ArticlePDF Available

The Cognitive Realism of Memory in Flaubert's Madame Bovary

Authors:

Abstract

The ‘‘cognitive realism' of memory in Madame Bovary is investigated by means of relevant research in the cognitive sciences, drawing conclusions which complement those of traditional literary criticism. In particular, Emma Bovary's memory is elucidated with reference to cognitive-dissonance theory: the human need for coherence between memory and self-image renders the trajectory of her married life psychologically explicable. The findings help account for critics' ambivalent or contradictory responses to Emma's story, and yield hypotheses concerning readers' responses more generally. They also suggest conclusions regarding the disjuncture between literary Realism (which corresponds to our assumptions about cognition) and cognitive realism (which corresponds to the underlying cognitive realities).
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 1
35 pp.
The Cognitive Realism of Memory in Flaubert’s Madame Bovary
Abbreviated title: Cognitive Realism in Flaubert
Abstract: The ‘cognitive realism’ of memory in Madame Bovary is investigated by means of
relevant research in the cognitive sciences, drawing conclusions which complement those of
traditional literary criticism. In particular, Emma Bovary’s memory is elucidated with reference to
cognitive-dissonance theory: the human need for coherence between memory and self--image
renders the trajectory of her married life psychologically explicable. The findings help account for
critics’ ambivalent or contradictory responses to Emma’s story, and yield hypotheses concerning
readers’ responses more generally. They also suggest conclusions regarding the disjuncture between
literary Realism (which corresponds to our assumptions about cognition) and cognitive realism
(which corresponds to the underlying cognitive realities).
Memory connects readers and characters in the experience of a fictional world in several
ways. Characters remember things that occurred earlier in the narrative, and we as readers remember
along with them, perhaps judging the accuracy of a character’s memory, or being reminded of
something we ourselves had forgotten. Or characters remember events, people, thoughts, and feelings
dating back further than the start of the narrative, and readers are thereby given a vicarious experience
of something like remembering -- remembering what we never knew. Or, again, readers may
remember what characters forget, or seem to have forgotten or misremembered. Remembering is an
integral part of the process of making sense of a narrative, and of experiencing it as such.
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 2
In the most essential sense, of course, reading cannot occur at all without memory. Most
basically, words and sentences previously read must be stored in ‘working memory’,
1
and enough
details to convey the ‘gist’ (see e.g. Adolphs et al., 2001) must then be transferred to long--term
memory if the text is a longer one, or if a text is read in separate sessions. The interactions between
types of memory when reading are in fact complex and ongoing, whatever the length or nature of the
text being read. Kintsch and Mangalath (2010: 3) suggest that what we know about a given word (its
long--term memory structure), together with the context in which it is currently being read, creates a
trace in working memory that makes available the currently relevant information about this word:
Long--term semantic memory is a decontextualized trace that summarizes all the experiences a person
has had with that word. This trace is used to construct meaning in working memory. Meaning is
therefore always contextual, generated from the interaction between long--term memory traces and
the momentary context existing in working memory. Importantly for the study of complex and full--
length literary texts, these interactions involve not only semantic traces but also syntactic constraints.
(2010: 20)
In the reading and comprehension of any linguistic text, then, semantics, syntax, and processes of
recall and inference interact in a complex memory--dependent operation through which meaning is
generated. Fictional texts, however, unlike recipes, news articles, or essays, make memory and
remembering not only functional prerequisites of the reading process, but also part of the explicit
subject--matter, and hence the reader’s experience, of what is read. In fiction, through evocations of
1
‘Working memory’ is the theoretical construct that denotes the ability to activate and retain limited
information in the short term, as required for demanding cognitive tasks such as language
comprehension, reasoning, and learning; the term is often now used to replace or include the term
‘short--term memory’, with its more passive implications. The term was coined by Miller, Galanter,
and Pribram (1960), and expanded by Baddeley and Hitch’s (1974) and Baddeley’s (2000) models.
See Baddeley (2003) for a review.
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 3
characters’ memories and by other means, experiences of remembering are induced that contribute
qualitatively to the aesthetic experience of reading as well as making reading itself cognitively
possible.
In this paper, I will focus on the ways in which a famous fictional character remembers (or
does not remember), and how this has affected critics’ responses to her story, and may affect readers’
responses more generally. I will outline relevant findings on aspects of memory from recent research
in cognitive science, cognitive neuroscience, and psychology. I will consider the ways in which the
evocations of memory in a Realist text correspond to -- and differ from -- these findings, which we
may deem the cognitive realities of remembering, and hence how ‘cognitively realistic’ this text may
be considered in the realm of memory.
2
I will ask what may be the effects on the reading experience
of these correspondences with, or divergences from, our current best understanding of how memory
works.
3
My subject is a major nineteenth--century text usually categorized as ‘Realist’, Gustave
Flaubert’s Madame Bovary.
4
In particular, I will focus on the means by which Emma’s memory both
2
‘Cognitive realism’ denotes the capacity of a text to tap in directly to some aspect of a reader’s
cognitive faculties, by evoking this faculty in a cognitively accurate way. A text that is cognitively
realistic corresponds to how we really remember, or see, or feel, and may therefore induce a
particularly effortless imaginative response on the reader’s part. The term was first used in Troscianko
(2010a).
3
Dixon et al.’s (1993) distinction between ‘text features’ and ‘text effects’ corresponds to my own
approach to the fictional text and its reader--orientated analysis.
4
Flaubert himself rejected the label of ‘Realist’, specifically with regard to the writing of Madame
Bovary: ‘On me croit épris du réel, tandis que je l’exècre; car c’est en haine du réalisme que j’ai
entrepris ce roman’ (to Mme Roger des Genettes, 30 October 1856, in Oeuvres complètes, XIII, 541).
This does not, however, prevent our reading the text as an exemplar of Realism. The ‘Realism’ of this
text was also one of the points of reference used by judges at the novel’s trial for obscenity, conflating
aesthetics and morality: Flaubert’s technique ‘conduirait à un réalisme qui serait la négation du beau
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 4
creates and reduces two types of a phenomenon known as ‘cognitive dissonance’. In this context, I
will demonstrate the inseparability of memory from emotion in Emma’s mental life, and how her
memories privilege the achievement of present coherence between memory and self--image over
correspondence to past facts. In general, I will show that Flaubert’s evocation of the workings of
memory in the title character is in general highly cognitively realistic, although there are also
divergences from cognitive realism. This analysis of the cognitive realism of memory can help us to
reach broader interpretive conclusions about Emma and her life that would not otherwise be possible.
The scientifically informed analysis of memory in Madame Bovary allows us to go beyond a
condemnation or exoneration of the protagonist on moral grounds. The initial serialized version of the
novel was put on trial for its immorality, and acquitted following its defence as a salutary morality
tale -- yet an understanding of the role memory plays in this text permits us to understand its
protagonist not merely as an illustration of moral principles, but as a human being with whom we, as
human beings, connect in explicable ways. Finally, by analysing Madame Bovary’s cognitive realism
of memory, I will ask whether traditional literary Realism, as exemplified in this text and through the
evocations of memory, can be considered ‘realistic’ in a cognitive sense.
