ArticlePDF Available

Self-Representation and Perspectives in Dreams

Authors:

Abstract

Integrative and naturalistic philosophy of mind can both learn from and contribute to the contemporary cognitive sciences of dreaming. Two related phenomena concerning self‐representation in dreams demonstrate the need to bring disparate fields together. In most dreams, the protagonist or dream self who experiences and actively participates in dream events is or represents the dreamer: but in an intriguing minority of cases, self‐representation in dreams is displaced, disrupted, or even absent. Working from dream reports in established databanks, we examine two key forms of polymorphism of self‐representation: dreams (or dream episodes) in which I take an external visuospatial perspective on myself, and those in which I take someone else's perspective on events. In remembering my past experiences or imagining future or possible experiences when awake, I sometimes see myself from an external or ‘observer’ perspective. By relating the issue of perspective in dreams to established research traditions in the study of memory and imagery, and noting the flexibility of perspective in dreams, we identify new lines of enquiry. In other dreams, the dreamer does not appear to figure at all, and the first person perspective on dream events is occupied by someone else, some other person or character. We call these puzzling cases ‘vicarious dreams’ and assess some potential ways to make sense of them. Questions about self‐representation and perspectives in dreams are intriguing in their own right and pose empirical and conceptual problems about the nature of self‐representation with implications beyond the case of dreaming.
Philosophy Compass 8/11 (2013): 10411053, 10.1111/phc3.12082
Self-Representation and Perspectives in Dreams
Melanie Rosen and John Sutton*
Macquarie University
Abstract
Integrative and naturalistic philosophy of mind can both learn from and contribute to the contempo-
rary cognitive sciences of dreaming. Two related phenomena concerning self-representation in dreams
demonstrate the need to bring disparate elds together. In most dreams, the protagonist or dream self
who experiences and actively participates in dream events is or represents the dreamer: but in an
intriguing minority of cases, self-representation in dreams is displaced, disrupted, or even absent.
Working from dream reports in established databanks, we examine two key forms of polymorphism
of self-representation: dreams (or dream episodes) in which I take an external visuospatial perspective
on myself, and those in which I take someone elses perspective on events. In remembering my past
experiences or imagining future or possible experiences when awake, I sometimes see myself from
an external or observerperspective. By relating the issue of perspective in dreams to established
research traditions in the study of memory and imagery, and noting the exibility of perspective in
dreams, we identify new lines of enquiry. In other dreams, the dreamer does not appear to gure at
all, and the rst person perspective on dream events is occupied by someone else, some other person
or character. We call these puzzling cases vicarious dreamsand assess some potential ways to make
sense of them. Questions about self-representation and perspectives in dreams are intriguing in their
own right and pose empirical and conceptual problems about the nature of self-representation with
implications beyond the case of dreaming.
1. Introduction
What can we learn about the self by considering dreams? Our experiences during sleep, or
our more occasional recollections and reports of those experiences, offer us signicant insight
into the operations of the mind in general. Philosophers continue to worry subtly at the
metaphysical and epistemological problems addressed by Descartesdream argument
(Valberg 2007), and even whether dreams really are experiences during sleep at all (Malcolm
1959; Dennett 1976; Child 2007). But the new sciences of dreaming, in the wake of the
discovery of REM (rapid eye movement) sleep and of the cognitive revolution, have opened
up both entirely new concerns and distinctive twists on older philosophical topics
(Churchland 1988; Revonsuo 1995; Flanagan 2000; Clark 2005; Windt & Metzinger
2007; Sutton 2009; Windt & Noreika 2011). Theories of consciousness, metacognition,
psychophysical reduction, and embodied cognition, to mention just a few examples, can
be both informed and constrained by the expanding array of psychological and
neurocognitive approaches within dream science (Solms 1997; Foulkes 1999; Hobson,
Pace-Schott & Stickgold 2000; Domhoff 2003; Schwartz et al. 2005; Nir & Tononi 2010;
Valli 2011).
In this paper, we pick out two related, highly specic, and (we think) deeply puzzling
dream phenomena which, in addition to their intrinsic interest, also exemplify the possibil-
ities for philosophical engagement with the cognitive sciences. These phenomena involve
the surprisingly complex ways in which we represent ourselves in dreams and experience
dream events from a rst-person perspective although as well see these are not exactly
© 2013 The Authors
Philosophy Compass © 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
equivalent. While these topics clearly connect back to traditional philosophical issues, our
methodological angle here is a strongly integrative form of naturalism, in which we seek
to put distinct and somewhat disconnected parts of the cognitive sciences into contact. This
philosophical strategy involves direct interactive engagement with the relevant sciences,
seeking mutual coevolution of theory and evidence, as is standard in philosophy of biology
or philosophy of neuroscience (Grifths & Sterelny, 1999; Craver 2007). In the philosophy
of psychology, such work can function as a catalyst, bringing together disparate elds of
enquiry within the relevant sciences (compare Sutton 2009, or for the case of emotion,
Grifths 1998 and Colombetti 2013). This catalyst function is increasingly important,
because of the daunting (sub-)disciplinary specialization of contemporary sciences. It can
be required not only to put into contact research programs across distinctive levels which
might be mutually informative, such as cognitive psychology and molecular neuroscience
but also across different neurocognitive domains. This latter kind of integration is specically
relevant in the current case, because certain processes of self-representation in dreams may
overlap with those involved in some forms of remembering and imagining.
Dreamings similarities to and differences from perception, imagination, and memory
respectively have been the subject of discussion and controversy in both philosophy and
science (Foulkes 1999; Sosa 2005; Horton, Moulin & Conway 2009; Ichikawa 2009; Windt
2010; Horton 2011). Dreaming involves a sharp bidirectional break in memory, such that
our dream selves seem to be signicantly disconnected: typically, we can neither reliably
access our own autobiographical memories while dreaming nor clearly recollect our dreams
on waking. This suggests that dreams and memory at least are rmly dissociated. But since
our common sense categories for psychological processes need not map neatly on to the
underlying mechanisms, there may also be overlaps and interactions across apparently distinct
domains of cognition. In this paper, addressing some of the ways in which self and body are
represented in dreams, we point to some specic and puzzling phenomena, which demand
treatment using pooled theoretical resources from different cognitive domains as well as
different disciplines.
Consider these two dream reports, gathered in controlled studies amongst large numbers
of recollected dreams:
I was in a sort of South American country, two hundred years ago, I was mounting a horse: with me
there were two more persons riding a horse, and other people on foot. We were pursuing a man,
who was myself, we were pursuing him because he had some money, and I was observing the
whole scene. (Cicogna & Bosinelli 2001, p.32)
I was walking (apparently it was me) in a suburban area, past a house whose yard was about one and
a half meters above the street level. In the yard a girl I know from medical school was leading a big
bearlike dog. I was leading a dog that actually was my female classmate from medical school. The
girl suddenly attacked the bear-dog and they fought. The person in the dream that so far had been
me, now was suddenly my classmate J. Somehow I became (physically) detached from myself and I
noticed that I was not me but him. This was accompanied by a funny feeling. (Revonsuo, 2005,
pp.2134)
These reports t a general picture of typical dreams as involving more or less bizarre
narrative sequences. In the sciences of dreaming, the bizarrenessof dream reports is often
analyzed into three distinct forms. The most common form of bizarreness is incongruity or
mismatch of character, event, or setting, followed by vagueness or uncertainty, while full-
scale discontinuity of narrative sequence is the least common (Stickgold & Hobson 1994;
1042 Perspectives in Dreams
© 2013 The Authors
Philosophy Compass © 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Philosophy Compass 8/11 (2013): 10411053, 10.1111/phc3.12082
Flanagan 2000, pp.1478; Revonsuo & Tarkko 2002): There is, however, ongoing disagree-
ment on precisely how to measure bizarreness and on its prevalence in all of our dreams as
opposed to those which are most memorable (Domhoff 2003; Sutton 2009, pp.5312;
Colace 2010; Rosen 2012, ch.2).
