425-4909
E-mail: romero@iar-conicet.gov.ar
2 Gustavo E. Romero
many varieties of this ontological position: presentism, becoming theory, prim-
itive tenses, branching universe theory, and so on. All of them distinguish the
present in some way. In particular, presentism is the doctrine that it is always
the case that, for every x,xis present. The logical quantification in this defini-
tion is unrestricted, it ranges over all existents. In order to make this definition
meaningful, the presentist must provide a specification of the term “present”.
A standard definition is:
Present: The mereological sum of all objects with null temporal distance
(Crisp 2003).
Since the mereological sum of objects is always an object, we can infer that
for a presentist the present is an object, i.e. an individual with some properties.
The open formula ‘xis present’ in the definition above, then means ‘xis part
of the mereological sum of all objects with null temporal distance’. It also
purports that what there is exists only at an instant, not over a span of time.
A B-oriented person considers all this as pure nonsense. She maintains that
past, present and future ‘equally’ exist. For her, the fundamental temporal
properties are relations of ‘earlier than’, ‘later than’ and ‘simultaneous with’.
These are relations between events. There is no present in any absolute sense.
The present is not an object. Then, it cannot move, since only objects can
move with respect to each other. There is no ob jective ‘flow’ or passage of
time.
What is, then, the present in this view? My aim, in this article, is to answer
this question from a B-perspective.
2 Against Presentism
The Englishman John McTaggart Ellis McTaggart presented a disproof of pre-
sentism in his famous paper Unreality of Time (McTaggart 1908). He reasoned
as follows.
1. There is no time without change.
2. If time passes, events should change with respect to the properties of past-
ness, presentness, and futureness.
3. A given event, then, should be able to be in absolute sense, past, present
and future.
4. These properties exclude each other.
Then: Events do not pass, just are.
There is no passage of time. There is no moving present. The mere idea
of a flowing time simply does not make any sense. An additional problem is
that if time flows, it should move with respect to something. If we say that
there is a super-time with respect to which time flows, then we shall need a
super-super-time for this super-time, and we shall have an infinite regress. In
Present time 3
addition, there is no flow without a rate of flow. At what rate does time go by?
The answer 1 sec per sec is meaningless. It is like saying that a road extends
along a distance of one km per each km that it extends!
On the physical side, the theory of special relativity seems not to be
friendly to the idea of an absolute present, at least in its usual Minkowskian
4-dimensional interpretation. Special relativity is the theory of moving bod-
ies formulated by Albert Einstein in 1905 (Einstein 1905). It postulates the
Lorentz-invariance of all physical law statements that hold in a special type
of reference systems, called inertial frames. Hence the ‘restricted’ or ‘special’
character of the theory. The equations of Maxwell electrodynamics are Lorentz-
invariant, but those of classical mechanics are not. When classical mechanics
is revised to accommodate invariance under Lorentz transformations between
inertial reference frames, several modifications appear. The most notorious is
the impossibility of defining an absolute simultaneity relation between events.
Simultaneity results to be frame-dependent. Then, some events can be future
events in some reference system, and present or past in another system. Since
what exists cannot depend on the reference frame adopted for the description
of nature, it is concluded that past, present, and future events exist. Conse-
quently, presentism, the doctrine that only what is present exists, is false.
The presentist or A-theorist of time might find a way around this argument
adopting a different (purely Lorentzian) interpretation of the theory (Crisp
2008, Zimmerman 2011), which relinquishes the concept of space-time. The
problems of this approach have been discussed at length by Saunders (2002),
and I do not insist on the topic here. Instead, I prefer to say a few words about
the much less discussed issue of the compatibility of presentism with general
relativity.
General relativity is the theory of space, time and gravitation proposed
by Einstein in 1915 (Einstein 1915). Space-time is an indispensable ingredient
of this theory. A 4-dimensional real and differentiable manifold is adopted to
represent space-time, the physical aggregation of all events (Romero 2013). A
rank-2 metric field gab is defined over the manifold to represent the potentials
of the gravitational field. Distances over the manifold are given by
ds2=gabdxadxb,(1)
where dxais a 4-dimensional differential length vector. The key issue to de-
termine the geometric structure of space-time, and hence to specify the effects
of gravity, is to find the law that fixes the metric once the source of the grav-
itational field is given. The source of the gravitational field is matter. The
energy-momentum tensor Tab represents the physical properties of material
things that generate space-time. The curvature of space-time at any event is
related to the energy-momentum content at that event by a set of differential
equations.
These equations, the Einstein field equations, can be written in the simple
form:
Gab =8πG
c4Tab,(2)
4 Gustavo E. Romero
Fig. 1 A ‘presentist-friendly’ space-time: Evolving 3-dimensional space-like surfaces in a
space-time with a preferred time-direction.
where Gab is the so-called Einstein’s tensor, which is linear in the curvature1
and non-linear in the metric. It contains all the geometric information on space-
time. The constants Gand care the gravitational constant and the speed of
light in vacuum. Einstein’s field equations are a set of ten non-linear partial
differential equations for the metric coefficients.
A crucial point of general relativity is that the 4-dimensional space-time
with non-zero curvature is not dispensable anymore. Contrarily to the Minkowskian
case, general relativity is not susceptible of a global Lorentzian formulation.
