ArticlePDF Available

Cognitive realism and memory in Proust’s madeleine episode

Authors:

Abstract

The famous ‘madeleine episode’ of Proust’s In Search of Lost Time is investigated with reference to cognitive realism in the evocation of memory, by asking how this literary memory experience compares with the conceptualization of memory in current cognitive science. Furthermore, what does close reading of the episode informed by current scientific findings and debates on memory and agency tell us about Proust’s categorization of this memory event as involuntary memory, and his presentation of voluntary and involuntary memory as a distinct opposition? I show that the madeleine episode (1) corresponds partly to cognitive realities as documented by recent science and partly to prevalent expectations about cognition or its narration, and (2) undermines the neat voluntary/involuntary distinction it initially seems to illustrate. I suggest how these qualities may affect readers’ responses to Proust’s famously evocative object.
Cognitive realism and memory in Proust’s madeleine episode
Emily T. Troscianko
Abstract
The famous ‘madeleine episode’ of Proust’s In Search of Lost Time is investigated with
reference to cognitive realism in the evocation of memory, by asking how this literary
memory experience compares with the conceptualisation of memory in current cognitive
science. Furthermore, what does close reading of the episode informed by current scientific
findings and debates on memory and agency tell us about Proust’s categorization of this
memory event as involuntary memory, and his presentation of voluntary and involuntary
memory as a distinct opposition? I show that the madeleine episode 1) corresponds partly to
cognitive realities as documented by recent science and partly to prevalent expectations about
cognition or its narration, and 2) undermines the neat voluntary/involuntary distinction it
initially seems to illustrate. I suggest how these qualities may affect readers’ responses to
Proust’s famously evocative object.
Keywords: Cognitive literary studies, free will, involuntary memory, memory studies,
Proust, voluntary memory
Marcel Proust’s In Search of Lost Time has a long history of cognitively orientated
interpretation (e.g. O’Brien, 1970; Shepherd-Barr and Shepherd, 1998; Delacour, 2001;
Utermohlen, 2002; Nalbantian, 2003; Ender, 2005), for this seminal twentieth-century text
not only emphasizes the crucial role that the cognitive capacity of memory plays in making
narration itself possible; it also evokes a form of memory previously under-recognized in
memory research, ‘involuntary memory’.1 This evocation has made ‘Proust’s madeleine’ a
shorthand for the vivid and emotionally powerful flooding-back of even very distant and
long-dormant memories when tasting or smelling something from one’s past: the madeleine
is ‘perhaps the most famous evocative object in all literature’ (Turkle, 2007: 318).
1. Methodological issues: Proustian memory, science, aesthetics, and folk psychology
My aim is to elucidate the madeleine as an evocative object with reference to the episode’s
cognitive realism in the evocation of memory, by evaluating the extent to which memory in
this episode corresponds to or differs from the cognitive realities of remembering, as
understood by current science (and without value judgements or attributions of authorial
intent). The article does not seek to elucidate the ‘meaning’ of the episode or indeed the
novel. Instead, it explores the episode’s textual features in relation to cognitive realities as
currently emerging in scientific research, and in relation to evocations of memory elsewhere
in the novel, and concludes by briefly hypothesising as to their possible effects on readers.
The analysis is intended to propose conclusions beneficial to literary criticism, and also to
suggest how memory studies might derive insights from a fuller understanding of the
passage.
The madeleine episode is of course not the only significant instance of involuntary memory
in the Search: the sequence of five instances in the final volume, Finding Time Again, most
of which are triggered by sensory cues (stimuli to remembrance) such as the sensation of
uneven flagstones or the feel of a stiffly starched napkin, constitute the major impetus to the
focalizer’s2 new understanding of involuntary memory and its potential. Beyond this key
sequence of involuntary memories, the novel contains a wide range of other memory events.
These include somatic memories, ‘memories’ based on hearsay, memories which have been
interpreted as ‘screen memories’ in a psychoanalytical sense, and memories which are more
fully voluntary in their retrieval. A recent word-count analysis of the novel finds 1,210 uses
of terms relating to memory on 3,125 pages, and suggests that it contains ‘a thorough analysis
of at least 10 main topics on memory’ (Bogousslavsky and Walusinski, 2009: 161). A full
account of memory in the Search would have to include all these varying instantiations, but
this article has a less ambitious scope: working outwards from a detailed examination of the
madeleine episode allows us to draw conclusions about the nature of involuntary memory and
its voluntary counterpart, in the novel and beyond.
Comparing this literary evocation of memory with scientific claims about memory may seem
an overly literal response to a passage of great aesthetic as well as cognitive interest.
However, a strict division between the aesthetic and the cognitive when considering literary
artworks is impossible, given that any fictional text is created through cognition, textually
evokes cognition in its characters, and achieves its effects only through the cognition of the
reader. Indeed, the roots of the term ‘aesthetics’, in the Greek for perception, sensation, or
feeling, mean that the cognitive is always at the heart of the aesthetic, broadly speaking. And
the Search in particular is structured to such an extent by the workings of memory that none
of the novel’s more ‘aesthetic’ concerns identity, time, beauty, love and sexuality, art and
life, intellectual ‘influence’ can easily be considered in isolation from cognitive issues.
Themes other than memory cannot be discussed in detail here, but insights gained in this area
may well have relevance to other themes: identity, the experience of time, and the relation
between literary art and lived life.
Evelyne Ender (2005) argues for the importance of investigating cognition in the Search; she
does so in two steps, both of which take account of the aesthetic angle.3 The first step invokes
the scientific significance of Proustian memory:
critics have suggested Proust’s preference [for involuntary memory over
voluntary] is motivated, above all, by aesthetic considerations: it enables him
to organize his story around a striking revelation, a sort of epiphany. But the
overwhelming response this model of remembrance has received among
scientists tells us something else. […] Proust emphasizes the physiological
underpinnings of remembrance and changes the very definition of recollection.
[…] With his stimulus-response model and his visionary idea that a mysterious
chemistry produces remembrance, Proust opened new vistas for the scientific
exploration of personal memory. (2005: 29)
The second step argues that Proustian memory is, in any case, inherently aesthetic: the
rememberer’s responses to memory events are rich in ways comparable to a viewer’s
response to visual art, or a listener’s response to music. Memory in the Search is, Ender
suggests, ‘a dynamic process that emerges from and is sustained by an aesthetic impulse; it is
creative in the fullest sense of the term’ (2005: 43).
The first part of Ender’s argument about Proust, cognition, and aesthetics can, however,
entail over-emphasis of Proust’s achievements as scientific. Drawing on work by Antonio
Damasio, Marigold Linton, Israel Rosenfield, and Oliver Sacks, Ender sometimes
foregrounds the notion that Proust’s ‘study of autobiographical memory’ (33) anticipat[es]
later discoveries’ (2007: 31) about memory, and that he makes a ‘contribution to memory
studies’ (24) with a novel that ‘reads at times very much like a case study or a treatise, even,
on the subject of personal remembrance’ (2005: 22). Jonah Lehrer’s Proust Was a
Neuroscientist goes further, foregrounding the notion that ‘We now know that Proust was
right about memory’ (2007: xi), and that he was one of numerous Modernist artists who
‘discovered truths about the human mind real, tangible truths that science is only now
rediscovering’ (2007: ix). By contrast, I will here attribute to Proust neither the intention to
engage in a proto-scientific study of memory, nor the achievement of intuitive access to
‘truths’ about memory that have only recently been ‘confirmed’. I do not claim that Proust
‘knew’ more about memory than, for example, William James or Paul Sollier, or that his
project was an essentially scientific one in the guise of literature. However, the implications
and effects of Proust’s specifically literary engagement with memory are rich and complex,
and I hope to show that recognising the mutual relevance of cognitive questions and the
Search can be beneficial to scholars of Proust and of memory.
In the context of an approach encompassing cognitive-scientific perspectives, biographical
considerations raise further questions related to the problematic notion of Proust as scientist.
Proust was in close touch with the scientific and epistemological advances of his time: he was
a passionate amateur psychologist from an early age (Zéphir, 1959: 13-31), and kept abreast
of advances in the psychology of memory (Jackson, 1966: 12-13). Proust’s interest in work
by contemporary psychologists suggests that his textual treatment of memory need not be
considered as divorced from the discourse and findings of his era’s science. However,
although Prousts engagement with contemporary science makes it likely that numerous
currents of indirect influence and assimilation were at play in his fictional evocation of
memory, any specific, direct influence is hard to prove. Even the relationship between Proust
and Bergson, which is frequently held to be especially close, is problematic both personally
and conceptually (see e.g. Delacour, 2001: 260-1), and may best be seen as a matter of
‘adaptation’ rather than ‘imitation’ (Nalbantian, 2003: 62). Comparisons of Proust’s novel
with scientific discourses contemporary to his writing cannot avoid complex and often
irresolvable questions of ‘influence’ and ‘intention’, whereas an approach based on the
findings and debates of recent cognitive science need posit no such connection.
Current cognitive science will be the basis for this inquiry, because its theories constitute the
best understanding of memory currently available. My use of a scientific framework assumes
neither that science makes absolute progress, nor that science is a unified entity from which
findings can unproblematically be abstracted and re-applied. The cognitive sciences
constitute (as the common plural suggests) a processual site of heterogeneous and often
competing theories and traditions. Scientific ‘truth’ is at any point only the theory whose
hypotheses and results best fit the current paradigm, in a Kuhnian sense (see Kuhn, 1996
[1962]). Especially in the study of the mind, however, new ground is constantly being
broken, and indeed, some of the most exciting developments in the cognitive sciences occur
when disparate disciplines (experimental psychology and philosophy of mind or artificial
intelligence, for example) collaborate and create convergences. On the whole there is
progress, not from falsity to truth, but either from demonstrably incorrect theories to more
accurate ones, or from sketchy theories to more complete ones. As long as we bear these
limitations in mind, it can be considered meaningful to analyse Proust’s text in terms of its
cognitive realism by engaging with late 20th-century and early 21st-century scientific results
and debates.
