Content uploaded by Damien Short
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Damien Short
Content may be subject to copyright.
1 23
!"
#$%&%'(%)%%%*%*)
1 23
Your article is protected by copyright and all
rights are held exclusively by Springer Science
+Business Media Dordrecht. This e-offprint
is for personal use only and shall not be self-
archived in electronic repositories. If you
wish to self-archive your work, please use the
accepted author’s version for posting to your
own website or your institution’s repository.
You may further deposit the accepted author’s
version on a funder’s repository at a funder’s
request, provided it is not made publicly
available until 12 months after publication.
Protecting the planet: a proposal for a law of ecocide
Polly Higgins &Damien Short &Nigel South
#Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013
Abstract A wide range of actions imperil the planet and threaten the future of humanity
and other species. This essay notes some examples of crimes and harms damaging to the
environment and human and non-human species as well as various forms of response that
have called for more effective and appropriate models of justice and law than currently
prevail. This leads to a discussion of several suggestions regarding the development and
expression of an earth jurisprudence and to the history of a proposal that “ecocide”be
recognised internationally as a crime. Analysis of documentary sources traces this idea
from debates about the concept of genocide to consideration by United Nations officials
as to how crimes against the environment might be defined, and shows how near such a
proposal has previously come toacceptance andenactment. The articleconcludes with an
argument for supporting a law of ecocide as the 5th Crime against Peace.
Introduction
The development of a green perspective in criminology has drawn attention to crimes and
harms affecting the environment, human and non-human life and the planet itself [3,19,
29,33,37,38,41,50,51]. Examples of such crimes and harms include: industrial
pollution; corporate criminality and its impact on the environment; health and safety in
the workplace where breaches have environmentally damaging consequences; involve-
ment of organised crime and official corruption in the illegal disposal of toxic waste; and
the impact and legacy of military operations on landscapes, water supply, air quality and
living organisms populating these areas. Despite this breadth of impact, the plundering of
the earth’sresourcesanddegradationoftheenvironment have only relatively recently
been thought of as activities that might be considered criminal or at leastseriouslyharmful
with intergenerational consequences and transnational impacts [39,52,54].
Crime Law Soc Change
DOI 10.1007/s10611-013-9413-6
P. Higgins
Environmental Lawyer, London, UK
D. Short
Institute of Commonwealth Studies and Human Rights Consortium, University of London, London, UK
N. South (*)
Department of Sociology, University of Essex, Colchester, UK
e-mail: soutn@essex.ac.uk
Author's personal copy
The distinction drawn here between “crime”and “harm”reflects a longstanding
challenge for criminology: whether to concern itself only with legally defined crimes
or also embrace study of those activities that lie within lawful practice but evidently,
at least to some and by some measures of evidence, have harmful consequences that
might merit legal proscription and response. Criminologists have therefore tended to
adopt either a legal-procedural approach to environmental issues, retaining a tradi-
tional focus on violations of enacted environmental law (including civil and regula-
tory violations), or a more critical or socio-legal approach examining environmental
harms that are not statutorily prohibited but regarded as equally or more damaging
than some actions that are legal offences. In the orbit of both –but perhaps partic-
ularly the latter –can be found discussion and assertion of principles of rights and
justice –environmental, species-related and human-specific [11]. Whichever position
is taken, in the furtherance of ensuring law is appropriate to its time and that
entitlement to rights and justice is fair and comprehensive, criminology has routinely
questioned the “taken for granted”nature of definitions and classifications of crime,
harm and deviance and offered alternative proposals about where concern and
regulation should be directed [32].
A wide range of actions imperil the planet and threaten the future of humanity and
other species. These crimes and harms need to be responded to through both informal
and formal means of resolution and restoration, underpinned by an internationally
applicable legal framework. The history of a proposal for instituting such a framework
in the form of international recognition of a crime of “ecocide”is presented, drawing on
research that reveals how close this has previously come to acceptance and enactment.
The paper concludes with support for a contemporary restatement of this proposal.
Environmental crime, harm and (in) justice
Examples of environmental harm and crime can be organized into, for example, primary
and secondary forms, classified as either resulting directly from the destruction and
degradation of the earth’s resources (primary) or as being symbiotic with or dependent
upon such destruction, and efforts made to regulate or prevent it (secondary). We can
suggest four main ‘primary’clusters of green crimes/harms negatively affecting the
environment and species other than humans brought about as a result of human actions,
and examples are given below. ‘Secondary’or symbiotic green harms and crimes can
arise from the exploitation of conditions that follow environmental damage or crisis
(e.g., illegal markets for food, medicine, water) and/or from the violation of rules that
attempt to regulate environmental harm and to respond to disaster. These can include
numerous major and minor practices whereby states violate their own regulations (either
by commission or omission) and in so doing contribute to environmental harms. For the
purpose of illustration and to emphasise the breadth and scale of primary crimes/harms,
consider the following examples.
Crimes/harms of water pollution
During the span of one century the global population tripled, water consumption
multiplied sixfold and “half the world’s rivers and lakes have become polluted by
P. Higgins et al.
Author's personal copy
waste water”[22, p.12, 53]. Some 58 % of the world’s reefs and 34 % of all fish may
be at risk due to over-fishing, poaching and non-sustainable fishing techniques, as
well as pollution [2]. Freshwater and marine pollution is an everyday occurrence but
was highlighted as a global news story in April 2010 by the explosion of the BP
Deepwater Horizon oil well, which had the immediate effect of killing 11 people and
injuring 17 others but also turning into an ecological disaster on an enormous scale.
This was however, only the latest in a line of incidents in which the oceans of the
world and coastal eco-systems and economies have been ravaged and damaged by oil
spills (see e.g. www.telegraph.co.uk/earth/environment/7654043/Major-oil-spills-
the-worst-ecological-disasters.html).