This poses a problem for presentism, because of the relativity of simultaneity
implied by the constancy of the speed of light in space-time. However, for some
cosmological models Mst =< M, gab, Tab >a kind of ‘cosmic time’ can be
re-introduced in space-time, and some presentists have tried to use it to their
advantage.
Thomas Crisp (2008) has proposed a “presentist-friendly” model of general
relativity. He suggests that the world is represented by a 3-dimensional space-
like hypersurface that evolves in a forth dimension (time). This interpretation
requires the introduction of a preferred foliation of space-time at large scales,
and to consider the 3 + 1 usual decomposition for the dynamics of space-time
in such a way that ‘the present’ is identified with the evolving hypersurface.
This situation is depicted in Figure 1.
In order to set up such a model for space-time, some global constraints
must be imposed: there should be a unique foliation into surfaces of constant
mean curvature. This is the case, for instance, of the Friedmann-Robertson-
Walker-Lemaˆıtre metric. This metric is isotropic and homogeneous. General
conditions for such kind of metrics require the absence of Cauchy horizons,
the fulfillment of the so-called energy conditions (Hawking and Ellis 1973),
and symmetry constraints. In this kind of metrics, the parameter along which
the hypersurfaces evolve is called ‘cosmic time’.
1The curvature is represented by the Riemann tensor Rabcd, formed with second deriva-
tives of the metric (see, e.g. Hawking and Ellis 1973).
Present time 5
I confess that I do not see how such ‘cosmic time’ can help the presentist’s
cause. The foliation of a manifold is nothing else than a computational device.
The selection of a given hypersuface as ‘present’ is completely arbitrary. A
hypersurface is nothing else than a class of events (i.e. a concept, not a thing),
which we decide to specify as initial data for subsequent calculations. Any
hypersurface can be used for this purpose, and since the Einstein equations
are time-reversible, we can compute the evolution with respect to both tand
t. There is not reason for thinking that a particular class of events, even if
they are all space-like, is the ‘present’. Moreover, classes do not flow, as the
present is supposed to do.
A similar criticism is valid for the definition of present given by Crisp
(2003), who considers that the present is the aggregation of all things (I would
say events) with null temporal distance. There are events with null temporal
distance in the past of the event of reading this line, which are simultane-
ous with the landing of Apollo 11 on the moon on July 20th 1969. There is
no reason to think that your reading of this line is ‘now’ and not the events
simultaneous with Armstrong’s remarkable step: both events form part of ag-
gregates with null temporal distances. Why one aggregate of events is present
and the other is not?
There are additional problems related to the actual structure of the uni-
verse if it is supposed to be represented by a smoothly foliable theoretical
space-time model Mst . First, there are black holes. Non-spherically symmet-
ric black holes (i.e. rotating or Kerr black holes) have Cauchy horizons. There
is no way to compute the evolution of any physical system inside these re-
gions, whatever be the external space-time foliation. There is no possibility
of synchronization between clocks outside and inside the inner horizon of a
Kerr black hole. And the evidence for rotating black holes in the universe is
overwhelming (e.g. Romero and Vila 2013). This point cannot be ignored by
the presentist.
Another problem for the ‘presentist-friendly’ space-time is that observa-
tional data indicate that remote supernovae Type Ia present redshifts that
either suggest the universe is expanding in an accelerated way or it is inho-
mogeneous. Both possibilities are ruinous for the presentist. The first requires
massive violations of the energy conditions in the universe. These violations
can be produced by dark fields with negative energy densities or by gravity
with modified dynamical equations. In either case, particle cosmological hori-
zons appear in the universe, disconnecting different regions and making global
time synchronization impossible. On the other hand, if the universe is inho-
mogeneous or anisotropic on medium scales, then the Friedmann-Robertson-
Walker-Lemaˆıtre model is not a correct description of space-time and more
complex models should be considered. No foliation of constant curvature is
possible with inhomogeneity or anisotropy, with the consequent problem for
synchronization.
Zimmerman (2011) has pointed out that in a desperate case of conflict with
general relativity the presentist can abandon Einstein’s theory, since one can
be sure that relativity is ultimately a wrong theory because it is incompati-
6 Gustavo E. Romero
ble with quantum mechanics. I protest. General relativity is not inconsistent
with quantum mechanics as it is sometimes loosely stated. The background
space-time of quantum mechanics is flat Minkowskian space-time. Even in a
space-time with non-zero curvature, quantum mechanical calculations can be
performed (Wald 1994). General relativity is a classical theory, and hence it
cannot deal with quantum interactions of the gravitational field. This is some-
thing very different from saying the there is incompatibility with quantum
mechanics or quantum field theory. What is not known is what a quantum
field theory of gravitation is. What we actually know is that at the scales that
are relevant for the presentist, general relativity is a well-tested theory. But
even if it is replaced by other field theory to better accommodate the phe-
nomenology of dark matter and the apparent universal accelerated expansion,
the very same problems I mentioned above will remain. For the presentist, the
battle is lost from the beginning: the very concept of space-time is at odds with
presentism. And this is because space-time is the ontological sum of all events.
The mere postulation of space-time implies a consent to events that can be
classified as past or future with respect to some other events. Space-time is
inconsistent with presentism.
Said all that, yet, we all have a kind of feeling that “our time is running
out”. Where does this feeling come from? To answer we should look not at
space-time, but into our own brains.
