ArticlePDF Available

Invisible-hand explanations: From blindness to lack of we-ness

Authors:

Abstract

The unintendedness of the phenomenon that is to be explained is a constraint visible in the various applications and clarifications of invisible-hand explanations. The article casts doubt on such a requirement and proposes a revised account. To have a role in an invisible-hand process, it is argued, agents may very well act with a view to contributing to the occurrence of the social outcome that is to be explained, provided they see what they do as an aggregation of their individual actions rather than as something they jointly perform.
http://ssi.sagepub.com/
Social Science Information
http://ssi.sagepub.com/content/52/3/450
The online version of this article can be found at:
DOI: 10.1177/0539018413482536
2013 52: 450Social Science Information
Emma Tieffenbach
Invisible-hand explanations: From blindness to lack of we-ness
Published by:
http://www.sagepublications.com
On behalf of:
Maison des Sciences de l'Homme
can be found at:Social Science InformationAdditional services and information for
http://ssi.sagepub.com/cgi/alertsEmail Alerts:
http://ssi.sagepub.com/subscriptionsSubscriptions:
http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navReprints:
http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navPermissions:
http://ssi.sagepub.com/content/52/3/450.refs.htmlCitations:
What is This?
- Aug 5, 2013Version of Record >>
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
Social Science Information
52(3) 450–470
© The Author(s) 2013
Reprints and permissions:
sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav
DOI: 10.1177/0539018413482536
ssi.sagepub.com
Invisible-hand explanations:
From blindness to lack of
we-ness
Emma Tieffenbach
University of Geneva, Switzerland
Abstract
The unintendedness of the phenomenon that is to be explained is a constraint visible
in the various applications and clarifications of invisible-hand explanations. The article
casts doubt on such a requirement and proposes a revised account. To have a role in an
invisible-hand process, it is argued, agents may very well act with a view to contributing
to the occurrence of the social outcome that is to be explained, provided they see what
they do as an aggregation of their individual actions rather than as something they jointly
perform.
Keywords
collective intentionality, conventions, David Lewis, invisible-hand explanations, joint
action, unintended consequences
Résumé
La non-intentionnalité du phénomène à expliquer est une contrainte évidente dans
les diverses explications par la main-invisible ainsi que dans les clarifications qui en
ont été présentées. L’article jette un doute sur une telle exigence et en propose
une représentation révisée. Pour jouer un rôle dans un processus de main-invisible,
affirme l’auteur, les agents peuvent très bien agir en vue de contribuer à l’occurrence
de l’effet qu’il faut expliquer, à partir du moment où ils voient ce qu’ils font comme la
simple agrégation de leurs actions individuelles plutôt que comme quelque chose qu’ils
accomplissent conjointement.
Mots-clés
action conjointe, conséquences inattendues, conventions, David Lewis, explications par
la main-invisible, intentionnalité collective
Corresponding author:
Emma Tieffenbach, University of Geneva – Centre Interfacultaire en Sciences affectives, 7 rue des Battoirs,
Geneva 1205, Switzerland.
Email: emma.tieffenbach@unige.ch
482536SSI52310.1177/0539018413482536Social Science InformationTieffenbach
2013
Trends and developments/Courants et tendances
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
Tieffenbach 451
While investigating the nature of collective intentions, John Searle (1990) offers the
example of some businessmen who are familiar with Adam Smith’s theory of the invis-
ible hand. Having learned in business school that the best way for them to help humanity
is by pursuing their selfish interest, they consequently each form an intention to this
effect. Searle intends this example to show the following: although the businessmen
pursue the same ultimate goal and are mutually aware of each other’s interdependent
intention, they can nevertheless not be adequately described as acting together. Helping
humanity is something each businessman intends to do, albeit individually rather than
jointly. A we-intention, the example purports to show, is not the sum of I-intentions,
however intricate and goal-converging the latter might be. It is, as Searle also says, a
primitive notion.
The example deserves attention for another reason as well. It construes the theory of
the invisible hand as an anti-We-ness theory. Wealth could be redistributed just as well,
the example indeed shows, even if the wealthiest had no inclination to act together to this
effect even if they were not inclined to ask themselves ‘what shall we do to help
humanity?’ rather than ‘what shall I do?’ The invisible hand is presented as a theory that
considers the capacity to act jointly as a superfluous component of the way the social
world works.
This article expands on the second idea, that of defining the invisible hand as an anti-
We-ness theory, by making use of the anti-reductivist view about collective intentionality
that Searle, among others, defends. In other words, I show that agents who are led by the
invisible hand are not allowed to act jointly provided and to the extent that joint actions
are different from an aggregation of individual actions. I show that approaching the
invisible hand in this manner entails a deep revision of its standard account. It entails in
particular a rejection of the idea that the invisible hand is about the unintended conse-
quences of actions that are directed toward other ends. Or, rather: although unintended-
ness is a sufficient feature of invisible-hand consequences, it turns out not to be a
necessary one.
The standard account and its problem
The invisible hand, as I first specify, has two facets. It is, on the one hand, well known as
a normative theory, one that some invoke in order to defend the privatization of public
goods, free entrepreneurship, and restricting state intervention in the economic, cultural
or political realms. It is also, on the other hand, an explanatory theory, one that conveys
a particular understanding of social outcomes, independently of the way they should be
obtained. I am presently interested in the other face of the invisible hand, that is, in its
explanatory value. Whether institutions ought to be left to the guidance of the invisible
hand or not is a question I do not address. Nor do I say anything about the relation
between the two sides of the invisible hand, that is, whether endorsing it as an explana-
tory device commits you in any manner to accepting it as a political principle. I focus on
invisible-hand explanations (IHE) and in particular on one of the constraints, namely the
unintendedness of the outcome that is to be explained, that one allegedly needs to meet
in order to provide an explanation of that type.
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
452 Social Science Information 52(3)
Instead of the well-known paradigm cases – Carl Menger’s account of money (1892),
Robert Nozick’s state-of-nature story of about how the state could arise (1974) or Thomas
Schelling’s checkerboard city (1969) the less canonical example of John Millar’s
explanation of the end of slavery (2006 [1771]) is our illustrative case. It is an account
which Millar, a member of the Scottish Enlightenment and disciple of Adam Smith, pro-
vides in the final chapter of his The Origin of the Distinction of Ranks (2006 [1771]:
262–282). In the beginning, Millar explains, slaves were owned in limited numbers.
They were located near their master’s house and worked under close supervision. New
conquests, however, brought in new slaves, who had to be housed further away. Because
they ceased to be closely watched over, the productivity of the slaves decreased, calling
for more coercive measures. Owning slaves turned out to be a more costly enterprise
than it had been before. Slave owners thus had to find an alternative way to make slaves
work, and they came up with the following idea: the slaves would be offered a reward in
proportion to the amount of work they performed. Slavery was brought to an end, in
Millar’s view, when hiring slaves became less costly than coercing them.1
Millar’s explanation is an invisible-hand explanation insofar as it dispenses with a
designing intelligence (Ullmann-Margalit, 1978). The end of slavery, Millar shows, need
not be first represented in someone’s mind as a blueprint, and then be put into effect
according to some establishment program. Millar describes the end of slavery as the
result of a process during which agents were not guided though their choices by the
Church, or by some Great Men. His account traces back the responsibility for the extinc-
tion of slavery to the slave owners, who acted in the light of what their personal interest
dictated, unaided in this task by any third-party enforcer. More crucially, his account
suggests how superfluous such authoritative intervention would have been. Had a central
authority endorsed the goal of banning slavery, the slave owners would have been given
a further incentive to choose an option, e.g. to pay their slaves, that they quite indepen-
dently had a reason to find attractive.
A decree is not the only explanatory hypothesis Millar means to dismiss. He also intends
to undermine an account that relies on the capacity of agents to engage in joint actions. The
end of slavery is not a shared goal, that is, something agents collectively agreed to put an
end to. There are no angry slaves purposefully joining forces with a shared view to subvert
the system. There are no slave owners mutually agreeing to end the practice of slavery after
having discussed its various advantages and disadvantages. Absent from the account is any
Lockean express agreement between the participants. The end of slavery is the result of
each slave owner’s similar but uncoordinated choice to resort to a new behavioural control
system, one based on material reward rather than compulsion.
Another feature of Millar’s explanation is that it involves agents who are strikingly
unaware of what each of their actions will ultimately bring about. Neither the slave own-
ers nor their slaves have the end of slavery in mind while acting. Of course neither of
them are entirely blind since they have goals and are able to assess whether they achieve
them or not. But the goal they individually pursue happens to be different from the large-
scale social pattern that they produce, and the latter is the outcome that is to be explained.
This is, by all accounts, what invisible-hand explanations do. Invisible-hand explana-
tions are consensually defined as accounting for some social outcomes in terms of the
actions of many individuals who, as Nozick says, do ‘not have that outcome in mind’
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
Tieffenbach 453
(1974: 14, 19) while acting. In her path-breaking article on invisible-hand explanations,
Ullmann-Margalit also takes the same restrictive view. She says that agents cannot be
aware, and hence foresee the overall effects, of their actions (1978: 271). According to
Raimo Tuomela’s conception as well, the unintended nature of the pattern to be explained
amounts to a lack of consciousness on the part of agents about what they are doing.