Crimes/harms of air pollution
Air pollution crosses national boundaries and can affect all who live and work in cities or
centres of high industrial concentration although it cannot be said that pollution is
egalitarian in impact insofar as those who are more able than others to live in low
pollution areas can avoid the worst excesses that are suffered by those living in high
density locations. All populations will however be subject to the effects of climate
change and ozone depletion, which are predominantly driven by air pollution. As
Walters [47] reports ‘The World Health Organisation estimates that air pollution causes
the annual premature death of two million people worldwide through respiratory
infections, heart disease and lung cancer—all accelerated by, or the direct result of,
poor air quality .... Not only are humans placed at risk, but wildlife, water, agriculture,
buildings and natural heritage are also damaged by air pollutants at great financial,
cultural and environmental expense. In addition, air pollution is a major contributor to
climate change and the increase in so called ‘natural disasters’.’
Crimes/harms of deforestation and spoiling of the land
Across the world the impact of illegal logging is depleting forestry resources and this
has worrying implications for global warming but the activities, actors and motives
involved are complex and it is important to recognise that illegal logging is pursued
for need as well as for greed. [7,45] Even so, the impact of giant industrial logging
companies on areas like the Amazon basin is devastating not only for the rainforest
but also for the survival chances of the few remaining nomadic hunter gatherer tribes
such as the Awá. As their land is taken over by illegal settlements and new cattle
ranches, the Awá are being murdered by pistoleros, hired gun men described by tribe
members as responsible for wiping out their families, a situation so grave that a
Brazilian judge has called it “a real genocide”[9,13]. Meanwhile, both criminal
enterprises and legitimate businesses continue to engage in toxic dumping and unsafe
waste disposal, frequently with a discriminatory impact on communities of the poor
and powerless [12,20, pp. 94–101, 34].
Crimes/harms against animals/non-human species
Abuse, mistreatment or death of animals and birds may be visible and stark as in
cases of destruction of habitats by war, catastrophe, oil spills, deforestation, or be less
Protecting the planet: a proposal for a law of ecocide
Author's personal copy
visible and indeed socially accepted when related to farming, medical experiments,
clearance of land for building, or where damage results from activities that cause air
or water pollution, soil erosion or climate change. Illegal wildlife trafficking is now a
global business rivalling the drugs and arms trades [42] but whether licit or illicit, the
smuggling of live animals or trading of animal parts is poorly and inadequately
regulated. Matters of ethics and justice related to species diversity are now facing a
new horizon, of a future where “synthetic biology provides the technology to create
life that has not and could not naturally have existed”[35, p. 33]. Organisations led
by Friends of the Earth have already called for a “moratorium on the release and
commercial use of synthetic organisms until proper regulation is in place.”
Responses –from weak compliance to restorative justice
Of course, in response to these various issues and challenges, legal and criminolog-
ical tools have been developed and applied, cases of environmental crime have been
reported and prosecuted, and matters of responsibility and reparation have been
analysed and debated. For example, Walters [47] notes that in response to the
damaging as well as differentially unequal impacts of air pollution, Vanderheiden
has called for “atmospheric justice”:“Drawing on Rawlsian concepts of liberal
egalitarian justice, as well as cosmopolitan justice and political realism”,
Vanderheiden proposes “an international climate change regulatory regime based
on equity, responsibility and compensation”. Similarly, various proposals outlining
principles and action in support of “Climate Justice”have emerged in the last decade
from international networks, activist groups and human rights-oriented organisations
such as the Mary Robinson Foundation (http://www.mrfcj.org/).
However the current system of governance is weak and dependent on models of
deregulation and voluntary compliance (based on the belief that the market will
provide effective and efficient remedies) and legislative-balancing-acts (where agen-
cies who are tasked with encouragement of compliance in the course of doing
business are also charged with prosecuting and penalising in cases of offending)
[40]. In addition, systemic problems of regulatory capture (where regulators are
largely representatives of the regulated) and “trivialisation”of injurious actions [16]
(following lengthy legal debate about mitigation) occur at levels from transnational
crime to local offending. Hence, as Huisman [27, p. 56] shows, those “soft law”
instruments that do exist and operate can “contribute to creating generally accepted
social norms”underpinning protection of human rights or the environment by
corporations - however “the worst offenders are not compelled to take part”and
“increasing numbers of corporations affiliated to the UN Global Compact initiative
do not comply with their reporting obligations”. Huisman [27, p. 59] rightly draws
attention to the “ambiguity and ambivalence”underlying the system as it operates.
Stewart [44, pp. 11–14] and the Open Society Justice Initiative argue that a more
rigorous approach can be developed and aim to apply this to the post-Cold-War
plunder of minerals, metals, timber and other natural resources which could be seen
as “pillage”, a concept with a long history of application as describing an offence
under the laws of war and an element of various war crime statutes. Stewart argues
that the so-called “resource curse”affecting nations rich in terms of resource endow-
ment but poor in terms of social development and most prone to violent upheaval can
P. Higgins et al.
Author's personal copy
be addressed by curtailing corruption, regulating the resource industries domestically
and enhancing judicial capacity in countries recovering from war. But the liability of
foreign businesses for trading in illicit commodities (whether conflict minerals or
wildlife) must also be recognised and this requires an effective legal tool. As the
argument of pillage
1
has been used against former politicians and in post-WWII
prosecutions of Nazi business leaders for theft of property from occupied countries
but rarely against modern corporations or their officials, the proposal is that on the
basis of similarities between these earlier crimes and corporate practices in the
resource wars affecting countries today it is time to put these ideas to the test.
One further important perspective and tool already applied in various cases of
contestation and conflict is the idea of restorative justice. This is now seen to hold
considerable promise as a means to resolve responsibility and agree recompense for
crimes against the environment and the human and non-human beings affected. The
idea of restorative justice is in one sense quite simple and has a long history but as
Braithwaite [10, pp. 7–8] notes, the important point for his purposes –and indeed for
ours - is that we have witnessed “a late modern revival of restorative justice that has
its deepest roots in a shift from most regulatory activities having individuals and their
bodies as their objects to a world where more of the wrongdoing is done by
organizations that are regulated in a mostly restorative fashion.”As Higgins [25,
p.143] puts it, “Restorative justice is built on an understanding of our relationship
with nature and the duty to remedy the harm caused”–addressing “the needs of the
beleaguered party to restore that which has been harmed rather than simply fixating
on the punishment of the perpetrator.”This kind of approach to the administration of
environmental justice, invoking methods and principles of mutual engagement and
shared learning, is both practical as well as consonant with green ideals.