3 When is ‘now’ ?
If the present is an instant of time instead of a thing, then the question of
“which instant is present?” follows. One possible answer is “now”. But...when
is ‘now’?
‘Now’, like ‘here’, is an indexical word. To say that I exist now gives no
information on when I exist. Similarly, to say that I am here, gives no infor-
mation on where I am. There is no particular moment of time defined as an
absolute now.
I maintain that ‘nowness’ and ‘hereness’ emerge from the existence of per-
ceiving self-conscious beings in a certain environment. What these beings per-
ceive is not time, but changes in things, i.e. events (Bunge 1977). Similarly,
they do not perceive space, but spatial relations among things. In particular,
we do not perceive the passage of time. We perceive how our brain changes. I
claim that there is no present per se, in the same way that there is no smell, no
pain, no joy, no beauty, no noise, no secondary qualities at all without sentient
beings. What we call “the present” is not in the world. It emerges from our
interaction with the world.
We group various experienced inputs together as present; we are tempted
to think that this grouping is done by the world, not by us. But this is just
delusional. I maintain that tenses are not needed and in fact are not wanted
by the natural sciences. This idea is clearly expressed by E. Poeppel on the
basis of neurological research (Poeppel 1978):
Present time 7
[...] our brain furnishes an integrative mechanism that shapes se-
quences of events to unitary forms...that which is integrated is the
unique content of consciousness which seems to us present. The in-
tegration, which itself objectively extends over time, is thus the basis
of our experiencing a thing as present.
[...] The now, the subjective present, is nothing independently; rather
it is an attribute of the content of consciousness. Every object of con-
sciousness is necessarily always now - hence the feeling of nowness.
The perception of motion gives an additional argument against the idea
that the present is an instant of time. According to Le Poidevin (2009):
1. What we perceive, we perceive as present.
2. We perceive motion.
3. Motion occurs over an interval.
Therefore: What we perceive as present occurs over an interval.
Recent research in neurosciences lends strong support to these claims.
Perception of events outside the brain and the construction of what we call
time is a complex cluster of processes that involves different cortical and sub-
cortical regions. Distortions in timing can be produced by narcotics, experi-
mental manipulation, strong emotions, and by different brain disorders such
as Alzheimer’s disease, clearly indicating a dependence of temporal experience
on brain processes. The involvement of sub-cortical areas in external change
perception explains why extreme fear and other abnormal emotional states
can modify the sub jective experience of time (e.g. Stetson et al. 2007).
A very important breakthrough in neurological research about the timing
mechanisms operating in the brain was made by Benjamin Libet and collabo-
rators (Libet et al. 1964, Libet 1973). In a series of now classical experiments,
Libet et al. demonstrated that there is a time delay of about 0.5 s between the
starting of brain stimulation and the appearance of awareness of the stimulus.
This shows that awareness of an event happens in the brain when the event
is past: what we become aware of has already occurred about 0.5 s earlier.
In Libet’s words: “We are not conscious of the actual moment of the present.
We are always a little late.” (Libet 2004). The entire battery of sensory stim-
uli are manipulated by the brain to create a coherent representation of the
external world in such a way that we are not aware of any time delay. The
subjective ‘present’ is actually a construction made with a manifold of sensory
information of events in the past.
The motor system does not wait 0.5 s before making its decisions. These
are done unconsciously and over spans as short as 10 ms in some cases. Con-
sciousness allows further interpretation and adjustments on the basis of later
information (Eagleman et al. 2000). The actual span required to create a tran-
sient representation of the environment can vary from an individual to another,
but should take more than 100 ms on average. In Eagelman’s words (Eagleman
2009):
8 Gustavo E. Romero
This hypothesis –that the system waits to collect information over
the window of time during which it streams in– applies not only to vision
but more generally to all the other senses. Whereas we have measured
a tenth-of-a-second window of postdiction in vision, the breadth of this
window may be different for hearing or touch. If I touch your toe and
your nose at the same time, you will feel those touches as simultaneous.
This is surprising, because the signal from your nose reaches your brain
well before the signal from your toe. Why didn’t you feel the nose-
touch when it first arrived? Did your brain wait to see what else might
be coming up in the pipeline of the spinal cord until it was sure it had
waited long enough for the slower signal from the toe? Strange as that
sounds, it may be correct.
It may be that a unified polysensory perception of the world has
to wait for the slowest overall information. Given conduction times
along limbs, this leads to the bizarre but testable suggestion that tall
people may live further in the past than short people. The consequence
of waiting for temporally spread signals is that perception becomes
something like the airing of a live television show. Such shows are not
truly live but are delayed by a small window of time, in case editing
becomes necessary.
All evidence from neuroscience research points to the hypothesis the ‘the
present’ is a construction of the brain; a construction that is not instantaneous.
We do not perceive time; we only are aware of events and can compare the
event rate or their clustering in the external world with the rate of activity of
our own brain (e.g. Karmarkar and Buonano 2007).
Any tentative definition of ‘present’ compatible with modern neuro-biology
science must take into account the role of the perceiving and sentient individ-
ual. In the next section I offer some provisional definitions that meet this
requirement and distinguish among the different meanings in which the word
‘present’ is used.