But the bizarreness in these two reports has the notable extra feature that it stretches to
touch the self, which is here variously shifting, doubled, observing, transformed, and de-
tached. Such disruptions are not typical in most peoples dreams, for sure. In by far the
majority of dream experiences, as Revonsuo puts it, the self in the dream is the character
who represents the dreamerand is positioned in the center of the dream worldsuch that
the dream setting and events are seen and experienced from his or her point of view
(2005, p.207). Even if, as David Foulkesdevelopmental studies suggest, it takes some time
and some cognitive sophistication before the self regularly appears as an active character in
extended dream narratives (Foulkes 1990, 1999), this does typically occur in the bulk of adult
dreams. In another large-scale study, Strauch and Meier found that the Dream Self appears
in nearly every dream, and for the most part (in 71% of dream reports) as a clear and active
participant in each persons own dream: but in addition to the 11% of cases in which the
dreamer is present but inactive, there were also some 18% of dream reports in which the
dreamer was either entirely uninvolved or explicitly absent (1996, pp.1145). Despite meth-
odological challenges in characterizing and coding different ways in which self-representa-
tion in dreams might diverge from the standard case, various studies show that such
divergence occurs in a sizeable minority of dreams. Our project here is to describe, probe,
and assess the implications of two of its primary forms. Revonsuo notes the theoretical
signicance of the fact that the dream self is not present in every single dream, such that
there is a simulated world of subjective experiences devoid of an explicit representation of
the self(2005, p.209). Here, we examine cases in which the self is displaced as well as miss-
ing. Even within the study of self-representation in dreams, one can ask a range of other live
questions, relating for example to our understandings of our own and otherscharacter and
psychology in dreams, to the mechanisms of identication and misidentication in dreams
and in delusions, and to the particular range of emotional experiences in dreaming (Foulkes
et al. 1991; McNamara, McLaren & Durso 2007; Gerrans 2012). We focus on two of a
number of possible forms of polymorphism of Selfin dreams (Occhionero & Cicogna
2011, p.1009): dreams (or dream episodes) in which I take an external visuospatial perspec-
tive on myself, and those in which I take someone elses perspective. These phenomena not
only demand explanation in their own right but also pose empirical and conceptual problems
about the nature of self-representation, which may have implications beyond dreaming.
2. Perspective in Dreams
In the rst dream report quoted above, involving a pursuit in South America, the dreamer is
both the pursuer and the pursued, either sequentially or simultaneously. But he is also
observing the whole scene, including himself. Likewise, in another report from the same
databank of 800 laboratory dreams, I was seeing my body lying on the bed, and it was
completely white, better beige. I was able to see myself lying on that bed …’ (Cicogna
& Bosinelli 2001, p.31). These are cases in which there is a clear self-representation in the
dream, and in which the dreamer is a character, but the visual or visuospatial perspective
of the dream experience does not coincide with what would be the perspective of the self
or the protagonist in the dream.
There are, we suggest, three key features of this kind of dream in which the dreamer
reports observing himself or herself; though each of these features can probably vary
Perspectives in Dreams 1043
© 2013 The Authors
Philosophy Compass © 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Philosophy Compass 8/11 (2013): 10411053, 10.1111/phc3.12082
independently, they do often coincide. Firstly, the dreamer reports seeing his or her own
body. Secondly, that body is immediately and unreectively taken to be the dreamer, the
dream self or the character representing the dreamer: there is no inference, uncertainty, or
further question about the identity of that observed character. Thirdly, there is a denite
visual or visuospatial perspective from which this observation occurs: this contrasts with cases
in which dream events are experienced from no visual or visuospatial perspective at all. We
suspect that our second initial report, in which the dreamer says that somehow I became
(physically) detached from myself and I noticed that I was not me but him, is a case of the
latter, distinct kind, accompanied as it was by a funny feeling.
In identifying these features of what we suggest are an important, if relatively rare type of
dream experience, we are explicitly guided by our understanding of related phenomena in
memory and imagery, which have been extensively studied in cognitive psychology and
(increasingly) cognitive neuroscience. Take memory rst. In remembering specic events
and experiences in my past, I may recall them from my original vantage-point, seeing the
remembered scene as through my own eyes, with what appears to be my original eld of
view; or I may recall them from an external vantage-point, such that I see myself in the
remembered scene, while adopting (now) an observers point of view. After rst being noted
by Freud and others in the 1890s, this distinction between eldand observermodes of
remembering has become a popular topic in mainstream cognitive psychology, since Nigro
and Neissersinuential paper (1983) and a systematic general renewal of interest in episodic
and autobiographical memory. Among an array of robust ndings, psychologists have shown
that, in general, memories retrieved from an own-eyesor eld perspective are more
common (especially for more recent events) and generally contain more information on
emotional and other subjective states than memories recalled from an observer perspective
(Berntsen & Rubin 2006; Rice & Rubin 2009). There are parallel phenomena in the case
of imagery. In imagining a possible or future action or event, for example, I can visualize
it either from my own point of view, or as if I am observing myself in action. There is solid
evidence that the perspective from which I imagine or tend to imagine future actions can
have denite and lasting effects on cognition, emotion, and action (Libby & Eibach 2011).
Philosophers have asked whether there can in fact be genuine memories in cases where
past events are recalled from an external perspective that diverges from that of the agents
perceptual experience at the time (Vendler 1979; Debus 2007; Sutton 2010). But this
distinction between eld (internal) and observer (external) perspectives in remembering
and imagining has also been studied intensively in applied domains of considerable
independent interest. In the psychology of sport and movement, for example, practices of
visualization among elite athletes and dancers are investigated to identify any differential
effects of imagining ones expert performances from the inside or as an observer (Morris &
Spittle 2012). Though it may seem natural to think that a eld visuospatial perspective in
imagery would tap and promote kinesthetic processes more effectively, in fact research
suggests that external or observer perspectives may be more useful for certain kinds of
movement task: the challenge of integrating kinesthetic sensation, 1
st
-person or eld visual
perspectives, and the experience of watching ones own moving body from the outside is
faced regularly for elite sportspeople in using video analysis of their performance (Callow
& Hardy 2004; Sutton 2012). In clinical psychology, in turn, there are ongoing discussions
on the point of view from which traumatic experiences are recalled or relived. In general,
remembering experiences from an observer perspective involves less detail on emotions
and bodily sensations. This leads some clinicians and psychologists to argue that the adoption
of an observer perspective in remembering trauma is a defense mechanism associated with
ongoing or increasing negative psychological symptoms, whereas the adoption of a eld
1044 Perspectives in Dreams
© 2013 The Authors
Philosophy Compass © 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Philosophy Compass 8/11 (2013): 10411053, 10.1111/phc3.12082
perspective can ward off or diminish such symptoms (McIsaac & Eich 2004; Kenny et al.
2009). Others see the abstraction, which external perspectives may bring as potentially
benecial, and argue that external perspectives can scaffold our capacity to consider different
evaluative and emotional perspectives on our own past (Mackenzie 2008; Goldie 2012).
Below, we focus in on a specic issue arising in these established research traditions on
perspective in memory and imagery, to apply back to the case of dreams. But rst, we under-
line the point that the availability of distinct perspectives appears to operate in many of the
same ways across all these domains. As in memory, dream experiences in which an external
or observer perspective is adopted may well be less common, but do occur in a signicant
minority of cases (Foulkes & Kerr 1994; Soper, Milford & Rosenthal 1994; Soper 1999).
Even though while dreaming we can rarely access anything like our full autobiographical
narrative, so that essential features of memory are not available in dreams, it is notable that
these same mechanisms of visuospatial perspective-taking can operate in common across
the domains. This can be harder to recognize because some scientic analyses of dream
reports do not clearly acknowledge the existence of dreams experienced from an observer
perspective. Strauch and Meier (1996) code participation of the dreamerunder the
categories of dreamer active,dreamer inactive,dreamer uninvolved,orno dream self.