Invisible-hand explanations, he says, involve ‘many individuals who are supposed to be
minding (only) their own business unaware of and hence not intending to bring about the
ultimate overall outcome’ (1984: 451). Uskali Mäki (1990) also subscribes to this view
when he defines an invisible-hand consequence as one that lies outside the agents’
‘sphere of intendedness’. Unintendedness is therefore a constraint visible in the various
applications and clarifications of invisible-hand explanations. The standard account (SA)
can be summarized as follows:
SA: An IHE is intended to explain a consequence of many actions performed by agents who do
not have it in mind.
This way of characterizing the invisible hand raises a difficulty, however. It puts for-
ward a constraint that is not obviously met by paradigm cases. The very capacity of
invisible-hand explanations to persuasively present their explanandum as an unintended
consequence has been questioned. Christina Petsoulas (2001), for example, refutes
Friedrich von Hayek’s (1948) inclusion of the Scottish Enlightenments within the tradi-
tion of spontaneous order on this ground. Mandeville, Hume and Smith, she argues,
assumed too many reflective and purposeful aptitudes in the development of institutional
rules for their accounts of institutions to qualify as invisible-hand explanations. Hillel
Steiner (1978) and Gerald Gaus (2011) address the same kind of criticism to Nozick’s
explanation of the minimal state when they claim that it is not obvious that the rise of a
minimal state is not among the goals of the dominant protective agency. As Gaus notes:
The actions and reasoning of the dominant protective agency in prohibiting unauthorized
enforcement by independents is too close to aiming at [the minimal state] to constitute a
satisfying invisible hand explanation of [the minimal state]: the agency is seeking to gain a
monopoly on the authorization of coercion, and its complex compensation reasoning is anything
but prosaic. It is not very surprising that the outcome of the dominant agency’s reasoning is a
claim to a minimal, Lockean, statehood. (Gaus, 2011: 124)
Because the attempt to gain a monopoly on the authorization of coercion is not truly
different from the intention to aim at a minimal state, the transition from an ultra-minimal
state to a minimal state seems more deliberately brought about than it is supposed to.
Nozick’s explanation of the minimal state is therefore too close to a social-pact explana-
tion of the same social phenomenon to be a compelling illustration of an invisible-hand
explanation. Leo Zaibert (2004) raises a similar point when he argues that sometimes the
relationship between what agents do individually and what they as a group bring about is
so obvious that their lack of awareness appears as mere stupidity. Describing the out-
come as an unintended consequence has the inconvenient implication that it restricts the
application of invisible-hand-type explanations to only societies of fools.
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
454 Social Science Information 52(3)
At the core of these various criticisms is the idea that many invisible-hand explana-
tions involve agents who are not sufficiently or, at least, not clearly minding their own
business and thus appear to some extent as seeking to realize the outcome, turning it into
an intended consequence of their actions. The gap separating the agents’ individual
intentions and what they bring about in the aggregate, it is argued, is not wide enough to
allow the working of an invisible hand. The disagreement between invisible-hand
explainers and their critics, it may be summarized, results from a clash of intuitions as to
how far from the agents’ view the consequence must be situated to count as unintended
rather than as intended.
There are various ways of dealing with these criticisms. One is to examine whether
the intended vs unintended consequences dichotomy can be disambiguated, i.e. to what
extent its sense can be sharpened so that it proves to be an adequate classificatory tool
after all. We need to figure out what level of theoretical knowledge agents who are led by
the invisible hand shall be (dis)allowed to have. Because there is no clear-cut boundary
between ignorance and awareness, however, there won’t be any straightforward answer
to this question. Tyler Cowen raises this problem when, in his discussion of the notion of
unintended consequences, he asks: ‘how fine a description of the final outcome … agents
… must intend in order to support a classification of the mechanism as an intended or
unintended consequence?’(Cowen, 1997: 135). Answers to this question are likely to
reveal a clash of intuitions given the grey zone that stands between blindness and clair-
voyance. The sphere of intendedness has fuzzy boundaries and is for this reason unlikely
to convincingly play the classificatory role it is supposed to.
Another line of inquiry is to examine whether the constraint is necessary and, in par-
ticular, whether it might not be too restrictive. Following the latter strategy, we ask to
what extent the outcome can enter agents’ ‘sphere of intention’ without ruling out the
operation of an invisible hand. Having proceeded by submitting the standard account to
various revisions of roughly increasing force, until a clearly inappropriate case for the
invisible hand is encountered, I reveal that quite a few revisions need to be tested before
such a boundary case is found.
To have the overall outcome in mind
Let us consider the SA from this revisionary perspective and see what would happen if
agents had the final outcome of their actions in mind while acting. Suppose, to take our
illustrative starting example, that the slave owners can recognize that their decision to
hire their slaves will result in the end of slavery. To be causally efficient, such a recogni-
tion would have to be the reason why they chose to hire them. Being aware of the effect
of one’s action is one thing. Being motivated by the prospect of such an outcome is
another.2 Doctors, to take a case in point, may act in a way they know will lead to the
death of a patient without intending to kill the patient. An invisible-hand theorist should
only worry about the case where agents not only anticipate the consequence of their
actions but also are moved by such anticipation. Someone advancing an invisible-hand
explanation should rule out only the possibility that agents act in full knowledge of these
consequences without intending to bring about these consequences. As an advocate of
parsimony, that person’s explanation should minimize only the number of causal
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
Tieffenbach 455
relations that are necessary to explain how the world works. Because merely being aware
of what one’s actions will bring about is an epiphenomenon, an explanation that accom-
modates such awareness is therefore as parsimonious as one that rules it out.
In sum, requiring blindness to the consequence of their actions is a constraint that is
unnecessarily restrictive.3 Agents who are led by the invisible hand shall be protected
only against having the outcome that figures among their reasons for acting,4 and the
standard account shall be revised accordingly:
Revised account (RA)1: An IHE is intended to explain a consequence of many actions
performed by agents who may have it in mind, but not in the form of a reason for action.
The case of wayward causal chains
What constraint must an agent meet in order to be led by the invisible hand? So far, we
have reached the following conclusion: Being aware of the consequences of one’s action,
while remaining unmoved by their prospect is not disqualifying. Suppose, however, that
the recognition of the outcome enters into the reason for which agents act. Would it pre-
clude the operation of the invisible hand? It seems so. There is apparently no way we can
avoid describing the outcome as being intentionally brought about. Yet the possibility
that agents acted unintentionally, leaving space for the working of an invisible hand,
should not be excluded too quickly.
Consider, for example, the explanation Marx offers of the wealth of European coun-
tries in modern time.5 These nations, as Marx recalls, were under the influence of mer-
cantilism, which is the view that prosperity depends on the possession of gold. However
faulty mercantilism might be as a theory, it did bring wealth to the nations who applied
it, according to Marx. It brought them wealth by motivating them to engage in efforts – to
colonize new countries, thus contributing to the proliferation of new needs, new
exchanges and of new commercial opportunities that ultimately brought them real
wealth. The mercantile system thus may have played a crucial, albeit unexpected, role in
the development of wealth.
The mechanism at play in Marx’s explanation is similar to the one exemplified in
La Fontaine’s fable The Labourer and His Children (cf. Elster, 1987). The fable tells
the story of three sons who were too lazy to work in the fields, as their father wished
them to. The father told them that there was a treasure buried in the ground. Eager to
get rich in a hurry, they turned over the soil in an unsuccessful search for the treasure,
and in doing so made it so fertile that they did indeed become wealthy, although not in
the way they had planned. Although the sons intended to get rich and ultimately got
rich, they cannot be said to have intentionally become so. Getting rich would have
been something that they intentionally did if the sons had become rich by way of find-
ing the treasure they were looking for. But wealth came to them through a very differ-
ent path.
In both La Fontaine’s fable and Marx’s explanation, the recognition of the effect
clearly is central to the reasons why agents act the way they do. In both examples, what
occurs corresponds to what was expected to occur. However, the mechanism that is
responsible for the correspondence between the two is completely unanticipated. These
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
456 Social Science Information 52(3)
examples show that the intention towards P (e.g. to become wealthy) is not yet a suffi-
cient condition for intentionally becoming P (e.g. wealth). The content of one’s intention,
e.g. to become wealthy, may represent the state of affairs in which that intention is satis-
fied. Yet having such an intention does not ensure that the state of affairs has been inten-
tionally brought about. This is because the identity between the goal and the produced
state of affairs might be a twist of fate. The wealth of nations did not arise in conformity
with mercantilist principles (whatever their worth), but rather as the side effect of meas-
ures taken in order to apply them. Although wealth happens to be what mercantilism
pursues, it arose in the course of applying the latter, rather than as the result of applying
the latter.
Agents may succeed in bringing about the consequence they intended to bring about,
but not in the way they thought the consequence would occur. The consequence is the
result of a so-called wayward process and cannot be described as something that is
intentionally brought about. Indeed, in order to fit that description, an effect must, in
addition to being intended, be brought about in the right way. Otherwise a wayward
process is at play. Such a wayward process is, aside from the more typical cases, another
way in which the invisible hand can be operative. Nozick has this type of case in mind
when he says that ‘a theory would be interesting if it showed that, although everyone
was aiming at a pattern, either their actions animated by that aim were not what pro-
duced the pattern, or, if they did, that the pattern did not arise by the route everyone
imagined – it was a side effect of their envisioned plans’ (1994: 314, fn 2). I propose that
we allow such cases to be genuine, although less typical, cases of invisible-hand expla-
nations. Although agents led by the invisible hand are in standard cases blind to the end
result of the process in which they participate, they may alternatively be blind to the
process by which such an outcome is brought about. If a wayward causal chain is a way
by means of which the invisible hand can operate, we should allow agents to be moved
by a recognition of the consequence of their action, provided this consequence does not
result from this recognition ‘in the right way’. The definition of the invisible hand
should be amended accordingly:
RA2: An IHE is intended to explain a consequence of many actions performed by agents who
may intend to bring it about as long as the consequence arises in the wrong way.