4 Defining the present
Physical events are ordered by the relations ‘earlier than’ or ‘later than’, and
‘simultaneous with’ (Gr¨unbaum 1973). There is no ‘now’ or ‘present’ in the
mathematical representation of the physical laws. What we call ‘present’ is not
an intrinsic property of the events nor an instant of time, much less a moving
thing. ‘Present’ is a concept abstracted from the relation between a certain
number of events and a self-conscious individual.
Present: Class of all events simultaneous with a given brain state.
To every brain state there is a corresponding present. The individual,
notwithstanding, needs not to be aware of all events that form the present. The
Present time 9
present, being a class of events, is an abstract object without any causal power.
Psychological present: Class of local events that are causally2connected
to a given brain state.
Notice that from a biological point of view only local events are relevant.
These events are those that directly trigger neuro-chemical reactions in the
brain. Such events are located in the immediate causal past of the brain events
that define the corresponding state. The psychological present is a conceptual
construction of the brain, based on abstraction from events belonging to an
equivalence class. The present, then again, is not a thing nor a change in a
thing (an event). It is a construction of the brain; a fiction albeit a very useful
one for survival. Yet again, individuals are not necessarily aware of all events
that are causally relevant for the construction of the psychological present.
E.R. Kelly (1882) introduced the concept of ‘specious present’, which William
James elaborated as “the short duration of which we are immediately and in-
cessantly sensible” (James 1908). I propose to update this definition to:
Specious present: Length of the time-history of brain processes necessary
to integrate all local events that are physically (causally) related to a given
brain state.
The specious present, being related to brain processes, can be different
for different individuals equipped with different brains. The integration of the
specious present can be performed in different ways, depending on the struc-
ture of the brain. It is even possible to imagine integration systems that can
produce more than one specious present or even systems that might ‘recall’
the future (see Hartle 2005 for examples based on computers). If biological
evolution has not produced such systems, it seems because of the existence of
space-time asymmetric boundary conditions that introduce a preferred direc-
tion for the occurrence of processes (Romero and P´erez 2011).
Finally, I introduce a physical present.
Physical present: Class of events that belong to a space-like hypersurface
in a smooth and continuous foliation of a time-orientable space-time.
Since in the manifold model of space-time every event is represented by
an element of the manifold, the introduction of this class does not signal a
special time identified with ‘now’. Every space-like hypersurface corresponds
to a different time and none of them is an absolute present ‘moving’ into
the future. Actually, naming ‘the future’ to a set of surfaces in the direction
opposite to the so-called Bing Bang is purely conventional.
2For a complete account of causality as a relation between events see Bunge (1979).
10 Gustavo E. Romero
5 Final remarks
I have distinguished three different types of present: psychological, physical,
and specious. The former two are classes of events, hence they are concepts.
The latter is not an instant of time but an interval in space-time associated
with the world history of a sentient individual.
In any case, the present does not flow or move. Only material individuals
(and their brains, if they have one) can change and move. Becoming is not
a property of physical events, but of the consciousness of the events. We call
‘becoming’ to the series of states of consciousness associated with a certain
string of physical changes. Events do not become. Events just are.
Appendix: Present time in quantum mechanics
Quantum mechanics has been invoked to justify almost every conceivable be-
lief, from free will to the existence of God. It is not surprising that the pre-
sentists have also appealed to it. Two main arguments have been proposed
to support presentism: the so-called ‘collapse of the wave function’, and the
non-locality implied by the experimental violation of Bell’s inequalities. In this
appendix I discuss and dismiss both arguments.
The collapse of the wave function is supposed to involve absolute simultane-
ity. Absolute simultaneity, in turn, allows to classify events into past, present
and future ´a la Newton. The argument runs as follows, in words of Michael
Tooley (Tooley 2008):
Consider an electron that has been fired towards the screen of a
cathode ray tube. According to quantum mechanics, the initial condi-
tions do not causally determine what point on the screen the electron
will strike. All that follows from the laws of quantum mechanics is that
there are various non-zero probabilities of the electron’s striking differ-
ent parts of the screen. But once the electron strikes the screen, the
probabilities of hitting other parts of the screen must change from hav-
ing non-zero values to being equal to zero. But then must it not be
the case that that all these changes are absolutely simultaneous with
the event that consists of the electron’s hitting the screen a certain
location?3
This is abhorrent. It is claimed that probabilities, a mathematical construct
that represents a certain propensity of a physical system, can change in space
and time. This reification of the concept of probability is wrong independently
of quantum mechanics. Think, for instance, of a roulette. A croupier spins
a wheel in one direction, then spins a ball in the opposite direction around
the tilted circular track running around the circumference of the wheel. The
ball eventually loses momentum and falls onto the wheel and into one of 37 (in
3My italics.
Present time 11
French/European roulette) or 38 (in American roulette) colored and numbered
pockets on the wheel. Let us consider a French roulette. There is an a priori
probability of 1/37 for a given number to be the winner. After the ball has
fallen into a given pocket, say number 7, the probability for this number is
still 1/37, no 1! Because of this low probability is that the casino is paying
you. Similarly, if you toss a coin, there is a probability of 1/2 of getting heads
both before and after a flipping. Probabilities are not a physical field that
suddenly collapses at some moment of time. As all mathematical constructs,
probabilities are timeless.