Parts of the following analysis will also refer to certain facets of ‘folk psychology: the
concepts and convictions that make up people’s everyday notions of human psychology, and
more specifically, attributions of law-governed qualities to psychological events for
example, the causal connection of smell with memory in popular understanding.4 In folk
psychology, as opposed to psychological science, there is relatively little difference between
the early 20th century and the early 21st, since folk-psychological notions are affected much
less by current scientific trends than by enduring perceptions of experiential cause and effect
(see e.g. Churchland, 1981: 74-6): the enduring nature of these principles is evidenced by
their relatively unchanging expression in, for example, popular proverbs. The substantial
effects of psychoanalysis on everyday conceptions and expressions of psychological
phenomena in the early 20th century may be seen as an exception to this stability, but many of
its bequests to everyday language repression, denial, the ego, and so on may in fact be
better seen as new terms for age-old concepts in the Platonic tradition. For my purposes here,
no substantial difference will be assumed between the folk psychology of Proust’s time and
of our own.
Folk psychological concepts and explanations constitute a rich and detailed framework for
understanding human psychology; many of its tenets are context-specific, although many are
also generalized to account for, predict, or guide behaviour or beliefs (Ohreen, 2004: 114-15).
Archival metaphors of memory and their associated predictions regarding memory function
have, for example, long predominated in the folk psychology of memory (see e.g. Burton,
2008: 322). These can be seen as a specific instance of the broader conceptual metaphor ‘the
mind is a container’ (Solomun, 2011: e.g. 25; see also Lakoff and Johnson, 2003: e.g. 148,
152), and serve the cognitive function of allowing memory to be understood in terms of our
everyday interactions with physical objects. These archival metaphors generally work well
enough to yield useful explanations, predictions, and strategies (otherwise they would not
have lasted millennia). However, Jens Brockmeier (2010) shows how they are inadequate to
account for many specific memory characteristics suggested by recent science. More broadly,
although there are some areas in which folk psychology and psychological theory converge,
Garth Fletcher (1995) points out that there are also many important differences between
scientific and folk-psychological accounts of cognition. The scientific distinctions between
episodic and semantic memory, or declarative and procedural memory, for example, ‘cut[] up
the dispositional cake’ quite differently from distinctions in folk psychology between ‘beliefs,
attitudes, abilities, and the like’ (1995: 35-6).
Finally, one might argue that conclusions about cognitive realism based on the workings of
memory in the general population cannot be applied to the literary output of a genius
someone who, by definition, differs from the psychological norm. There is evidence that
creative writers exhibit especially high rates of severe and lifelong personality deviations
(compared with the general population and with other types of creative individual), in
particular with avoidant, obsessive-compulsive, and dependent characteristics, and certain
emotional traits (Post, 1994). Proust is one of the writers whom Felix Post diagnoses with
severe psychopathology. However, even in relatively severe cases, memory effects such as
intrusive and repetitive flashbacks, and their emotional and behavioural consequences, can
still be accounted for by general psychological principles (see e.g. Holmes and Hackmann
(eds), 2004). More ‘positive’ features of creativity, such as problem-solving and the ability to
perceive novel connections, may be linked to working-memory capacity, for example, but do
not obviously implicate the aspects of memory function and experience discussed in this
article. My working assumption is that Proust’s memory and memory in the general
population are likely to differ in degree rather than in kind. And, after all, the memories in the
Search are of course fictional constructions, not (or as well as) specific psychological events
experienced by the author of the novel.
With reference to specific areas of memory research, then, I will show that the madeleine
episode is in part cognitively realistic (corresponding to cognitive realities, as documented by
current science) and in part cognitively unrealistic (corresponding to common folk-
psychological assumptions about cognition, or about the narration of cognition). Furthermore,
defining the madeleine episode as an instance of involuntary memory, and more generally
considering voluntary and involuntary memory as categorical opposites, as Proust usually
presents them and we generally think of them, becomes problematic when we consider the
textual details in light of scientific research. The episode’s negotiation of the (apparent)
boundaries between voluntary and involuntary memory is crucial to the novel’s structure, not
least because it complicates Proust’s generally categorical distinction between the two.
Returning to the text can thus deepen our understanding of both textual and cognitive
phenomena, and how they interact.
2. Involuntary memory: introductory remarks
Involuntary memory was first systematically categorized by the psychologist Hermann
Ebbinghaus, who in 1885 (1-2) distinguished between past ‘psychische Zustände’ (mental
states) that are reproduced either ‘willkürlich’ or ‘unwillkürlich’ (voluntarily or
involuntarily), the latter ‘ohne jedes Zuthun des Willens, scheinbar von selbst’ (without any
involvement of the will, seemingly of their own accord). Other psychologists contemporary
to Proust, such as Henri Bergson, William James, Frédéric Paulhan, and Théodule-Armand
Ribot, studied the related phenomenon of ‘affective memory’, although without making
strong claims about its voluntary or involuntary nature (see Jackson, 1966: 240-42). Proust
acknowledged literary forebears in his evocation of (sense-cued) involuntary memory,
including François-René de Chateaubriand, Gérard de Nerval, and Charles Baudelaire (VI
228-29), but heightened its significance as the mediator of a Modernist form of epiphany
founded on intermittency. When the first volume of the Search was published in 1913, Proust
gave an interview with Elie-Joseph Bois (reproduced in Kolb and Price, 1971: 215-20) in
which he stated that ‘mon œuvre est dominée par la distinction entre la mémoire involontaire
et la mémoire volontaire’ (‘my work is dominated by the distinction between involuntary
memory and voluntary memory’).5 He cited the madeleine as the prime example.
Since then, involuntary memory as a phenomenon in itself (as distinct from the involuntary
processes intrinsic to voluntary memory) has not been investigated nearly as thoroughly as its
voluntary counterpart partly because it is less susceptible to systematic laboratory study
(see Ball, 2007). Many of the existing scientific papers on involuntary memory, such as John
H. Mace’s (2004) article ‘Involuntary Autobiographical Memories Are Highly Dependent on
Abstract Cuing: The Proustian View Is Incorrect’, have engaged with its evocation by Proust,
and the madeleine episode in particular. Yet most of these studies quote or paraphrase the text
so selectively that crucial aspects of the experience evoked are omitted: in general, the
focalizer’s tasting of the tea and cake is followed by an ellipsis which makes the transition
from tasting to remembering seem instantaneous (e.g. Baars et al., 2007; Berntsen, 2007; Chu
and Downes, 2000a; Herz and Schooler, 2002).6 I will try to show that what occurs between
the two is crucial to understanding and classifying this memory experience in terms of its
cognitive realism (see also Jellinek, 2004).
The novel’s opening pages describe the focalizer as lying in bed remembering his childhood,
but able to remember only very specific, decontextualized times and places, primarily the
events surrounding his bedtime (I 7-46). Anything else, the narrator declares, would in any
case have been furnished only by ‘voluntary memory, the memory of the intelligence’, which
is inherently limited: ‘since the information it [voluntary memory] gives about the past
preserves nothing of it, I would never have had any desire to think about the rest of Combray.
It was all really quite dead for me’ (I 46). The chance occurrence of being offered lime-
flower tea and cake by his mother at the end of a tiring winter’s day (I 44-48) is what allows
the focalizer to remember more of his childhood than just ‘the theatre and drama of my
bedtime’ (I 47), in a manner clearly presented in opposition to voluntary memory. After
tasting a tea-soaked spoonful of madeleine, an initial experience of unidentified ‘delicious
pleasure’ (I 47) has to be interrogated as to its origins, and threatens to fade with repeated
tastes of the stimulus.7 The focalizer tries self-directed concentration and creative search,
reconstructs the initial state and flavour, refreshes himself with distraction,8 then tries a
further reconstruction; he senses a perceptual memory-image failing to emerge fully, fears it
lost, tries ten times to reach it, resisting the laziness of letting it go, and at last suddenly
grasps the memory of being given the cake by his aunt on Sunday mornings at Combray. This
realization leads to remembrance of the house, the street, the town, and its inhabitants
which in turn launches the narrative of events between ages about five and fourteen. The
focalizer comes to understand the madeleine episode only near the end of the final volume,
when more involuntary memories make him reflect on their qualities, consequences, and
meaning.
3. The madeleine episode: cognitively realistic aspects
The madeleine episode’s evocation of memory is cognitively realistic in four important ways:
in the relationship between the focalizer’s life-situation and the afternoon when he eats the
madeleine, in his mental and occupational state when the madeleine is tasted, in the
emotionality of odour- or flavour-cued memories, and in the longevity of such memories.
Involuntary memory can be understood as arising from the interaction of a current life-
situation and the immediate situation, the former exerting a priming effect on cues that appear
in the latter that is, making some stimuli more or less likely to be noticed and to effectively
trigger memory experiences (Berntsen, 2007: 41). The focalizer’s current life-situation when
the madeleine episode occurs is clearly characterized as one of repeated reflection on the
years of his childhood, but accessing only memories of bedtime routines: ‘this sort of
luminous panel, cut out from among indistinct shadows’ (I 46). All other memories from this
period may be assumed to be very weakly activated during reminiscence (Mace, 2005): too
weakly to be experienced as memories at the time, but strongly enough to increase their
chances of subsequent retrieval, through associative priming. This means that, for at least a
few days after reminiscence (Mace, 2005: 882-83), cues such as the cake and tea, which seem
to occur and operate randomly, are in fact primed to be noticed and to induce memories of
their original occurrence. This happens, as the text has it, through ‘the attraction of an
identical moment’ (I 49): that is, through the workings of associative memory. A cognitive
connection is established by a single factor common to both a present and a past event, and to
both the immediate situation and the content of one of the weakly activated memories.
There is also evidence that the majority of involuntary memories occur in non-focussed, or
‘diffuse’, states of attention, and when people are alone, and/or engaged in routine or
automatic tasks which do not require full attention (e.g. Berntsen, 1998). This pattern may be
due to enhanced cue-processing in such states, or because an inhibitory mechanism
preventing such memories arising during focussed states is relaxed. The focalizer’s state prior
to eating is non-focussed, and the act of doing so is automatic: he raises the spoon to his lips
‘mechanically’ (I 47), depressed by the day that is past and the one to come, but not dwelling
on the details of either. His life situation, then, is one of dissatisfaction with the present and
preoccupation with the past, a combination sharpened by the immediate situation: his
temporary coldness, tiredness, and inattentiveness. The ‘chance’ appearance of the madeleine
is therefore in fact highly primed to be noticed and to act as an effective memory cue
primed by the life situation (dissatisfaction and reminiscence) and by a non-focussed state
and mechanical task.