The case of Lewis conventions
Suppose now that the consequence did arise in the right way. Would it exclude the opera-
tion of the invisible hand? At first sight, it seems so. Agents led by the invisible hand are
supposed to lack a clear view of what they do. A certain gap must separate what they are
aware of and what they are actually doing. Since we previously let them be aware of
what their actions add up to, it seems that we shall at least not allow them to be aware of
the process by which it actually occurs.
Consider, however, the rule of driving on the right side of the road that prevails in
many countries. There are many ways of explaining it. One is to describe it as the result
of a policy. A legislator decides which side will be the driving side and punishes those
who violate that rule. Alternatively, the rule can be described as the result of a collective
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
Tieffenbach 457
agreement. The drivers can discuss the matter and decide which side they will drive on,
unaided by any third-party coordinator. Either way, the explanation relies on the ability
of some designing minds to devise the rule. For this reason, the explanation will not be
an invisible-hand explanation. There is, however, an alternative explanation that does not
rely on a centralized system of sanction nor on some previous agreement. The explana-
tion Schelling (1960) and David Lewis (1969) offer of conventions is, as I purport to
show, of that kind.
Conventions are, in Lewis’s view, solutions to coordination problems. Deciding
which side of the road should be the driving side, choosing something (e.g. cowrie shells
or coconuts) as a medium of exchange, deciding who should call back when a phone
conversation has been interrupted (Lewis, 1969: 9), limiting in some way the use of gas
as a weapon (Schelling, 1960: 75) are coordination problems. The latter are the sort of
problem you have to deal with when you have an interest in doing whatever the other
does whereas more than one option could be a solution. There is no outcome by which
agents’ interests would be better served than another. Driving on the right side is not, per
se, a superior option to that of driving on the left side.6 What matters is that you and I end
up choosing the same one.
It is Lewis’s view that a coordination problem is resolved when agents succeed in
converging on one of the equally valuable options. The capacity to form the right sort of
mutual expectations plays, in this respect, a crucial role. Except in England and its for-
mer empire, agents expect each other to drive on the right side of the road. Mutual expec-
tations split in turn into first-order expectations, as when I expect you to drive on the
right-hand side and vice versa, and higher-level expectations about what you expect me
to expect you to do, about what you expect me to expect you to expect me to do, and so
on. Schelling also recognizes such infinitive iterative interdependence in the formation
of mutual expectations. ‘The best choice for either’, he argues, ‘depends on what he
expects the other to do, knowing that the other is similarly guided, so that each is aware
that each must try to guess what the second guesses the first will guess the second to
guess and so on, in the familiar spiral of reciprocal expectations’ (Schelling, 1960: 87).7
This being said, the left side would solve the coordination problem as well. So the
crucial question is: What makes the option of driving on the right side of the road the
option of concordant mutual expectations?
Rational-choice theory is in this respect markedly unhelpful. Take its central assump-
tion, namely, the maximizing utility principle. Obviously, the propensity to choose the
option that delivers the best payoff does not point to any side of the road. Indeed, either
of the two combinations of options – left/left or right/right – allows us to maximize our
expected utility. Moreover, rational choice forbids agents to be influenced by the way the
options are labelled (Sugden & Zamarrón, 2006). This is because, in rational-choice
theory, what truly distinguishes one option from another one is its payoff and not its
description. ‘Driving on the left’ and ‘driving on the right’ could be respectively referred
to as ‘%&*’ and ‘§+/’ without altering their respective worth. To be distracted by the
apparent extra value that a label such as ‘driving on the right side’ gives to one of the
options it designates is to be the victim of an irrational ‘framing effect’. It is to have one’s
attention focused on contingent matters, i.e. how an option happens to be labelled, rather
than on what is essential to it, namely its payoff.
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
458 Social Science Information 52(3)
The preceding reasoning is certainly counter-intuitive. Not only is rational-choice
theory unhelpful at explaining how we solve coordination dilemmas, it also forbids us to
use a device that seems intuitively useful. Undoubtedly, we rely on the way options are
labelled in order to have our expectation converge on one of them. We do so because, as
Lewis argues, the distinctive connotations that are attached to the description of each
option make some of them more salient, allowing them to become the content of our
mutual expectations.
A salient option is an option that commands attention, i.e. one that ‘stands out from
the rest by its uniqueness in some conspicuous respect’ (Lewis, 1969: 35). It is, in
Schelling’s words (1960), a ‘focal point’ and can be used as such as a coordination cue.
For an option to be salient it must be so for many, and believed to be so among those for
whom it is so. As Lewis says, ‘agents might expect each other to expect each other to
expect each other to have [the] tendency [to pick the salient option] and act accordingly’
(Lewis, 1969: 33–34). In the same vein, he also says that a salient option is ‘unique in
some way the subjects will notice, expect the other to notice, and so on’ (1969: 35).
What makes an option salient? A prominent source of saliency is precedence. An
option is eye-catching because we reached it last time. Driving on the right side is a sali-
ent option because it is what drivers are used to doing.8 Other factors may however
contribute to the salience of an option. The right side is the side of the road on which it
also is legal to drive, a part of everyone’s habit. What commands attention may thus be
what is legal to do. Conspicuousness can, still alternatively, depend[s] on ‘analogy, …
accidental arrangement, symmetry aesthetic or geometric configuration, casuistic rea-
soning, and who the parties are and what they know about each other’ (Lewis, 1960: 57).
While the cultural context will determine why certain options are in particular more
striking than others, the very possibility of relying on salience as a way of meeting each
other’s expectations is always there.
Four features characterize a Lewis convention (1969: 58). First, it is a regularity ‘to
which everyone conforms’. Regularities that are only legally prescribed, such as the San
Diego law forbidding the possession of more than two dogs, are not Lewis conventions.
Second, it is a regularity to which ‘everyone expects everyone else to conform’. That
second condition excludes the general tendency (not) to follow the traffic monitor’s tips.
So too is the widespread habit of brushing one’s teeth ruled out from the class of Lewis
conventions inasmuch as the latter is not a regularity to which, thirdly, ‘everyone prefers
to conform … on condition that the others do’. Finally, these three conditions must, as a
final condition, be the content of common knowledge. The fourth condition excludes the
possibility where each driver falsely believes that he is the only one acting strategically
within a group made of parametric decision-makers. Everyone must assume that the ‘I
will if you will’ condition is everyone’s reasoning, not only one’s.
An invisible-hand explanation
Lewis explicitly intended his theory to replace an explanation of conventions that assign
a crucial role to either a legislator or to a collective agreement. He says that legislators
(or, in the present case, the highway patrol) play a superfluous role in the existence of
conventions. To be sure, the prospect of receiving a fine for driving on the left side gives
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
Tieffenbach 459
me an incentive to drive on the right. The punishments operate as an external incentive
that outweighs all reasons I may have for acting otherwise. Driving conventions happen
to be the result of a policy enforced by sanctions that leave no room, it appears, for the
mutual expectations identified by Lewis. Yet, as deterring as that fine may be, Lewis
argues, what ultimately dictates my choice is what I expect others will do. In fact, our
mutual expectations are more fundamental than fines. He says that ‘the punishments are
superfluous if they agree with our convention, are outweighed if they go against it, are
not decisive either way, and hence do not make it any less conventional to drive on the
right’ (1969: 45). It is especially true of driving conventions where staying alive is at
stake.
In line with the tradition of the invisible hand, Lewis also aims to provide an explana-
tion that dispenses with collective agreement. To be sure, Lewis grants that all conven-
tions could in principle originate in, and maintain themselves by, a binding agreement.
They need not do so, however. Lewis offers five different reasons for rejecting what
might be called the agreement conception of convention.
First, agreements are redundant when agents have no interest in acting differently
from the majority. Typically an agreement is ‘an exchange of formal or tacit promises’
(1969: 34). Promises are mainly called for, Lewis notes, when the action one promises to
perform is both collectively beneficial and against the individual interest of the agents. It
makes sense, for example, to make the promise to use less water during a drought because
the unconditioned inclination everyone has is not to decrease one’s consumption. In a
case like this, agents need to bind themselves to prevent themselves from being tempted
to free ride, and promising is one efficient way to do this. But unlike prisoner-dilemma-type
situations, agents’ interests are, in a coordination situation, well served when they simply
act on mutual expectations. Promises therefore are superfluous and ‘an exchange of dec-
larations of present intention’ suffices (1969: 34).
Second, agreements are not, strictly speaking, solutions to a coordination dilemma.
Rather they are ways to escape that dilemma. When I agree to drive on the right side, I
make the promise to drive on it unconditionally. As a consequence, one option clearly
becomes the promisor’s dominant option, i.e. the option he promises to choose uncondi-
tionally, thus imposing it on all. The situation is no longer a coordination problem
because the mutual expectations that define the latter are replaced by a one-sided expec-
tation. Surely the coordination dilemma is eluded this way. But the ensuing regularity of
behaviour is not a convention, since the latter is a solution to a coordination problem,
rather than a way of evading it.