Even the so-called ‘collapse of the wave function’ is non-sense since the
wave function is a mathematical function defined in a Hilbert space, not an
entity propagating through space-time, and hence it cannot collapse at all. The
wave function allows to estimate probabilities of a given event. It is a solution
of the Schr¨odinger or Dirac equations, which are linear differential equations.
The physics of the non-linear interaction of the quantum system represented
by the wave function and the environment is surely non-linear and must be
discussed in the context of a theory of quantum measurement, that depends on
the details of the detector. Certainly, it is not enough just to add a postulate
(as von Neumann’s) to account for such a complex theory (see Bunge 1967,
Perez-Bergliaffa et al. 1993).
Let us turn to the claim that quantum non-locality reestablishes abso-
lute simultaneity and introduces a preferred foliation of space-time. Einstein,
Podolsky and Rosen (1935) -EPR- were the first to notice that quantum me-
chanics might imply non-locality. Consider two electrons prepared in a singlet
state and fired in opposite directions from a central source with equal veloci-
ties. This event occurs at a time t0. Quantum mechanics describes the system
with a single two-particle wave function that is not the product of indepen-
dent particle wave functions. Because electrons are indistinguishable particles,
it is not proper to say that electron 1 goes this way and electron 2 that way.
At a later time t1> t0, a measurement of one electron’s momentum4would
instantly reveal the momentum of the other electron - without need of mea-
suring it. This is a non-local correlation that seems to violate relativity if the
separation of the electrons is space-like. Schr¨odinger described the two elec-
trons as “entangled” (verschr¨ankt) at their first measurement, so the EPR
“non-locality” phenomenon is also known as “quantum entanglement”.
Contrary to Einstein’s expectations, experiments have generally favored
quantum mechanics as a description of nature, over local hidden variable the-
ories. Any physical theory that supersedes or replaces quantum theory must
make similar experimental predictions and must therefore also be non-local
in the specific sense of showing the existence of space-like correlations for en-
tangled quantum systems. Does this imply the existence of the present? I say
no.
4Although I am considering the momentum, a conserved quantity, in this example, con-
servation laws do not seem to play a role in the phenomenon, since these kind of correlations
are observed in the polarization of photons, which certainly in not a conserved quantity (see
Maudlin 2002).
12 Gustavo E. Romero
The existence of correlations between components of entangled systems
does not require superluminal matter transport or signaling. Much less of
information. Information is a property of languages, not of physical systems.
Contrary to what Tim Maudlin (2002) states, superluminal transmission of
information is not required by quantum entanglement. Information has not,
and cannot, have any effect upon physical systems.
The correlations just show that once a system is formed, it remains a sys-
tem. Although the actual mechanism that enforces the systemic memory is not
clear, quantum non-locality cannot be used to define an absolute simultane-
ity, since far from be universal, its very nature requires it to be selective and
operating only on systems that were prepared in a singlet state once. There
is no way to know the output of a measurement on the second electron of our
example above if the data on the preparation and the first measurement were
not transmitted to the second detector. This transmission is only possible at
the speed of light, at most.
I conclude that the concept of present is alien to quantum mechanics.
References
1. M. Bunge (1967). Foundations of Physics. New York: Springer-Verlag.
2. M. Bunge (1977). Treatise of Basic Philosophy. Ontology I: The Furniture of the World.
Dordrecht: Reidel.
3. M. Bunge (1979). Causality in Modern Science. New York: Dover, 2nd ed.
4. T. Crisp (2003). Presentism. In M. J. Loux & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), The Oxford
Handbook of Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 211-245.
5. T. Crisp (2008). Presentism, eternalism and relativity physics. In W. L. Craig & Q. Smith
(Eds.), Einstein, Relativity and Absolute Simultaneity. London: Routledge, pp. 262-278.
6. D. M. Eagleman and T. J. Sejnowski (2000). Motion integration and postdiction in visual
awareness, Science,287, 20362038.
7. D. M. Eagleman (2009). Brain time, Edge, http://edge.org/conversation/braintime.
8. A. Einstein (1905). Zur Elektrodynamik bewegter K¨orper. Annalen der Physik,17 (10),
891-921.
9. A. Einstein (1915). Die Feldgleichungen der Gravitation. Preussische Akademie der Wis-
senschaften, 844-847.
10. A. Einstein, B. Podolsky, and N. Rosen (1935). Can quantum-mechanical description
of physical reality be considered complete?. Physical Review 47 (10), 777780.
11. A. Gr¨unbaum (1973). Philosophical Problems of Space and Time. Dordrecht: Reidel,
2nd ed.
12. J.B. Hartle (2005). The physics of now, American Journal of Physics,73, 101-109.
13. S. Hawking and G.F.R. Ellis (1973). The Large-Scale Structure of Space-Time. Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press.
14. W. James, (1893). The Principles of Psychology. New York: H. Holt and Company.
15. U.R. Karmarkar and D.V. Buonomano (2007). Timing in the absence of clocks: encoding
time in neural network states, Neuron,53, 427-438.
16. E. Robert Kelly (1882). The Alternative: A Study in Psychology. London: Macmillan
and Co.
17. B. Libet, W.W. Alberts, E.W. Wright, L.D. Delattre, G. Levin, and B. Feinstein (1964).
Production of threshold levels of conscious sensation by electrical stimulation of human
somatosensory cortex, J. Neurophysiol.,27, 546-578.