Dreaming from an external or observer perspective does not quite map on to any of these
categories, which do not distinguish the agency of the dream character from the perspective
from which the dream events are experienced. Likewise, in a more ne-grained scheme
derived from the large Italian sample, Occhionero and colleagues code some reports as
including a representation of self as a passive observer of the dream events; but their use
of the term observerhere is potentially misleading, since by this, they mean not what
memory researchers call an observer perspective, but a dream from a standard eld perspec-
tive in which the dream self is inactive (I was at a service station and I was observing this
scene …’). In contrast, they classify the case in which the dreamer reports seeing himself
or herself lying on the bed under the category of a total or partial Self body image
(Occhionero & Cicogna 2011, p.5; compare Occhionero et al. 2005, pp.7980): this charac-
terization misses the key extra fact that this Self body imageis experienced and observed
from outside, from an external vantage-point.
Thefactthattheliteratureoneld and observer perspectives in memory and imagery
is not explicitly discussed in contemporary research on self-representation in dreams is
both puzzling and problematic. In the 1980s, there was a lively research focus on links
between memory, dreams, imagery, and out-of-body experiences (OBEs), in which
people see their own body from an external perspective. Susan Blackmoresinitial
hypothesis that people who report more regular OBEs would also remember their past
more often from an external or observer perspective turned out to be unsupported. But
those people did report adopting observer perspectives in their dreams more often than
others, and were able to switch between internal and external perspectives in memory
and imagery more easily (Blackmore 1987, 1988; compare Irwin 1986). But these earlier
connections between dreaming and OBEs, on the one hand, and memory and imagery,
on the other hand, have not been studied even in the recent dramatic revival of research
on OBEs, as we now explain.
Out-of-body experiences are one of a range of autoscopic phenomena, in which one
sees oneselfas if from the outside. The pathological waking conditions in this domain
include not only OBEs but also cases in which people see a duplicate or double of their
own body, while retaining their own standard rst-person perspective on that doubled
body (an autoscopic hallucination)(Brugger2002;Blanke&Mohr2005;Mishara
2010). OBEs, previously a focus of some scepticism among scientists, have recently
Perspectives in Dreams 1045
© 2013 The Authors
Philosophy Compass © 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Philosophy Compass 8/11 (2013): 10411053, 10.1111/phc3.12082
turned out to be linked to quite specicneurologicaldisturbances,andtobeopento
experimental induction (Blanke & Metzinger 2009). But these researchers have not
incorporated observer perspectives in memory and imagery into their classicatory
schemes. We suggest that the adoption of external perspectives in remembering,
imagining, and dreaming temporarily replicates certain features of OBEs, with which
it is likely to share certain neurocognitive mechanisms. A link between dreaming in
general and OBEs has been drawn by both Metzinger (2004, 2005) and Occhionero
and Cicogna (2011), and there is ongoing investigation into possible neurocognitive
commonalities with regard to vestibular function and the disintegration of standard
waking mechanisms for binding multisensory information, leading to an usually partial
or polymorphous representation of body image(Occhionero & Cicogna 2011,
p.1013). The link back to the ordinary temporary adoption of external perspectives in
memory and imagery has not been made by these authors, but, we suggest, recollection
from an observer perspective is another full-scale form of autoscopy. By explicitly noting
and thematizing the existence of observer perspectives in both memory and dreams,
researchers can now focus on psychological and neural links between both sets of
ordinary psychological phenomena and the rarer cases of OBEs.
We believe that both the prevalence and the signicance of exibility or uidity in
visuospatial perspective-taking, which may be particularly striking in dreams, have been
underestimated in a number of domains. Perhaps internal or eld perspectives are the
defaultmode (Morris & Spittle 2012), and perhaps it will turn out that in the case
of memory at least, they are more likely than observer perspectives to arise when we
are remembering accurately. But recent evidence suggests that external or observer
perspectives in memory may also turn out be relatively common, diverse, and functional
(Rice & Rubin 2009, 2011). So in dreams too, the availability of external perspectives
may signal the exibility of our self-representational capacities, rather than their
disruption, incompleteness, and weakness (Occhionero 2004). To note just two lines
for inquiry, which could draw on established methods elsewhere in psychology, it
would be useful to know if the emotions generally associated with distinctive perspec-
tives in memory also typically accompany those perspectives in dreams and to get a
better grip on the role of perspective in the way we represent our own movements
through space both in waking and dreaming cognition (Schönhammer 2005; Cook
2011; Tversky 2011).
3. Vicarious Dreams
In documenting a variety of ways in which the selfcan be represented in dreams,
Occhionero and Cicogna note that the dream self can also be experienced either by
way of embodiment-in or identication-with other characters or even objects(2011,
p.1013). Occasionally, on waking, the dreamer remembers having a dream in which
the protagonist the character or agent in the dream from whose viewpoint the dream
events were experienced was not the dreamer herself. Revonsuos dream database
includes the following report from a 25-year-old, blond female student:
Its the Second World War and I am a dark-haired, strongly built, Finnish male soldier. The
enemies are probably German [Later in the same dream]: I could see myself in a mirror.
Now I was a blond, strongly built woman. (Revonsuo 2005, p.213)
1046 Perspectives in Dreams
© 2013 The Authors
Philosophy Compass © 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Philosophy Compass 8/11 (2013): 10411053, 10.1111/phc3.12082
In a case from the Italian studies, the dreamer reports a lot of beautiful actresses
Im transformed and become a famous actor(Occhionero et al. 2005, p.80). In these
cases, the dreamers report a shift within the dream, either to or from being the
protagonist of their own dream. In other cases, the protagonist is not an embodied
person at all. I was inside a giant photocopying machine. I knew I was inside this
machine, not as a physical human being but as an abstract entity, as a mind, so I
couldntseemyself(Cicogna & Bosinelli 2001, p.32); another female student was a
dog or some other animalin the dream, and reported events experienced from the an-
imals point of view, running in a dark forest with another animal, hunting for prey
(Revonsuo 2005, p.214).
Each of these dream reports has its own unusual features. In some cases, perhaps
including the photocopy machine, the dream protagonist is still the dreamer, albeit
atypically located in some other kind of body. These are not cases of observer perspec-
tives, but simply of muted or incongruous forms of self-representation within otherwise
standard dream experience. But other cases, such as the woman dreaming as a dark-
haired male soldier, are arguably distinct again: these, we suggest, are vicarious dreams,
in which the holder of the rst-person perspective in the dream is someone (or some-
thing) other than the dreamer. In vicarious dreams, the perspective of the dream is that
of one of the dream characters, the one we call the protagonist, but this protagonist does
not identify himself as the dreamer, and correlatively, the dreamer does not treat or
identify herself as the protagonist.
Vicarious dreams are rare, certainly. As we noted above, in most remembered dreams the
protagonist is, or is in some sense continuous with, the dreamer: this is true too in the cases of
dreaming from an external observers perspective discussed in Section 2 above. In those cases,
there is no doubt that the observed protagonist is still me. Vicarious dreams are unlike
observer perspective dreams and like standard dreams in that the events are experienced from
an own-eyesor eld perspective, such that the rst-person perspective is occupied by a
character in the dream. But they are unlike standard dreams in that the protagonist from
whose perspective the dream occurs is someone other than the dreamer. One of us (MR)
has had dream experiences in which the protagonist was a male engineer on a spaceship,
trying to prevent the ship from crashing into the earth, and in another case, an old man
having a heart attack. In addition to the cases described in the scientic literature, what we
are calling vicarious dreams have received some philosophical discussion. J.J. Valberg rst
describes a more complex case, a dream in which the two characters are X and JV, but where
the rst person perspective is occupied by X: in the dream I am not JV but X (X is me),so
that in the dream I am a human being other than the human being that I am(2007, p.62). X
can interact with JV in the dream, refer to JV as himand observe JV from an external
perspective. If the protagonist feels pain and thinks I am feeling pain, Valberg suggests, I
refers to X rather than JV, whereas JVs pain behavior is observed in the dream from an
external perspective. Valberg then introduces what we see as the paradigmatic vicarious
dream by noting that JV need not have been in the dream at all(p.63): in this case, the
protagonist X, from whose rst person perspective the dream events are experienced, is still
someone other than Valberg the dreamer. In this case, the dreamer or the waking self is not
represented in the dream at all: the protagonist or subject of the dream, the one at the centre
of the dream(Valberg 2007, p.65) just is X (or the dark-haired Finnish soldier, or the famous
actor, or the running animal).