Lewis gets his inspiration for the third argument from Hume. Initial agreements, he
says, may have taken place a long time ago. Yet an agreement made in the past ceases at
some point to have any binding effect. It is too remote or does not have any direct effect
on those who are not party to the agreement. At most, it motivates indirectly, that is, by
inducing mutual expectations among those who inherited conventions based on their
forefathers’ agreements. But mutual expectations are then what directly motivate us. If
this is so, ‘a convention created by agreement is no longer different from one created
otherwise: it bears no trace of its origin’ (1969: 84).
Finally, the condition of interdependency, which, according to Lewis, defines conven-
tion, excludes the possibility that they originate in agreements, i.e. promises to act
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
460 Social Science Information 52(3)
unconditionally.9 While an agreement may sow the seeds of a new convention, it only
fully comes into bloom once the agreement ceases to affect our choice. As Lewis says,
‘we have a convention only after the force of our promises has faded to the point where
it is both true and common knowledge that each would conform to some alternative regu-
larity R' instead of R if the others did’ (1969: 84).10
It should now be clear that Lewis argues against two rival conceptions of conventions
that both attribute a key role to a designing mind. Lewis does not show that these concep-
tions are empirically inaccurate. External punishments and agreements might very well
play a causal role in the actual emergence and maintenance of conventions. What Lewis
distinctively shows is that they are nevertheless inessential to their existence. If either a
sanction or an agreement were in fact involved in a given case, they would be contingent
facts about that convention.
It follows that Lewis’s account of conventions clearly satisfies the ‘no designer condi-
tion’ of all invisible-hand explanations.11 Yet a Lewis convention also clearly lacks the
feature of unintendedness. Driving on the right side is not construed as an unintended
consequence of actions directed toward other ends. Agents deliberately converge on that
option. Lewis’s view, in sum, is that the situation of agents when they follow a conven-
tion is a situation they deliberately bring about. It is a solution to a coordination dilemma
and not a by-product of some other concern. Nor is it a situation that agents ‘stumble
upon’, to use Ferguson’s oft-quoted expression.12 It results instead from everyone’s suc-
cessful, individual intentions to create it.
A Lewis convention is thus not an unintended consequence, and therefore lacks what
is largely recognized as an essential feature of an invisible-hand consequence. What is
more, no wayward causal chain is involved in the establishment of a Lewis convention.
A Lewis convention is a consequence of many actions performed by agents who, first,
have its establishment in mind; who, second, let its establishment enter into their reasons
for acting; and, third, whose intentions are the non-deviant causes of that consequence.
Our last revised account of the theory of the invisible hand, RA2, turns out to be as
unable as the standard definition to accommodate a Lewis convention. If the latter really
illustrates an invisible-hand explanation, any account of the latter should not rule out the
case where agents successfully act with the view to producing the outcome to be
explained.
Specifying such an account is uneasy, however, for it will have to accommodate the
case of Lewis conventions without blurring the distinction between invisible-hand expla-
nations and social-pact explanations. To explain an outcome as the result of a social pact
is indeed to depict it as what agents intended to bring about and managed to produce in
the way they intended to produce it. Remember, however, that a social-pact account and
an invisible-hand explanation are incompatible. The invisible hand denies the need of
collective agreement and the latter is a crucial stage of a social pact. So, any account
should be able to draw the line between these two conflicting views.
The solution, I believe, is to distinguish between two modes of intention, namely an
individualistic mode, an I-intention, and a non-reducible collective mode, a we-intention.
While the latter is typically at play when agents collectively agree to conform to a con-
vention, the former is operative when agents can rely neither on speech nor on any
explicit bargaining as a way to converge on the same convention.
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
Tieffenbach 461
Searle’s example (1990) of the graduate businessmen case presented above can be
helpful once again in order to grasp the difference between these two modes of intention.
The graduate students, remember, are not acting together, although it is common knowl-
edge among them that they are pursuing the same goal by the same means, that is, by
acting selfishly. Afterwards, Searle offers a suggestion as to what they would have to do
to act jointly. Let them ‘all get together on graduation day’, Searle suggests in this regard,
‘and form a pact to the effect that they will all go out together and help humanity by way
of each pursuing his own selfish interests’ (1990: 407), and a genuine case of collective
intentionality will be obtained. On Searle’s view, social-pact theories involve agents who
are acting together who are forming a common idea of how the reality should be
shaped. Having this shared goal in mind, participants in the pact bind themselves by
mutually agreeing to act so that their shared idea of social reality can be brought into
effect.
Conventions can be approached according to these two perspectives.13 They (like any
social pattern) can be the result of many actions performed by agents who are acting
individually, albeit interdependently, and with the same purpose in mind. Or they can be
the result of many choices undertaken by agents who are also acting interdependently
and with the same purpose but who distinctively view themselves as acting jointly.
If a Lewis convention can be shown to be one that specifically involves an I-intention,
the boundary condition of an invisible-hand explanation will have been found. I indeed
propose to draw the line that separates invisible-hand explanations from intentional-
design explanations by using the difference between these two modes of intention. On
the related account, a convention would be the product of an invisible-hand process only
in cases where it arises out of a process during which agents reason and act individually
during which agents are each moved by an I-intention. Let agents reason and act
jointly – let the latter be moved by a we-intention – however, and the same convention
would fall within the scope of an intentional-design explanation.
RA3: An IHE is intended to explain a consequence of many actions performed by agents who
may act with a view to producing the outcome to be explained, as long as they represent to
themselves this intention in a solo mode rather than as a together-with-the-other mode.
Acting jointly
RA3 is meant to be a compelling way of drawing the line between invisible-hand expla-
nations and intentional-design explanations. On the proposed account, the former does
not differ from the latter in virtue of its distinctive ability to describe its explanandum as
an unintended consequence, as the standard account suggests. It differs from the latter in
virtue of its ability to describe its explanandum as the intended result of many individual
(rather than joint) actions.
RA3 will sound compelling if the example that motivated it is itself convincing. In
other words, it is only if a Lewis convention is persuasively presented as involving agents
who do not act jointly that RA3 will be accepted. Yet the latter claim may be resisted.
Sceptics may indeed quote passages where Schelling and Lewis present their theory of
conventions as if it involved some sort of capacity to act together on the part of agents.
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
462 Social Science Information 52(3)
They will select the sentence where salience reasoning is said to require a ‘meeting of
minds’ (Schelling, 1960: 163) without which ‘some kind of collaborative or mutual
accommodation’ (1960: 83) can hardly be achieved. They will stress the passages where
Lewis says that the salient option will be found ‘by putting ourselves in the other fellow’s
shoes’ (1969: 27). Surely, these quotes do not serve our purpose well, to say the least.
They admittedly suggest that salience reasoning is a matter of attuning oneself to the
others’ minds – of ‘doing one’s best to mirror each other, mirror each other mirroring
each other, and so on’, as Lewis also says (1969: 32), in a way that seems typical of joint
actions. A focal point, in other words, seems to be both discovered by a we-attention and
issuing in a we-intention to act on its basis.
This section is devoted to making the contrary interpretation plausible. Notwithstanding
the various quotes in the previous paragraph, there are reasons to believe that a Lewis
convention involves no we-ness. A straightforward way of advancing the point is to
recall its underlying game-theoretical framework. Because game theory postulates that
no one other than individuals can choose, the question ‘what should we choose?’ does
not make sense to any of its advocates. The reason is that individuals, the latter assume,
are the only unit of agency conceivable.14 Speaking about a group mind can only be, at
best, a façon de parler.
Still, the idea of an irreducible plural subject is not the only way to approach joint
intentions. Another way – one that is compatible with the game theorist’s stance against
group minds – is to assign it to the content of the intentions, rather than to their allegedly
unique bearer.15 On the related view, taking the group’s perspective affects what agents
intend to do. Such a content-based approach to joint action comes in many versions,
some of which could apparently accommodate the sort of agency that gives rise to a
Lewis convention. Next I critically review these versions and advance some reason to be
sceptical about their relevance. My purpose is quite humble, suitably couched in terms of
casting doubts on rather than refuting the operation of a collective intention in a
Lewis convention. My strategy is as follows: to review the various features of a Lewis
convention in light of which it may appear to be based on a we-intention and show how
each of these features is subject to counter-examples of two kinds. The first are examples
of individual actions that display those features, and the second are examples of we-
actions that lack them.
To begin with, take an account of joint action that conceives it as nothing more than
several infinitely reiterated I-intentions, plus common knowledge of the situation. On
such an account, we intend to do something together if and only if:
– I intend to F and you intend to do something.
– I know that you intend to F and you know that I intend to something.
You know that I know that you intend to do something and I know that you know
that I intend to do something, and so on.
Surely a Lewis convention is compatible with such a distributive account of joint action.
However, the latter can be rejected on the basis of its inclusion of other cases, such as
Searle’s example of the businessmen graduate students, which are clearly not cases of
joint actions.
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
Tieffenbach 463
The relevance of approaching a Lewis convention as involving a capacity to act
together may, however, be defended by revising the above account. The amendment
consists in adding the disposition to act interdependently (see Bratman, 1993; Miller,
2001). While the businessmen clearly lack such a disposition, since they have learned to
pursue their individual interest regardless of what the others do, agents involved in a
Lewis convention clearly have it. Interdependency is also at the core of the various stra-
tegic decisions on which a Lewis convention is based. I intend to choose the right side
conditionally upon my knowing that you intend to choose the same side, and vice versa.