18. B. Libet (1973). Electrical stimulation of cortex in human subjects and conscious sensory
aspects. In A. Iggo (ed.), Handbook of Sensors Physiology Vol. 2, Heidelberg: Springer-
Verlag, pp. 743-790.
Present time 13
19. B. Libet (2004). Mind Time - The Temporal Factor in Consciousness. Cambridge:
Harvard University Press.
20. T. Maudlin (2002). Quantum Nonlocality and Relativity. Oxford: Blackwell.
21. R. Le Poidevin (2009). The experience and perception of time, The Standfrod Encyclo-
pedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/time-experience/.
22. J.M.E. McTaggart (1908). Unreality of time, Mind,17, 456-473.
23. S.E. Perez Bergliaffa, G. E. Romero, and H. Vucetich (1993). Axiomatic foundations
of non-relativistic quantum mechanics: A realistic approach, Int. J. Theor. Phys. 32,
1507-1522.
24. S.E. Perez Bergliaffa, G. E. Romero, and H. Vucetich (1996). Axiomatic foundations of
quantum mechanics revisited: The case for systems, Int. J. Theor. Phys.,35, 1805-1819.
25. E. Poeppel (1978). Time perception. In Richard Held et al. (eds.), Handbook of Sensory
Physiology, Vol. VIII: Perception , Berlin: Springer-Verlag, pp. 713-729.
26. G.E. Romero (2013). From change to spacetime: an Eleatic journey, Foundations of
Science,18, 139-148.
27. G.E. Romero and D. P´erez (2011). Time and irreversibility in an accelerating universe,
International Journal of Modern Physics D,20, 1-8.
28. G.E. Romero and G.S. Vila (2013). Introduction to Black Hole Astrophysics. Heidelberg:
Springer.
29. S. Saunders (2002). How relativity contradicts presentism. In C. Callender (Ed.), Time,
Reality &Experience, Royal Institute of Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, pp. 277-292.
30. C. Stetson, M.P. Fiesta, D.M. Eagleman (2007). Does time really slow down during a
frightening event?, PLoS ONE,2(12), e1295. doi:10.1371/ journal.pone.0001295.
31. M. Tooley (2008). A defense of absolute simultaneity. In W. L. Craig & Q. Smith (Eds.),
Einstein, Relativity and Absolute Simultaneity. London: Routledge, pp. 229-243.
32. R.M. Wald (1994). Quantum Field Theory in Curved Spacetime and Black Hole Ther-
modynamics. Chicago: The Chicago University Press.
33. D. Zimmerman (2011). Presentism and the space-time manifold. In C. Callender (Ed.),
The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Time. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 163-
244.
14 Gustavo E. Romero
Gustavo E. Romero
Full Professor of Relativistic Astrophysics at the University of La Plata and
Chief Researcher of the National Research Council of Argentina. A former
President of the Argentine Astronomical Society, he has published more than
300 papers on astrophysics, gravitation and the foundations of physics. Dr.
Romero has authored or edited 9 books (including Introduction to Black Hole
Astrophysics, with G.S. Vila, Springer, 2013). His main current interest is on
black hole physics and ontological problems of space-time theories.
... The reader is referred to, for example, refs. [14,[71][72][73][74] for details. ...
Article
Full-text available
The ontology behind quantum mechanics has been the subject of endless debate since the theory was formulated some 100 years ago. It has been suggested, at one time or another, that the objects described by the theory may be individual particles, waves, fields, ensembles of particles, observers, and minds, among many other possibilities. I maintain that these disagreements are due in part to a lack of precision in the use of the theory’s various semantic designators. In particular, there is some confusion about the role of representation, reference, and denotation in the theory. In this article, I first analyze the role of the semantic apparatus in physical theories in general and then discuss the corresponding ontological implications for quantum mechanics. Subsequently, I consider the extension of the theory to quantum fields and then analyze the semantic changes of the designators with their ontological consequences. In addition to the classical arguments to rule out a particle ontology in the case of non-relativistic quantum field theory, I show how the existence of black holes makes the proposal of a particle ontology in general spacetimes unfeasible. I conclude by proposing a provisional pluralistic ontology of fields and spacetime and discussing some prospects for possible future ontological economies.
... Lo cual dista de ser una buena idea, ya que dada la constancia de la velocidad de la luz en el espacio-tiempo, la 'simultaneidad' resulta ser una noción dependiente del marco de referencia adoptado para realizar una descripción, y la existencia no puede depender de algo que sea marco-dependiente (cfr. Romero, 2015). ...
Article
Full-text available
The post-rationalist approach in psychotherapy is proposed by Vittorio Guidano as an epistemology for a new era that goes beyond rationalism. However, such an approach creates a caricatured vision of "empiricism-objectivism" and then opposes it. By analy-zing the seminal book The Self in Process (Guidano, 1991/1994) and writings of other theorists associated with the approach, I will argue that their disconnection with major developments in twentieth-century philosophy leads them to posit philosophically pro-blematic theses without noticing their internal inconsistencies. I will argue that Guidano (i) fails to define central philosophical terms (process, knowledge, truth), (ii) presents an internally contradictory (if not unintelligible) definition of reality (iii) that is inconsis-tent with developments in his theory, and (iv) perpetuates the Cartesian dogma of first-person infallibility. I will conclude that current realist philosophies pick up Guidano's epistemic concerns, and that postrationalism's emphasis on the construction of one's own reality may hinder the understanding of the other in therapy and promote interventions that ignore social and biochemical causal factors. Finally, I will show that despite the common caricature that current psychotherapeutic theory makes of early 20th-cen-tury positivism (logical empiricism), Carnap's linguistic pluralism, Neurath's epistemic fallibilism and Hempel's aletic coherentism -among other positivist theses- are akin to several constructivist premises of Guidano et al.'s post-rationalism.