Rights and justice on an endangered planet
There have been several previous calls for forms or expressions of law and justice that
relate to crimes and harms against the planet and the species that share it. Cullinan
[14, p.144], for example, notes that “A few prescient commentators have for several
decades drawn attention to the need for legal systems to take an evolutionary leap
forward by recognizing legally enforceable rights for nature and other-than-human-
beings.”Cullinan refers to this body of work as “the evolution of earth jurisprudence”
and cites, among others, the work of Stone [43] who questioned whether the
widening of protection and rights to the formerly disempowered should be extended
to natural objects such as trees, and Berry [6, p.161] who argued that: “we need a
jurisprudence that would provide for the legal rights of geological and biological as
well as human components of the Earth community. A legal system exclusively for
humans is not realistic.”According to this view, both pragmatic reforms of law and
governance, as well as radical revisions, should build on recognition of, and respect
for, the interdependence of eco-systems and the principle of intergenerational equity.
1
Although the terms pillage, plunder, spoliation and looting are all commonly used in legal discussion with
more or less the same meaning, pillage is the only one that features in treaties governing the laws of war
[44, p.15].
Protecting the planet: a proposal for a law of ecocide
Author's personal copy
However, as Benton [4, p.10] cautioned “giving weight to considerations of justice in
the context of sustainability poses a significant challenge to established ways of
thinking in several respects”and this applies to the idea of ‘sustainable development’
and even more so to the more challenging aspiration of ‘ecological sustainability’.
2
As Benton continues, in the current global context those agencies charged with
developing strategies for securing sustainability (of whatever variety) “generally lack
either the will or the resources to do so. The current dominance of neo-liberal
ideology and its associated institutional framework for regulating international trade
and investment runs directly counter to the imposition of normative restraints on
economic activity.”
Yet in th e f a ce of cli m a t e chan g e , c arbon emission and potentially irrevers-
ible harms to the planet such restraint is required. The argument here is that
this could be expressed through radical additions to and revision of human
legal systems that would recognize, as Cullinan [14, p.144] puts it, “that a
primary cause of environmental destruction is the fact that current legal systems
are designed to perpetuate human domination of nature instead of fostering
mutually beneficial relationships between humans and other members of the
earth community.”
The proposal for a law of ecocide
Ecocide as a concept has a longer history than some of the proposals and approaches
discussed so far although the term has perhaps not made the degree of impact that
might have been expected given its pertinence and usefulness. One set of reasons for
this is discussed in detail below. As to its history, it is recorded as being used as early
as 1970 at the “Conference on War and National Responsibility”in Washington,
where Professor Arthur W. Galston “proposed a new international agreement to ban
‘ecocide’”.
3
Gray [24] used the term to describe the “causing or permitting [of] harm to
the natural environment on a massive scale”, reflecting a “breach of duty of
care owed to humanity in general”.Berat[5]usedthetermGeocideina
similar way, to provide a means in international law to preserve the right to
a healthy environment. In the green criminology literature, Boekhout van
Solinge [8, p. 26] referred to the idea of ecocide as a “delict”(an offence or
transgression) citing Gray, while South [39, p.239] suggested that support for
Gray’s proposal that ecocide be written into international law might be pre-
mised on the threat, or breach of rights, to health and to life. This argument
draws on Hulme [26] who refers to the importance of the 1972 Stockholm
Declaration of the United Nations Conference on the Human Environment
which observes that “Both aspects of man’s environment, the natural and the
manmade, are essential to his well-being and to the enjoyment of basic human
rights, the right to life itself”, and also to the Report on Human Rights and the
Environment,
4
in which section 248 argues that environmental damage has
2
The authors are grateful to Rob White for this and several other points.
3
In Gauger et al. [22] citing The New York Times, 26 February 1970 as quoted in Weisberg [48].
4
U.N. Commission on Human Rights, 1994, Rapporteur Ksentini, Sub-commission Report.
P. Higgins et al.
Author's personal copy
direct effects on the enjoyment of a series of human rights, such as the right to
life and to health.
Ecocide as the missing 5th crime against peace
In April 2010 a proposal for an international law of Ecocide was submitted to
the United Nations Law Commission by U.K.-based lawyer, Polly Higgins [25].
Higgins proposed the following as an amendment to the Rome Statute:
“Ecocide is the extensive damage to, destruction of or loss of ecosystem(s) of
a given territory, whether by human agency or by other causes, to such an
extent that peaceful enjoyment by the inhabitants of that territory has been
severely diminished”.Within this definition, Higgins identifies two types of
ecocide; human caused and naturally occurring ecocide. In so doing, a legal
framework is created for pre-empting, preventing and prohibiting ecocide. As
part of the proposal the principle of superior responsibility applies to not only
big business but also nations. By creating a legal duty of care which pre-empts,
nations will be legally bound to act before mass damage, destruction or
ecosystem collapse occurs and the law will impute a legal duty of care on all
nations to provide assistance to those countries that are at risk of or are
suffering from ecosystem collapse as a result of rising sea-levels or catastrophic
events such as tsunamis and floods. Naturally occurring ecocide, whether
related to climate change or not, becomes a responsibility of governments.
Human-caused ecocide becomes a responsibility of governments as well as
businesses –those who are policy makers, directors or who are responsible
for funding or investment, become legally bound to ensure that any business
practice that causes mass damage, destruction or loss of ecosystems is brought
to an end. To put such an international law in place requires an amendment to
the Rome Statute. Once a Signatory country calls for an amendment, a confer-
ence can be held to open the process whereby the crime of Ecocide can be
included. In so doing, an international law that imposes duties and responsibil-
ities on heads of State as well as heads of business will create a framework that
has enormous implications, both economically and governmentally. Such a law
will trigger a green economy and put in place a powerful global governance
mechanism.