A key characteristic of the madeleine episode consists in the combination of the sensory
(primarily olfactory) cue and its strong emotional effect. Here too the evocation of cognition
is cognitively realistic. The lateral olfactory stria (which connects the olfactory bulb to other
brain areas)9 has a direct anatomical connection with the amygdala-hippocampus complex,
the ‘neural substrate of emotional memory’ (Herz and Schooler, 2002: 22). Thus olfactory
information has direct access to emotion- and memory-related neural areas, which helps
explain the potency of odours and flavours in triggering emotionally potent memories. But
although ‘Proustian’ memory is usually described as emotionally charged, the text itself
presents the memory-emotion connection rather differently. The most obvious focus of
empirical studies on emotion, memory, and olfaction is the emotional quality of the original
event-stimulus or of the odour-cued memories. In the madeleine episode, however, the
memory initially triggered by the tea-soaked cake is not essentially imbued with emotions
the central event remembered, of being given tea and cake on Sunday mornings, is quite
ordinary, although events later associated with it by temporal contiguity are more emotionally
laden. Furthermore, what causes the pleasure is not the remembering (this has not yet
occurred), but the experience of tasting again the once-familiar flavour. Recognition occurs
long before remembering does, as first signalled by the focalizer instinctively dipping a piece
of madeleine into his tea, just as his aunt used to do.10 The ‘delicious pleasure’ and the
‘powerful joy’ (I 47) are emotions in the present, induced by the experience of familiarity
even before retrieving the memories associated with it.
The neurological connection between olfaction and emotion, with only two synapses
separating the olfactory nerve from the amygdala (Herz and Engen, 1996: 300) or, more
precisely, the lateral olfactory stria from the cortico-medial region of the amygdala , entails
‘a special physiological preparedness for odors to acquire emotional significance beyond that
of the other senses’ (ibid.: 309). Furthermore, olfactory and gustatory neural messages
converge in orbitofrontal cortex, which has reciprocal informational links with the amygdala,
and plays an important role in mediating hedonic experience and sensory reward/punishment
associations (Kringelbach, 2005). The focalizer’s mood-change is thus explicable with
reference to the ‘strong signal [. . .] sent from the olfactory system, reinforced by the taste
system, to the reward center in the orbitofrontal cortex’ (Utermohlen, 2002: 102). Explicit
memory retrieval is therefore not necessary for the odour to induce emotion.
An additional factor, the ‘exposure effect’, may also be at work here, however. The exposure
effect is the pleasure we find in and preferences we form for familiarity; this well-
documented phenomenon can be explained with recourse to the positive emotion that results
from processing fluency (Bornstein, 1989). Studies on the exposure effect with odour and
flavour have in general confirmed its existence, especially with initially unfamiliar foods (as
tea-soaked madeleine will have been to the young boy) and especially with delay between
exposure and rating (Bornstein, 1989: 278; see also Sulmont et al., 2002). Furthermore,
olfactory perception and preference are determined by past experience more than other
sensory modalities (Stevenson and Boakes, 2003; see also Shepherd-Barr and Shepherd,
1998: 53-54). This fact, combined with the positive emotional effects of familiarity, may
heighten the neuroanatomically determined emotional effects of the odour/flavour
experience. Thus we can account for the focalizer’s extreme positive reaction in a more
nuanced way than previously. Even before the odour and flavour are explicitly identified or
their associated memories retrieved, positive emotion is likely to be induced by a
combination of neurological determinants and the exposure effect.
The strong neurological link between olfaction, emotion, and memory also means that
olfactory cues are strikingly effective at retrieving even very old memories. Studies suggest
that although accuracy of short-term recognition is lower for odours than for visual stimuli, in
long-term memory much less olfactory than visual information is lost (e.g. Engen and Ross,
1973). If olfactory elements of experiences are especially enduring, other elements may have
decayed too much to serve as retrieval cues, but still be accessible enough to be retrieved
when cued by olfactory aspects of the same experience. Precisely this is evoked in the
madeleine episode:
of these recollections abandoned so long outside my memory, nothing
survived, everything had come apart; the forms and the form, too, of the little
shell made of cake, so fatly sensual within its severe and pious pleating had
been destroyed, or, still half asleep, had lost the force of expansion that would
have allowed them to rejoin my consciousness. But, when nothing subsists of
an old past, after the death of people, after the destruction of things, alone,
frailer but more enduring [French ‘vivace’], more immaterial, more persistent,
more faithful, smell and taste still remain for a long time, like souls,
remembering, waiting, hoping, on the ruin of all the rest, bearing without
giving way, on their almost impalpable droplet, the immense edifice of
memory. (I 49-50)
Here the madeleine’s appearance has lost the capacity to induce cognitive ‘expansion’ in
neurological terms, the activation of synaptic connections strengthened by previous
encounters with the stimulus but its odour and flavour retain this capability. This may partly
be a function of the specific case: the narrator remarks just prior to these lines (I 49) how
often he had since seen madeleines, without ever smelling or tasting them, so that their
appearance had become dissociated from the memory by repeated exposure leading to cue
overload (see Watkins, 1990: 331-32), where their odour and flavour had not. However, these
lines also underscore the nature of odour and flavour as more ‘frail’ and insubstantial it is,
for instance, notoriously difficult to verbalize the complex ‘odour images’ created by activity
within the olfactory bulb (Shepherd, 2006: 318) but conversely more ‘enduring’,
‘persistent’, and ‘faithful’ than vision (or hearing). Empirical data speak to this
characterization: one laboratory study (Herz and Cupchik, 1992) found that odour-cued
memories are highly emotional (60.4% of participants’ memories were rated thus), vivid
(50.9% were rated ‘very clear’), specific, rare, and relatively old (25.6% of those dated to
periods earlier than the past 12 months were from the ‘early childhood’ period).
4. The madeleine episode and folk psychology
Memories cued by olfactory sensations therefore seem privileged in several ways. There is,
however, also evidence that the vividness and specificity (and, by implication, accuracy) of
odour-cued memories may be exaggerated because of their emotional quality, which creates a
greater sense of being ‘brought back’ by the memories, leading them to be reported as more
vivid and specific than they actually are (e.g. Herz and Schooler, 2002). It has also been
suggested that the greater age of odour-cued memories may be an illusion created by their
greater inaccessibility (Rubin et al., 1984); but other data, based on older participants’
memories, demonstrate a significant shift back in the ‘memory bump’ for odour-cued as
opposed to verbally cued memories (Chu and Downes, 2000b). So the ‘fidelity’ of such
memories may be an illusion, but the ‘persistence’ (longevity) and ‘endurance’ (including an
emotional power to ‘bring back (to life)’, in the adjective ‘vivace’) seem less likely to be.
Proust seems to tap into cognitive realities (as conceived by current science) regarding the
longevity and power of odour-cued memory, and, as further explored below, perhaps rather
into our assumptions about cognition regarding the vividness and specificity of odour-cued
memories.11 This latter aspect the correspondence to assumptions about cognition rather
than to cognitive realities is one possible cognitively unrealistic feature of the episode.
The episode taps into ‘folk psychology’ rather than what seem to be the cognitive realities in
a second respect: the relative frequencies of sensory and other cues in eliciting involuntary
memories. Recent evidence suggests that, contrary to popular belief, involuntary memories
are more likely to be triggered by abstract or verbal cues than by sensory or state
(physiological or mood) cues. Mace (2004) found that 68% of participants’ involuntary-
memory experiences were triggered by verbal cues, with only 30% due to sensory cues and
2% to state cues. Of the sense-cued memories, only a small number 3% of the total
memories were induced by odours or flavours. Here too, the memories’ emotional quality
may be responsible for misconceptions: Mace suggests that this, and a stronger sense of being
‘brought back’, makes sense-cued involuntary-memory experiences more salient and hence
memorable than those triggered by abstract/verbal cues, thus making them seem a more
common occurrence than they really are. Sense-cued memories are also, Mace suggests,
likely to be less congruent with current cognitive activity, again making them more salient
and less likely to be confused with a voluntary memory, as may occur if the cue is a thought
or the reading of a word (2004: 898-99).
5. Folk psychology and narrative convention
A further consideration important to understanding Proust’s madeleine episode is the
specificity and extent of the retrieved memories. These constitute arguably the episode’s
single greatest deviation from cognitive realism in the evocation of memory. The quantity of
details that, in the following section of the novel, are narrated implicitly as being recalled
about location, people, and especially conversations goes beyond everyday inflations of the
amount of detail provided by odour/flavour-cued memories. The imperfect tense used
throughout much of ‘Combray II’ invites the interpretation that the dialogue, for instance, is
not being recalled and recorded verbatim (an implausible feat of memory for a normal
human), but is being reconstructed and paraphrased from numerous similar specific episodes.