An instinctive conceptualization of memory is that its function is the cognitive preservation of
the past. As theories of Antiquity had it, an event, person, etc. makes an imprint on one’s mind rather
like that of a stamp on wax,
5
and this imprint can be consulted by the deliberate effort to recall the
et du bon’, 428). Since then, critics have made many attempts to define Flaubert’s relation to Realism:
see e.g. Culler (2006: xxi-xxii) and Orr (2000: 208).
5
See Plato’s Theatetus (191c, d). The ‘wax tablet’ conception of memory is one aspect of the more
general tendency to conceive of cognition and consciousness as pictorial in essence. Plato, for
instance, also describes vision in terms of an inner artist who (metaphorically) paints pictures of what
we see in the soul (Philebus 39b, c). This pictorialist notion of consciousness has dominated
philosophical and scientific thought ever since the Ancient Greeks (Troscianko 2010b: Ch. 1), and has
also been prevalent in the ‘lay view’ of many aspects of human experience, from vision, imagination,
and memory to consciousness more generally.
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 5
past. However, memory is in many ways less predictable, less static, and less passive than this notion
implies. Memory is better thought of as a process of reconstruction than as one of reproduction:
‘instead of reproducing the original event or story, we derive a reconstruction based on our existing
presuppositions, expectations and our “mental set”’ (Foster 2009: 12). The opposing pair,
reconstruction and reproduction, can be thought of as serving similarly opposed functions, both of
which memory has to some extent to fulfil. To be useful, memory has to correspond sufficiently well
to the original experience: an animal that cannot preserve accurate records of past situations,
responses, and outcomes on the basis of which to learn and adapt its behaviours is evolutionarily
unviable. However, apart from the obvious storage and retrieval problems that would be encountered
by a system that preserved analogue, or even highly detailed, records of each moment of all or most
experiences, there is a second, positive requirement acting in the opposite direction from that of
correspondence: coherence. As Conway (2005: 595) puts it:
Coherence is a strong force in human memory that acts at encoding, post--encoding remembering, and
re--encoding, to shape both the accessibility of memories and the accessibility of [various aspects of]
their content. This is done in such a way as to make memory consistent with an individual’s current
goals, self--images, and self--beliefs.
Memory is dependent upon the behaviours and beliefs of the present as well as upon past realities, and
as I will show below, this fact is central to the evocation of memory in Madame Bovary.
Memory, like all of cognition, is driven by specific goals, and not least by the need to avoid
goal--change, and the risks this poses to the maintenance of a stable self--image. For instance,
evidence that goes against a current life--goal such as establishing a career in academia -- the memory
of reading about recent job cuts in departments in one’s own field, say -- may be dealt with by
ignoring the information or seeking out opposing arguments to reduce this memory’s significance.
There is evidence (Beike and Landoll 2000, Greenwald 1980, Holmes 1970) that dissonant memories
are dealt with by strategies such as outweighing, justification, closure, and processing neglect --
although in other cases (see Förster, Liberman, and Higgins 2005: esp. 221) they may be
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 6
disproportionately ruminated upon (so, one may instead recall those job cuts repeatedly, painfully but
serving to keep the unfulfilled goal of one’s career choice in mind, maximizing the likelihood of
noticing and acting upon future prospects in this or other fields). Given the many practical
requirements for correspondence in the short--term, recent memories tend to ‘correspond’ more than
they ‘cohere’, whereas the opposite is true of long--term memory (Conway 2005: 597). This may be
one reason why long--term memories are more frequently foregrounded in literary texts, including
Madame Bovary: the distortions and suppressions carried out for the sake of identity--bolstering
coherence are more revealing of fictional characters’ motivations and personality than is the
correspondence--driven preservation of accurate detail in the service of transitory behavioural goals.
Textual evocations of memory are part of the more general evocation of character and of
action: personality is conveyed in part by what is remembered (or not), and how and when it is
remembered, whilst behaviours and interactions between characters are motivated in part by
memories (and by things forgotten or misremembered). The characters in fictional texts are of interest
to us as readers because they correspond to some extent to how real human beings think, feel, and
behave, or because they diverge in comprehensible ways from the realities of human experience as we
understand them. To the extent that we believe in the potential reality of the people and lives evoked
by a fictional text, we will engage with them cognitively and emotionally. This is true even of genres
such as fantasy and science fiction, which seem to reject a direct connection with familiar realities,
whether by altering the nature of subjectivity (to that of elves or aliens rather than humans) or by
transposing the action to remote or imaginary settings (outer space, or an imagined world in which the
physical or cultural laws of this world do not hold). We engage with characters and their actions and
interactions by drawing comparisons and contrasts with those we know and understand; even the most
alienating sci--fi cannot be conceived of as anything other than a variation on the human, not least
because human language (however tweaked to convey difference) has evolved to express human
realities, and we have no other frame of reference than the human. Furthermore, there is no necessary
conflict between fictionality and emotional response; we need not be reduced to the sterile conclusion
that an emotional response to fiction ‘involves us in inconsistency and incoherence’ (Radford 1975:
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 7
78).
6
There is evidence that caring about fictional characters in fact bears many similarities in
cognitive terms to caring about other real people, especially strangers (e.g. Vermeule 2009).
7
Detailed
comparison of any aspect of fictional characters’ cognition with our own does not, however,
presuppose any naïve attribution of historical ‘reality’ or ‘pseudo--reality’ to these characters;
8
we do
not have to inquire into the possible real--life models for characters to acknowledge that their appeal
is based on cognitive realism (as defined above), the analysis of which is an important means of
enhancing our understanding of the connections that may be established between text and reader.
In Madame Bovary, the memories of the title character are the medium by which she
experiences emotional dissonances, and by which she seeks emotional coherence at the expense of
factual correspondence. The extent to which Emma’s memories are affected by her emotions -- and
6
The ‘paradox of fiction’ is also a starting point or point of reference for a number of contributions to
the edited volume Emotion and the Arts (ed. Hjort and Laver 1997).
7
See also a structuralist counterclaim -- that fictional characters are understandable despite being
fundamentally unrealistic -- in Knight (1997: 441).
8
Flaubert’s typically contradictory remarks on the relation or lack of it between himself and his
heroine Emma seem expressly designed to prevent textual judgements based on tenuous
autobiographical connections: he claims on the one hand that ‘Madame Bovary n’a rien de vrai. C’est
une histoire totalement inventée; je n’y ai rien ni de mes sentiments, ni de mon existence. L’illusion
(s’il y en a une), vient au contraire de l’impersonnalité de l’oeuvre’ (to Mlle Leroyer de Chantepie, 18
March 1857, in Oeuvres complètes, XIII, 567) and on the other hand that ‘Ma pauvre Bovary, sans
doute, souffre et pleure dans vingt villages de France à la fois, à cette heure même’ (to Louise Colet,
14 August 1853, in Oeuvres complètes, XIII, 383). The first statement separates the novel, as
‘invented’, from ‘truth’ or ‘reality’ in both a general and a personal sense; the second attributes to it
not just an unquestioned realism, but a ubiquitous reality. (The oft--quoted statement ‘Madame
Bovary, c’est moi’ is probably apocryphal; on the means by which it became a Flaubertian idée reçue,
see e.g. http://passouline.blog.lemonde.fr/2009/10/25/madame-bovary-cest-qui/; accessed 24
November 2010.)