During war-time, it is already a crime to cause damage where the spatial size
affected exceeds 200 km in length or where impact on ecosystems exceeds 3 months,
causing severity of impact to human, natural or economic resources [25, p. 64]. Yet,
during peace-time such damage occurs daily to our soils and seas, whether as a
consequence of the business of agrochemical companies or heavy extractive industry.
By creating a crime of Ecocide, no longer will it be lawful to commit daily damage,
destruction or loss of ecosystems of the kind already criminalised during time of war.
But is the prospect of realising a law of Ecocide simply too fanciful and naive? The
answer would seem to be “no”because enactment of such a proposal has been under
serious consideration on several past occasions and the laws and constitutions of
several nations now incorporate expressions of what has been called ‘Earth
Law’[14,15].
Protecting the planet: a proposal for a law of ecocide
Author's personal copy
Documents examined in the report Ecocide is the Missing Crime against Peace
[23] demonstrate that the idea of Ecocide as an international crime to stand alongside
Genocide was very much at the forefront of various discussions underway between
1972 and 1996. For over a decade, in work undertaken by the United Nations,
debates and drafting exercises included Ecocide until it was finally removed
from the text that became known as the Rome Statute, which codifies the four
Crimes against Peace.
The institutional history of the concept of ecocide
The institutional history of ecocide is inextricably bound up with that of its more famous
relation: genocide. In 1933, Raphael Lemkin, a Polish Jurist, spoke at the International
Conference for Unification of Criminal Law in Madrid and urged the international
community to converge on the necessity to ban the destruction, both physical and
cultural, of human groups, invoking the linked concepts of “barbarity”and “vandalism”.
In his subsequent seminal text, Lemkin [28] combined his prior formulations, barbarity
and vandalism, to form a new, more comprehensive concept –genocide, combining the
Greek word genos meaning tribe or race and the Latin cide meaning destruction.
5
Lemkin envisaged a law consisting of the deliberate destruction of a nation or ethnic
group in the following ways: a) by killing its individual members, i.e. physical genocide
(derived from Lemkin’s notion of “barbarity”); b) by undermining its way of life, i.e.
cultural genocide (derived from “vandalism”). His original definition crucially identified
the destruction of a people by other factors not directly involved in killing. Ecocide can
and often does lead to cultural damage and destruction. Like genocide, ecocide can be
direct and indirect; it can be the destruction of a territory and it can also be the under-
mining of a way of life - ecological as well as cultural.
For Lemkin, it was culture that animated the genos in genocide - a social group
existed by virtue of its common culture. Thus, during the construction of the draft
United Nations Convention on Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide,
Lemkin argued that “Cultural Genocide is the most important part of the Convention”
[30, pp.12–13]. In his 1958 autobiography [18, p.82], Lemkin subsequently wrote: “I
defended it (cultural genocide) successfully through two drafts. It meant the destruc-
tion of the cultural pattern of a group, such as the language, the traditions, the
monuments, archives, libraries, churches. In brief: the shrines of the soul of a nation.
But there was not enough support for this idea in the Committee…So with a heavy
heart I decided not to press for it”.[17] Lemkin was forced to drop an idea that, in his
words, “was very dear to me”.
6
5
[29, p.79 –95]. For further discussion, see Moses [31].
6
In fact one out of five acts of cultural genocide did remain in the Convention, this is “(a) forcible transfer
of children to another human group”; the excluded other categories being: “(b) forced and systematic exile
of individuals representing the culture of a group; (c) prohibition of the use of the national language even in
private intercourse; (d) systematic destruction of books printed in the national language or of religious
works or prohibition of new publications; (e) systematic destruction of historical or religious monuments or
their diversion to alien uses, destruction or dispersion of documents and objects of historical, artistic, or
religious value and of objects used in religious worship.”[http://www.preventgenocide.org/law/ conven-
tion/drafts/]. Cases of the forcible removal of indigenous children –the ‘stolen generations’–in Australia
and Canada have produced enormous controversy and invoked the notion of cultural genocide but none has
produced a prosecution let alone conviction at the international level.
P. Higgins et al.
Author's personal copy
The Genocide Convention had lost its coherence and conceptual integrity, more-
over, a major method of genocide was not criminalised. The removal of this method
led to a preoccupation, in legal and scholarly realms, with establishing perpetrator
intention rather than genocidal effects and to the popular (mis)understanding of the
crime of genocide as simply racially motivated mass killing [36]. Eventually, it also
led to reviews within the U.N. system of the Convention’s effectiveness since it was
not being used and seemed to offer little to those groups it was designed to protect. It
was in just such a review that we find the first attempt to criminalise in international
law, environmental destruction.
7
A draft International Convention on the Crime of Ecocide was prepared by Richard
A. Falk and was introduced as part of a review process which sought to evaluate the
effectiveness of the Genocide Convention. The proposal to include, in an amended
Convention, a law against ecocide that could address both direct ecological crimes and
ancillary cultural ecocide was explored at length. There was concern in the U.N. that the
Convention on Genocide was deficient and that there were other destructive phenomena
that needed to be criminalised. Falk drew up the proposed Convention for a journal
article he published in 1973, [21] which was then included in a study conducted by the
U.N. Sub-Commission on Prevention of Discrimination and Protection of Minorities
regarding evaluation of the effectiveness of the 1948 Genocide Convention. Falk argued
that it was necessary to recognise “that we are living in a period of increasing danger of
ecological collapse”[…] and “that man has consciously and unconsciously inflicted
irreparable damage to the environment in times of war and peace”[21, p.93]. In spite of
the recognition that environmental damage can be caused consciously and unconscious-
ly, the majority of the draft Ecocide Convention primarily focused on ecocide as a war-
crime with intent and did not set out similar peacetime provisions. Another commenta-
tor, Westing, argued at the time that: “Intent may be not only impossible to establish
without admission but, I believe, it is essentially irrelevant.”[49]. Within the Sub-
Commission Mr. Bouhdiba voiced support for criminalising ecocide: “any interference
with the natural surroundings or environment in which ethnic groups lived was, in effect,
a kind of ethnic genocide because such interference could prevent the people involved
from following their own traditional way of life.”