This would correspond more accurately to the psychological facts than does the widespread
folk concept of memory as a static storage capacity; memory is more ‘reconstruction’ than
‘reproduction’ (Bartlett, 1932; Schacter and Addis, 2007). Nonetheless, there are many
instances of dialogue tagged by the simple past (‘dit-il’, ‘demandai-je’; ‘he said’, ‘I asked’,
etc.). Furthermore, the structural conceit which makes the madeleine the cognitive trigger for
remembrance of all that follows compels us to read the memories not as reconstructed by
‘intellectual’, or voluntary, memory, but as yielded spontaneously (after the initial effort) by
involuntary memory. Similarly, although one sentence presents the effort (to remember) as a
creative, constructive act (‘Seek? Not only that: create’, I 48), it is contradicted both by all
the surrounding terminology of effortful search and by the final transition to sudden
recollection (‘And suddenly the memory appeared’, I 49). Thus our understanding of what
the focalizer remembers is subject to an irresolvable tension: either the memories are
themselves cognitively unrealistic (as highly detailed spontaneous recollections), or they
contradict (as retrospective reconstructions) much of the textual evidence of searching and
finding, and the madeleine episode’s wider import as a trigger of involuntary memories that
instantaneously bring back a whole era.12
The double internal focalization of the Search foregrounds the questions of who narrates, and
therefore who remembers; the novel’s memory-based structure thus inevitably entails a
conflict between the textual scope and detail, and the evocation of remembering as a
cognitive activity. And given the further aim to contrast voluntary and involuntary memory,
the former’s capacities have to be denigrated and the latter’s exaggerated, to make the novel
possible. As a novel, this works rather well, since the less attention is drawn to
incompleteness or informational gaps, the more coherently, reassuringly familiar a narrative
seems. Cognition and consciousness consist of fundamentally multiple, parallel, non-unified
processes, and Daniel Dennett’s (1991) metaphor of ‘multiple drafts’ is in this sense more
accurate than the folk-psychological commonplace of a single ‘stream of consciousness’
(James, 1891: I 360). Nonetheless, the habit of narrativizing making retrospectively
meaningful, linear, and singular narratives out of one’s own experiences is ubiquitous,
whether the narratives are unarticulated or made public: ‘An important property of the life
story, both linguistically and psychologically, is that is must be coherent. Its coherence is not
a property of the life, but rather an achievement of the speaker in constructing the story’
(Linde, 1987: 346). Literary narratives that do this therefore have an instinctive appeal, which
increases the more proficiently they balance referential detail with efficient meaningfulness.
Important things should no more be missing than trivial things should be included, so that the
effect of reality itself, with all its potentially unsettling aspects, is subordinated to the ‘effet
de réel’, the reality effect (Barthes, 1986). This is what the sections following the
madeleine’s consumption achieve, deflecting the question of how much could realistically be
remembered through the ease with which familiar cognitive narratives are set in motion.
Coherence as a property of memory reports rather than of the memories themselves is a
demand convergent with that of literary form. The description of ‘all of this which is
assuming form and substance’ (I 50) after eating the madeleine seems, indeed, ‘better suited
to the content of a self-narrative than the typical fragment of content associated with
involuntary autobiographical memories’ (Ball et al., 2007: 116). This observation reinforces
the conclusion that in the memories elicited as distinct from their cueing and retrieval the
relationship between narrative and psychological factors is especially complex: the narrative
of ‘remembered’ events taps into our expectations about what good narratives should do, but
these in turn may well derive from our cognitive habits of narrativization. We might therefore
conclude that the wealth of coherently linear ‘recalled’ events is cognitively unrealistic
because it belies the multiple parallelisms of cognitive activity, but feels plausible because it
corresponds to our folk-psychological understanding of cognition, based on our habits of
creating coherent cognitive narratives.
6. The madeleine episode as voluntary memory
We have now considered the ways in which the madeleine episode is cognitively realistic in
evoking an involuntary memory, and the ways in which it can be considered unrealistic in
corresponding to common habits and expectations rather than to what current science
suggests are the cognitive realities. Lastly, we will consider some ways in which the episode
is cognitively realistic, but not as involuntary memory and indeed how this category itself
may need reconsidering. The factors of specificity in initial remembering, and time and effort
taken to remember, are key here. Martin Conway has proposed that the preferred level of
access to autobiographical memory is the general event (e.g. a holiday, or a habitual weekend
excursion), rather than the specific event (e.g. going to a particular museum, a single time) or
the life period (e.g. the childhood years when one lived in the country) (Conway, 1996: 69-
70; see also Conway, 2005: 612). This can be considered the ‘basic level’ of autobiographical
memory (Rosch, 1977): at this level of specificity, memories yield the proportionally greatest
amount of information for the effort required to access them. And this is the level of
specificity at which the memories elicited by the madeleine initially emerge. The focalizer
realizes:
That taste was the taste of the little piece of madeleine which on Sunday
mornings at Combray (because that day I did not go out before it was time for
Mass), when I went to say good morning to her in her bedroom, my Aunt
Léonie would give me after dipping it in her infusion of tea or lime-blossom. (I
49)
The combination of the imperfect tense (in the French ‘je ne sortais pas’, ‘j’allais’, etc.) and
the explicit temporal marker of repetition (‘on Sunday mornings’) clearly denotes this as a
general event a repeated event, or a sequence of related events which is just accessible
enough through general autobiographical knowledge structures that it can, after some effort,
be retrieved, and just specific enough to trigger the numerous specific-event memories that
constitute the following text. Interestingly, though, the general-event priority posited by
Conway applies to voluntary rather than to involuntary autobiographical memory; substantial
evidence suggests that amongst involuntary memories, where a hierarchical search process is
not required, there is a higher proportion of specific episodes relative to general events
(Berntsen, 1998 and 2007). This is a first clue that the madeleine episode involves something
other than self-evidently involuntary memory.
The madeleine episode also demonstrates, in exaggerated form, cognitive realism in a second
area that challenges the memory’s definition as involuntary: that of time-scale and effort. The
episode is structured by the striking slowness of autobiographical memory retrieval compared
to retrieval of other forms of knowledge, such as word meanings (which tends to take a few
hundred milliseconds) and autobiographical factual knowledge (around 1,200 milliseconds)
(Conway, 2005: 620). And memory experiences that require voluntary, ‘generative’ retrieval
are significantly slower than involuntary memories that are triggered spontaneously without
efforts of cue elaboration (Ball et al., 2007: 121-23). A recent study (Schlagman and
Kvavilashvili, 2008) using both laboratory and diary methods to compare retrieval times
found consistently longer mean retrieval times for voluntary memory (around 10 seconds)
than for involuntary memory (around 5 seconds). Retrieval may be all the more effortful and
time-consuming if it involves first identifying an odour/flavour cue; empirical research has
suggested that odours frequently elicit ‘tip-of-the-nose’ failures of identification, despite
strong feelings of familiarity. Lawless and Engen (1977), for instance, found that familiarity
judgements took an average of around 7 seconds, retrieval of associations around 9 seconds,
and naming around 12 seconds. I do not wish to suggest that this passage of Proust’s should
be expected to conform to (or diverge from) behavioural studies at the level of seconds or
milliseconds. However, the temporal guidelines provided here by scientific findings are
helpful in broaching the significant question of this memory’s status as voluntary or
involuntary.
In the madeleine episode, retrieval of associations only minimally precedes, or occurs
simultaneously with, identification: ‘And suddenly the memory appeared. That taste was the
taste of the little piece of madeleine’ (I 49). But overall, the process of memory retrieval
through odour identification is a long-drawn-out one. It is hard to tell precisely how much
time elapses between first tasting the madeleine and retrieving the associated memories:
descriptive detail is extensive at each stage, and deictic temporal indicators denote the
passage of time through references to contiguous sections of experience rather than to the
absolute intervals of clock time. Words and phrases such as ‘soon’, ‘immediately’, ‘at the
very instant when’, ‘As soon as I had recognized the taste’, and ‘Ten times I must begin
again’ (I 47-50) create a continuous sequence whose intervals are evoked only subjectively,
and whose frequent transitions between imperfect, pluperfect, present, and future tenses
create a network of cause and effect that expresses the significance and complexity of the
event without stating its duration explicitly. Nonetheless, the process clearly lasts for at least
many seconds, and probably many minutes. Although it is later clearly characterized as
involuntary, remembering here is much more like voluntary retrieval in terms of the time and
iterative effort involved.13
The definition of involuntary memory is that it (the memory itself, not just a preliminary
sensation or emotion) is triggered unintentionally, whether by internal (mental, emotional,
or state-related) or external (sensory or verbal) stimuli. A common misconception about the
madeleine episode is that the cued memory is ‘involuntary’ in the sense of requiring no
deliberate effort to be accessed.14 On the contrary, as has been pointed out by some memory
researchers and literary critics (e.g. Ball et al., 2007: 116; Delacour, 2001: 262; Ender, 2005:
32; Shepherd-Barr and Shepherd, 1998: 45-46, 54-5), considerable effort is involved in
rendering the memory identifiable and explicit. The focalizer’s questioning of his great
pleasure leads to identification of what is being sought as, specifically, ‘le souvenir’. After
this partial definition, a search specifically for that memory takes place, consisting of all the
stages described above (p. 00). Rather than an involuntary memory occurring in isolation, or
prompting subsequent elaboration by voluntary generative retrieval, the text clearly evokes
the process of generative retrieval, or cue elaboration, in which a given cue is cognitively
elaborated until episodic memories emerge, often in vivid perceptual-imaginative form.15
This culminates in a memory which feels involuntary because of its sensory cue, sudden
(though delayed) emergence, and vivid and comprehensive details, but which in experimental
terms would certainly be defined as the end-point of cue elaboration in voluntary memory.
This general-event memory in turn yields a great number of specific-event memories through
a process of memory chaining (Mace, 2007; see also Shepherd-Barr and Shepherd, 1998: 55).
All this seems to undermine the entire voluntary/involuntary distinction of which Proust
made so much, perhaps as will be discussed in conclusion because the neat theoretical
distinction could not be upheld in the narrative practice of extended psychological evocation.
Why, then, has the madeleine episode become so famous an example of involuntary
memory? The novel contains plenty of other striking instances of sense-cued involuntary
memory, notably the five cases in Finding Time Again (VI 174-96). There, although
deliberate effort may be involved in seeking out the ‘meaning’ of what is remembered, the
memories themselves in most cases come quickly and unbidden. Why should the madeleine
episode have eclipsed these other, rather better, examples? Elizabeth Jackson argues that it is
the most beautiful memory of its kind, and the most tension-filled and directly joyful
(Jackson, 1966: 185-86, 235-36). The madeleine episode is also the only instance of
‘involuntary memory’ that yields a substantial narrative of the past (Terdiman, 1993: 227). Or
perhaps the key is its use of an olfactory/gustatory cue to memory: given the privileged
neurological position of the olfactory system, the other examples may reasonably seem less
potent. Indeed, in Finding Time Again, the memories induced by sensations other than
odour/flavour or taste are discussed as examples of imaginative ‘tasting’ (French ‘goûter’,
translated as ‘enjoy’, VI 179-80), presenting this as a fundamental quality of ‘involuntary
memory’ and its metaphysical consequences. Any and all of these factors may contribute to
the madeleine’s preferential treatment in cultural history over the novel’s other, more clearly
involuntary memories.