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 8
are emotional in their manifestations -- powerfully illustrates how memory is a ‘cognitive’ function
not in the sense of being affect--neutral, or ‘rational’. Rather, memory is ‘cognitive’ in the
psychologically valid sense of being inherently interconnected with all the other aspects of cognitive
life that regulate behaviour, an important one of which is emotion. In evolutionary terms, emotion is
an appraisal process which contributes to our assessment of a situation as requiring, for example, fight
or flight responses. To feel is to judge an object or a situation with regard to what it means to you:
what its meaning is for future personal concerns or actions (Frijda 2007: 93): there is no fundamental
disjuncture between ‘thinking’ and ‘feeling’. The Platonic distinction between the two is the basis for
common assumptions about ‘cognitive’ faculties such as thought and memory: that they ideally have
no emotional component, and that if they do, they are reduced in validity by the ‘intrusion’ of
emotion. But emotions have evolved as a crucial part of all cognition:
9
in the case of memory,
emotional stimuli induce a physiological state that aids survival in life--threatening situations by
enhancing memory encoding, retention, and retrieval through increased neuro--chemical activity. For
instance, the sight of a man similar to the one who once mugged you will induce emotions of fear as
experienced during the original event, and your memories of that event, as enhanced by the re--
experienced emotion, will be more vivid than memories of emotionally neutral events.
10
Hence these
memories are more likely to trigger the behavioural response appropriate in the first instance, that is,
flight (which may now be experienced simply as nervousness, muscular tension, a ‘shiver down the
spine’, and so on). There is thus also no fundamental disjuncture between ‘remembering’ and
9
The term ‘cognitive realism’ is also based on a concept of cognition as encompassing emotion;
when, in what follows, I refer to both ‘cognitive’ and ‘emotional’, it is as reminder and emphasis of
their interconnection.
10
Emotionally enhanced memories may be more vivid, but they are not necessarily more accurate,
since heightened emotion, especially extreme stress, can result in narrowed attention (the ‘weapon
focus effect’) and perceptual biases (e.g. Ochsner 2000), and emotion can enhance memory for gist at
the expense of that for detail (Adolphs et al. 2001).
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 9
‘feeling’: numerous well--documented effects modulate the interactions of memory and different
types of emotion (see e.g. Levine and Pizzaro (2004) for a review), and many of these are manifested
in the relation between past and present emotions throughout Emma Bovary’s life.
Many of the interactions between memory and emotion which Emma experiences can be
attributed to cognitive dissonance (Festinger 1957, Aronson 1969). Cognitive dissonance is the result
of holding two incompatible cognitions simultaneously, or, more specifically, of being in a state or
acting in a way that contradicts a fundamental element of one’s self--concept or belief--system.
11
The
element contradicted by a current state or action may be, for instance, the belief that one was born for
passion and luxury, or the conviction that ‘I am intelligent’; these both play important roles in
Emma’s self--concept. Cognitive dissonance -- the uncomfortable feeling caused by holding
conflicting ideas simultaneously -- manifests itself directly as anxiety or unease (Emma experiences
‘un insaisissable malaise’ (83) in the early days of her married life), but can also have secondary
effects on how emotional appraisals are made and how they and life events are remembered, as part of
the attempt to reduce dissonance. Emma makes a single decision (to marry Charles) which results in
the disappointment of her dreams of wealth, sophistication, grand passion, and all the other ideals she
has gleaned from literature. This is a form of hedonistic dissonance (dissonance created by actions
that result in negative consequences for oneself) which reduces all subsequent decisions (to blame
Charles for everything, to have affairs, to spend more money than she and Charles have on clothes
and furnishings, to kill herself) to vain attempts to negate or vindicate that initial decision. These later
decisions in turn create moral dissonance (dissonance aroused when acting in a way that causes
negative consequences for others), so that Emma’s married life becomes defined by two major
cognitive dissonances and the attempts to reduce them. Both the dissonances themselves and the
cognitive combating of them occur through memories that are directed less towards accurate recall
than towards cognitive and emotional coherence.
11
For an early and a recent criticism of cognitive--dissonance theory, see Chapanis and Chapanis
(1964) and Chen and Risen (2010).
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 10
The progression of emergent dissonances and their attempted resolution, both through
coherence--orientated operations of memory, can thus help us understand the entire trajectory of
Emma’s married life. Emma’s rapid disappointment in her married life is itself a direct consequence
of her memories of the romantic novels she read at the convent, which defined ‘les mots de félicité, de
passion et d’ivresse’ (78) in a way that real life could never live up to. She reduces the resulting
memory--induced dissonance in two main ways. Firstly, she does so by making Charles, and her
marriage to him, into the unequivocal cause of her misery by means of a thread of reasoning running
something like this: I am passionate and intelligent and deserve happiness, but I cannot be passionate
or intelligent or happy with you, therefore you must be dull, stupid, and selfish. The hyperbolic but
psychologically necessary conclusion is as follows: ‘Pour qui donc était--elle sage? N’était--il pas, lui,
obstacle à toute félicité, la cause de toute misère, et comme l’ardillon pointu de cette courroie
complexe qui la bouclait de tous côtés?’ (146). Charles’s generosity, both emotional and material, his
good sense, and his love of her are ignored in favour of the version of him which lets Emma be a
victim, and allows her to preserve her self--concept as intelligent, since the greatest intelligence can
sometimes be the victim of deception, or of momentary madness: ‘Comment donc avait--elle fait (elle
qui était si intelligente!) pour se méprendre encore une fois? Du reste, par quelle déplorable manie
avoir ainsi abîmé son existence en sacrifices continuels?’ (214). Memories of past reading--matter are
responsible for how she defines her relation to her husband, he as the cause of unhappiness, she as the
intelligent but briefly mad or mistaken victim.
Memories thus bring about a certain (limited) understanding of the present. They also reorder
other existing memories such that they correspond with the new understanding of the present. For
example, when watching the fictional marriage performed at the opera, Emma compares herself with
the heroine, and her melodramatic metaphor of the abyss makes her the helpless victim, and her
wedding day a day of mistaken joy on which all suffering began:
Emma rêvait au jour de son mariage; et elle se revoyait là--bas, au milieu des blés, sur le petit sentier,
quand on marchait vers l’église. Pourquoi donc n’avait--elle pas, comme celle--là, résisté, supplié?
Elle était joyeuse, au contraire, sans s’apercevoir de l’abîme où elle se précipitait... (247-48)
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 11
The wedding thus fulfils the role of the past ‘catastrophe extraordinaire qui l’avait
bouleversée […] la cause de ce qui la faisait souffrir’ (205). Attributing to the single event of her
marriage, as ‘extraordinary catastrophe’, all subsequent unhappiness, and reordering her memories of
the day accordingly, is an easier strategy than asking whether her whole self--concept might be
flawed, or whether her behaviours might need changing. This predominant focus on negative event
outcomes and on the consequences of failure to attain certain goals is a clear manifestation of the state
of sadness or mild depression which rapidly sets in after the marriage; as the quotations given in the
last two paragraphs illustrate, Emma reflects far less on future goals than on past failures and
disappointments. Sadness induces the cognitive--emotional ‘appraisal tendency’ to concentrate on
failure and its consequences in order to aid adjustment to the failure and its implications for other
goals (Levine and Pizarro 2004: 543) -- and the tendency is all the stronger given that such reflection
also forms part of Emma’s dissonance--reduction strategy.