8
By this time a sizeable majority of
parties to the United Nations were in favour of ecocide as a crime during peacetime.
However, the draft International Convention on the Crime of Ecocide was shelved very
late in the day without being put to the vote and for no apparent recorded reason [23].
In 1947 the General Assembly of the United Nations had assigned the
International Law Commission (ILC) to formulate “the principles of international
law recognized in the charter of the Nuremberg Tribunal and in the judgment of the
Tribunal”and to “prepare a draft code of offences against the peace and security of
mankind, indicating clearly the place to be accorded to the [aforementioned] princi-
ples”.
9
Between the years 1984 –1996 there was extensive engagement in the ILC
about the inclusion of environmental damage and Ecocide into the list of Crimes
against Peace. The Special Rapporteur on the draft Code of Offences against the
7
Sub-Commission on The Prevention of Discrimination and Protection of Minorities. Study of the
Question of the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide. Prepared by Mr. Nicodème
Ruhashyankiko. 4 July 1978. E/CN.4/Sub.2/416.
8
E/CN.4/Sub.2/SR.658, p. 53.
9
General Assembly resolution 177 (II) of 21 November 1947.
Protecting the planet: a proposal for a law of ecocide
Author's personal copy
Peace and Security of Mankind, Doudou Thiam, had included the crime based on
precedence in international law.
10
Furthermore, in the draft Articles on State
Responsibility legislation that the ILC was working on concurrent to the Code,
Crimes against the Environment had been included in Article 19 of Part 1 which
referred to “wilful and severe damage to the environment”[23].
11
The consideration, since 1984, of whether to include “acts causing serious damage
to the environment”as a Crime against Peace led some members to re-open the
debate on whether this was a crime of intent. By 1991 discussions were focussing on
the inclusion of the element of intent and the final drafting of Article 26. For the
purposes of the Code previous drafts were removed and Article 26 was reduced to
“wilful and severe damage to the environment”. After the element of intent had been
added, the governments of Australia, Belgium, Austria and Uruguay went on record
criticising the re-drafting, in recognition that ecocide during peacetime is often a
crime without intent [23]. Belgium argued “[t]his difference between articles 22 [war
crimes]
12
and 26 [“wilful and severe damage to the environment”] does not seem to
be justified. Article 26 should be amended to conform with the concept of damage to
the environment used in article 22, since the concept of wilful damage is too
restrictive.”Australia objected on the grounds that “the requisite mens rea in
Article 26 should be lowered so as to be consistent with article 22”, and Austria
went on record stating that “since perpetrators of this crime are usually acting out of a
profit motive, intent should not be a condition for liability to punishment.”
13
Even so,
the ILC, instead of removing the element of intent, determined to remove Article 26
altogether.
Reactions within the ILC and Legal Committee to the announcement of the
withdrawal of Article 26 were only partially recorded but it is clear that the decision
was not based on agreement between the parties [23]. Subsequent off-the-record
debates between Commission members failed to further the law of ecocide: the
Chairman in 1995 decided twice to hold informal meetings “to facilitate the con-
sultations and ensure a truly frank exchange of views”.
14
Thus, in true U.N. fashion,
in 1995 it was decided to establish a further Working Group but one restricted to
consideration of “the issue of wilful damage to the environment.”In 1996, at the start
10
The Special Rapporteur refers to the following international instruments: the Treaty on the Prohibition of
the Emplacement of Nuclear Weapons and Other Weapons of Mass Destruction on the Sea-Bed and the
Ocean Floor and in the Subsoil Thereof; the Treaty Banning Nuclear Weapon Tests in the Atmosphere in
Outer Space and Under Water; the Treaty on Principles Governing the Activities of States in the
Exploration and Use of Outer Space, including the Moon and other Celestial Bodies; and the Convention
on the Prohibition of Military or any other Hostile Use of Environmental Modification Techniques; see
A/CN.4/377 and Corr.1, para. 44 and 51, p.94-96.
11
A/CN.4/377 and Corr.1, para. 46, p.95.
12
One provision of Art.22 on war crimes covers damage caused to the environment in times of war.
“Article 22. Exceptionally serious war crimes: 2. For the purposes of this Code, an exceptionally serious
war crime is an exceptionally serious violation of principles and rules of international law applicable in
armed conflict consisting of any of the following acts: […] (d) employing methods or means of warfare
which are intended or may be expected to cause widespread, long-term and severe damage to the natural
environment; […]”. See: Yearbook of the ILC 1995, Vol.II, Pt.2, p.97.
13
A/CN.4/448 and Add.1, contained in Yearbook of the ILC 1993, Vol.II, Pt.1, p.66, para.50 (Australia),
and p.68, para.30 (Austria)
14
A/CN.4/448 and Add.1, contained in Yearbook of the ILC 1995, Vol.I, 2386
th
m., pp. 52; and 2387
th
m.,
p. 52–53
P. Higgins et al.
Author's personal copy
of the ILC’s 48th session, the Working Group convened to consider this far more
limited inclusion of crimes of environmental damage in the Code.
15
The members
included Mr. Thiam, Mr. Tomuschat, Mr. Kusuma-Atmadja, Mr. Szekely and Mr.
Yamada.
16
As the group was not listed with the other working groups at the beginning
of the 1996 Yearbook of the ILC, it has not been possible to detect exactly which
members took part in its discussions [23]. Nevertheless, a Working Group report on
the topic was published titled “Document on crimes against the environment”
17
by
Mr. Tomuschat. In his recommendations he suggests either a) retaining environmental
crimes as a distinct and separate provision; or b) including environmental crimes as
an act of crimes against humanity; or c) adding the ecocide part to the provision on
war crimes.
A defining moment came in 1996 at a meeting of the ILC, when the then
Chairman, Mr. Ahmed Mahiou, unilaterally chose to remove the crime of ecocide
completely as a separate provision without putting it to a vote. This singular act was
not just a procedural irregularity but also contrary to the remit of the Working Group
which was “to work on crimes against the environment”. Hence, it was not surprising
that at least one member, Mr. Szekely, strongly objected –albeit to no avail.