In waking life, Williams argues, I can imagine being Napoleon and looking over the
battleeld without this entailing either that Napoleon exists now, or that I might have been
Napoleon (1973, pp.4245). So it seems from the examples we have given above that I can
Perspectives in Dreams 1047
© 2013 The Authors
Philosophy Compass © 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Philosophy Compass 8/11 (2013): 10411053, 10.1111/phc3.12082
dream as Napoleon. This means not that in the dream my waking self has somehow been
transplanted into Napoleons body, or vice versa; rather, it means that the centered and
embodied (or dream-embodied) subject position of the dream protagonist, from whose
rst-person perspective the dream events unfold, is occupied by Napoleon and not by me.
But the phenomenon of vicarious dreaming raises puzzles about ownership of experience,
self-representation, and self-reference. Who do the experiences belong to in such dreams,
the dreamer or the protagonist? Who exactly is the protagonist? And to whom does Irefer
when, in the dream, Napoleon thinks or says I see the battle, or the dark-haired Finnish
soldier thinks I see the Germans? We work with the Napoleon case because it underlines
the implausibility of answering these questions by simply identifying the dream self, the
one occupying the rst-person perspective in the dream, with the apparent thinker and
speaker. Napoleon does not now exist: even if he did it would be odd for him, that actual
person, to be thinking and speaking in dreams which my brain generates and hosts. But what
alternative approaches are available here? Shortly we examine some philosophical resources
developed to deal with the parallel cases in waking imagination, but rst we examine three
other options. We do not offer a single preferred solution here, but intend to raise the
problems sharply for further attention.
Perhaps, rstly, the occupant of the rst-person perspective in vicarious dreams really is,
despite all appearances, the dreamer. On this view, the label vicariousis a little misleading,
for a dream protagonist is always an altered version of the waking self. In my dream, perhaps,
I am a shorter, more megalomaniacal version of myself. Perhaps the soldier dream is of this
kind, with the 25-year-old female student inhabiting a different dream body, but still
identifying herself as the protagonist. But though such cases do occur, as we have noted, they
do not exhaust the possibilities or entirely capture the phenomena we have described. In
general, the psychological discontinuity between waking self and dreaming self can be
extreme. And in particular, in our other examples of vicarious dreaming the waking self just
does not enter the picture within the dream at all. As Valberg says of such cases, in the dream
JV is not me (I am not JV): rather, someone else X or Napoleon or the soldier –‘is at the
center of the dream(2007, p.67).
Secondly, if the protagonist is neither Napoleon nor the dreamer, perhaps it is just a
dream Napoleon. This would be a challenging result, because unlike other characters in
the dream, dream Napoleon appears to be consciously experiencing the dream environment
from a rst-person perspective. This would mean that some experiencing protagonists only
exist for a short period during a dream, in what could be considered an extreme implemen-
tation of Lockean psychological continuity theory. Locke considers the possibility of two
distinct incommunicable consciousnesses acting in the same body, the one constantly by
day, the other by night(1690/1975, II.27.23, p.344), arguing that they would be distinct
selves. In dreams, however, the protagonist is not always the same person: the protagonist
of last nights dream is not usually psychologically linked with other dream protagonists in
the way Locke seems to think of his nightman. Given the uidity and discontinuity of
dreams as shown by our examples above, a dream protagonist may exist only for a short part
of a dream, as with the famous actor dream. Each protagonist, both within and across dreams,
may have varying levels and kinds of connectedness with other dream protagonists and with
the dreamer, and many such protagonists may have no such connectedness at all. So the
nightman would not be a singular dream protagonist who persists constantlythrough all
of my dreams.
This line of thought might force us to posit temporary and highly eeting subjects of
experience in vicarious dreams. We think this option is worth pursuing, but acknowledge
that it may be so counterintuitive as to encourage adoption of a third possibility, that the
1048 Perspectives in Dreams
© 2013 The Authors
Philosophy Compass © 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Philosophy Compass 8/11 (2013): 10411053, 10.1111/phc3.12082
dream protagonist just is no kind of subject or self at all, and that the rst-person perspective
apparently occupied in these dream experiences is in fact empty after all. We return to these
thoughts after discussing an attempt to defuse the puzzle by pushing harder on the parallel
with imagining.
David Velleman (1996) argues that the use of the rst person pronoun is
unproblematic when imagining that I am someone else. In such cases, as the actual
subject, I actively frame my thoughts and imaginings so that they diverge from my
own and arise from the perspective of the notional subject, the imagined center of
perspective: imagining that I am Napoleon is rst-personal, but it is, so to speak,
rst-personal about Napoleon, in the sensethatitisframedfromNapoleons point of
view(1996, p.40). This framing of perspective is unlike the genuine reexivity of
unselfconscious rst-person thoughts, yet raises no special mystery once we understand
that thoughts thus framed enact this explicitly specied gap between actual and notional
subjects. He applies this account not only to imagining being someone else but also to
certain possible relations between the present self and past or future selves, seeking a
unied framework for understanding perspectival selfhood across a range of psycholog-
ical states and processes.
Although Velleman does not discuss dreams, we might naturally try to extend his
approach from imagining and remembering to dreaming. Perhaps when I dream of being
Napoleon, my rst-person thoughts are not genuinely reexive. Rather, a self-conscious
framing contextualizes I see the battle: the dreamer is the actual subject who frames the
thought from the perspective of Napoleon, the notional subject.
Unfortunately, this tidy solution does not work. In vicarious dreams, there need be no
explicit framing: the actual dreamer, whose brain is generating or hosting the dream, is
nevertheless not accurately described as an actual subject of the dream. In lucid dreams,
certainly, the dreamer realizes that she is dreaming and might thus be in a position to frame
certain thoughts and experiences as being those of a distinct notional subject (LaBerge &
DeGracia 2000). But ordinary, non-lucid dreams are quite unlike this. The dreamer is neither
in the dream nor framing the dreamed perspective. This contrasts sharply with the case of
imagining as described by Velleman, in which the actual subject unselfconsciously retains
her own perspective whilst deliberately adopting the imagined perspective. In vicarious
dreams, there is only one centered subjective perspective, and it is the rst-person perspective
of the dream protagonist, Napoleon (or X or the soldier). In contrast to the kind of
imagining discussed by Williams and Velleman, the dream protagonist experiences the dream
world as if he is the actual subject. (In some kinds of imagining, such as more hallucinatory
forms of fantasy or mind wandering, the duality of perspective which Velleman describes also
disappears, perhaps giving rise to related problems).
There are two possible responses here, further ways to develop a Velleman-style solution
to the problem of vicarious dreaming. Perhaps the dreamer either forgets the framing that
occurred during the dream, or frames the perspective of the dream protagonist tacitly or
unconsciously. We do not think either option works for vicarious dreams. Regarding the
rst explanation, indeed, forgetting of the framing thoughts may sometimes occur, but it is
unlikely as a plausible explanation of all vicarious dreams. There seems to be a clear distinc-
tion between dream reports in which the protagonist remains somehow aware of the waking
self despite doing Napoleonic things such as riding a horse and looking over a battle, and
dreams in which the dream protagonist believes they are Napoleon, in which there is no
distinction between the actual subject and the notional subject just because the actual subject
is out of the picture entirely and not even engaged in some tacit or background framing.