Finding the focal points, according to Schelling, requires that agents ask themselves:
‘What would I do if I were she wondering what she would do if she were I wondering
what I would do if I were she...?’ (Schelling, 1960: 54). To make room for a Lewis con-
vention, one thus only needs to amend the previous account of joint action with the
additional and mutually known ‘I will if you will’ condition.
But is interdependency really an essential ingredient of all joint actions? There are
various reasons to consider it is too weak a requirement. As Michael Bacharach has
shown (see Bacharach, 2006; also Gold & Sugden, 2007), interdependency is, with com-
mon knowledge, a feature of all Nash equilibria, including some that are intuitively not
the outcome of a collective intention. The case of mutual defection in the prisoner’s
dilemma is such a case. Even if each individual’s intention to defect is a best response to
her true beliefs about the others’ action, the resulting defection certainly does not result
from a we-intention. Another counter-example is the case of Susan and Bill, the spiteful
theatregoers, which Kay Mathiesen puts forward (Mathiesen, 2002) in order to show
why interdependency is not a sufficient feature of joint action. Bill hates Susan, and
Susan knows that her appearance at the play will ruin Bill’s enjoyment. Similarly, Susan
hates Bill, and Bill knows that his appearance at the play will ruin her enjoyment. So the
following conditions have been met: (a) Susan intends that Bill and she go to the play;
(b) Bill intends that Susan and he go to the play; (c) Susan intends to go because Bill is
going, and Bill intends to go because Susan is going; (d) there is common knowledge
between Bill and Susan about (a), (b) and (c). Susan and Bill may very well end up going
to Death of a Salesman. Yet there would be something odd in either of them saying that
‘we’ intend to go. As this example shows, agents may have interdependent intentions,
they may pursue the same end, and this may be common knowledge among them, and
yet they may be unconnected by any we-intentions to act together. Interdependency is
therefore not a sufficient condition of joint actions.
Nor is it, as Mathiesen further notes, a necessary condition of joint action. The case
she offers in defence of this point is one where I intend to go see Death of a Salesmen
with you, but still intend to go even if you cancel. Thus, my performing my part of this
collective action is not dependent on my belief that you will perform yours. As Mathiesen
explains, there may be cases where you and I share a collective intention to do some-
thing, even if I would still do it on my own without you. Interdependency, i.e. the rule ‘I
will if you will’, which partly defines a Lewis convention, thus seems not to be a feature
of the way conventions are jointly discovered and followed.
At this point, those who remain convinced that Lewis couched his theory of conven-
tions in a way that assigns a role to collective agency could invoke the participatory view
that characterises many accounts of the latter. They could say that, when drivers choose
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
464 Social Science Information 52(3)
the right side of the road, they have a sense of what they do as ‘doing their part’ of a
combination of action. Such a personal contribution to an action that has other contribu-
tors is considered an essential component of joint actions. The latter are typically per-
formed by several agents who see themselves as doing their bit and expect each other to
do so. The requirement is at the core of Sugden’s idea of collective intentionality, which
he articulates in terms of team reasoning. When agents intend to act together, they view
themselves as the members of a team, Sugden argues, and consider their individual con-
tribution as a way of ‘playing their part’ in the combination of actions that is best for the
team (Sugden, 2000: 187; 2003: 167–168; Sugden & Gold, 2007: 119; Sugden &
Zamarrón, 2006: 615). This participatory view of joint action is also central to Searle’s
conception. The individual participations, as he also stresses (Searle, 1990), derive from
the joint action. To be able to see what I do as ‘doing my bits of act A’, I must first see
what I do as ‘we are doing act A’.
Now it is true that agents acting individually may also act by bits.16 They may parti-
tion an action into smaller, more manageable parts. And they may also see the latter as
parts of an overall act that they intend to perform. Yet these sub-acts are, in the case of an
individual action, performed by the same agent. Let someone else take charge of a few
of these sub-acts,17 in other words, and the latter will become a case of joint action.
A Lewis convention also exhibits the same participatory structure. Driving on the
right side can be described as a choice drivers make collectively, by each of them doing
their part in the combination right/right. A Lewis convention thus involves agents who
view their choice in a participative way. The coordination dilemma will not get solved,
each agent knows, if each fails to do ‘his part of one of the possible coordination equilib-
ria’ (Lewis, 1969: 25).
But is the sense of doing one’s part an ingredient that is essentially constitutive of a
joint action or is it a mere desideratum of the latter? Such a requirement may be too
restrictive, as Hans-Bernard Schmid argued, in light of the possibility of having ‘negli-
gent, sloppy, unfocused, forgetful and weak-willed’ (Schmid, 2009:47) and otherwise
‘recalcitrant’ (2009: 47) participants in actions that nonetheless remain jointly performed.
The participatory requirement that characterizes the dominant view may be founded on
a ‘bias for smooth cooperation’ that makes us blind to the ‘unruly fellows who do not
only just happen to fail but even have the intention not to do their part in a shared coop-
erative activity?’ Schmid puts forward the case of two persons who have the intention to
lunch together at the cafeteria but are so engaged in the topic of their lively debate that
one of them ends up forgetting about where she is going. In spite of the lack of participa-
tory intentionality, it remains appropriate to refer to their action as going to the cafeteria.
Such a case certainly casts doubt on the necessity of actively doing one’s part in an action
as a condition of joint action. It consequently questions whether agents who succeed in
converging on a Lewis convention really are acting together.
The idea that agents who are involved in forming a Lewis convention act individually –
even if they act interdependently and are willing to do their part and have the same goal
in mind – should now, I hope, sound plausible. This is not to say that conventions could
never rest on common reasoning. Whereas Lewis conventions are not of that kind, con-
ventions could alternatively be construed as the result of agents jointly acting with the
shared purpose of bringing them about together. One well-known instance of such an
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
Tieffenbach 465
account is Margaret Gilbert’s idea of convention (Gilbert, 1989, 2008), which self-
consciously differs from Lewis’s in many respects. First, it is an account that rules out all
of Lewis’s conditions. For example, the convention that the members of some depart-
ments adopt regarding formal clothing at department meetings, she argues, shows why
conformity, expectation and an underlying coordination structure are neither sufficient
nor necessary. Second, unlike Lewis’s individualistic account, Gilbert’s is said to be a
holistic one in that it appeals to a non-reducible concept of joint commitment. Whereas,
in the case of personal commitments, ‘each must commit himself ’, in the case of joint
commitment ‘all commit all’ (Gilbert, 2008: 11). A joint commitment arises when each
party tacitly or explicitly expresses to the others his willingness ‘to participate with the
others in committing them all’ (2008: 11). Those who create a joint commitment together
impose a constraint on each of the parties with respect to what it is rationally open to
them to do. Each party, as Gilbert says, owes to every other party his conformity to the
commitment. A third un-Lewisian feature of Gilbert’s account is the offence which
someone’s failure to conform will induce in those who have fulfilled their commitment.
Such an offence opens the way to a fourth feature, which is the position in which the
offended find themselves able to rebuke the transgressor for not having performed his
committed action. The three ingredients of joint commitment, offence and reprimand
confer on conventions a think-normative dimension which Lewis’s account certainly
lacks, insofar as he thinly conceives the ‘oughtness’ of conventions as a matter of instru-
mental rationality (Lewis, 1969: 97–100).
In sum, because it requires more than mere interdependency and common knowledge,
and because it involves a robust social normativity, Gilbert’s conception of conventions
as the result of joint action adequately serves as a limiting case for the operation of the
invisible hand. It points to what agents should not do and think for being led by it.
The performance of joint action represents the limit that agents led by the invisible
hand shall never cross. It is where the line dividing invisible-hand accounts from rival
accounts is to be found.18 In the search for such a line, several explanatory options have
been encountered, which it is time to review. These conflicting or partly overlapping
mechanisms by which social outcomes arise out of agents’ coordinated choices differ
from one another in virtue of the sort of coordinating clues that they put out. Choices, we
have seen, can be coordinated as the result of: (i) the intervention of a central authority,
(ii) a social pact (Locke), (iii) a wayward causal chain (Marx), (iv) mutual expectations
around some focal points (Lewis), (v) team reasoning (Sugden) or as the product of (vi)
some previous joint commitment (Gilbert).
Conclusion
I have argued against the conventional way of defining the scope of the invisible hand in
terms of unintended consequences. I have shown that precluding the existence of design-
ers, be it an external ruler or a group of agents acting jointly to produce some outcome,
is not sufficient to ensure the unintendedness of the outcome to be explained.
On the revised account that I propose, agents led by the invisible hand should not be
prohibited from having the ultimate outcome of their actions in mind. Nor should they be
prevented from having the production of that outcome as part of their intention. They
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
466 Social Science Information 52(3)
should only be prevented from having the production of that outcome as part of their
collective intention. To have a role in an invisible-hand process, agents may act with a
view to contributing to the occurrence of the pattern to be explained, provided they see
what they do as an aggregation of their individual actions rather than as something they
jointly perform. They should, in other words, be allowed to have the intention to do their
part in bringing about the outcome to be explained, inasmuch as they see ‘bringing about
the outcome to be explained’ as an effect they intend to produce individually. Let agents
start thinking of themselves as members of a collective agency, however, and no invisible-
hand explanation will be available.