18
As a
placatory measure, it seems, a far narrower remit was finally put to a vote but with
ecocide gone the only decision left to take was whether to include environmental
damage solely in the context of a war crime or to include it as a crime against
humanity.
19
The final result of the Working Group process was that the Drafting
Committee was instructed to draft with the far narrower remit of “environmental
damage in the context of war crimes”and not in the context of “crimes against
humanity”.
Thus, Article 26 was removed in 1996 and the final Article adopted by the ILC,
which was further amended by the Drafting Committee, refers to intentionally
causing “widespread, long-term and severe damage to the natural environment”
within a war context.
20
This was the final reference to a crime against the environ-
ment which made it into the Rome Statute. And so, contrary to the prevailing mood at
the time, 1996 saw the crime of ecocide suddenly removed from all draft documents.
A full picture of exactly how and why this happened is not available from the U.N.
documentation but the research conducted [23]hasdiscoveredtwoimportant
pointers. First, a comment by the Special Rapporteur on the Draft Code of Offence
15
Working group was established at the 2404
th
meeting. See: Vol.I and Vol. II, Pt.2 of the Yearbook of the
ILC, 1995.
16
Yearbook of the ILC, 1996, Vol. I, 2428th meeting, p.5, para.5.
17
ILC(XLVIII)/DC/CRD.3 (included in Yearbook of the ILC, 1996, Vol. II, Pt. 1).
18
Yearbook of the ILC, 1996, Vol. I, 2431th meeting, Tuesday, 21 May 1996.
19
Ibid. Including environmental damage in the context of war crimes: 12 votes in favour to 1, 4
abstentions; in the context of crimes against humanity: 9 votes to 9, 2 abstentions.
20
Article 8. War crimes:
2. For the purpose of this Statute, “war crimes”means:
(a) Grave breaches of the Geneva Conventions of 12 August 1949, namely, any of the following acts
against persons or property protected under the provisions of the relevant Geneva Convention: […]
(b) Other serious violations of the laws and customs applicable in international armed conflict, within
the established framework of international law, namely, any of the following acts: […] (iv) Intentionally
launching an attack in the knowledge that such attack will cause […] widespread, long-term and severe
damage to the natural environment which would be clearly excessive in relation to the concrete and direct
overall military advantage anticipated; […]
Protecting the planet: a proposal for a law of ecocide
Author's personal copy
against the Peace and Security of Mankind, Mr. Thiam of Senegal, who stated in his
13th report that the removal was due to the comments of a few governments who
were largely opposed to any form of inclusion of Article 26 (“wilful and severe
damage to the environment”).
21
Second, Christian Tomuschat, who was a long-term
member of the ILC from 1985 to 1996–11 years in total - and a member of the
Working Group on the issue of wilful damage to the environment, published a brief
article in 1996 where he reflected on the development of the provisions regarding
crimes against the environment during the drafting and codification process of the
draft Code. In a telling passage he writes:
One cannot escape the impression that nuclear arms played a decisive role in the
minds of many of those who opted for the final text which now has been
emasculated to such an extent that its conditions of applicability will almost
never be met even after humankind would have gone through disasters of the
most atrocious kind as a consequence of conscious action by persons who were
completely aware of the fatal consequences their decisions would entail. [46]
A law of ecocide
A law of Ecocide should recognise human-caused environmental damage and deg-
radation (whether committed during or outside of war-time), as a crime of strict
liability (in other words, without intent). Of the ten countries that have already
included Ecocide in their criminal penal codes, not one of them sets out a test of
intent. An international law of Ecocide where intent was a necessary component of
the crime opens up the legal loophole of sidestepping responsibility on the basis that
mass damage or destruction was not intended. Most corporate ecocide is not
intended; often it is deemed collateral damage or an accident. Where intent or
knowledge is required, many corporations would hide behind the defence that they
did not know what was happening or what could happen. Thus the defence “I did not
know”would be robustly put forward by virtually every company. What is recog-
nized by this proposal is that very rarely do corporations intend to cause mass damage
and destruction; rather it is a consequence. To impute strict liability is to impute
accountability. Under current legislation there is very little onus on business to be
accountable.
Moreover, implementation of the crime of Ecocide stops the flow of destruction at
source and creates a pre-emptive duty on corporate activity to prohibit mass damage
and destruction to ecosystems from the outset. This has huge implications for climate
change - by stopping the major polluters from continuing to produce escalating levels
of carbon dioxide, instability in the atmosphere is abated. In so doing, the crime of
Ecocide becomes a powerful preventative measure that would render those in a
superior position of responsibility at-risk of prosecution where they are responsible
for taking decisions that lead to, support or finance mass damage and destruction
(whether or not it contributes to climate instability: measurement of carbon dioxide
emissions being only one way of measuring Ecocide). By levying responsibility on
21
A/CN.4/466, included in the Yearbook of the ILC 1995, Vol.II, Pt.1, p.35
P. Higgins et al.
Author's personal copy
persons, not legal entities (the corporate body), the cycle of destruction and accrual of
silent rights to destroy is halted. Thus, instead of “the polluter pays”(if caught), the
new governing principle becomes “the polluter does not pollute”and the protection of
interests shifts from those few who have ownership to the many who are at risk of
suffering.
The matter of implementation and operationalisation of such a law would be one
that connects well to parallel proposals for the extension of environmental courts and
the establishment of an International Environmental Court. The value of such courts
lies in the focus and expertise that can be brought to bear on complex and technical
matters that are often unfamiliar when introduced and processed through the tradi-
tional courts (see Walters and Westerhuis, and White, this volume).
Conclusion
One aspect of the climate change debate that is often overlooked is the rule of law.
Who owes whom a duty of care to help in times of need? Who will step in and assist
before sea levels rise to disastrous levels? The problem is, no-one has a legal duty of
care to throw a life-line. A law of Ecocide will be more than a lifeline –it will impose
a legal duty of care upon all nations to pre-emptively help. The implication of such a
law for many Small Island States is huge: not only does such a law abate the threat of
climate-driven ecocide it puts in place a legal duty of care to assist. The power of law
to act as a mechanism to encourage transformation to a green economy is also under-
estimated. Using law to prioritise the adoption of technologies that are benign and
renewable on a world-wide basis and to prohibit dangerous industrial activity while
imposing a legal duty of care, will all redirect investment into clean technologies and
a green economy.