The dissonance--reducing strategy of making Charles and the marriage the cause of all
unhappiness has a further consequence for memory: it creates nostalgia for life before marriage. This
is also more a consequence of the unhappiness of present circumstances, and the changed appraisals
of the past that have arisen from this unhappiness, than it is an accurate record of past realities. When
she is reminded of her days at the convent (319), or the years spent at home with her father, Emma
engages in the common act of nostalgically enhancing the happiness of these past eras: her time at
home is recalled as a series of bucolic images of simplicity, and through the abstractions of ‘bonheur’,
‘liberté’, and ‘espoir’ (205). Recent studies have demonstrated two interesting facts about memory of
one’s own past: firstly that people’s reports of past emotion are dependent upon their current appraisal
of the past events in question (e.g. Safer et al. 2002), and secondly, paradoxically, that nostalgia --
positive sentiments about a past stage of one’s life, with or without the desire to return to that past --
may be due to positive feelings caused by the act of successful recall (Leboe and Ansons 2006). That
is, the mere fact of managing to remember the past creates pleasure, which is then misattributed to a
pleasant past. Given the time she spends and the pleasure she derives from reminiscing, this second
phenomenon may well be contributing to Emma’s nostalgia, and in any case it is clear that,
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 12
conforming to the first finding, Emma’s nostalgic memories have more to do with present
unhappiness than with past happiness. The extent of the change which has occurred between past
experience and present recollection is manifest to the reader who, reading of Emma’s memory of the
idyllic simplicity of her youth in the country (e.g. 204-5), recalls that at the time, we learnt of her that
‘Mlle Rouault ne s’amusait guère à la campagne, maintenant surtout qu’elle était chargée presque à
elle seule des soins de la ferme. Comme la salle était fraîche, elle grelottait tout en mangeant [...]’ (62-
3). The extreme difference between the past experienced as present and the past remembered is highly
revealing of Emma’s emotional state as she remembers, and here it is our memories as readers that
allow us to identify the telling discrepancy. Nonetheless, this is unlikely to result in mere censure of
her inconsistency, because, again, the essential cognitive realism of the mental manoeuvre is one
which we can all recognize from our own experience, and makes her as much a character to be
empathized with as one to be condemned. More broadly, the cognitively realistic intertwining of
emotion and memory in the service of a coherent life--story complicates such condemnation, as our
own emotions are engaged inseparably from our own memories, inferences, and reasoning, and the
inseparability of Emma’s is both felt and understood -- even whilst our preconceptions about memory
tell us that something is not as it should be.
Another form of emotional memory, regret, is the precursor to Emma’s second dissonance--
reduction strategy, which is to seek confirmation of her self--concept as intelligent and deserving of
happiness, passion, and luxury through affairs with other men. Emma begins to regret missed chances
for happiness with other men. Her regretful memories of the ball at La Vaubyessard are part of a
sequence of attentional, perceptual, and cognitive biases that clearly signal the importance of the
Viscount (and all men such as him) to Emma’s search for emotional coherence. At the ball, Emma
focuses only on the aspects of the evening which reinforce her concept of wealth and breeding as
positive sources of pleasure, not noticing, for example, how Charles is ignored for hours on end,
standing watching a card game he doesn’t understand (95). Her emotion reaches its peak when she is
asked to dance by the Viscount, and the physical exertion of the dancing adds to the emotional
excitement; finally, ‘elle se renversa contre la muraille et mit la main devant ses yeux’ (94). When,
back at home, she sees and smells the cigar case dropped under their carriage on the way home by the
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 13
passing horsemen, one of whom might have been the Viscount, she invests it with an imagined
history, concocted around her memories of him (98).
12
Later, when she is being seduced by Rodolphe,
the equivalent role of the two men is made clear when the smell of him reminds her powerfully of the
Viscount:
même elle sentait le parfum de la pommade qui lustrait sa chevelure. Alors une mollesse la saisit, elle
se rappela ce vicomte qui l’avait fait valser à la Vaubyessard, et dont la barbe exhalait, comme ces
cheveux--là, cette odeur de vanille et de citron; et, machinalement, elle entreferma les paupières pour
la mieux respirer. (181)
Here an involuntary memory (one not deliberately retrieved) is cued by the smell of the pomade,
which resembles that used by the Viscount, and Emma closes her eyes so as to focus on this sensory
input alone, and the memories it triggers. Involuntary memory can be conceived of as arising from
the interaction of a current life--situation and the immediate situation, the former possibly exerting a
priming effect on the cues that appear in the latter (Berntsen 2007). The life--situation of an unhappy
marriage primes the recollection of a closely related past event within the immediate situation of this
new seduction, and the past event can be recalled because Emma is able to remember the smell of the
Viscount’s pomade clearly and without effort, nearly four years later, even though most of the other
details (save the sense of regret) were forgotten in a matter of weeks: ‘Et peu à peu, les physionomies
se confondirent dans sa mémoire, elle oublia l’air des contredanses, elle ne vit plus si nettement les
livrées et les appartements; quelques détails s’en allèrent; mais le regret lui resta’ (97). The fact that it
is a smell that triggers memory is psychologically significant: because the olfactory system synapses
12
Marder (1997: 59-60) notes how Emma uses the cigar case to ‘preserve her memory of the event [of
the ball]’, but strays from demonstrable textual fact when she goes on to claim that this entails her
using it ‘as if this thing could somehow objectify lost time’, as ‘a temporal lost object, a
representational container capable of incorporating time’. Its non--metaphysical capacity to stimulate
memory is significance enough.
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 14
directly with the amygdala--hippocampus complex, which can be considered the ‘neural substrate of
emotional memory’ (Herz and Schooler 2002: 22), olfactory information has direct access to
emotional and memory--related neural areas, which makes smells an effective and emotionally potent
trigger even for very old memories. When, as here, a smell is part of the original emotionally arousing
stimulus, the connections between smell, memory, and emotion are intensified by attention--
narrowing (Easterbrook 1959) and prioritized processing (Kensinger 2004). These lead to a long--
term selective--memory effect consisting of memory enhancements in the long term for the central
stimulus, and memory deficits in recalling peripheral elements (Christianson 1992). Furthermore, the
‘post--stimulus elaboration hypothesis’ proposes that more effort may be invested in retrospective
elaboration of an arousing emotional experience than of a neutral one, and that the links between new
and previously stored information thus created, and the deeper level of processing involved in creating
them, result in better memory. ‘Post--stimulus elaboration’ is certainly what Emma engages in: she
keeps herself awake after the dancing stops (87), to revel in the illusion of luxury that will soon end,
presumably connecting this specific event with all her prior notions of romance, luxury, and happiness
(80-1); and, back home, ‘Ce fut donc une occupation pour Emma que le souvenir de ce bal’ (97), and
she procures ever more reading matter to keep investing the memory with further significance. She
associates the cigar case with the Viscount; she associates him with his imagined mistresses
(modelled, doubtless, on all the lovers in the books she has read, e.g. 80) and with Paris, and all the
preconceptions she has of the capital. The lasting emotional response to the remembered stimuli is
‘regret’ (that the excitement couldn’t last, that she didn’t somehow act to make it last), itself a
consequence of the second of Emma’s dissonance--reducing beliefs: that she can be (and has been)
passionate and happy with other men. This regret gradually makes it impossible for her to remember
anything but the idealized sources of that regret, and, equally, makes those impossible to forget.