Such cases are the ones we nd most philosophically interesting.
Perspectives in Dreams 1049
© 2013 The Authors
Philosophy Compass © 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Philosophy Compass 8/11 (2013): 10411053, 10.1111/phc3.12082
Secondly, the possibility that the framing of certain thoughts could occur outside conscious
awareness is not consistent with Vellemans framework. For Velleman, only standard, genuinely
reexive rst-person thoughts are unselfconscious about their reference, in that they require no
other thought about whom they refer to. I can think of NB as notionally meonly by
deliberately placing him where he will intercept this inward-directed pointer, thus rendering
its reference to him self-conscious(Velleman 1996, p.60). If we allow that non-genuine
reexive thoughts can also be established in an unselfconscious manner, it is not clear how
the distinction between genuine and non-genuine cases can be maintained. Perhaps such auto-
matic or non-conscious framing does operate in the case of imagining, where there is an
ongoing duality of coexisting distinct perspectives: the actual subject, doing the framing, is still
in the picture at the same time as the notional subject roams free in the imagined world. But
even if this is possible in imagining, it will not explain vicarious dreaming: in vicarious dreams,
there is no actual subject distinct from the notional subject during the dream. The dream
protagonist is the holder of the center of perspective, and the waking self is not represented
in the dream. When the protagonist uses a rst-person pronoun, it points out the center of
perspective: other perspectives, such that of the waking self, are not involved. This contrasts
with the case of imagining as described by Velleman, in which the waking self has a real world
perspective whilst adopting the imaginary world perspective. In such dream experience is there
is only one perspective, that of the dream protagonist.
So vicarious dreams are not analogous to imagining being someone else. Perhaps we are
left with the possibility that the dream protagonist is a temporary separate entity, a eeting
self (Rosen 2012). We leave this open as a live option, but nish with one further note
about the idea that there is no subject or self at all in such dreams. Even such a diehard
realist about dream experience as Antti Revonsuo, discussing dreams in general rather than
vicarious dreams in particular, offers a line of thought which might support this notion.
Revonsuo argues that it is only with the subsequent waking reconstruction of a dream
experience on the basis of memory traces that a sense of ownership of the dream arises:
only at that point do I feel that this experience originally took place in the same system
of conscious experience in which my current experiences take place.Thisideathatthe
dream becomes my experience only after the original experience is long gonehas, as
Revonsuo notes, the striking consequence that there is no sense of ownership of
unremembered dreams: they were experiences in my brain, but their potential to be my
experiences is unactualized (2005, pp.209210).
The two unusual dream phenomena we have discussed external perspectives and
vicarious dreams are much less common than ordinary dreams in which the dreamer is
straightforwardly represented in the dream protagonist. Yet they appear to occur in a
signicant minority of dreams, and plausibly more for some dreamers and in some
circumstances than others. They need to be incorporated into our best understanding of
the nature of self-representation in dreams. We have suggested some speciclinesof
enquiry in each case, along with some direct connections to parallel but strangely
disconnected literatures on remembering and imagining. We see dreaming as a fruitful
domain for integrative, naturalistic work at the interface between philosophy and the
cognitive sciences.
Acknowledgments
Our thanks to Glenn Carruthers, Max Coltheart, Helen Gillespie, Chris McCarroll, and
Peter Menzies, as well as to an anonymous reviewer for helpful comments and suggestions,
and to Ron Mallon and Edouard Machery.
1050 Perspectives in Dreams
© 2013 The Authors
Philosophy Compass © 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Philosophy Compass 8/11 (2013): 10411053, 10.1111/phc3.12082
Short Biographies
Melanie Rosen is interested in the intersection between philosophy and cognitive science.
Her research takes a broad focus toward the philosophy of mind, consciousness, the self,
and the relevance of our scientic knowledge of the brain and cognition. Rosen completed
a BABFA (Fine Arts and Philosophy Conjoint) and MA (Philosophy) at Auckland University
and recently in 2013, graduated from her PhD at Macquarie University, Sydney. Her thesis
titled Dream Pluralism: A Philosophy of the Dreaming Mindfocused on dreaming and its
relevance for philosophy and cognitive science. Rosen argued that a pluralistic approach to
the wide variety of cognitive phenomena that occur during sleep can help further our under-
standing of a variety of cognitive states. Dreaming is a conscious state that involves interesting
features such as body representation in absence of the real, waking body, and a variety of cog-
nitive defects that provide insight into the self, consciousness and cognition. She is currently
teaching at Macquarie University and the Australian Catholic University and does research at
the Australian Commonwealth Scientic and Industrial Research Organization (CSIRO).
Her teaching interests range from ethics to metaphysics, philosophy of mind and critical
thinking. She won the 2009 International Association for the Study of Dreams (IASD) paper
prize and is currently preparing further papers on dreaming.
John Sutton is Professor of Cognitive Science at Macquarie University, Sydney, where he
was previously head of the Department of Philosophy. His degrees are in Classics from
Oxford and in Philosophy from Sydney, and he has held visiting fellowships at UCLA,
UCSD, Edinburgh, and Warwick. His research centers on memory, both in and at the inter-
sections of philosophy, the cognitive sciences, and the social sciences. His book Philosophy and
Memory Traces: Descartes to Connectionism (Cambridge) was reissued in paperback in 2007, and
he is coeditor of DescartesNatural Philosophy (Routledge, 2000) and of the interdisciplinary
journal Memory Studies. His recent work addresses distributed cognition, collaborative and
social memory, perspective in autobiographical memory, skilled movement and embodied
cognition, and cognitive history.
Note
*Correspondence: Cognitive Science, Macquarie University. Email: john.sutton@mq.edu.au.
Works Cited
Berntsen, Dorthe and David C. Rubin. Emotion and Vantage Point in Autobiographical Memory.Cognition and
Emotion 20 (2006): 11931215.
Blackmore, Susan. Where Am I? Perspectives in Imagery and the Out-of-Body Experience.Journal of Mental Imagery
11.2 (1987): 5366.
——.A Theory of Lucid Dreams and OBEs.Conscious Mind, Sleeping Brain: Perspectives on Lucid Dreaming. Eds. Jayne
Gackenbach and Stephen LaBerge. New York: Plenum Press, 1988. 373387.
Blanke, Olaf and Thomas Metzinger. Full-Body Illusions and Minimal Phenomenal Selfhood.Trends in Cognitive
Sciences 13 (2009): 713.
Blanke, Olaf and Christine Mohr. Out-of-Body Experience, Heautoscopy, and Autoscopic Hallucination of
Neurological Origin: Implications for Neurocognitive Mechanisms of Corporeal Awareness and Self-
Consciousness.Brain Research Reviews 50 (2005): 184199.
Brugger, Peter. Reective Mirrors: Perspective-Taking in Autoscopic Phenomena.Cognitive Neuropsychiatry
7.3 (2002): 179194.
Callow, Nicola and Lew Hardy. The Relationship between the Use of Kinaesthetic Imagery and Different Visual Im-
agery Perspectives.Journal of Sports Sciences 22 (2004): 167177.
Child, William. Dreaming, Calculating, Thinking: Wittgenstein and Anti-Realism about the Past.Philosophical
Quarterly 57 (2007): 252272.
Perspectives in Dreams 1051
© 2013 The Authors
Philosophy Compass © 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Philosophy Compass 8/11 (2013): 10411053, 10.1111/phc3.12082
Churchland, Patricia Smith. Reduction and the Neurobiological Basis of Consciousness.Consciousness in Contemporary
Science, Eds. A. J. Marcel and E. J. Bisiach. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988. 273304.
Cicogna, PierCarla and Marino Bosinelli. Consciousness during Dreams.Consciousness and Cognition 10 (2001): 2641.
Clark, Andy. The Twisted Matrix: Dream, Simulation, or Hybrid?Philosophers Explore the Matrix. Ed. C. Grau. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2005. 177197.