The madeleine episode seems, then, a powerful evocation of memory in spite not because of
its intra- and extratextual presentation in opposition to voluntary memory; the
voluntary/involuntary distinction seems almost a red herring. Jackson suggests that the
involuntary quality of affective memory’ or ‘unconscious memory’ was an afterthought in
the evolution of involuntary memory in Proust’s thinking: originally, she argues, the
‘affective’ – emotional and sensory factors were key, and the involuntary element may later
have been emphasized to increase the contingency and hence drama (1966: 15). Richard
Terdiman argues that the voluntary/involuntary distinction which forms the novel’s
superstructure and its culmination is central to the unsuccessful attempt to reduce multi-
valence to singularity and contingency to the absolute by making memory solve all the
questions and problems the novel poses. This requires that the positive emotional effects of
the involuntary memories that counter the deadening effects of habit be exaggerated, along
with the freedom of involuntary memory from the suspect distortions of ‘conscious’
subjectivity that shape voluntary memory (1993: 155, 181-83, 209-12, 227, 235).
7. Voluntary and involuntary memory in the Search and beyond
Although in the Search itself Proust does not explicitly use the term involuntary memory (‘la
mémoire involontaire’) to denote experiences like that of the madeleine, the
voluntary/involuntary opposition is nonetheless conceptually significant in the novel. The
notion of the involuntary is frequently paraphrased, as for instance when the episodes of
sense-cued remembering are discussed in Finding Time Again:
their primary character was that I was not free to choose them, that they were
given to me just as they were. And I sensed that this was the mark of their
authenticity. I had not been looking for the two uneven paving-stones in the
courtyard where I stumbled. But the very fortuity, the inevitability of the
manner in which the sensation was encountered, controlled the authenticity of
the past that it resuscitated, the images it let loose, since we feel it striving
towards the light, we feel the joy of the real, found again. (VI 187)
The ‘authenticity’ of such memories, and the ‘joy of the real, found again’ which they induce,
derive from their being unsusceptible to choice, to being sought out, and instead being both
‘fortuitous’ (will power not causing them) and ‘inevitable’ (will power unable to avoid them).
These facets are emphasized in the madeleine episode by remarks on the taking of tea being
‘contrary to my habit’ and the acceptance of it occurring ‘I do not know why’ (I 47); these
interjections stress that there was no ‘deliberate’ seeking-out of the stimulus. As we have
seen, though, the involvement of priming effects means that the ‘deliberate’ and the ‘chance’
are less distinct than Proust would have them be.
Distinctions contributing to the fundamental claim to authenticity through unwilled chance
are woven through the novel: the ‘conscious’ is repeatedly opposed to the ‘unconscious’,
‘intelligence’ to ‘sensation’ or ‘impression’. These oppositions can be seen as reflecting the
cultural importance of the unconscious in early 20th-century Europe, as the artistic avant
garde responded to Freud’s expansion and popularizing of pre-existing theories of the
unconscious, and psychoanalytic terminology became part of everyday discourse. All these
oppositions are bound up with that only partially articulated voluntary/involuntary
dichotomy,16 and all express an essentially dualist conception of selfhood and subjectivity.
The value judgements associated with this dualism in the Search are not simplistic: the
passage partially quoted above also intimates that the ‘unconscious’ pole, the ‘sensation’, is
not itself the end-point, but the means to a ‘new truth’, or a ‘precious image’, conveyed
through the ‘signs’ or ‘hieroglyphics’ of the sensory stimuli; this preserves a valid role for
intelligence and intellectual knowledge (VI 186-87; see also 207). Ender (2003: 28) argues
that the madeleine episode represents a shift in the rememberer’s conception of memory,
from a privileging of mind over body to a recognition of the latter’s importance. But this of
course does not dissolve dualism: the acknowledgement that there are two poles perhaps even
reinforces their opposed nature.
Such oppositions, however subtly structured, presuppose that there is a fundamental
difference between doing something voluntarily and doing it involuntarily, and between
intellect and sensation (a sensation arising and experienced involuntarily, its intellectual
interpretation then willed). In Proust’s discourse, these oppositions are inseparable from the
oppositions between a controlling ‘consciousness’ and the otherwise uncontrolled and more
authentic workings of the ‘unconscious’, and between a ‘mind’ and the ‘matter’ of brain
and body. Neither of these related oppositional structures is supported by psychological or
physiological evidence.17 Work in psychology has suggested, for example, that factors such
as priority, consistency, and exclusivity in the relation between a thought and an action alter
the degree to which a sense of control over even forced actions is experienced (Wegner and
Wheatley, 1999). Proprioceptive and kinaesthetic feedback also play an important role
(Nahmias (2005: 773-74), in a critique of Wegner). We may therefore conceive of the
experience of agency as constituted by a complex set of factors which cannot be neatly
divided into voluntary and involuntary. Experiments in neuroscience, meanwhile, have
demonstrated that neural activity (in specific areas of fronotopolar and parietal cortices)
encodes the outcome of a decision up to ten seconds before awareness of the outcome (Soon
et al., 2008), further blurring the voluntary/involuntary distinction and sharpening the
question of what role, if any, consciousness plays in voluntary action.
Ultimately, we may conclude that drawing a categorical distinction between voluntary and
involuntary actions (or decisions, or memory retrievals) requires an invocation of what
Dennett (1991) calls the Cartesian Theatre: the place in the brain where everything comes
together ‘in consciousness’, and where the privileged audience of one watches the
performance. The Cartesian Theatre entails a dualist boundary between the conscious and the
unconscious and equally, I argue, between the voluntary and the involuntary that can be
upheld ‘all the way in’, to the micro-level of neural events. Whether or not this is explicitly
envisaged in the stronger terms of an inner homunculus as an ‘I’ who acts (decides,
retrieves), the same basic, potentially misleading structure is at work (see also Blackmore,
2005: e.g. 128-31). Any given action, decision, or memory retrieval is perhaps better thought
of as beginning when it does because neurological, physiological, and environmental factors
combine at a given moment to make the process start.
Thus the memory categories ‘voluntary’ and ‘involuntary’ become as questionable as are
those of conscious and unconscious. George Mandler (2007) points out that we have no
theory of consciousness which could tell us how ‘voluntary’ thought comes about – and
empirical evidence to refute its existence and suggests an alternative to the
voluntary/involuntary and conscious/unconscious pairings: ‘expected’ and ‘unexpected’,
envisaged as a continuum rather than an oppositional distinction. The more expected and the
more unexpected might denote, respectively, lesser or greater deviation from current
cognitive activity, physiological and mood states, and action goals. This would complement a
perspective outlined above (p. 00): one of Mace’s possible explanations of people’s tendency
to over-estimate the proportion of sense-cued involuntary memories was that these may
present a more salient contrast with current cognitive activity, and hence seem more
obviously and memorably ‘involuntary’ (Mace, 2004). In other words, memories seem
involuntary because they come as a surprise, are unexpected. Whether the immanent cue is a
flavour, an emotion, a mood, a physical state or action, a word, or a thought, the ensuing
process is not categorically different; a ‘thought’ should arguably not have a status entirely
different from that of other potential cues, because it is no more ‘intended’ by the non-
existent Cartesian Theatre’s audience of one (Dennett, 1991).
Some brain-imaging data provide evidence of a neuroanatomical dissociation between
voluntary and involuntary recall, but a number of these studies are based on problematic
assumptions such as the equation of recognition with recall, and there is also evidence to the
contrary: for example, activation of the amygdala, hippocampus, and dorsolateral prefrontal
cortex regardless of the ‘intentional’ or ‘incidental’ nature of retrieval (for a review see Hall,
2007). Discrepant results of this sort indicate that more investigation is needed of the neural
correlates of memory experiences associated with different cues, retrieval modes,
memory/recall characteristics, and post-retrieval monitoring/evaluation, not least in boundary
cases, to establish whether neural activation patterns denote a qualitative distinction or a
continuum. In this sense, while exploration of the varying conditions, qualities, and effects of
variously cued memories is invaluable, it may be inaccurate, if convenient, to create a sharp
dividing line between ‘voluntary’ and ‘involuntary’. Proust does this explicitly, for example
in the interview quoted above, and implicitly through paraphrase and antithesis in the Search
itself. But it is telling that his key instantiation of ‘involuntary memory’, the one which
introduces the theme and to which his narrator refers most often in the generalizing
conclusions of the final volume, resists this classification in a manner so striking that, if we
do want to retain the opposing categories, it falls into the wrong one.
8. Conclusion: The madeleine, memory, and readers’ responses
Literature’s most famous example of involuntary memory turns out not to be involuntary
after all; but as a detailed evocation of generative retrieval cued by an olfactory/gustatory
sensation, it is cognitively realistic in numerous aspects, and where it is unrealistic, our
narrativizing mental habits and our expectations regarding cognition and narrative coherence
mean that we probably accept it anyway. The episode performs the unlikely feat of never
being cognitively realistic in ways likely to forcefully contradict our expectations about
cognition. Without exception, the realistic features priming through reminiscence, state-
dependent retrieval, the emotionality and longevity of odour-/flavour-cued memories, the
effortful search sometimes required to identify odours and flavours and to retrieve the
memories associated with them can be aligned with common facets of folk psychology. We
have, for example, certain ‘common-sense’ expectations about memory which can be
connected to the archival metaphor of memory as static storage mentioned on p. 00 above:
these include the notion that remembering one thing makes related memories more likely
because stored items ‘nearby’ are more likely to be easily found and that memories come
easier when one’s mind is at rest because other activity is not interfering with the ‘search’
process. Where there are unrealistic features, they again converge with common assumptions
about memory (and narrative) that is, in the vividness and specificity of sense-cued
memories (and of narrative), and in the frequency of memories cued thus as opposed to by
abstract cues. Where realities and expectations converge, Proust evokes cognition
accordingly; where they diverge, he follows folk psychology rather than cognitive reality.