As well as looking to the future, there are lessons to be learned from the past. Two
hundred years ago, in response to calls for the abolition of slavery, the slave industry
responded by asserting that any restriction on their trade would be uneconomic, lead
to loss of jobs, and remove a public necessity from society. Slavers argued for the
right to self-regulate and to voluntarily limit the number of slaves traded (a precursor
to cap and trade), as well as suggesting restrictions on the usage of slaves and
improvement of conditions. The market mechanisms proposed were based on com-
pliance, the use of tradable permits and payment of fines if limits were exceeded. All
these proposals were ultimately rejected but today these very same principles and
methods are what we rely on to address a problem with a fundamental economic
similarity - slaves were in effect a form of energy replaced by the machine age and
dependence on fossil fuel.
Today ten countries have a law of Ecocide although it is of interest (and should be
immediately acknowledged) that adoption of the wording and objectives of a pro-
gressive law does not necessarily imply that the adopting state is a progressive
democracy. For example, Viet Nam, no doubt as a consequence of its experiences
during the long Viet Nam war, was the first country to adopt a law of ecocide,
followed by the Soviet Union in 1996, just prior to its collapse. Although Ecocide had
been taken off the table at the United Nations during the same year, the crime itself
was adopted by States who preferred to include all the Crimes against Peace that were
Protecting the planet: a proposal for a law of ecocide
Author's personal copy
in the draft document. In the aftermath of the collapse of the USSR, over a period of
seven years, the new States that were formed drew up their own Criminal Penal
Codes. Some have included Ecocide as a named Crime against Peace in their Penal
Codes - Armenia, Belarus, Moldova, Ukraine, Georgia, Kazahkstan, Kyrgyztsan and
Tajikistan. What is striking is that none of these newly formed states became
signatories of the Rome Statute (they could not have been signatories at the time of
the creation of the Statute in 1996 because they were only established following
secession from the Soviet Union after 1998). These states adopted Ecocide as part of
the draft Code of Crimes against the Peace and Security of Mankind (the precursor to
the Rome Statute). Elsewhere (e.g. Ecuador, see White, this volume), other countries
have adopted new constitutions which may not explicitly reference the crime of
ecocide as outlined above but which do place emphasis on recognition of the rights
of ecosystems and nature.
There was a moment in recent years when a law to prevent mass damage or
destruction affecting the environment had a name and was very nearly adopted at an
international level to be embraced both in peace-time and war-time. The paper trail
that has been followed has raised questions about why ecocide as a peace-time crime
against the environment was suddenly removed. In the next few years, the concept
and its application might be expected to receive increasing attention from policy
makers as they take notice of experiments with mock trials that prosecute under a
‘law of ecocide’and of the emerging evidence of the value of specialist environmen-
tal courts.
For now, in law outside of wartime, it is not a crime to cause mass destruction or
loss of ecosystems. Our world has normalized the daily ecocide caused by the
practices that drive economies as they currently function [1,39]. Two rules to change
these practices and the world we live in are proposed under one law: first, prohibit
mass damage, destruction or loss of ecosystems, and second, impose a legal duty of
care upon persons in positions of superior responsibility. The proposal is for a law of
Ecocide.
References
1. Agnew, R. (2013). The Ordinary Acts that Contribute to Ecocide: A Criminological Analysis. In N. South
& A. Brisman (Eds.), The Routledge international handbook of green criminology. London: Routledge.
2. Annan, K. A., & Flavin, C. (2002). State of the world, 2002: a worldwatch institute report on progress
toward a sustainable society. London: WW Norton and Company.
3. Beirne, P., & South, N. (Eds.). (2007). Issues in green criminology. Cullompton: Willan.
4. Benton, T. (2007). Ecology, community and justice: the meaning of green. In P. Beirne & N. South
(Eds.), Issues in green criminology. Cullompton: Willan.
5. Berat, L. (1993). Defending the right to a healthy environment: towards a crime of geocide in
international law. Boston University International Law Journal, 11, 327–348.
6. Berry, T. (1999). The great work: our way into the future. New York: Bell Tower.
7. Bisschop, L. (2012). Out of the woods: the illegal trade in tropical timber and a European trade hub.
Global Crime. doi:10.1080/17440572.2012.701836.
8. van Boekhout Solinge, T. (2008). Crime, conflicts and ecology in Africa. In R. Sollund (Ed.), Global
harms: ecological crime and speciesism. New York: Nova.
9. van Boekhout Solinge, T., & Kuijpers, K. (2013). The Amazon Rainforest: A Green Criminological
Perspective. In N. South & A. Brisman (Eds.), The Routledge international handbook of green
criminology. London: Routledge.
P. Higgins et al.
Author's personal copy
10. Braithwaite, J. (2002). Restorative justice and responsive regulation. New York: Oxford University
Press.
11. Brisman, A. (2013). Environmental and human rights: land, property and crime. In G. Bruinsma & D.
Weisburd (Eds.), Encyclopaedia of criminology and criminal justice. New York: Springer.
12. Bullard, R. (1994). Dumping in Dixie: race, class and environmental quality. Boulder: Westview Press.
13. Chamberlain, G. (2012). ‘They’re killing us’: world’s most endangered tribe cries for help. The
Observer, 22
nd
April: 8.
14. Cullinan, C. (2010). Earth jurisprudence: from colonization to participation. In Worldwatch Institute
(Eds.) State of the world, 2010, transforming cultures. www.Worldwatch.org
15. Cullinan, C. (2011). Wild law: a manifesto for earth justice (2nd ed.). Vermont: Chelsea Green.
16. De Prez, P. (2000). Excuses, excuses: the ritual trivialisation of environmental prosecutions. Journal of
Environmental Law, 12, 65–77.
17. Docker, J. (2004). Raphael Lemkin’s history of genocide and colonialism. Contribution for
United States Holocaust Memorial Museum. Washington D.C.: Center for Advanced Holocaust
Studies, 26th Februar.