The proposed revised account captures what most invisible-hand explainers have – or
should have – in mind when they reject the need for a ‘collective agreement’ or for a
‘social pact’. It is superior to the standard account in three ways. First, it saves us the task
of resolving the various puzzles that surround the identification of unintended conse-
quences. Second, it accommodates a case of invisible-hand explanations, namely all
Lewis conventions, which would have otherwise been ruled out. Finally, it distinguishes
the invisible hand from the social pact by assigning a different kind of agency to each of
these two rival accounts of social reality.
Nevertheless, it may still be found important to keep the unintendedness assumption.
It may, for example, be justified on the ground that it reflects the condition of opacity in
which agents find themselves in regard to the social reality. It may alternatively be of
instrumental value inasmuch as it enables the advancement of a fundamental, that is non-
circular, explanation, one that will not refer to the outcome to be explained in the course
of the explanans (Nozick, 1974). Or it may simply be praised for the quite elitist pleasure
of giving a description of a social phenomenon that the very agents who make it possible
cannot themselves provide.
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank Kevin Mulligan, Leo Zaibert and two anonymous referees for their comments
and criticisms on previous versions of this article.
Funding
This article was written with the support of the Swiss National Centre for Competence in Research
(NCCR) in Affective Sciences.
Notes
1. Millar was writing in 1771, at a time when the issue of slave emancipation was widely dis-
cussed but had not been resolved in most European countries (let alone in America). This
might explain the historical inaccuracy of his explanation, since he could not foresee that
slavery would be terminated by state intervention rather than by spontaneous economic pro-
cesses. He therefore was simply making a conjecture as to how things might develop, not
on what had happened. Yet it is not certain, one may alternatively argue, that, had Millar
correctly anticipated or observed the abolition of slavery, he would have revised his explana-
tion accordingly. His invisible-hand explanation may indeed be deliberately a ‘potential’ one
(Nozick, 1974: 7), and an illustration of Dugald Stewart’s (1753–1828) idea of ‘conjectural
histories’ (Stewart, 1858: 34). (D Stewart’s [1858] Biographical memoirs of: Adam Smith,
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
Tieffenbach 467
LLD, William Robertson, DD and of Thomas Reid, DD, read before the Royal Society of
Edinburgh, were collected into one volume, with some additional notes, in Collected Works,
vol. X, Edinburgh, 1858.)
2. The same revision has been proposed in the context of a discussion about the ingredients of
functional explanations. Against Elster (1978), who argues that, in functional explanation,
the effect that (retroactively) explains the social phenomenon, must be unrecognized by the
actors who bring it about, Grimen (1994) observes that; ‘neither knowledge nor recognition
is on its own causally efficient in a relevant sense for functional explanations of the mainte-
nance of patterns of behaviour or institutions. The fact that an actor knows or recognised that
p does not alone bring about anything which could invalidate a functional explanation on the
one hand, or contribute to its explanatory force on the other. Hence there is no need to protect
against the actors’recognition of knowledge per se of the beneficial consequences of pat-
terns of behavior or institutions. In order to be causally efficient, knowledge or recognition
must be acted on or used, that is, it must enter among the actors’ reasons for acting’ (Grimen,
1994: 119).
3. Also, in ordinary language, a consequence does not have to be unforeseen to be described as
‘unintended’. Take the situation in which everyone is asked to reduce his water consumption
and most choose not to follow the directive, correctly anticipating that everyone else will
similarly free ride. Although all correctly foresee the drought, no one can be said to have the
intention to bring it about.
4. There might be a case, however, for not being so liberal. How could agents resist having the
intention to end the slavery system, it could be replied, once they recognize it as a cheaply
obtained effect of their initially selfish actions? It can, however, be replied that making sure
that the end of the slavery system is unanticipated is just a guarantee that its recognition won’t
play any motivating role. Lack of awareness is in this regard important insofar as it ensures
the behaviour is not intended in order to produce the effect to be explained.
5. The explanation appears in Marx (1973) and is presented by Elster (1985: 22–24).
6. There is a caveat to this claim. Although these two options are commonly considered as
equally attractive, driving on the right side actually is an inferior option because people have
the tendency to swerve to the left in an accident, with the prospect of running into oncoming
drivers. If this is so, the dilemma involved in choosing between left and right should therefore
be construed as a Hi-Lo game rather than as pure coordination dilemma.
7. Lewis acknowledges a practical limit to the length of that spiral, however, namely the fourth
level.
8. Using an evolutionary game-dynamic approach, Young (1996) offers an account of the emer-
gence of the right-hand driving rule. He shows that, although the left side was the dominant
convention in most of Western Europe before the French Revolution, a chain of historical
circumstances, symbolic reasons and rational inclination to adjust to the nearby countries’
rule tipped the balance in favour of the right side.
9. Surely, we may promise to conform to R on condition that others do as well, as Lewis
observes (1969: 84). However, most conceptions that derive the existence of conventions
from an agreement nevertheless do not conceive the promises to conform to R to have such a
conditional character.
10. This last argument, it must be noted, does not show the superfluity of agreements in regard to
the existence of conventions, only its inconsistency with Lewis’s idea of convention.
11. This classification is not uncommon. Having distinguished between ‘straightforward and
more complicated cases’ of invisible-hand explanations, Brennan and Pettit subsume Lewis’s
account of conventions under the latter category (Brennan & Pettit, 1993: 203–207; see also
Aydinonat, 2008: 147–152).
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
468 Social Science Information 52(3)
12. Here is the full quote: ‘Nations stumble upon establishments, which are indeed the result of
human action, but not the execution of any human design’ (Ferguson, 2006[1782]: 187).
13. Besides these two approaches, the French school of ‘Economies des conventions’ represents
still another conception of conventions (cf. Dupuy et al., 1989; Orléan, 2004). Unlike the
Lewisian account, the members of the French school will stress the condition of uncertainty
in which agents find themselves as the result of their bounded rationally. They will also cast
light on the agents’ interpretative skills as well as on the normative dimension which gives
to conventions either their legitimate or, on the contrary, their unjustified character. Unlike
the holistic approach, however, the French school spells out its conception of conventions
in individualistic terms. The French tradition therefore represents an interesting alternative
view, one that stands somewhere in between the two conflicting views to which I refer in the
article. Because it is an individualistic approach, however, I find it too close to the Lewisian
account to play the role of the limiting case, vis-a-vis the invisible hand, which the Gilbertian
approach suitably illustrates.
14. The idea that no other entity but individual agents can choose is an ontological presupposition
– an assumption – about the basic constituents of social reality (cf. Mäki, 2001: 369–372),
which is, as such, mostly left un-supported by game theorists and mainly debated by philoso-
phers working in the field of social ontology.
15. A third approach conceives the difference between joint and individual actions as involving a
distinctive mode of representation. On this view, there are two modes of intending one and the
same thing, namely a solo mode and a together-with-another mode. Searle seems to endorse
this approach when he says that the reference to a group appears in each one of us under the
primitive form ‘we intend to F’, rejecting the content-based approach of the form ‘I intend
that we F’, on the one hand, and an implausible world spirit floating above individuals, on the
other.
16. ‘In the standard theory, the individual appraises alternative options in relation to … her pref-
erences, given her beliefs about the actions that other individuals will choose. An individual
engaged in team-directed reasoning appraises alternative arrays of action by members of the
team in relation to [the] team-directed preferences’ (Sugden, 2000: 187). Consider also this
quote: `When an individual reasons as a member of a team, he considers which combination
of actions by members of the team would best promote the team’s objective, and then per-
forms his part of that combination’ (Sugden, 2003: 167).
17. There are, interestingly, an indeterminate number of bit(s) of my individual action that I can
delegate to someone else before turning it into a joint action.
18. The difference between the two sorts of accounts is where the dividing line between invisible-
hand explanations and intentional-design explanations lies. Compatible with that claim, it is
important to stress, is any appraisal regarding the merit of each sort of explanation.
References
Aydinonat E (2008) The Invisible Hand in Economics: How economists explain unintended social
consequences. London/New York: Routledge.
Bacharach M (2006) Beyond Individual Choice: Teams and frames in games theory, edited by
Gold N & Sugden R (eds). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Bratman M E (1993) Shared intention. Ethics 104(1): 97–113.
Brennan G, Pettit P (1993) Hands invisible and intangible. Synthèse 94(2): 191–225.
Cowen T (1998) Do economics use social mechanisms to explain social mechanisms? An ana-
lytical approach to social theory. In: Hedström P, Swedberg R (eds) Social Mechanisms: An
analytical approach to social theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 125–146.
Dupuy J-P, et al. (1989) Introduction. Revue Economique 40(2): 141–145.
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
Tieffenbach 469
Elster J (1978) Logic and Society. Chichester: Wiley.
Elster J (1985) Making Sense of Marx. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Elster J (1987) Le Laboureur et Ses Enfants. Deux essais sur les limites de la rationalité. Paris:
Editions de Minuit.
Ferguson A (2006[1782, 1767]) An Essay on the History of Civil Society. London: T Cadell.
Gaus G (2011) Explanation, justification, and emergent properties: An essay on Nozickean
metatheory. In: Bader RM, Meadowcroft J (eds) The Cambridge Companion to Nozick’s
Anarchy, State, and Utopia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 116–144.
Gilbert M (1989) On Social Facts. London/New York: Routledge.
Gilbert M (2008) Social convention revisited. Topoi (27): 5–16.
Gold N, Sugden R (2007) Collective intentions and team agency. Journal of Philosophy
104(3):109–137.