Colace, Claudio. Childrens Dreams: From Freuds Observations to Modern Dream Research. London: Karnac Books, 2010.
Colombetti, Giovanna. The Feeling Body: Affective Science Meets the Enactive Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2013.
Cook, Roger F. Correspondences in Visual Imaging and Spatial Orientation in Dreaming and Film Viewing.Dreaming
21.2 (2011): 89104.
Craver, Carl. Explaining the Brain: Mechanisms and the Mosaic Unity of Neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2007.
Debus, Dorothea. Perspectives on the Past: A Study of the Spatial Perspectival Characteristics of Recollective
Memories.Mind & Language 22.2 (2007): 173206.
Dennett, Daniel C. Are Dreams Experiences?Philosophical Review 73 (1976): 15171.
Domhoff, G. William. The Scientic Study of Dreams: Neural Networks, Cognitive Development, and Content Analysis.
Washington, DC: American Psychological Association, 2003.
Flanagan, Owen. Dreaming Souls: Sleep, Dreams, and the Evolution of the Conscious Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.
Foulkes, David. Dreaming and Consciousness.European Journal of Cognitive Psychology 2 (1990): 3955.
——.Childrens Dreaming and the Development of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1999.
Foulkes, D., M. Hollield, L. Bradley, R. Terry, and B. Sullivan. Waking Self-Understanding, REM-Dream Self
Representation, and Cognitive Ability Variables at Age 58.Dreaming 1 (1991): 4151.
Foulkes, David and Nancy H. Kerr. Point of View in Nocturnal Dreaming.Perceptual and Motor Skills 78 (1994): 690.
Gerrans, Philip. Dream Experience and a Revisionist Account of Delusions of Misidentication.Consciousness and
Cognition 21 (2012): 217227.
Goldie, Peter. The Mess Inside: Narrative, Emotion, and the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012.
Grifths, Paul. What Emotions Really Are. Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1998.
Hobson, J. Allan, Edward F. Pace-Schott, and Robert Stickgold. Dreaming and the Brain: Toward a Cognitive
Neuroscience of Conscious States.Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23 (2000): 793842.
Horton, Caroline L.. Recall and Recognition of Dreams and Waking Events: A Diary Paradigm.International Journal of
Dream Research 4(1) (2011): 816.
Horton, Caroline L, Christopher J.A. Moulin, and Martin A. Conway. The Self and Dreams during a Period of
Transition.Consciousness and Cognition 18 (2009): 710717.
Ichikawa, Jonathan. Dreaming and Imagination.Mind and Language 24.1 (2009): 103121.
Irwin, Harvey J. Perceptual Perspective of Visual Imagery in OBEs, Dreams and Reminiscence.Journal of the Society for
Psychical Research 53 (1986): 210217.
Kenny, L.M., R.A. Bryant, D. Silove, M. Creamer, M. ODonnell, and A.C. McFarlane. Distant Memories: A
Prospective Study of Vantage Point of Trauma Memories.Psychological Science 20 (2009): 10491052.
LaBerge, Stephen and Donald J. DeGracia. Varieties of Lucid Dreaming Experience.Individual Differences in Conscious
Experience. Eds. R.G. Kunzendorf and B. Wallace. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 2000. 269307.
Libby, Lisa K. and Richard P. Eibach. Visual Perspective in Mental Imagery: A Representational Tool That Functions
in Judgment, Emotion, and Self-Insight.Advances in Experimental Social Psychology volume 44. Eds. M.P. Zanna and J.
M. Olson. San Diego: Academic Press, 2011. 185245.
Locke, John. An Essay concerning Human Understanding. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975 (originally published 1690).
McIsaac, Heather K. and Eric Eich. Vantage Point in Traumatic Memory.Psychological Science 15.4 (2004): 248253.
Mackenzie, Catriona. Imagination, Identity, and Self-Transformation.Practical Identity and Narrative Agency. Eds. K.
Atkins and C. Mackenzie. London: Routledge, 2008, 121145.
McNamara, Patrick, Deirdre McLaren, and Kate Durso. Representation of the Self in REM and NREM Dreams.
Dreaming 17.2 (2007): 113126.
Malcolm, Norman. Dreaming. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1959.
Metzinger, Thomas. Being No-one: The Self-Model Theory of Subjectivity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2004.
——.Out-of-Body Experiences as the Origin of the Concept of a Soul.Mind & Matter 3.1 (2005): 5784.
Mishara, Aaron L. Autoscopy: Disrupted Self in Neuropsychiatric Disorders and Anomalous Conscious States.
Handbook of Phenomenology and Cognitive Science. Eds S. Gallagher and D. Schmicking. Berlin: Springer, 2010.
591634.
Morris, Tony and Michael Spittle. A Default Hypothesis of the Development of Internal and External Imagery
Perspectives.Journal of Mental Imagery 36.1-2 (2012): 130.
Nigro, Georgia and Ulric Neisser. Point of View in Personal Memories.Cognitive Psychology 15 (1983): 467482.
1052 Perspectives in Dreams
© 2013 The Authors
Philosophy Compass © 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Philosophy Compass 8/11 (2013): 10411053, 10.1111/phc3.12082
Nir, Yuval and Giulio Tononi. Dreaming and the Brain: From Phenomenology to Neurophysiology.Trends in
Cognitive Sciences 14.2 (2010): 88100.
Occhionero, Miranda. Mental Processes and the Brain During Dreams.Dreaming 14.1 (2004): 5464.
Occhionero, Miranda and Piera Carla Cicogna. Autoscopic Phenomena and Ones Own Body Representation in
Dreams.Consciousness and Cognition 20 (2011): 10091015.
Occhionero, Miranda, Piera Carla Cicogna, Vincenzo Natale, Maria José Esposito, and Marino Bosinelli.
Representation of Self in SWS and REM Dreams.Sleep and Hypnosis 7.2 (2005): 7783.
Revonsuo, Antti. Consciousness, Dreams, and Virtual Realities.Philosophical Psychology 8 (1995): 3558.
——.The Self in Dreams.The Lost Self: Pathologies of the Brain and Identity. Eds. Todd E. Feinberg and Julian Paul
Keenan. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2005. 206219.
Revonsuo, Antti and Krista Tarkko. Binding in Dreams: The Bizarreness of Dream Images and the Unity of
Consciousness.Journal of Consciousness Studies 9.7 (2002): 324.
Rice, Heather J. and David C. Rubin. I can see it Both Ways: First- and Third-Person Visual Perspectives at Retrieval.
Consciousness and Cognition 18 (2009): 877890.
——.Remembering from any Angle: The Flexibility of Visual Perspective During Retrieval. Consciousness and
Cognition 20 (2011): 568577.
Rosen, Melanie. Dream Pluralism: A Philosophy of the Dreaming Mind. PhD thesis, Macquarie University,
Sydney, 2012.
Schönhammer, Rainer. Typical Dreams: Reections of Arousal.Journal of Consciousness Studies 12 (2005): 1837.
Schwartz, S., T.T. Dang-Vu, A. Ponz, S. Duhoux, and P. Maquet. Dreaming: A Neuropsychological View.Schweizer
Archiv für Neurologie und Psychiatrie 156 (2005): 426439.
Solms, Mark. The Neuropsychology of Dreams: A Clinico-Anatomical Study. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1997.
Soper, Barlow. A Comparison of Daydream and Dream Perspectives.College Student Journal 33 (1999): 217218.
Soper, Barlow, Gary E. Milford, and Gary T. Rosenthal. Dream Perspective: A Research Note.Journal of Mental
Imagery 18 (1994): 181182.
Sosa, Ernest. Dreams and Philosophy.Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 79.2 (2005): 718.
Sterelny, Kim and Paul E. Grifths. Sex and Death: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Biology. Chicago: Chicago
University Press, 1999.