Emma’s regret about not having acted to make anything happen with Léon during the first
period of their intimacy is also fuelled by nostalgic recollections of him and the time spent with him,
themselves fuelled less by love of him than by hatred of the present. The day after Léon’s departure,
she recalls him as more perfect than he ever was:
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 15
Comme au retour de la Vaubyessard, quand les quadrilles tourbillonnaient dans sa tête, elle avait une
mélancolie morne, un désespoir engourdi. Léon réapparaissait plus grand, plus beau, plus suave, plus
vague; quoiqu’il fût séparé d’elle, il ne l’avait pas quittée, il était là, et les murailles de la maison
semblaient garder son ombre. Elle ne pouvait détacher sa vue de ce tapis où il avait marché, de ces
meubles vides où il s’était assis. La rivière coulait toujours, et poussait lentement ses petits flots le
long de la berge glissante. Ils s’y étaient promenés bien des fois, à ce même murmure des ondes, sur
les cailloux couverts de mousse. Quels bons soleils ils avaient eus! quelles bonnes après--midi, seuls,
à l’ombre, dans le fond du jardin! Il lisait tout haut, tête nue, posé sur un tabouret de bâtons secs; le
vent frais de la prairie faisait trembler les pages du livre et les capucines de la tonnelle… Ah! il était
parti, le seul charme de sa vie, le seul espoir possible d’une félicité! Comment n’avait--elle pas saisi
ce bonheur--là, quand il se présentait! Pourquoi ne l’avoir pas retenu à deux mains, à deux genoux,
quand il voulait s’enfuir? Et elle se maudit de n’avoir pas aimé Léon; elle eut soif de ses lèvres. (159-
60)
This passage provides a potent evocation of regret as an emotional and coherence--orientated form of
memory which makes up part of the delicate balance of Emma’s conceptualization of herself and her
situation. Already, a few months after the fact, the times she spent with Léon by the river have
coalesced in Emma’s memory into a generalized episode that ‘stands for’ all the individual instances:
the sunshine, the place where he sat, the flowers, make this an extremely efficient, ‘schematized’
representation (see Barclay 1986) of a series of more equivocal events (e.g. 127-30, 143). This
summarized memory emphasizes the invariant quality of the attraction between Léon and Emma at
the expense of changing and less straightforwardly idyllic details. It does so with a cognitive
efficiency that is perfectly constructed to allow Emma to attribute all her present unhappiness to her
failure to act in this regard. The fact that Léon appears, along with all the other increases in the
desirability of his appearance and character, also as ‘plus vague’ is a further function of his status as
remembered, and as the object of schematizing regret. The direct juxtaposition of the darkness of
Emma’s mood and the completeness of Léon’s remembered perfection is a clear expression of the
extent of her regret, and shows this regret -- like nostalgia -- not to be something that emerged directly
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 16
from the original experience but to be a consequence of her current emotional state, which has
induced memories that improve on past realities.
The initial parallel which is drawn here between Emma’s current state and the morning after
the ball is also, of course, instructive, in that it increases still further the generalizing equivalence
between all the men in her life, and between all the missed chances and their consequences for
happiness. Emma engages in retrospective reasoning, supported by generalized and idealizing
memories, to find the cause of her current bleakness in her inaction where Léon was concerned, just
as she did with the Viscount. Savitsky, Medvec, and Gilovich (1997) found that (even controlling for
differences in their life impact) inaction regrets, which felt like psychological ‘unfinished business’,
were more often ruminated over in the long term, therefore more easily recalled, and increasingly
likely to be the lasting object of regret than action regrets. Gilovich and Medvec (1995) attribute this
temporal pattern of regret (inaction regrets becoming more salient in the longer term) to three possible
factors. Lasting inaction regrets may be due firstly to the greater ease with which we comprehend
causal factors that compel behaviour than those that inhibit it, and secondly to a tendency towards
increased confidence that past obstacles could have been overcome. The rhetorical questions in
Emma’s thoughts (‘why didn’t I act?’) make clear that these factors are playing a part in her regret.
Thirdly, long--term inaction regrets may be due to an asymmetry in consequences: with inaction
regrets, the possible benefits of having acted are of an open--ended nature, so can grow in imagined
scope over time, whereas the negative outcomes of a regretted action remain static and can thus be
countered by various compensation strategies. This enhancement of formerly possible benefits of
acting occurs strongly in Emma’s case, and within twenty--four hours: her past inaction represents, as
Davison and Feeney (2008: 387) put it, ‘a blank canvas of possibilities for what “might have been”’,
and she fills this canvas with the superlative abstractions of ‘charm’, ‘joy’, and ‘happiness’.
Regret of ‘an accumulated, unfocused pattern of inaction’ (Gilovich and Medvec 1995: 381)
is powerful in Emma’s case: she had many opportunities to say or do something explicit to initiate an
affair with Léon, but she did not do so (although this pattern of inaction culminated in the moment of
Léon’s parting, when she failed to beg him to stay, or to tell him how she felt, 153). As soon as he is
gone, she dwells on his supposed perfection, and by extension on the happiness she might have found
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 17
with him, such that, as Davison and Feeney (2008: 398) have it, ‘the emergent quality of general
regrets makes them […] more like retrospective judgements than straightforward recollections’. When
we learn of Emma, in the midst of her affair with Rodolphe, that ‘Elle se repentait, comme d’un
crime, de sa vertu passée, et ce qui en restait encore s’écroulait sous les coups furieux de son orgueil’
(214), the simile equates the general pattern of inaction with a specific (criminal) action. This
cognitive--linguistic reduction of a repeated into a singular event allows Emma’s virtue to be much
more easily dismissed, destroyed, and left behind than it could be were it to be remembered as a
recurrent part of herself. The simile, as linguistic feature and figure of thought, connects language and
cognition in a way that completes the shift from regret of inaction to justification of (adulterous)
action. The simultaneous naturalness and cognitive sleight of hand of the move towards dissonance--
reducing adultery makes this stage of Emma’s life as comprehensible as it is disconcerting. The
cognitively realistic nature of these contradictions makes Emma’s reminiscences more than tritely
poetic fancies -- or rather, it gives these fancies their significance and necessity, and hence makes
them powerful evocations of the fallibilities of human cognition, as well as of the irritating
indulgences of a deluded woman. Many readers may be inclined to stand in judgement upon such
idealizing excesses, but the location of these excesses in the complex network of motivation described
above makes them hard to dismiss as complete trivialities.
Emma then takes first Rodolphe and later Léon as lovers, using these other men to confirm
the reality of her identity: she can be passionate, intelligent, happy, with them if not with her husband.
Memories of past reading are also crucial here: at the opera, ‘Elle se retrouvait dans les lectures de sa
jeunesse, en plein Walter Scott’ (246), and soon afterwards, partly as a consequence of this
heightened romantic state, she succumbs to Léon’s seduction. But being with these other men creates
the second dissonance: she now also experiences moral dissonance (aroused when acting in a way that
causes negative consequences for others) because of how she is hurting Charles and acting against
social mores. At the inevitable point where the affairs with Rodolphe and with Léon begin to turn
sour, she responds, on both occasions, with renewed passion, born of a desperation in which regret
and desire conflict. With Rodolphe, the desire and the regret coexist: ‘elle redoubla de tendresse; et
Rodolphe, de moins en moins, cacha son indifférence. Elle ne savait pas si elle regrettait de lui avoir
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 18
cédé, ou si elle ne souhaitait point, au contraire, le chérir davantage’ (203). With Léon, she allows
herself a brief moment of emotional honesty, but the regret it implies is not made explicit, and desire
soon succeeds it: ‘elle s’avouait ne rien sentir d’extraordinaire. Cette déception s’effaçait vite sous un
espoir nouveau, et Emma revenait à lui plus enflammée, plus avide’ (302). Thus in both these cases,
Emma’s memories of the ways in which she has ‘compromised herself’ contribute to enhance both her
regret and her desire.