Grimen H (1994) Causally inefficient knowledge and functional explanation. Social Science
Information 33(1): 117–127.
Hayek FA von (1948) Individualism and Economic Order. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Lewis D (1969) Convention. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Mäki U (1990) Practical syllogism, entrepreneurship and the invisible hand. In: Lavoie D (ed.)
A Critique of the Analytic Hermeneutics of G. H. von Wright: Economics and hermeneutics.
London: Routledge, 149–176.
Mäki U (2001) The way the world works (www): Towards an ontology of theory choice. In:
Mäki U (ed.) The Economic World View: Studies in the ontology of economics. Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 369–389.
Marx K (1973[1857–1861]) Grundrisse der Kritik der Politischen Ökonomie (Outlines of the
Critique of Political Economy), transl. by Nicolaus M. London: Penguin.
Mathiesen K (2002) Searle, collective intentions, and individualism. In: Meggle G (ed.) Social
Facts and Collective Intentionality. Frankfurt: Dr Hänsel-Hohenhausen AG, 185–204.
Menger C (1892) On the origins of money. Economic Journal 2(6): 239–255.
Millar J (2006)[1771]) The Origin of the Distinction of Ranks; or, An Inquiry into the Circumstances
which Give Rise to Influence and Authority in the Different Members of Society, ed. by Garrett
A. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.
Miller S (2001) Social Action: A teleological account. New York, NY: Cambridge University
Press.
Nozick R (1974) Anarchy, State and Utopia. Oxford: Blackwell, Basic Books.
Nozick R (1994) Invisible-hand explanations. American Economic Review 84(2): 327–332.
Orléan A (2004) L’Economie des conventions: Définitions et résultats. In: Orléan A (ed.) Analyse
Economique des Conventions. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. (2nd edn)
Petsoulas C (2001) Hayek’s Liberalism and Its Origins: His idea of spontaneous order and the
Scottish enlightenment. Studies in Social and Political Thought. London: Routledge.
Schelling T C (1960) The Strategy of Conflict. Cambridge, MA: London: Harvard University
Press.
Schelling T C (1969) Models of segregation. American Economic Review 59(2): 488–493.
Schmid H-B (2009) Plural Action: Between philosophy and the social sciences. Dordrecht:
Springer Verlag.
Searle JR (1990) Collective intentions and actions. In: Cohen P, Morgan J, Pollack M (eds)
Intentions in Communication. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 401–415.
Steiner H (1978) Can a social contract be signed by an invisible hand? In: Birnbaum P, et al. (eds)
Democracy, Consensus and Social Contract. London/Beverly Hills: SAGE Publications.
Sugden R (2000) Team preferences. Economics and Philosophy 16(2): 175–204.
Sugden R (2003) The logic of team reasoning. Philosophical Explorations 6(3): 165–181.
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
470 Social Science Information 52(3)
Sugden R, Gold N (2007) Collective intentions and team agency. Journal of Philosophy 104(3):
109–137.
Sugden R, Zamarrón I (2006) Finding the key: The riddle of focal points. Journal of Economic
Psychology 27: 609–621.
Tuomela R (1984) A Theory of Social Action. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Ullmann-Margalit E (1978) Invisible-hand explanations. Synthese (39): 263–291.
Young P (1996) The economics of conventions. Journal of Economic Perspectives 10(2): 105–122.
Zaibert L (2004) Toward meta-politics. Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 7(4): 113–128.
Author biography
Emma Tieffenbach graduated in history from the University of Geneva (1998) and obtained a
Diplôme d’études approfondies (2000) at the Centre de Recherche Politique Raymond Aron
(EHESS, Paris). Her doctoral dissertation (University of Geneva) deals with the cognitive value of
‘invisible-hand explanations’. Since April 2012, she has been working on the nature and motiva-
tional power of economic values at the Swiss Center for Affective Sciences (University of Geneva).
She was awarded a Marie Heim-Vögtlin subsidy from the Swiss National Foundation.
at Universite de Geneve on September 9, 2013ssi.sagepub.comDownloaded from
... The crucial element in collective intentionality is a sense of doing (wanting, believing, etc.) something together, and the individual intentionality that each person has is derived from the collective intentionality that they share (Searle 1995, 24-25) For Searle (ibid.), if individuals act selfishly as in Adam Smith's invisible hand model, there is no cooperation and, as a consequence, there is no collective intentionality (see also Tieffenbach 2013). ...
... Since the systemic coordination of modern market societies is partly unintentional, Searle's claim that collective intentionality is the key to understanding the structure of social reality is an overstatement. It must be added that his view that invisible hand explanations are at odds with collective intentionality because, if individuals acted selfishly, there would be no cooperation, is also problematic (see Searle 1990, 406;Tieffenbach 2013). As pointed out above, invisible hand theorists from Adam Smith to Hayek conceive their approach as related to forms of cooperation, rather than as radically opposed to agreement-oriented processes (see Hayek 1973). ...
Article
Full-text available
According to Searle's theory of collective intentionality, the fundamental structure of any society can be accounted for in terms of cooperative mechanisms that create deontic relations. This paper criticizes Searle's standpoint on the ground that, while his social ontology can make sense of simple systems of interaction like symphony orchestras and football teams, the whole coordinative structure of the modern market society cannot be explained solely in terms of we-intentional collaboration and deontic relations. As clarified by Hayek, because of its complexity, this society is a self-organizing system. It results not only from micro-level agreed constraints, but also from an unintended cybernetic mechanism that affects and shapes both its micro and macro dynamics via a circular causality. Searle ignores the coordination problem posed by complexity and provides strawman arguments against the theory of action underpinning the invisible hand explanation of social phenomena.
... This last interpretation, as I have argued elsewhere, could well be the most coherent one (cf. Tieffenbach, 2013). 5. Another way of applying the invisible hand to a normative goal is to have it perform a justificatory role (see Schmidtz, 1990). ...
... 2), Menger's explanation of the emergence of money (Menger, 1892) and Nozick's explanations of the spontaneous institution of a minimal state (1974) are often cited as paradigm examples. While Nozick first coined the term 'invisible-hand explanations', Ullmann-Margalit's reference article (1978) remains perhaps the most comprehensive conceptual clarification of the notion (see also Aydinonat, 2008;Brennan & Pettit, 1993;Tieffenbach, 2013). ...
Article
Full-text available
Self-centred based explanations such as invisible-hand accounts look like armchair constructions with no relevance to the real world. Whether and how they nonetheless provide an insight into social reality is a puzzling matter. Philip Pettit's idea of self-interest virtually bearing on choices offers the prospect of a solution. In order to assess the latter we first distinguish between three variants of invisible-hand explanations, namely: a normative, an historical and a theoretical one. We then show that, while the model of virtual self-interest is a helpful gloss on each variant, it may not convincingly succeed, pace Pettit, in reconciling the economic mind with the common mind. Résumé Les explications qui font l'hypothèse de motivations exclusivement intéressées de la part des individus, comme les explications dites 'par la main invisible', paraissent dénuées de pertinence eu égard au monde social réel. Dans quelle mesure ces explications éclairent tout de même la réalité est une question épineuse. L'idée défendue par Philip Pettit selon laquelle l'intérêt personnel influence virtuellement les choix se présente comme une solution. Pour l'évaluer, nous distinguons d'abord trois variantes des explications par la main invisible en fonction des buts respectivement normatifs, historiques et théoriques que poursuivent ceux qui les avancent. Nous montrons ensuite que le modèle de la réalité virtuelle de l'intérêt personnel permet d'élucider chacune de ces variantes sans toutefois parvenir de façon convaincante à réconcilier la psychologie économique et celle du sens commun.
... The answer comes into view once one sees genealogical fictions as akin to idealizing models in the sciences. Drawing on the interpretation of Craig's genealogy developed by Martin Kusch and Robin McKenna (Kusch 2009, 2013Kusch and McKenna 2018a, b), I suggest that pragmatic genealogies are best interpreted as dynamic models -as idealizations with a time-axis. ...
Chapter
Full-text available
There is an under-appreciated tradition of genealogical explanation that is centrally concerned with social functions. I shall refer to it as the tradition of pragmatic genealogy. It runs from David Hume (T, 3.2.2) and the early Friedrich Nietzsche (TL) through E. J. Craig (1990, 1993) to BernardWilliams (2002) and Miranda Fricker (2007). These pragmatic genealogists start out with a description of an avowedly fictional “state of nature” and end up ascribing social functions to particular building blocks of our practices – such as the fact that we use a certain concept, or live by a certain virtue – which we did not necessarily expect to have such a function at all. That the seemingly archaic device of a fictional state-of-nature story should be a helpful way to get at the functions of our actual practices must seem a mystifying proposal, however; I shall therefore endeavor to demystify it in what follows. My aim in this chapter is twofold. First, by delineating the framework of pragmatic genealogy and contrasting it with superficially similar methods, I argue that pragmatic genealogies are best interpreted as dynamic models whose point is to reveal the function – and non-coincidentally often the social function – of certain practices. Second, by buttressing this framework with something it notably lacks, namely an account of the type of functionality it operates with, I argue that both the type of functional commitment and the depth of factual obligation incurred by a pragmatic genealogy depend on what we use the method for: the dynamic models of pragmatic genealogy can be used merely as heuristic devices helping us spot functional patterns, or more ambitiously as arguments grounding our ascriptions of functionality to actual practices, or even more ambitiously as bases for functional explanations of the resilience or the persistence of practices. By bringing these distinctions into view, we gain the ability to distinguish strengths and weaknesses of the method’s application from strengths and weaknesses of the method itself.