This means that we nowhere find cognitive realism contradicting expectations, entailing the
ambivalent response both compelled and unsettled that seems to occur when, for example,
Kafka evokes vision counter to our pictorialist assumptions (Troscianko, 2010) or when
Flaubert evokes memory counter to our understanding of it as static storage (Troscianko,
forthcoming 2012). Even the border case of vacillation between evoking the effort to
remember as searching/finding or creating leaves us free to choose the interpretation we
prefer, rather than imposing a counterintuitive one upon us.
Nonetheless, the result of all this is cognitively realistic in a highly counterintuitive manner:
the suggestion that there is no categorical distinction between voluntary and involuntary
memory. Because the madeleine episode defies the characterizations of it later in the novel
and elsewhere, by making ‘involuntary’ memory the stuff of protracted and effortful search,
it becomes ultimately more cognitively realistic than Proust himself, intent on rescuing past
reality from present distortion and authentic memory from the strictures of consciousness or
intelligence, may have wished to acknowledge. The major cognitively unrealistic feature
the amount of detail retrieved is a concession to expectations of completeness born of
mental habits and both fostered and satisfied by narrative conventions. However, even this
can be redefined as a form of cognitive realism if we reinterpret the episode’s one explicit
distinction between creating and seeking/finding (I 48) as in fact an acknowledgement that
they are always combined (the phrase is, after all, Seek? Not only that: create, I 48). While
remembering has some search-like qualities and a neural basis in ‘long-term potentiation’ of
synaptic connections, it is always creative too: every memory retrieval is a reconstruction,
never recreating exactly the same memory twice, and profoundly dependent on many aspects
of the present context (Brockmeier, 2010; Conway, 2005). The madeleine episode is
cognitively realistic despite the narrative’s (and Proust’s) later gloss on it as involuntary, and
despite the shift from extended effort to instantaneous ‘total recall’. Yet this fact seems very
easy to ignore, judging from the episode’s reception by critics, readers, and memory
researchers over the decades.
The most remarkable achievement of the madeleine episode is in allowing readers to read in
it confirmation of their assumptions about memory about flavour-cued memories being
involuntary, instantaneous, and rich in accurate detail; about remembering being only a
search of pre-existing contents rather than involving goal-orientated (re)creation whilst
simultaneously contradicting these assumptions. This effect is especially significant in a
novel which defied aesthetic conventions and readers’ expectations regarding many features,
including chronology, descriptive style, and syntax. In the area of memory, by contrast, the
text does not confront the reader forcefully with what is counterintuitive or unexpected, but
creates a more subtle challenge to expectations. Empirical research on readers unfamiliar
with the novel could help to establish how far this effect would hold if the episode were read
in isolation, without the later interpretive passages (and others’ reformulations of these)
affecting their responses.
In any case, the paradox is a striking, and psychologically telling, one: cognitive realism is in
some ways less powerful a force than are our assumptions about cognition, yet the two can
coexist quite happily within the same famous section of narrative. Here they contradict each
other yet may well manage to reap the rewards of both at once: the sense of pleasing
familiarity that may result from assumptions confirmed, and the sense of compelling ease
more likely to result when cognitive realities are directly tapped into. This allows the episode
to ‘smuggle through’ an idea that might otherwise be highly unsettling: that there is less
difference than we think between doing something voluntarily and doing it involuntarily. A
startling reality is there amongst all the compelling and reassuring features but they allow
us to ignore it if we wish. Maybe this is why the madeleine has become one of the world’s
most famously evocative flavours.
Acknowledgements
I thank Sue Blackmore, David Mossop, John Sutton, and three anonymous reviewers for their
generous and helpful comments on earlier versions of this article.
Funding
This research received no specific grant from any funding agency in the public, commercial,
or not-for-profit sectors.
Notes
1 Involuntary memories can also be ‘semantic’ (e.g. of words/tunes) but I use the term
‘involuntary memory’ to designate ‘involuntary autobiographical memory’ (of
events/experiences in one’s past).
2 The term ‘focalizer’ (deriving from Genette, 1980: 189-211) denotes the experiencer, as
opposed to the narrator, of the fictional events. In the Search, structured by ‘double internal
focalisation’ (Rogers, 1965: 121-23), the ‘I’ shifts between the naïvely experiencing and the
retrospective comprehending focalizers, who fuse in the final volume, when the latter
becomes his own narrator.
3 Epstein (2004) also offers a complex account of the emergence of Proust’s ‘theory of
aesthetic perception.
4 The prevalence of these associations between smell and vivid, emotional memories is
evidenced by testimony collected in 1935, before the Search had become a ubiquitous point
of reference (or source of bias) in this area (Laird, 1935). Donald Laird reports how
respondents to an inquiry about odour-cued memories provided rich documentation of how,
for example, ‘odors have been prodding my memory possibly throughout my life’ (127) or,
‘having long since come to the conclusion that in my particular case the sense of smell is an
especially effective memory-stimulus, I have accepted it and ceased to note down particular
cases’ (127). It thus seems legitimate to claim (pace Chu and Downes, 2002: 511) that Proust
taps into, rather than creating, such beliefs.
5 In the novel itself, the term ‘voluntary memory’ occurs three times, its opposite only once,
and merely in passing (VI 5).
6 This strategy is not limited to scientific commentators: see e.g. Lennon (2007).
7 On the neurological mechanisms of sensory adaptation, see Shepherd-Barr and Shepherd
(1998: 50).
8 See Mandler (1994) on the possible benefits of this.
9 The olfactory system processes odours and flavours either via orthonasal perception
(breathing in through the nose) or via retronasal perception (volatile molecules from food in
the mouth being pumped up from the back of the oral cavity when breathing out through the
nose). Eating the madeleine activates both olfactory routes, plus the gustatory system (via
tongue receptors for sweetness). The general emphasis, in experimental studies referring to
Proust, on odours alone is potentially problematic, since beyond their common connection to
the amygdala-hippocampus complex, flavour-processing involves multiple sensory
modalities, motor systems, and generally far more widespread neural activation than odour-
processing (Shepherd, 2006: 317).
10 See Shepherd-Barr and Shepherd (1998: 49) on how this strengthens the madeleine’s
aroma essences.
11 See Note 4.
12 On Proust’s ‘pseudo-iterative’, see Genette (1980: Ch. 3).
13 Shepherd-Barr and Shepherd (1998: 55) suggest neuroanatomical reasons for the
focalizer’s highly motivated state.
14 See p. 00 above for scientific commentators who overlook the time and effort involved in
the memory retrieval; and in literary studies, for example, the introductory essay by Jordan
(2001: 112-13) and the in-depth analysis by Zéphir (1959).
15 The specification ‘visual memory’ indicates the perceptual-imaginative nature of the
memory sought; see Conway and Pleydell-Pearce (2000: 263) on imagery and memory.
16 Delacour (2001: 257) notes that the equations voluntary = conscious and involuntary =
unconscious are untenable, but although he gives a common-sense example of how a memory
retrieval can be ‘involuntary’ but ‘fully conscious’, he does not ask whether a retrieval can,
conversely, be voluntary but unconscious, or interrogate what it means for a retrieval to be
conscious or unconscious in the first place. I suggest below that both distinctions are based on
the same problematic structures.
17 Although many neurobiological processes, e.g. the release of neurotransmitters, are
fundamentally non-conscious (and non-mental), this does not entail a distinction between
‘mental states’ as ‘conscious’ or ‘unconscious’.
References
Throughout the article, where volume and page number alone are cited refer to the following
edition of the book:
Proust M (2002 [1913-1927]) In Search of Lost Time. 6 vols, Prendergast C (general ed.).
London: Penguin.
Baars BJ, Ramamurthy U and Franklin S (2007) How deliberate, spontaneous, and unwanted
memories emerge in a computational model of consciousness. In: Mace JH (ed.)
Involuntary Memory. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 177-207.
Ball CT (2007) Can we elicit involuntary autobiographical memories in the laboratory? In:
Mace JH (ed.) Involuntary Memory. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 127-52.
Ball CT, Mace JH and Corona H (2007) Cues to the gusts of memory. In: Mace JH (ed.)
Involuntary Memory. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 113-126.
Barthes R (1986) The reality effect. In: Barthes R The Rustle of Language. Translated by R
Howard. Oxford: Blackwell, 141-48.
Bartlett, FC (1932) Remembering: A Study in Experimental and Social Psychology.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Berntsen D (1998) Voluntary and involuntary access to autobiographical memory. Memory 6:
113-41.
Berntsen D (2007) Involuntary autobiographical memories: Speculations, findings, and an
attempt to integrate them. In: Mace JH (ed.) Involuntary Memory. Malden, MA:
Blackwell, 20-49.
Blackmore S (2005) Consciousness: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Bogousslavsky J and Walusinski O (2009) Proust and Paul Sollier: The involuntary memory
connection. Schweizer Archiv für Neurologie und Psychiatrie 4: 130-36.
Bornstein RF (1989) Exposure and affect: Overview and meta-analysis of research, 1968-
1987. Psychological Bulletin 106: 265-89.
Brockmeier J (2010) After the archive: remapping memory. Culture and Psychology 16: 5-
35.
Burton J (2008) Bergson’s non-archival theory of memory. Memory Studies 1: 321-39.
Chu S and Downes JJ (2000a) Odour-evoked autobiographical memories: Psychological
investigations of Proustian phenomena. Chemical Senses 25: 111-16.
Chu S and Downes JJ (2000b) Long live Proust: The odour-cued autobiographical memory
bump. Cognition 75: B41-B50.
Chu S and Downes JJ (2002) Proust nose best: Odors are better cues of autobiographical
memory. Memory and Cognition 30: 511-18.
Churchland PM (1981) Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of
Philosophy 78: 67-90.
Conway MA (1996) Autobiographical memories and autobiographical knowledge. In: Rubin
DC (ed.) Remembering Our Past: Studies in Autobiographical Memory. New York:
Cambridge University Press, 67-93.
Conway MA (2005) Memory and the self. Journal of Memory and Language 53: 594-628.
Conway MA and Pleydell-Pearce C (2000) The construction of autobiographical memories in
the self-memory system. Psychological Review 107: 261-88.
Delacour J (2001) Proust’s contribution to the psychology of memory: The réminiscences
from the standpoint of cognitive science. Theory & Psychology 11: 255.
Dennett DC (1991) Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown.