18. Docker, J. (2008). Are settler colonies inherently genocidal? Re-reading Lemkin. In A. D. Moses (Ed.),
Empire, colony, genocide: conquest, occupation and subaltern resistance in world history. Oxford:
Berghahn Books.
19. Eman, K., Meško, G., & Fields, C. (2009). Crimes against the environment: green criminology and
research challenges in Slovenia. Journal of Criminal Justice and Security, 11(4), 574–592.
20. Faber, D. (2009). Capitalising on environmental crime: a case study of the U.S.A. Polluter-industrial
complex in the age of globalization. In K. Kangaspunta & I. Marshall (Eds.), Eco-crime and justice.
UNICRI: Turin.
21. Falk, R. A. (1973). Environmental warfare and ecocide - facts, appraisal, and proposals. In T. Marek
(Ed.), Bulletin of peace proposals 1973 (Vol. 1, pp. 80–96). Oslo: Universitersforlaget.
22. Frerot, A. (2011). Wate r –towards a culture of responsibility.Lebanon:UniversityofNewHampshirePress.
23. Gauger, A., Rabatel-Fernel, M P., Kulbicki, L., Short, D. and Higgins, P. (2012). Ecocide is the Missing
5th Crime against Peace, London: The Ecocide Project, Human Rights Consortium, School of
Advanced Study, University of London. http://www.sas.ac.uk/hrc/projects/ecocide-project
24. Gray, M. A. (1996). The international crime of ecocide. California Western International Law Journal,
26, 215–271.
25. Higgins, P. (2010). Eradicating ecocide: laws and governance to prevent the destruction of our planet.
London: Shepheard-Walwyn.
26. Hulme, K. (2008). Do we need a human right to a healthy environment? Paper presented at Human
Rights and the Environment Panel, February 21st, University of Essex, Human Rights Centre 25th
Anniversary.
27. Huisman, W. (2010). Business as usual? corporate involvement in international crimes. The Hague:
Eleven International Publishing.
28. Lemkin, R. (1944). Axis rule in occupied Europe: laws of occupation - analysis of government -
proposals for redress (pp. 79–95). Washington, D.C.: Carnegie Endowment.
29. Lynch, M. (1990). The greening of criminology: a perspective on the 1990s. Critical Criminologist, 2
(3–4), 11–12.
30. Moses, D. (2008). Empire, colony, genocide: keywords and the philosophy of history. In D. Moses
(Ed.), Empire, colony, genocide: conquest, occupation, and subaltern resistance in world history (pp.
3–54). Oxford: Berghahn Books.
31. Moses, D. (2010). Raphael Lemkin, culture, and the concept of genocide. In D. Bloxham & A. D.
Moses (Eds.), Oxford handbook of genocide studies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
32. Passas, N., & Goodwin, V. (2004). A crime by any other name. In N. Passas & V. Goodwin (Eds.), It’s
Legal but it ain’t right: harmful social consequences of legal industries. Ann Arbour: University of
Michigan Press.
33. Ruggiero, V., & South, N. (Eds.). (2010). Green criminology, special issue of. Critical Criminology, 18
(4).
34. Ruggiero, V., & South, N. (2010). Green criminology and dirty-collar crime. Critical Criminology, 18
(4), 251–262.
35. Savulescu, J. (2012). Master the new loom before life’s tapestry unravels at our hands. Times Higher
Education, 19th April, 32–33.
36. Short, D. (2010). Cultural genocide and indigenous peoples: a sociological approach. The International
Journal of Human Rights, 14(6–7), 831–846.
37. Sollund, R. (Ed.). (2008). Global harms: ecological crime and speciesism. New York: Nova.
Protecting the planet: a proposal for a law of ecocide
Author's personal copy
38. South, N. (1998). A green field for criminology?: a proposal for a perspective. Theoretical
Criminology, 2(2), 211–233.
39. South, N. (2010). The ecocidal tendencies of late modernity: trans-national crime, social exclusion,
victims and rights. In R. White (Ed.), Global environmental harm: criminological perspectives. Willan:
Cullompton.
40. South, N., & Brisman, A. (2012). Critical green criminology, environmental rights and crimes of
exploitation. In S. Winlow & R. Atkinson (Eds.), New directions in crime and deviance. London:
Routledge.
41. South, N., & Brisman, A. (Eds.). (2013). The Routledge International Handbook of Green
Criminology. London: Routledge.
42. South, N., & Wyatt, T. (2011). Comparing illicit trades in wildlife and drugs: an exploratory study.
Deviant Behavior, 32(1), 1–24.
43. Stone, C. (1972). Should trees have standing? Towards legal rights for natural objects. Southern
California Law Review, 45. p. 450
44. Stewart, J. (2011). Corporate war crimes: prosecuting pillage of natural resources. New York: Open
Society Foundation.
45. Tacconi, L. (Ed.). (2007). Illegal logging: Law enforcement, livelihoods and the timber trade. London:
Earthscan.
46. Tomuschat, C. (1996). ‘Crimes Against the Environment’. In: Environmental Policy and Law. 1996.
Vol. 26, 6.
47. Walters, R. (2013). Air crimes and atmospheric justice. In A. Brisman & N. South (Eds.), The
Routledge International Handbook of Green Criminology. London: Routledge.
48. Weisberg, B. (1970). Ecocide in Indochina. San Francisco: Canfield Press.
49. Westing, A. H. (1974). Prosciption of ecocide. Science and Public Affairs, 1974, 24–27.
50. White, R. (2008). Crimes against nature: Environmental criminology and ecological justice.
Cullompton: Willan.
51. White, R. (Ed.). (2010). Global environmental harm: criminological perspectives. Cullompton: Willan.
52. White, R. (2011). Transnational environmental crime: toward an eco-global criminology. New York:
Routledge.
53. World Water Council, http://www.worldwatercouncil.org
54. Wright, G. (2011). Conceptualising and combating transnational environmental crime. Trends in
Organised Crime, 14, 332–346.
P. Higgins et al.
Author's personal copy