The ‘effort--justification paradigm’ of cognitive--dissonance reduction proposes that the more
extreme (effortful or degrading) the means of achieving an aim, the more highly the aim, once
reached, will be valued (Aronson and Mills 1959). As predicted by this model, Emma’s regrets at
having acted as she has do not make her denounce herself and her lovers, but instead make her seek to
reduce the dissonance created by her knowledge of her immorality and lack of delight by exaggerating
the perfection of her lovers and the force of her pleasure, and memories play an important role in this
exaggeration, both countering and enhancing Emma’s present dissatisfaction: ‘en écrivant [à Léon],
elle percevait un autre homme, un fantôme fait de ses plus ardents souvenirs, de ses lectures les plus
belles, de ses convoitises les plus fortes [...]’ (308).
13
Léon, as Emma longs for him, is created out of a
potent mixture of memory, desire, and regret in which no single element can win out over the others,
since Emma’s second form of cognitive dissonance is only partially resolved.
This solution is an essentially unstable one, since the exaggeration of her own desire and her
lovers’ perfection only makes more, and more thrilling, affairs necessary, which will in turn lead to
13
Emma’s excessive purchases are her final tactic: they serve to offset her unhappiness, her regret,
and the wrongness of her decision to marry, and she justifies the purchases through the extent of her
‘sacrifices’, and by assuring herself and Charles that they are ‘indispensable’. But the more she
spends, the greater her regret (‘quand ses yeux se reportaient [...] sur toutes ces choses enfin qui
avaient adouci l’amertume de sa vie, un remords la prenait, ou plutôt un regret immense et qui irritait
la passion, loin de l’anéantir’, 313) and her sense of impurity (‘Elle aurait voulu, s’échappant comme
un oiseau, aller se rajeunir quelque part, bien loin, dans les espaces immaculés’, 309) and thus her
desperate, passionate need for happiness from them, exactly as with her lovers.
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 19
more dissonance thanks to disappointment and regret. There is, ultimately, no way of stabilizing this
situation or of neutralizing its conflicting elements, except deep self--analysis and fundamental life
changes -- or death. The two coexisting dissonances and their incomplete resolutions are connected by
a fragile set of coherence--orientated memories that could, at any moment, be collapsed by memory
itself. When Emma’s memory fails her in the shock that follows Rodolphe’s final refusal of financial
help, she does still remember her love (of whom, it is not specified), and this memory is experienced
as though she is losing her soul through it, as through a wound:
elle ne se rappelait point la cause de son horrible état, c’est--à--dire la question d’argent. Elle ne
souffrait que de son amour, et sentait son âme l’abandonner par ce souvenir, comme les blessés, en
agonisant, sentent l’existence qui s’en va par leur plaie qui saigne. (326-27)
The desire for a solution to her predicament makes Emma transfer the entire cause of her suffering on
to what she designates her love, makes her memory recall nothing but this love (see below, p. 000,
on post--traumatic amnesia), and hence exchanges the pain of shame, guilt, and responsibility for the
much gentler agony of a love remembered as innocent and unrequited. A little later, as she lies dying,
the mention of the nurse induces an emotionally unbearable response in her: ‘Et, à ce nom, qui la
reportait dans le souvenir de ses adultères et de ses calamités, madame Bovary détourna sa tête,
comme au dégoût d’un autre poison plus fort qui lui remontait à la bouche’ (331). Having visited the
nurse with Léon, the word recalls him and all that he represents in terms of infidelity and its
consequences; it is as if she has drunk another, stronger poison than the arsenic she has already
swallowed. The metaphors of physical harm -- the wound and the poison -- by means of which
memory is invoked make it a powerful equivalent to the actual cause of her death: arsenic (whose
location she remembered perfectly, 328) was the immediate means of suicide, but her memory is the
cognitive cause. Memory creates the first cognitive dissonance, and serves to reduce but not to negate
it and the second; ultimately it keeps both present in Emma’s mind, as a conflict between the
memories that tell her she is as she believes herself to be, and deserves all she desires, and those that
remind her what lengths she has gone to to reassure herself of precisely that.
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 20
Madame Bovary is the story of a woman whose memories, in spite and because of the extent
to which they help create coherence within her own self--image and life--story, do not permit her any
peace.
14
The famous ‘impersonality’ of Flaubert’s narrative mode in this novel,
15
in which the
focalization shifts between omniscience, a limited external focalization with access to none of the
characters’ perspectives, and, primarily, variable internal focalization that adopts various of their
perspectives in turn, means that Emma’s weakness, shallowness, and failure to learn from experience
are presented not as pre--judged flaws, but as parts of the experience of being human. The single
seemingly unequivocal, unironized judgement brought to bear on Emma is that she has been corrupted
by the reading of literature: ‘Pendant six mois, à quinze ans, Emma se graissa donc les mains à cette
poussière des vieux cabinets de lecture’ (80).
16
The overtly judgemental nature of this statement,
conveyed through the basic metaphorical equivalence of the dirty with the immoral, may, however, be
better read as ironically undermining the easy answers of such received wisdom, and as suggesting
14
See Auerbach (1957: 431) on Flaubert’s innovation in ‘directly captur[ing] the chronic nature of
this psychological situation’. The novel has given rise to its own psychological condition,
‘bovarysme’, defined by Le Nouveau Petit Robert as ‘Evasion dans l’imaginaire par insatisfaction;
pouvoir “qu’a l’homme de se concevoir autre qu’il n’est” (J. de Gaultier)’ (2000: 287), but the
preceding analysis has shown that no special diagnosis is required to comprehend Emma’s
psychology.
15
See Flaubert’s correspondence above, n. 0. Auerbach (1957: 432) coins the term ‘objective
seriousness’ to describe Flaubert’s impartiality, but the connected claims that he exercises no
‘psychological understanding’ (432) and does not provide any ‘naturalistic representation of
consciousness’ (428) are hard to accept unreservedly.
16
See also Riffaterre (1981: 6) (‘I need hardly point out that Madame Bovary is a fiction about the
dangers of fiction’) and Culler (2006: 146) (‘If there is anything that justifies our finding the novel
limited and tendentious it is the seriousness with which Emma’s corruption is attributed to novels and
romances’).
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 21
that the problem lies in Emma’s attitude to literature rather than in literature itself.
17
The source of
Emma’s ‘corruption’ may thus be seen as consisting in her belief that literature can and should be
immoral: she lets it redefine the emotional abstractions of ‘bonheur’ and ‘félicité’ and their
constituents (‘liberté’, ‘espoir’, ‘charme’, ‘passion/ivresse’), and makes them central to her appraisals
of life (see above, pp. 00). Emma’s clichéd response to a certain sort of novel is, then, what this novel
presents as the cause of the original dissonance, which makes her marriage seem instantly such an
unbearable disappointment and sets the rest of the progression above in motion.