Ebbinghaus H (1885) Über das Gedächtnis: Untersuchungen zur experimentellen
Psychologie. Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot.
Ender E (2005) Architexts of Memory: Literature, Science, and Autobiography. Ann Arbor:
University of Michigan Press.
Engen T and Ross BM (1973) Long-term memory of odors with and without verbal
descriptions. Journal of Experimental Psychology 2: 221-27.
Epstein R (2004) Consciousness, art, and the brain: Lessons from Marcel Proust.
Consciousness and Cognition 13: 213-240.
Fletcher GJO (1995) The Scientific Credibility of Folk Psychology. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum.
Genette G (1980) Narrative Discourse: An Essay in Method. Translated by JE Lewin. Ithaca,
NY: Cornell University Press.
Hall NM (2007) Experimental induction of involuntary memories. In: Mace JH (ed.)
Involuntary Memory. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 153-76.
Herz RS and Cupchik GC (1992) An experimental characterization of odor-evoked memories
in humans. Chemical Senses 17: 519-28.
Herz RS and Engen T (1996) Odor memory: Review and analysis. Psychonomic Bulletin &
Review 96: 300-13.
Herz RS and Schooler JW (2002) A naturalistic study of autobiographical memories evoked
by olfactory and visual cues: Testing the Proustian hypothesis. American Journal of
Psychology 115: 21-32.
Holmes E and Hackmann A (eds) (2004) Mental Imagery and Memory in Psychopathology.
Special issue: Memory 12 (4).
Jackson E (1966) L’Évolution de la mémoire involontaire dans l’œuvre de Marcel Proust.
Paris: Nizet.
James W (1891) The Principles of Psychology, 2 vols. London: Macmillan.
Jellinek JS (2004) Proust remembered: Has Proust’s account of odor-cued autobiographical
memory recall really been investigated? Chemical Senses 29: 455-58.
Jordan J (2001) The unconscious. In: Bales R (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Proust.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 100-16.
Kolb P and Price LB (eds) Textes retrouvés. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.
Kringelbach ML (2005) The human orbitofrontal cortex: Linking reward to hedonic
experience. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 6: 691-702.
Kuhn TS (1996) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Laird DA (1935) What can you do with your nose? Scientific Monthly 41:126-30.
Lakoff G and Johnson M (2003 [1980]) Metaphors We Live By. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Lawless H and Engen T (1977) Associations to odors: Interference, mnemonics, and verbal
labeling. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory 3: 52-59.
Lehrer J (2011) Proust Was a Neuroscientist. Edinburgh: Canongate.
Lennon TM (2007) Proust and the phenomenology of memory. Philosophy and Literature
31: 52-66.
Linde C (1987) Explanatory systems in oral life stories. In: Holland DC and Quinn N (eds)
Cultural Models in Language and Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
343-68.
Mace JH (2004) Involuntary autobiographical memories are highly dependent on abstract
cuing: The Proustian view is incorrect. Applied Cognitive Psychology 18: 893-99.
Mace JH (2005) Priming involuntary autobiographical memories. Memory 13: 874-84.
Mace JH (2007) Does involuntary remembering occur during voluntary remembering? In:
Mace JH (ed.) Involuntary Memory. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 50-67.
Mandler G (1994) Hypermnesia, incubation, and mind popping: On remembering without
really trying. In: Umiltà C and Moscovitch M (eds) Attention and Performance XV:
Conscious and Nonconscious Information Processing. Cambridge, MA: MIT, 3-34.
Mandler G (2007) Involuntary memories: Variations on the unexpected. In: Mace JH (ed.)
Involuntary Memory. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 208-23.
Nahmias E (2005) Agency, authorship, and illusion. Consciousness and Cognition 14: 771-
85.
Nalbantian S (2003) Memory in Literature: From Rousseau to Neuroscience. Basingstoke:
Palgrave Macmillan.
O’Brien J (1970) Proust confirmed by neurosurgery. PMLA 85: 295-97.
Ohreen DE (2004) The Scope and Limits of Folk Psychology; A Socio-Linguistic Approach.
Berne: Peter Lang.
Post F (1994) Creativity and psychopathology: A study of 291 world-famous men. British
Journal of Psychiatry 165: 22-34.
Rogers BG (1965) Proust’s Narrative Techniques. Geneva: Droz.
Rosch E (1977) Classification of real-world objects: Origins and representations in cognition.
In: Johnson-Laird PN and Wason PC (eds) Thinking: Readings in Cognitive Science.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rubin DC, Groth E and Goldsmith DJ (1984) Olfactory cuing of autobiographical memory.
American Journal of Psychology 97: 493-507.
Schacter DL and Addis DR (2007) The cognitive neuroscience of constructive memory:
Remembering the past and imagining the future. Philosophical Transactions of the
Royal Society 362: 773-86.
Schlagman S and Kvavilashvili L (2008) Involuntary autobiographical memories in and
outside the laboratory: How different are they from voluntary autobiographical
memories? Memory & Cognition 36: 920-32.
Shepherd GM (2006) Smell images and the flavour system in the human brain. Nature 444:
316-21.
Shepherd-Barr K and Shepherd GM (1998) Madeleines and neuromodernism: Reassessing
mechanisms of autobiographical memory in Proust. Auto/Biography Studies 13: 39-60.
Solomun S (2011) A Mobile Army of Metaphors: Archiving, Sharing, and Distributing the
Social in Digital Photography. Master’s dissertation, Queen’s University, Ontario.
Abstract and excerpt available at: http://hdl.handle.net/1974/6825.
Soon CS, Brass M, Heinze H-J and Haynes J-D (2008) Unconscious determinants of free
decisions in the human brain. Nature Neuroscience 11: 543-45.
Stevenson RJ and Boakes RA (2003) A mnemonic theory of odor perception. Psychological
Review 110: 340-364.
Sulmont C, Issanchou S and Köster EP (2002) Selection of odorants for memory tests on the
basis of familiarity, perceived complexity, pleasantness, similarity and identification.
Chemical Senses 27: 307-17.
Terdiman R (1993) Present Past: Modernity and the Memory Crisis. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
Troscianko E (2010) Kafkaesque worlds in real time. Language and Literature 19: 151-71.
Troscianko E (forthcoming 2012) The cognitive realism of memory in Flaubert’s Madame
Bovary. Modern Language Review 107: 775-99.
Turkle S (2007) What makes an object evocative? In: Turkle S (ed.) Evocative Objects:
Things We Think With. Cambridge, MA: MIT, 307-27.
Utermohlen V (2002) Was Proust a taster? Taste sensitivity to 6-n-propylthiouracil and the
relationships among memory, imagination, synesthesia, and emotional response to
visual experience. Food and Foodways 10: 99-109.
Watkins MJ (1990) Mediationism and the obfuscation of memory. American Psychologist 45:
328-35.
Wegner DM and Wheatley T (1999) Apparent mental causation: Sources of the experience of
will. American Psychologist 54: 480-92.
Zéphir JJ (1959) La Personnalité humaine dans l’oeuvre de Marcel Proust: Essai de
psychologie littéraire. Paris: Lettres Modernes.
Author biography
Emily Troscianko is currently Junior Research Fellow in Modern Languages at St John’s
College, Oxford, and an Associate Researcher with the Balzan Interdisciplinary Seminar
‘Literature as an Object of Knowledge’. Her doctoral thesis explored Kafka’s fiction in
relation to pictorialist and enactivist theories of vision, and she is now investigating the
evocation of other areas of cognition in French and German ‘Realist’ and ‘Modernist’
literature, with the broad aim of illuminating literary Realism from a cognitive perspective.
... All these fields generally acknowledge that the work of Proust is an important contribution to the psychology of memory. Indeed, cognitive and phenomenological studies have already used Proust's work as an effective strategy for investigating memory (Fuchs, 2012;Groes, 2016;Rowland, 2017;Troscianko, 2013). From the standpoint of the cognitive sciences, the studies have been focused on the cognitively realistic aspects of the madeleine-memory (Delacour, 2001;Troscianko, 2013). ...
... Indeed, cognitive and phenomenological studies have already used Proust's work as an effective strategy for investigating memory (Fuchs, 2012;Groes, 2016;Rowland, 2017;Troscianko, 2013). From the standpoint of the cognitive sciences, the studies have been focused on the cognitively realistic aspects of the madeleine-memory (Delacour, 2001;Troscianko, 2013). Phenomenologically, the studies on Proustian memory have been part of more comprehensive investigations on embodied temporality and memory (De Warren, 2009;Kaushik, 2008). ...
... Scholars have made some attempts to analyze Proustian memory within a taxonomy of memory from the standpoint of both cognitive science (Delacour, 2001;Troscianko, 2013) and phenomenology. However, it seems reasonable to embrace the phenomenological tradition because it aims "to overcome the dualism of representational mind and external world […] through the medium of the body" (Fuchs, 2016). ...
Article
Full-text available
This paper investigates the madeleine -memory (so-called from Proust's novel In Search of Lost Time ) as a case of pre-reflective experience, from the genesis of its sedimentation into the body. Indeed, I aim to address the question of the literary protagonist Marcel on the roots of his happiness and the genesis of his memories. Until now, the madeleine -memory has been described as bodily and involuntary. In phenomenology, a wide literature has confirmed the relationship between the sense of body ownership and pre-reflective self-awareness. I aim to build upon such a mutual link and show that the pre-reflective roots of the madeleine -memory have to be traced back to the genesis of the involuntary recollections. To this purpose, I will illustrate that the epistemological relationship between the object and the subject plays a relevant role in the way the subject remembers. First, I will present that madeleine -memory is a unique case of bodily memory, by analyzing the main features that characterize it. Secondly, I will analyze the original experience of the madeleine within the phenomenological logic of transcendence in immanence . For this aim, I will rely on the Husserlian notions of “epistemological inadequacy of perception” and “background experiences”. Through these notions, I will show that Proustian involuntary recollections are pre-reflective experiences because previously subjects have pre-reflectively experienced the content of recollections.
... It is clear that point 2 allows a scientific analysis of Proust"s experience in terms of the biology of memory. I found many papers dealing with this relationship [16][17][18][19][20][21][22] . But, having had a similar experience (Hypothesis 1), I found that certain suggestions/comments/ideas in some of them deserve a comment. ...