Article
In the absence of a threat of maldistribution, what reason could there be to bar trade of a genuine good that is otherwise owned? Market skeptics have asserted that, once permitted, trade tends to crowd out gifting. Why should we care, though, if needs are satisfied via sales? More importantly, why suppose that permitting trade will cause crowding out? In this paper, I address both questions with an emphasis on the second. Normatively, I claim that gifting has expressive value over and above its value in satisfying needs. Causally, I differentiate between possible cultural and psychological mechanisms, and I offer an original, institutional one. The cultural mechanism relies on the notion that pricing symbolizes a good as a mere commodity. The psychological mechanism draws on empirical evidence that introducing a monetary incentive can diminish a good’s provision. And the institutional mechanism invokes an assumed division of moral labor that dictates that each of us sometimes eschews opportunities to gift so that, together, we enable the invisible hand. I further argue that the institutional mechanism is likely to be more widely applicable than the more familiar cultural and psychological mechanisms.
Chapter
This paper orchestrates a confrontation between the social ontology, social and political philosophy of Searle and the views on these matters of the earliest phenomenologists. According to Searle, social objects depend on declarations and on collective acceptance or recognition of the results of declarations. After first (§2) drawing attention to some distinctions and claims which go back to Reinach and which will be important in what follows, I then (§3) consider what Reinach and Searle have to say about declarations. Since collective acceptance is a type of collective intentionality I examine what Searle and the phenomenologists have to say about collective intentionality and the subjects or bearers of this type of intentionality (§4). I then look at the relation between states and social acts (§5), the relations between what Searle calls deontic powers and Reinach jural powers and some possible roles of such powers (§6) and conclude with a brief sketch of the role of primitive certainty in social ontology (§7).
Chapter
Intentions in Communication brings together major theorists from artificial intelligence and computer science, linguistics, philosophy, and psychology whose work develops the foundations for an account of the role of intentions in a comprehensive theory of communication. It demonstrates, for the first time, the emerging cooperation among disciplines concerned with the fundamental role of intention in communication. The fourteen contributions in this book address central questions about the nature of intention as it is understood in theories of communication, the crucial role of intention recognition in understanding utterances, the use of principles of rational interaction in interpreting speech acts, the contribution of intonation contours to intention recognition, and the need for more general models of intention that support a view of dialogue as a collaborative activity. Contributors Michael E. Bratman, Philip R. Cohen, Hector J. Levesque, Martha E. Pollack, Henry Kautz, Andrew J. I. Jones, C. Raymond Perrault, Daniel Vanderveken, Janet Pierrehumbert, Julia Hirschberg, Richmond H. Thomason, Diane J Litman, James F. Allen, John R. Searle, Barbara J. Grosz, Candace L. Sidner, Herbert H. Clark and Deanna Wilkes-Gibbs. The book also includes commentaries by James F. Allen, W. A Woods, Jerry Morgan, Jerrold M. Sadock Jerry R. Hobbs, and Kent Bach. Intentions in Communication is included in the System Development Foundation Benchmark Series. Bradford Books imprint
Chapter
The advancement of social theory requires an analytical approach that systematically seeks to explicate the social mechanisms that generate and explain observed associations between events. These essays, written by prominent social scientists, advance criticisms of current trends in social theory and suggest alternative approaches. The mechanism approach calls attention to an intermediary level of analysis in between pure description and story-telling, on the one hand, and grand theorizing and universal social laws, on the other. For social theory to be of use for the working social scientist, it must attain a high level of precision and provide a toolbox from which middle range theories can be constructed.
Chapter
The beliefs of economists are not solely determined by empirical evidence in direct relation to the theories and models they hold. Economists hold 'ontological presuppositions', fundamental ideas about the nature of being which direct their thinking about economic behaviour. In this volume, leading philosophers and economists examine these hidden presuppositions, searching for a 'world view' of economics. What properties are attributed to human individuals in economic theories, and which are excluded? Does economic man exist? Do markets have an essence? Do macroeconomic aggregates exist? Is the economy a mechanism, the functioning of which is governed by a limited set of distinct causes? What are the methodological implications of different ontological starting points? This collection, which establishes economic ontology as a coordinated field of study, will be of great value to economists and philosophers of social sciences.
Book
1: Philosophy and the Theory of Social Action.- I Scientific Realism and the Social Sciences.- II Theorizing about Social Action.- 2: Individualism and Concept Formation in the Social Sciences.- I Holistic Social Concepts.- II Conceptual Individualism.- III We-Intentions and Social Motivation.- 3: Theories of Action.- I Views of Human Action.- II Mental Cause Theory.- III Agency Theory.- IV Hermeneutic Theory.- V Arguments for and against Causal Theories of Action.- 4: The Purposive-Causal Theory of Human Action.- I The Fundamental Elements of the Purposive-Causal Theory of Action.- II The Structure of Single-Agent Action.- 5: The Structure of Social Action.- I The General Nature of Social Action.- II Simple Social Actions.- III Complex Social Actions.- IV The Acting of Social Collectives.- V Group Interests Revisited.- 6: Action Generation.- I Action Generation and the By-Relation.- II Action Generation and the Theory of Automata.- III Social Actions, Grammars, and Social Conduct Plans.- 7: Practical Inference and Social Action.- I Loop Beliefs and Practical Inference.- II Mutual Beliefs.- III The Replicative Justification of Social Beliefs.- IV Social Action and Practical Inference.- V Mixed Interest Games and Practical Inference.- VI Social Rules and the Scope of Social Action.- 8: Norms, Rules, and Social Structures.- I Social Norms.- II Social Rules.- III Similarity and Roles.- IV Social Structures.- 9: Social Interaction and Control.- I Acting in Social Relation.- II Overt Social Interaction.- III Covert Social Interaction.- 10: A Pragmatic Theory of Explanation.- I Explaining as Communicative Action.- II Emphasis.- III Understanding and Presuppositions.- 11: Proximate Explanation of Social Action.- I Explanation and Social Action.- II Teleological Explanation.- III Purposive-Causal Explanation.- IV Reason-Explanation.- V Explaining the Style of Action.- VI Understanding Action.- 12: Dynamic Explanation of Social Action.- I Explanation and Other-Regarding Utilities.- II Expected Utilities, Motives, and the Explanation of Social Action.- III The Nature of Dynamic Action Explanations.- 13: Functional and Invisible Hand Explanation of Social Action.- I Action-Functions and Functional Explanations.- II Invisible Hand Explanations of Social Action.- 14: Explanatory Individualism and Explanation of Social Laws.- I Explanatory Individualism.- II Explanation of Social Laws.- Notes.- Name index.- Index of Symbols, Definitions, and Theses.
Chapter
INTRODUCTION In some ways, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (ASU) has been a victim of its own success. For over thirty-five years it has been one of the most provocative works in political philosophy, and the preeminent defense of Lockean libertarianism. Almost all readers have read it with an eye to its conclusions. Statists and redistributionists see it as something to be combated and defeated; libertarians start out to defend it or, at least, modify it in constructive ways. Given this it is hardly surprising that the second part of ASU, arguing against the redistributive state, has been the focus of by far the most extensive, and famous, discussions. One shudders to think of how many essays have been written on Nozick's witty, four-age, Wilt Chamberlain example. The first part of ASU, in which Nozick argues against the anarchist, showing that minimal state is (in some sense) justifiable, has received much less attention. Eric Mack's contribution to this volume is an insightful analysis of Nozick's substantive case against anarchism, and how it might be modified to achieve success. If within ASU the first part generally goes unnoticed, within that part Nozick’s path-breaking analysis of invisible-hand explanations is almost entirely ignored in political philosophy. Readers focus on Nozick’s substantive claims, and not what he calls his “abstract” and “metatheoretical” comments about explanation and justification (p. 3). This is partly Nozick’s own doing; he directs readers away from his metatheoretical comments about the benefits of state of nature theories and invisible hands to his substantive account of the state of nature and the rise of the minimal state (p. 4).
Book
The Origin of the Distinction of Ranks is one of the major products of the Scottish Enlightenment and a masterpiece of jurisprudence and social theory. Building on David Hume, Adam Smith, and their respective natural histories of man, John Millar developed a progressive account of the nature of authority in society by analyzing changes in subsistence, agriculture, arts, and manufacture. The Origin of the Distinction of Ranks is perhaps the most precise and compact development of the abiding themes of the liberal wing of the Scottish Enlightenment. Drawing on Smith's four-stages theory of history and the natural law's traditional division of domestic duties into those toward servants, children, and women, Millar provides a rich historical analysis of the ways in which progressive economic change transforms the nature of authority. In particular, he argues that, with the progress of arts and manufacture, authority tends to become less violent and concentrated, and ranks tend to diversify. Millar's analysis of this historical progress is nuanced and sophisticated; for example, his discussion of servants is perhaps the best developed of the "economic" arguments against slavery. John Millar (1735-1801) explored, through his works, the nature of English governance through a prism of the natural law tradition and Scottish philosophical history. Millar was a student of Adam Smith's at Glasgow University and his most important immediate intellectual heir. His works provide an essential linkage to Smith. Aaron Garrett is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Boston University. Knud Haakonssen is Professor of Intellectual History and Director of the Centre for Intellectual History at the University of Sussex, England.