Tracing the means by which memory serves both to mitigate and to exacerbate that
dissonance, and others arising from it, enables us to see Emma as more than a wicked woman,
18
or a
misguided fool,
19
or a victim of society,
20
men,
21
womanhood,
22
fate,
23
language,
24
or romantic fiction
17
Williams (1973:53-55) argues that Emma’s character determines how she responds to literature,
rather than literature moulding her character.
18
Henry James (1919 [1878]: 205) condemns her in an early review as ‘ignorant, vain, naturally
depraved’.
19
Barash and Barash’s Madame Bovary’s Ovaries: A Darwinian Look at Literature (2005: 101)
argues that an evolutionary approach to literary criticism can help us understand how ‘smart women
[like Emma Bovary] really do make foolish choices’.
20
Cook (1973: 304): ‘Emma is rather a reflector of meagerness than a meager reflector’.
21
Ferguson (2002: 771-72) argues that Charles ‘actually does fail Emma’, and Bourgeois (1968: 126)
contends that Homais plays the role of ‘le serpent biblique’, ‘le diable’, who is ‘à la base de chaque
malheur qui s’abat sur l’héroine et finalement l’écrase et la tue’.
22
See Sabiston (1973: 339) on the ‘prison of womanhood’ in which Emma is incarcerated, in part
because she has “internalized” the values of her society.
23
See e.g. Paskow 2005: 331-33.
24
See Tanner 1979: esp. 363-65.
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 22
(see above, n. 0), or even a sufferer of mental illness.
25
A study of Emma’s memories allows us to
understand her as merely -- and fully -- human, and as such provides scope for flexible readings that
need not posit one single destructive trait or agent or ‘tragic flaw’. A better comprehension of the
inevitable nature of the progression from cognitive dissonance to distortions of memory, to the state
that means suicide is the only escape, helps to explain why it is possible to engage with the
protagonist as a human being rather than as simply sinner or sinned--against.
Emma’s weakness lies in her inability to realize what her mind is doing to her, and, through
such awareness, to change her mental practices for the better. But the mutually reinforcing nature of
the patterns that are soon established makes this an understandable failing. The common
conceptualization of memory as an essentially passive means of preserving the past, which may fail to
preserve but does not tend to distort, is what makes Emma succumb so unwittingly to her distorting
memories and their effects, and what makes the reader likely to feel at once alienated from her and
drawn into her story by its cognitive realism.
26
I have demonstrated that the evocation of memory in Madame Bovary is cognitively realistic
in fundamental ways. Is, then, the cognitive realism of Emma’s memory in this text flawless? The
answer, of course, is no: there are slight deviations from cognitive realism in Flaubert’s evocation of
various aspects of Emma’s memory. For instance, her post--traumatic amnesia is an occurrence
25
Beizer (1994: 138) diagnoses Emma with hysteria (see also Goldstein 1991); Marder (1997)
pronounces her to be sick with ‘temporal bulimia’.
26
This sense of incontrovertible realism seems to have been an effect that Flaubert deliberately sought
in writing the novel: ‘Ce qui est atroce de difficulté, c’est l’enchaînement des idées et qu’elles
dérivent bien naturellement les unes des autres’ (to Louise Colet, 19 June 1852, in Oeuvres complètes,
XIII, 206). Williams (1973: 16) cites this remark and parses it as expressing Flaubert’s efforts to
achieve a presentation of mental causes and effects ‘consistent with some notional standard of
psychological feasibility’; this ‘standard’ may now be seen to constitute ‘feasability’ not just in the
notional sense of conforming to a (possibly erroneous) lay view, but also in conforming to
psychological realities.
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 23
common in films and novels but extremely rare in real life (McNally 2003: 186), and its evocation
thus corresponds to common preconceptions about how memory works rather than to the realities.
The imagery of memory as death may also be considered hyperbolic, despite the completeness of
Emma’s mental and emotional entrapment as demonstrated above. However, divergences such as
these do not significantly detract from the fundamental cognitive realism of the biography of a mind
created through memory and cognitive dissonance, and indeed serve to render more vivid some
aspects of this account. The frequency with which amnesia is evoked in fiction and films means that
its occurrence here will be accepted as plausible by many readers, and will be likely to induce a sense
of comfortable recognition as far as the evocation of psychology goes, as well as the thrill of
recognizing a supposed psychological marker of deep trauma.
Those aspects of the evocation of memory which are cognitively realistic are likely to have a
different, more complex, effect. Our instinctive conceptualizations of memory as a passive storage
capacity, which either manages or fails to provide us with accurate reproductions of past events, may
make evocations of memory such as those found in Madame Bovary unsettling, because their
emphasis on distortions for the sake of mental and emotional coherence contradict the lay view.
However, these evocations may also be compelling because of their cognitively realistic nature
27
--
and the possible duality of response thus created may help explain the dualities often present in
critics’ responses to Emma’s story: condemning yet simultaneously empathizing or sympathizing with
her, or even admiring her. Tillett (1966), for example, condemns Emma as a ‘dramatizer of self’ (5)
who is ‘completely selfish’ and lacks all ‘warmth of heart’ (3) but also sympathizes with her plight as
27
Neither type of response presupposes a specific, articulate awareness on the reader’s part of what
has caused it -- as Flaubert knew and intended, effects can be felt without their textual trigger being
noticed: ‘Le lecteur ne s’apercevra pas, je l’espère, de tout le travail psychologique caché sous la
forme, mais il en ressentira l’effet’ (to Louise Colet, 2 January 1854, in Oeuvres complètes, XIII, 450).
Flaubert’s preparatory ‘psychological work’ for the novel was extensive, and included the reduction
of specificity in characters’ psychological developments, so as not to jeopardize their effect on the
reader as desired above (see Williams 1973: 37, 43).
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 24
‘a young woman far superior in intelligence and sensibility to her acquaintances, ambitious, sighing
for life in Paris, suffering from frustration, unwisely married, driven by despair to death’ (5). Henry
James (1919 [1878]) states this conflict explicitly, through a sequence of reflections on Emma’s
character and the reader’s response to it. James describes Emma as ‘ignorant, vain, naturally
depraved’ (205), and seems to espouse the opinion that women like her ‘deserve but a limited degree
of sympathy’ (204); but he also declares that ‘she remains a living creature, and as a living creature
she interests us’ (204), and by means of this argument from ‘typicality’ and from vividness of
evocation he concludes:
one is dragged into the very current and tissue of the story; the reader himself seems to have lived in it
all, more than in any novel we can recall. At the end the intensity of illusion becomes horrible;
overwhelmed with disgust and pity he closes the book. (206)
Here the duality of responses that may be induced by the novel is expressed in its most extreme form,
and attributed to a large extent to Emma’s character and her morality or otherwise; the judgement on
her morality is in turn modulated by the ‘poignant and convincing’ way in which her character is
evoked and the ‘illusion’ of reality thereby upheld (206). In discussion of the works of Franz Kafka, it
has been argued that the evocation of vision and imagination in his characters creates a paradoxical
duality of response, by corresponding to the reality of how these processes work but not to our
preconceptions about them (Troscianko 2010a and 2010b). Something similar seems to occur in
Madame Bovary: the evocation of morality through memory may, through the intensity of the illusion
it creates, be at once disturbing, even off-putting, and convincing and compelling.