... But, having had a similar experience (Hypothesis 1), I found that certain suggestions/comments/ideas in some of them deserve a comment. Troscianko states that "…Proust"s engagement with contemporary science makes it likely that numerous currents of indirect influence and assimilation were at play in his fictional evocation of memory …" [16] . I do not think so. ...
... Th e famous madeleine scene, where the taste of a cake dipped in herbal tea causes an intense joy leading to the recovery of childhood memories, overshadows other meaningful nonmnemonic impressions and prevents the narrator (and many readers) from understanding its true signifi cance. 6 Occurring barely 30 or 40 pages into the novel, the madeleine scene can only hint at the fi nal revelation, and so it is not the ultimate truth of the novel. Just as love signs use the love object as a stand-in for a world outside of the lover, the intense pleasure derived from impression signs leads the narrator to search for the origin of the impression in another object. ...
Chapter
While Gilles Deleuze infamously described his early work in the history of philosophy as “a sort of buggery,” “making a child behind the back” of other thinkers by using their own words to produce a new and monstrous thought, his 1964 study of the novelist Marcel Proust, Proust and Signs, departs from this intraphilosophical procreation to embrace the uniqueness of literary thought. Instead of one philosopher rereading another, a philosopher engages with a novelist to bring out the philosophical implications of literary thought. Deleuze was one of the first readers of Proust to follow the logical chain of thought of In Search of Lost Time, arguing that the novel is not about memory or madeleines, but about the apprenticeship of signs.
... As the theory refers to the French novelist Marcel Proust who recalled his childhood after tasting a madeleine, a shell-shaped French sponge cake (Bray, 2013;Séraphin, 2021), the theory is often used in research related to the subconscious. MPT is also associated with other concepts, namely the concept of "habitus," which is about re-enacting some behaviour triggered by a specific context (Lukajic, 2020;Meguro, 2015;Troscianko, 2013;Vries & Elferen, 2010); and "lieu de mémoire", the materialisation of a community and/or individual heritage and/or memory (Benhaim, 2005). Nevertheless, Melyon-Reinette (2009, 2010 argues that from the second generation onward, a phenomenon referred to as "dediasporisation" occurs among the younger generation, in other words, a lessening of attachment to the country of origin. ...
Article
There is sufficient evidence in academic scholarship that points to the important role diaspora tourism plays for the economies of homeland communities and countries. Given previous research shows a decreased level of attachment to the homeland in the second generation of immigrants, this research seeks to explore the effects of childhood experiences on adult behaviours and outcomes in relation to diaspora tourism. The research reveals the important role played by families in transmitting knowledge, memories, traditions and other cultural practices to diaspora children. Destination Marketing Organisations (DMOs), however, are neglecting to engage this lucrative market partly because communication strategies are aimed at adults of the diaspora and not at children. Based on these findings, we propose DMOs take a child-centred approach by actively engaging diaspora children to devise tourism marketing strategies that are child-friendly.
... The possible explanations behind positive spillover effect among topics are not limited to social media, but rather intrinsic in human mind. For example, the evocation of memories by apparently unrelated events has been extensively studied in current cognitive studies (Troscianko, 2013). The most famous example of this phenomenom can be found in the novel Proust (1913), in which the author gives a famous description of the flood of sensations and memories of his childhood which were revived in him by the mere ingestion of a typical French cookie called "Madeleine". ...
Article
Full-text available
Can cultural representations be used to therapeutic effect in the treatment of mood disorders like depression and anxiety? This article develops a theoretical framework that outlines how this might be achieved by way of mid-level cultural metrics that allow otherwise heterogeneous forms of representation to be grouped together. Its prediction is that abstract representations—as measured by Shannon entropy—will impact positively on anxiety, where concrete representations will positively impact on depression. The background to the prediction comes from construal level theory, a branch of social psychology that deals with the effects of abstraction on psychological distance; the types of cultural representations analysed include image, narrative and film. With a view to evaluating the hypothesis, the article surveys the empirical literature in art therapy, creative bibliotherapy and cinema therapy.
Article
In this paper, I claim that self-knowledge is at the heart of Descartes’s Cogito. Following Hintikka, many commentators have focused their attention on the rational link between « I think » and « I exist », without proposing a unified account of the Cogito that could shed light both upon its structure and upon the essential role played by introspective self-knowledge. In addition, many contemporary theories of self-knowledge, inspired by Gareth Evans’ influential transparency intuition, have been put forward as reactions against a supposedly « Cartesian » image of introspection. In this context, Peacocke’s recent vindication of Descartes’ argument could prove to be a crucial milestone in the history of the Cogito’s readings. Departing boldly from Gilbert Ryle’s interpretation of Cartesian introspection as involving a privileged access to an inner world, Peacocke claims that the certainty of the Cogito is due to the very identity of the concepts involved in it. On this rationalist reconstruction, the transition from « I think » to « I exist » can be seen as both rational and non-inferential, and I argue that this could lead to a new understanding of the debate on the inferential character of the Cogito. I also argue, ultimately, that Peacocke does not deliver a fully unified theory of introspective self-knowledge.
Article
The current paper offers a selective review of the study of memory appraisal, focusing on recollections of the personal past, with the goal to bring attention to a missing component in this study. To date, memory appraisal studies have concentrated on participants’ assessments of the content of their personal recollections (e.g., their perceptual detail and story-like feel), including beliefs about the accuracy of that content. Participants’ assessments of reflection processes accompanying their recollections (e.g., a sense of piecing-together recollection fragments) have yet to be extensively examined. The lack of information on process-based appraisals is related to prior studies’ procedural constraints (e.g., kinds of cue prompts and their timing, minimal opportunities for reflection). Reasons for addressing this missing component provide the central themes of the paper. The reasons emerge from the analysis of autobiographical cueing studies, including integration of narrative research studies and autobiographical works. The analysis leads to suggestions for future research involving the use of personal narratives that are intended to address critiques of reconstruction accounts and unresolved questions in the study of memory appraisal.
Article
Full-text available
An important claim made for second-generation accounts of cognition is that they help solve the problem of dualism, which arguably remains unchallenged in much literary criticism. Kafka’s short story “Ein Hungerkünstler” (A Hunger Artist) is about a profoundly embodied experience of (unsuccessfully) denying embodiment: fasting to death. With this text’s cognitive realism as my focal point, I use insights from second-generation cognitive science (which acknowledges the embodied, embedded, enactive, and extended nature of human cognition), including studies of eating disorders and starvation, to provide purchase on two traditional literary-critical concerns: thematic interpretation and paradox. I also suggest that a first-person perspective which acknowledges the complexities of individual real-world embodiment may sometimes enrich cognitive literary studies. This combined first-person and second-generation methodology can help us recognise that for the real people who read our scholarship and learn from us, the dangers of dualism are ethically as well as interpretively profound.
Chapter
The papers in this volume, a multidisciplinary collaboration of anthropologists, linguists, and psychologists, explore the ways in which cultural knowledge is organized and used in everyday language and understanding. Employing a variety of methods, which rely heavily on linguistic data, the authors offer analyses of domains of knowledge ranging across the physical, social, and psychological worlds, and reveal the importance of tacit, presupposed knowledge in the conduct of everyday life. The authors argue that cultural knowledge is organized in 'cultural models' - storylike chains of prototypical events that unfold in simplified worlds - and explore the nature and role of these models. They demonstrate that cultural knowledge may take either proposition-schematic or image-schematic form, each enabling the performance of different kinds of cognitive tasks. Metaphor and metonymy are shown to have special roles in the construction of cultural models. The authors also demonstrates that some widely applicable cultural models recur nested within other, more special-purpose models. Finally, it is shown that shared models play a critical role in thinking, allowing humans to master, remember, and use the vast amount of knowledge required in everyday life. This innovative collection will appeal to anthropologists, linguists, psychologists, philosophers, students of artificial intelligence, and other readers interested in the processes of everyday human understanding.
Chapter
By the early 1980s, the idea that ordinary human social cognition is rational or scientific in character was under serious attack in personality and social psychology. Personality psychology was in the throes of the debate concerning whether behavior was consistent across situations and, although the jury was still out on the issue, powerful voices and persuasive data suggested that the concept of personality traits was a quaint shibboleth of commonsense psychology. As Nisbett and Ross (1980) put it, “the personality theorists’ (and the layperson’s) conviction that there are strong cross-situational consistencies in behavior may be seen as merely another instance of theory-driven covariation assessments operating in the face of contrary evidence” (p. 112).
Article
In December 1905, eight years before he published the first volume of "In Search of Lost Time", Marcel Proust entered a sanatorium to follow a six-week treatment for "neurasthenia" under the care of Dr Paul Sollier who, along with Babinski, was considered the cleverest pupil of Charcot. Following Charcot's wish, Sollier had studied memory in depth, and he used this knowledge to provoke emotional surges of involuntary memories in his patients. Proust's novel contains over 1200 allusions to memory, with a specific emphasis on involuntary memory, which was largely inspired by Sollier's theories. Beyond that, Sollier highlighted several other concepts which make him a major precursor of modern cognitive neurology: memory stabilisation requires specific conditions, learning is based on cellular changes and plasticity, memory is a universal phenomenon of the nervous system, memory organisation centres differ from perception centres, memory organisation is controlled by the frontal lobe, and neurophysiological mechanisms explain the difference between perception and memory.The rediscovery of Sollier's extraordinary work on memory should rehabilitate a forgotten, atypical neurologist whose critical interest in psychology may, in retrospect, make him one of the first modern neuro-psychologists.
Chapter
Involuntary memory was identified by the pioneering memory researcher Hermann Ebbinghaus more than a century ago, but it was not until very recently that cognitive psychologists began to study this memory phenomenon. This book is the first to examine key topics and cutting-edge research in involuntary memory. Discusses topics such as involuntary memories in everyday life, across the life-span, and in the laboratory; the special ways in which involuntary memories sometimes manifest themselves and a number of theoretical treatments of the topic. Presents innovative research that not only represents the starting point of the study of involuntary memory, but also places it in such broader topics as autobiographical memory, consciousness and memory, aging and memory, implicit and explicit memory, depression, and psychosis.