Stickgold, Robert and J. Allan Hobson. Home Monitoring of Sleep Onset and Sleep-Onset Mentation Using' the
Nightcap. Sleep Onset: Normal and Abnormal Processes. Eds. R.D. Ogilvie and J.R. Harsh. Washington, DC: American
Psychological Association, 1994. 141160.
Strauch, Inge and Barbara Meier. In Search of Dreams: Results of Experimental Dream Research. Albany, NY: State
University of New York Press, 1996.
Sutton, John. Dreaming.The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Psychology. Eds. J. Symons and P. Calvo. London:
Routledge, 2009. 522542.
——.Observer Perspective and Acentred Memory: Some Puzzles about Point of View in Personal Memory.Philosophical
Studies 148 (2010): 2737.
——.Memory Before the Game: Switching Perspectives in Imagining and Remembering Sport and Movement.
Journal of Mental Imagery 36 (2012): 8595.
Tversky, Barbara. Visualizing Thought. Topics in Cognitive Science 3.3 (2011): 499535.
Valberg, J.J. Dream, Death, and the Self. Princeton: Princeton UP, 2007.
Valli, Katja. Dreaming in the Multilevel Framework.Consciousness and Cognition 20 (2011): 10841090.
Velleman, David. Self to Self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
Vendler, Zeno. Vicarious Experience.Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 84 (1979): 161173.
Williams, Bernard. Imagination and the Self.InProblems of the Self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
(1973), 2645.
Windt, Jennifer M. The Immersive Spatiotemporal Hallucination Model of Dreaming.Phenomenology and the Cognitive
Sciences 9 (2010): 295316.
Windt, Jennifer M. and Thomas Metzinger. The Philosophy of Dreaming and Self-Consciousness: What Happens to
the Experiential Subject during the Dream State?.The New Science of Dreaming, vol. 3: Cultural and Theoretical Perspec-
tives. Eds. D. Barrett and P. McNamara. Westport, CT: Praeger-Greenwood, 2007, 193247.
Windt, Jennifer M. and Valdas Noreika. How to Integrate Dreaming into a General Theory of Consciousness: A
Critical Review of Existing Positions and Suggestions for Future Research.Consciousness and Cognition 20
(2011): 10911107.
Perspectives in Dreams 1053
© 2013 The Authors
Philosophy Compass © 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Philosophy Compass 8/11 (2013): 10411053, 10.1111/phc3.12082
... It is currently accepted that dreams are experiences that occur during sleep (Rosen & Sutton, 2013), although beyond this there is much disagreement. Dreams have been described as hallucinogenic delirium (Hobson, 2004), virtual reality involving illusions (Windt, 2010(Windt, , 2017, imagination (Ichikawa, 2008(Ichikawa, , 2016Sosa, 2005), a state that shifts between imagination, hallucination and illusion (Rosen, 2018(Rosen, , 2021a(Rosen, , 2024, or a sui generis state unlike the aforementioned (Thompson, 2016;Windt, 2015Windt, , 2021. ...
... The assumption of a sharp distinction between the dreamed self and the dreamer is not a very plausible interpretation of common dreams. Although one might argue that the same brain can generate distinct individuals at different times (Rosen & Sutton, 2013) or distinct conscious streams simultaneously (Nagel, 1971;Schechter, 2018), the relationship between the dreamed self and the dreamer is more in continuity than in dissociation (Rosen & Sutton, 2013;Schredl & Hofmann, 2003) since individuals usually identify the dream self as the same person as their waking selves (Schredl, 2020). Dream selves usually look like and behave as the waking selves do. ...
... The assumption of a sharp distinction between the dreamed self and the dreamer is not a very plausible interpretation of common dreams. Although one might argue that the same brain can generate distinct individuals at different times (Rosen & Sutton, 2013) or distinct conscious streams simultaneously (Nagel, 1971;Schechter, 2018), the relationship between the dreamed self and the dreamer is more in continuity than in dissociation (Rosen & Sutton, 2013;Schredl & Hofmann, 2003) since individuals usually identify the dream self as the same person as their waking selves (Schredl, 2020). Dream selves usually look like and behave as the waking selves do. ...
Article
Full-text available
When we dream, we feel emotions in response to objects and events that exist only in the dream. One key question is whether these emotions can be said to be “essentially unfitting”, that is, always inappropriate to the evoking scenario. However, how we evaluate dream emotions for fittingness may depend on the model of dreams we adopt: the imagination or the hallucination model. If fittingness requires a match between emotion and evaluative properties of objects or events, it is prima facie plausible that dream emotions could fail to fit under the imagination model because it is unfitting to have an emotion toward an object we do not believe to be real. Under the hallucination model, dream emotions could be unfitting because their objects do not exist but we believe them to be real. More nuance, however, is required. By comparing dream emotions with the emotions we experience while imagining, engaging with fiction, and hallucinating, we conclude that although there are compelling arguments in support of the claim that dream emotions are essentially unfitting, these arguments are not entirely convincing, and it is more plausible that particular dream emotions can be assessed for fittingness under either model of dreaming.
... If a dreamer does indeed experience poor binding due to altered cognitive capacities, we might expect poor attention to also be a feature, resulting in the mismatch going unnoticed. Such dreams might even involve a disconnection between the dream self and waking self (Rosen & Sutton, 2013). In such cases, a PE occurs only after waking when the memory of the dream conflicts with what the dreamer predicts should have happened during such an occurrence. ...
Article
Full-text available
It is widely known that dreams can be strongly affected by traumatic events, but there may be other ways in which dreams relate to trauma. In this paper, we argue that different types of dreams could both contribute to trauma and alleviate it according to the prediction errors that occur either in dreams or in response to them after waking. A prediction error occurs when an experience contradicts one’s expectation and it is often accompanied by surprise. Prediction errors are involved in memory updating processes that can be long-lasting. Not only nightmares but also unpleasant, and surprisingly, even neutral and pleasant dreams have the potential to contribute to trauma, affecting our waking lives in a similar way to waking traumatic experiences. We postulate that certain dreams can also be beneficial for trauma alleviation. Further, clinical evidence suggests that working with prediction errors that occurred in dreams and during our response to dreams after waking can assist in alleviating the negative effects of trauma.
... If a dreamer does indeed experience poor binding due to altered cognitive capacities, we might expect poor attention to also be a feature, resulting in the mismatch going unnoticed. Such dreams might even involve a disconnection between the dream self and waking self (Rosen & Sutton, 2013). In such cases, a PE occurs only after waking when the memory of the dream conflicts with what the dreamer predicts should have happened during such an occurrence. ...
Book
Full-text available
Michelle Maiese: Trauma, dissociation, and relational authenticity Caroline Christoff: Performative trauma narratives: Imperfect memories and epistemic harms Aisha Qadoos: Ambiguous loss: A loved one's trauma Alberto Guerrero Velazquez: El trauma está en la respuesta. Hacia una visión post-causal en la definición de trauma psicológico Clarita Bonamino, Sophie Boudrias, and Melanie Rosen: Dreams, trauma, and prediction errors Gabriel Corda: Memoria episódica y trastorno de estrés postraumático en animales no humanos: una propuesta metodológica María López Ríos, Christopher Jude McCarroll, and Paloma Muñoz Gómez: Memory, mourning, and the Chilean constitution Sergio Daniel Rojas-Sierra, and Tito Hernando Pérez Pérez: Subjetividades rememorantes, marcas narrativas y trauma cultural en la construcción de memoria de desmovilizados de las FARC-EP en el AETCR Pondores Germán Bonanni: Y después de la guerra... ¿Qué?
... 10. Subjects sometimes experience Dream Self acts from the third-person (see M. Rosen & Sutton 2013). Sometimes perspectives switch (Cicogna & Bosinelli 2001). ...
Article
Full-text available
Are subjects ever morally responsible for their dreams? In this paper I argue that if, as some theories of dreams entail, dreaming subjects sometimes express agency while they dream, then they are sometimes morally responsible for what they do and are potentially worthy of praise and blame while they dream and after they have awoken. I end by noting the practical and theoretical implications of my argument.