... Lo cual dista de ser una buena idea, ya que dada la constancia de la velocidad de la luz en el espacio-tiempo, la 'simultaneidad' resulta ser una noción dependiente del marco de referencia adoptado para realizar una descripción, y la existencia no puede depender de algo que sea marco-dependiente (cfr. Romero, 2015). ...
Article
Full-text available
El enfoque posracionalista en psicoterapia es planteado por Vittorio Guidano como una epistemología para una nueva época que va más allá del racionalismo. No obstante, dicho enfoque crea una visión caricaturesca del "empirismo-objetivismo" para luego oponerse a ella. Mediante el análisis del libro seminal El sí-mismo en proceso (Guidano, 1991/1994) y escritos de otros teóricos afines al enfoque, argumentaré que su desconexión con los desarrollos principales de la filosofía del siglo XX los lleva a plan-tear tesis filosóficamente problemáticas sin advertir sus inconsistencias internas. Argumentaré que Guidano (i) no define términos filosóficos centrales (proceso, conocimiento, verdad), (ii) presenta una definición internamente contradictoria (si es que no ininteligible) de realidad (iii) que resulta inconsistente con desarrollos de su teoría, y (iv) perpetúa el dogma cartesiano de la infalibilidad de la primera persona. Concluiré que las preocupaciones epistémicas de Guidano son recogidas por filosofías realistas actuales, y que el énfasis del posracionalismo en la construcción de la propia realidad puede dificultar la comprensión del otro en terapia y promover intervenciones que ignoren factores causales sociales y bioquímicos. Finalmente, mostraré que pese a la caricatura común que la teoría psicoterapéutica actual hace del positivismo de inicios del s. XX (empirismo lógico), el pluralismo lingüístico de Carnap, el falibilismo epistémico de Neurath y el coherentismo alético de Hempel-entre otras tesis positivistas-son afi-nes a varias premisas constructivistas del posracionalismo de Guidano y compañía. The post-rationalist approach in psychotherapy is proposed by Vittorio Guidano as an epistemology for a new era that goes beyond rationalism. However, such an approach creates a caricatured vision of "empiricism-objectivism" and then opposes it. By analyzing the seminal book The Self in Process (Guidano, 1991/1994) and writings of other theorists associated with the approach, I will argue that their disconnection with major developments in twentieth-century philosophy leads them to posit philosophically problematic theses without noticing their internal inconsistencies. I will argue that Guidano (i) fails to define central philosophical terms (process, knowledge, truth), (ii) presents an internally contradictory (if not unintelligible) definition of reality (iii) that is inconsistent with developments in his theory, and (iv) perpetuates the Cartesian dogma of first-person infallibility. I will conclude that current realist philosophies pick up Guidano's epistemic concerns, and that postrationalism's emphasis on the construction of one's own reality may hinder the understanding of the other in therapy and promote interventions that ignore social and biochemical causal factors. Finally, I will show that despite the common caricature that current psychotherapeutic theory makes of early 20th-century positivism (logical empiricism), Carnap's linguistic pluralism, Neurath's epistemic fallibilism and Hempel's aletic coherentism-among other positivist theses-are akin to several constructivist premises of Guidano et al.'s post-rationalism.
Chapter
I present a condensed exposé of systemic materialism, a synthesis of materialism and systemism originally proposed by Mario Bunge. Matter is identified with mutability of propertied particulars, and a concrete or material system is defined as an object with composition, structure, mechanism, and environment. I review different aspects of this ontology, and discuss some of its implications for epistemology, ethics, and aesthetics. I also try to identify some problems of this view and offer some ways to overcome the difficulties. I conclude that systemic materialism is a promising philosophical project still in the making.
Article
Full-text available
A possible solution is offered to help resolve the “two times problem” regarding the veridical and illusory nature of time. First it is recognized that the flow (passage) of time is part of a wider array of temporal experiences referred to as manifest time, all of which need to be reconciled. Then, an information gathering and utilizing system (IGUS) model is used as a basis for a view of manifest time. The model IGUS robot of Hartle that solves the “unique present” debate is enhanced with veridical and (corresponding) illusory components of not only the flow of time but also the larger entity of manifest time, providing a dualistic IGUS robot that represents all of the important temporal experiences. Based upon a variety of prior experiments, that view suggests that the veridical system is a reflection of accepted spacetime cosmologies and through natural selection begets the illusory system for functional purposes. Thus, there are not two opposing times, one outside and one inside the cranium. There is just one fundamental physical time which the brain developed, now possesses and is itself sufficient for adaption but then enhances. The illusory system is intended to provide a more satisfying experience of physical time, and better adaptive behavior. Future experiments to verify that view are provided. With a complete veridical system of temporal experiences there may be less need to reify certain temporal experiences so that the two times problem is less of a problem and more of a phenomenon.
Article
Full-text available
There is a long standing debate as to whether or not time is ‘real’ or illusory, and whether or not human time (the flow/passage of time) is a direct reflection of physical time. Differing spacetime cosmologies have opposing views. Exactly what human time entails has, in our opinion, led to the failure to resolve this ‘two times’ problem. To help resolve this issue we propose a dualistic model of human time in which each component (e.g. change, motion, and temporality) has both an illusory and non-illusory (‘real’) aspect. With the dualistic model we are able to provide experimental tests for all of the human time assertions of 10 chosen spacetime cosmologies. The illusory aspect of the ‘present,’ i.e. a ‘unique present’ was confirmed. An information gathering and utilizing system (IGUS) was constructed using a virtual reality (VR) apparatus allowing the observer to experientially roam back and forth along the worldline ad lib. The phenomenon of ‘change’ was experimentally found to be illusory at high frequency observation and non-illusory (‘real’) at low frequency observation, the latter phenomenon coinciding with ‘change’ referred to in the ‘Order of Time’ and ‘Relativity Refounded’ views. Additional experiments are presented indicating that both motion and temporality are dualistic. In sum, the dualistic model of human time allows for the existence of both illusory and non-illusory (‘real’) aspects of human time that are not in conflict with one another. It also provides experimental evidence for various spacetime cosmological assertions regarding human time.
Chapter
This brief review of Mario Bunge’s research on physics begins with an analysis of his masterpiece Foundations of Physics, and then it discusses his other contributions to the philosophy of physics. Following that is a summary of his more recent reactions to scientific discoveries in physics and a discussion of his position about non-locality in quantum mechanics, as well as his changing opinions on the nature of spacetime. The paper ends with a brief assessment of Bunge’s legacy concerning the foundations of physics.
Chapter
Discussions about the nature of space and time in Western thought can be traced to the early Pre-Socratic philosophers.
Article
A recently published hypothesis on the nature of time by physicist Robert Muller seeks to provide an objective account of the present moment (the ‘now’) and the ‘flow’ of time. Muller also claims that his hypothesis makes testable predictions. It is shown that the predictions offered cannot be used to test Muller’s hypothesis, that the hypothesis (as presented) does not rate scientific status, has a number of questionable metaphysical premises, and is merely a re-fashioning of the Growing Block theory of time.
Book
Einstein's General Theory of Relativity leads to two remarkable predictions: first, that the ultimate destiny of many massive stars is to undergo gravitational collapse and to disappear from view, leaving behind a 'black hole' in space; and secondly, that there will exist singularities in space-time itself. These singularities are places where space-time begins or ends, and the presently known laws of physics break down. They will occur inside black holes, and in the past are what might be construed as the beginning of the universe. To show how these predictions arise, the authors discuss the General Theory of Relativity in the large. Starting with a precise formulation of the theory and an account of the necessary background of differential geometry, the significance of space-time curvature is discussed and the global properties of a number of exact solutions of Einstein's field equations are examined. The theory of the causal structure of a general space-time is developed, and is used to study black holes and to prove a number of theorems establishing the inevitability of singualarities under certain conditions. A discussion of the Cauchy problem for General Relativity is also included in this 1973 book.
Article
In this Introduction' we shall sketch the business of ontology, or metaphysics, and shall locate it on the map of learning. This has to be done because there are many ways of construing the word 'ontology' and because of the bad reputation metaphysics has suffered until recently - a well deserved one in most cases. 1. ONTOLOGICAL PROBLEMS Ontological (or metaphysical) views are answers to ontological ques­ tions. And ontological (or metaphysical) questions are questions with an extremely wide scope, such as 'Is the world material or ideal - or perhaps neutral?" 'Is there radical novelty, and if so how does it come about?', 'Is there objective chance or just an appearance of such due to human ignorance?', 'How is the mental related to the physical?', 'Is a community anything but the set of its members?', and 'Are there laws of history?'. Just as religion was born from helplessness, ideology from conflict, and technology from the need to master the environment, so metaphysics - just like theoretical science - was probably begotten by the awe and bewilderment at the boundless variety and apparent chaos of the phenomenal world, i. e. the sum total of human experience. Like the scientist, the metaphysician looked and looks for unity in diversity, for pattern in disorder, for structure in the amorphous heap of phenomena - and in some cases even for some sense, direction or finality in reality as a whole.
Book
When all was over — that is, when it became clear that nothing important is ever over in physics — in came the Duchess and drew her morals.
Chapter
The experience of time and how it might be explained has always been a persistent challenge. One of the most compelling analyses of subjective time is the one given by Augustinus (397/398 A.D.) in the 11th book of his “Confessions.” His ideas about the subjective measurement of time are still impressive today; he relates time to the perception of events, an idea that recently has been discussed by Gibson (1973, “Events are perceivable but time is not”). This chapter has been written in order to argue for such a substitution of time perception by event perception. It shall further be argued that in order to deal with human time perception one has to establish a taxonomy of temporal experiences. It appears that different unrelated temporal experiences are often subsumed under the term time perception and that many controversies found in the literature on subjective time stem from an absence of such a taxonomy of temporal experiences.
Book
This chapter introduces the concept of a space-time and outlines the General Theory of Relativity and some of its extensions.