... 210-211). Another summary article, reflecting on not just the frequency but also the potency of "first-person" dreams, notes that "among an array of robust findings, psychologists have shown that, in general, [dream] memories retrieved from an 'own-eyes' or field perspective" are not only much more common but also tend to "contain more information on emotional and other subjective states than [dream] memories recalled from an observer perspective" (Rosen & Sutton, 2013, p. 1044. Still another summary article, richly informed by film and media theory, explores not just differences but "correspondences between the cinematic image and the kinematic imagery of dreams"; citing work that dates back to the early 1980s, the author suggests that experience with cinema possibly has had "a profound effect on both the content and form of our dreams," but he suggests as well, and more credibly, that typical dream imagery-almost always seen from the perspective of what he calls "the embedded viewer"-has had a profound effect on cinema (Cook, 2011, pp. ...
Article
Full-text available
Oneiric sequences have figured into cinema almost from the medium’s inception. In modern cinema, music often plays a key role in helping audiences distinguish between action that is supposedly “real” and action, whether enacted or recalled, that amounts to “just a dream.” However, the convention of announcing a forthcoming dream scene by means of relatively strange music had a clear starting point in the 1940s, contemporaneous with the introduction of Freudian–Jungian dream theory into the mainstream of popular culture. How, one wonders, were dreams “signalled” in earlier cinema? This essay discusses filmic dream scenes in general, and in passing it notes—as readers of this journal surely know—that almost invariably the content of filmic dreams bears little relationship to what dreamers in fact experience. But the focus here is not on the content of filmic dreams but on their presentation, especially during the premodern era of the so-called silent film. Drawing on evidence from such diverse sources as published collections of “photoplay music” and animated cartoons from the 1930s, this essay suggests that the framing of cinematic dreams in films from the early decades of the 20th century was not at all like what audiences of today perhaps take for granted.
Chapter
Full-text available
In his 1925 book Les cadres sociaux de la mémoire (The Social Frameworks of Memory), the French sociologist Maurice Halbwachs (1877–1945) developed a sustained comparison between remembering and dreaming. Drawing on a new first full English translation of this material, this chapter assesses Halbwachs’ critique of individualism about memory, his scientifically-informed analysis of dream experience, and his ambitious program for a sociological psychology. In work relevant both to contemporary dream science and to approaches to memory inspired by distributed and 4E cognitive theory, Halbwachs argues that dreaming is a natural experiment that tests the cognitive powers of the isolated brain, and that its fragmentary nature confirms that social frameworks are necessary for rich memory experience. Remembering is an activity that involves significant cognitive work in context. Having rejected individualism, Halbwachs offers a more subtle account of dreams as retaining some minimal orientation to society, space, and time. In sharp contrast to prevailing assumptions that Halbwachs ignored individual psychology, his intriguing account of dreams and his social ontology of memory offer rich materials for contemporary integrative approaches to dreaming and remembering across the social and the cognitive sciences.
Chapter
What is it to remember a dream accurately? This paper argues that neither of the two available concepts of mnemic accuracy, namely, truth and authenticity, enables us to answer this question and that a new understanding of accuracy is therefore needed: a dream memory is accurate not when it is true or authentic but rather when it is “faithful” to the remembered dream. In addition to memory for dreams, the paper applies the notion of faithfulness to memory for perceptual experiences, memory for imaginations, and memory for hallucinations and briefly considers the broader implications of adopting an understanding of mnemic accuracy as faithfulness.
Chapter
How skeptical should we be of dream memory? It’s hard to deny that some form of conscious experience occurs while we sleep that leaves memory traces which are reported on waking. However, a form of weak skepticism towards dream reports is warranted: many of the reports we make on waking are not of conscious episodes that occurred during sleep. Instead, we become conscious of most ‘dreams’ only upon waking. This is because both memory and other cognitive capacities in dreams can be severely degraded. The conditions under which mental events occur in sleep might prevent such processes from making it to the ‘global workspace’ or, alternatively, they may lack ‘access consciousness’. This makes it possible that when a subject is woken up during rapid eye movement (REM) sleep, they become retroactively conscious of dreams, an updated version of Dennett’s cassette theory of dreaming. According to this weak skeptical view, most dream reports are of, in some sense, false memories.
Chapter
When we are awake, we occupy a spatiotemporal perspective, and while occupying that spatiotemporal perspective we can simultaneously exercise a capacity to represent a distinct spatiotemporal perspective that we do not occupy—for example, when we imagine or recollect events. The first half of the paper compares and contrasts the ways in which this capacity is exercised in imagination and episodic recollection. The second half of the paper draws on the above accounts in order to frame hypotheses about the ways in which perspectives can feature in dreams. The paper argues that some unusual and distinctive features of dreams can be explained by making intelligible the idea that it is possible to represent a spatiotemporal perspective while failing to meet the conditions required for occupying a such perspective. In such circumstances, one fails to occupy a conscious perspective that makes possible even the minimal orienting knowledge ‘I am here now’.
Chapter
Dream experiences are heterogenous and involve a complex and varied phenomenology. While mental states like belief and desire can be easily characterised by their attitudes and contents, dreaming seems to involve a variety of attitudes, including beliefs, desires, and more. How do we make sense of dreaming itself as well as its relationship to the attitudes involved? We outline an attitudinal pluralism about dreaming. Attitudinal pluralism is the view that the dream self can adopt a variety of attitudes—beliefs, desires, hopes, fears, etc.—towards the content of the dreamscape. On this view, there are multiple attitudes that the dream self can adopt within the simulated dream world. The best way to understand this pluralism is not by narrowly taking dreaming to just involve thinking itself, but rather by taking dreaming to involve a dream self experiencing thoughts within the dream. The attitudes belong to the dream self (the character one identifies with in the dream) not the dreamer per se (the sleeping subject). This attitudinal pluralism has consequences for thinking about the nature of dream experiences and the content of dream memories. First, the attitudes we experience as part of the dream world seem to go beyond mere phenomenology and may be part of the ontological structure of dream experiences. Second, accuracy in dream memories will involve recalling the various attitudes that one adopted while dreaming. Understood in this way, accuracy in dream memory requires a condition of authenticity, such that the dream memory represents not just the content of the dreamscape, but the way in which the dream subject experienced the dream world. Accurate dream memories will be authentic dream memories.
Book
Full-text available
This book presents a new neurocognitive model of dreams that draws from empirical research to explain the process of dreaming and the nature of dream content. Until now, dream studies have been limited in their usefulness, but recent advances in neuroscience, dream content analysis, cognitive linguistics, statistics, and computer software have made it possible to revitalize this area of research with the use of scientific methods. G. W. Domhoff's model helps explain the neural and cognitive bases for dreaming. He discusses how dreams express conceptions and concerns and how they are consistent over years and decades. He also shows that there may be limits to understanding the meaning of dreams, as there are many aspects of dream content that cannot be related to waking cognition or personal concerns. In addition, the book includes a detailed explanation of the methods needed to test the new model as well as a case study of a comprehensive dream journal. A new system of content analysis that can be used for highly sophisticated studies is discussed.
Chapter
The Matrix is a computer-generated dreamworld built to keep us under control. -Morpheus, early in The Matrix In dreaming, you are not only out of control, you don’t even know it I was completely duped again and again the minute my pons, my amygdala, my perihippocampal cortex, my anterior cingulate, my visual association and parietal opercular cortices were revved up and my dorsolateral prefrontal cortex was muffled.
Chapter
Lucid dreams have much in common with out-of-body experiences, or OBEs. Harvey Irwin has described, elsewhere in this book, the empirical evidence for similarities and statistical relationships between the two experiences. I believe these relationships are important: so much so that any theory of one experience must also be able to account for the other.KeywordsBody ImageSensory InputMental ImageryTestable PredictionAltered StateThese keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.