The question of how generalizable claims about readers’ responses to texts are is a delicate
one, which may be best resolved through empirical testing (see Troscianko 2010b: Ch. 5). In this
paper I wish to suggest that the accurate evocation of scientifically demonstrated generalities in
human cognition through cognitive realism is likely to have certain effects on many readers, broadly
speaking in a duality of response (both unsettling and compelling), and more specifically in the form
of equivocal moral judgements of Emma Bovary. My intention is not to deny the importance of
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 25
individual expectations and tendencies in reading, nor therefore to claim that all readers respond
identically: for instance, in feeling sympathy for Emma. Rather, I wish to offer ways of engaging with
the fact that readers’ responses to literature have similarities as well as differences, affected as they
are by stable textual features and cognitive universals as well as by individual variation and context.
As I hope to have shown, meaningful statements about the cognitive features and effects of Madame
Bovary and literary Realism are possible on the basis of a scientifically informed understanding of
certain aspects of memory. Generalizations about textual effects on such a basis may be considered
valid as an interpretive framework, even though individual responses can and will differ to some
degree.
How, then, does Madame Bovary compare with other major exemplars of literary Realism as
regards the evocation of memory? In many other nineteenth--century Realist texts, memory is used as
a neutral, functional plot device: in Dickens’s Great Expectations (1993 [1861]) for example, Pip
narrates from memory, and although his reliance on memory, and its possible imperfections, are
indicated at intervals (‘My first most vivid and broad impression of the identity of things seems to me
to have been gained on a memorable raw afternoon towards evening’, 3), no real distortions or other
salient characteristics of this cognitive faculty are ever foregrounded,
28
and the narrative depends on
Pip’s capacity for ‘total recall’. This is the case in most texts using first--person narration, because of
the functional requirements of the form, and also in some third--person narratives: in Henry James’s
The Portrait of a Lady (1995 [1881]), memory serves to emphasize certain mental revolutions (‘It was
extraordinary the things she remembered. Now that she was in the secret [...] she remembered a
thousand trifles; they started to life with the spontaneity of a shiver’, 595) but its evocation is in
general encompassed by the simple dichotomy of recall and forgetting. This is not to say that other
28
A rare mention of a failing of the narrator’s memory (‘Forasmuch as they hang in my memory by
only this one slender thread, I don’t know what they did, except that they forbore to remove me’, 457)
does not alter the evocation of memory as an essentially passive and preservative capacity; it merely
acknowledges that this type of memory can fail sometimes.
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 26
Realist texts do not thematize memory or use its complexities to contribute to characterization or
imagery or the shaping of plot: this occurs in many texts that employ third--person narration (with a
variety of forms of focalization), such as Stendhal’s Le Rouge et le Noir and La Chartreuse de Parme,
and Balzac’s La Peau de chagrin, Le Colonel Chabert, Eugénie Grandet, Le Père Goriot, and others
in La Comédie humaine. Eliot’s Middlemarch (1996 [1874]) evokes the idiosyncrasies of memory in a
way comparable to Madame Bovary, presenting memory’s counter--intuitive changeability (‘The
memory has as many moods as the temper, and shifts its scenery like a diorama’, 484), and the
emotional transformations of the past which it can bring about (‘pain must enter into its glorified life
of memory before it can turn into compassion’, 727). However, the fact that many of these
observations on memory are presented as generally valid characteristics, rather than as cause and
effect in the course of a character’s experiences, may mean that their effect on the reader is
manifested primarily as retrospective reflection on what the text ‘teaches us’ about memory, and less
as an immediate emotional response such as that of being compelled yet simultaneously unsettled.
Realist texts of course vary in the extent to which they make memory a central and complex
facet of character and narrative, but taken together they do not contradict the deep--rooted ‘wax
tablet’ conception of memory. Popular contemporary fiction of such genres as science fiction, crime,
romance, and fantasy, which, despite superficial differences, bear fundamental resemblance to
nineteenth--century Realism, also tend not to enforce any such contradiction. This conception remains
the default: metaphors of memory as a static storage system are deeply embedded in the history of
human thought.
29
Plato’s wax tablet is echoed by numerous thinkers, culminating in Freud’s ‘mystic
writing pad’, which is then superseded by computer metaphors; and, in another strand, St Augustine’s
‘great storehouse’, or ‘wonderful system of compartments’ in inner space becomes, in the Middle
Ages, a library, and is reprised in its earlier form by such popular authors as Conan Doyle: Holmes
describes his theory of the ‘brain--attic’ in A Study in Scarlet (1999 [1887], 15). Such metaphors are
part of the fabric of our thought about memory.
29
See Draaisma (2000) for details of the following examples.
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 27
At this point it is worth mentioning that although Madame Bovary is often described as a
quintessentially Realist text,
30
some critics have also questioned its status as Realist, citing in
particular its use of style indirect libre and its lack of action in the conventional sense as establishing a
greater affinity with (high) Modernism.
31
The term ‘Realism’ is problematic as a tool for literary
analysis, largely because it seems so instinctively meaningful and familiar: it is easy to attribute
normative status to an art form that aims at ‘close resemblance to what is real; fidelity of
representation, rendering the precise details of the real thing or scene’.
32
But ‘close resemblance’ and
‘fidelity’ are as open to interpretation and selection as are ‘what is real’ and ‘the real thing or scene’.
The approach espoused here has taken the term ‘Realism’ and re--appropriated it as one with a
specific and easily definable meaning, making the connection established with generalizable features
of readers minds -- rather than any other stylistic or formal, philosophical or ideological
considerations -- the prime criterion of classification. This is not to imply that classification is or
should be the primary aim of literary criticism, but the urge to categorize is unavoidably human
(Knight 1981), and making our tools maximally effective can only be a good thing.
My analysis of the evocation of memory in the text may contribute to an understanding of
those textual elements which do not entirely correspond to expectations about what a Realist text is or
should be, since this analysis allows us to answer precisely the sorts of questions about Madame
Bovary which some critics have claimed to be unanswerable and therefore to define the entire text as
30
To quote two contrasting, but perhaps representative, authorities: Henry James states that ‘Realism
seems to us with “Madame Bovary” to have said its last word’ (1919 [1878]: 202), whilst the current
Wikipedia entry for the novel declares that it ‘now stands virtually unchallenged not only as a seminal
work of Realism, but as one of the most influential novels ever written’
(http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Madame_Bovary; accessed 18 January 2011).
31
See e.g. Ferguson 2002. See also Palermo Di Stefano (2003: 62, n. 85): ‘ce qui frappe, c’est
l’insignifiance des faits par rapport aux conséquences psychologiques’.
32
Oxford English Dictionary, 3rd edition, December 2008; online version November 2010,
http://www.oed.com:80/Entry/158931, accessed 6 December 2010.
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 28
non--Realist. Fleming (1989) contends that in Emma’s actions and reactions we may perceive
‘efficient causes’ but that satisfying explanations are impossible to derive for questions such as why
Emma is seduced by Rodolphe or Léon: ‘The answer seems to be merely: because the choices at any
one time are limited to the two extremes of virtue and vice, and we have not had the latter in a while’
(767).
33
Fleming’s conclusion is that ‘Emma is not a character with a personality at all, but rather a
walking textbook of seductions’ (772) -- but this means he has to account for the sympathy we seem
nevertheless to feel for Emma by saying we sympathize not with her but with the constraints that
first create the seductions. The notion of sympathizing with constraints in the absence of a character is
difficult to reconcile with any plausible account of the actual experience of reading Madame Bovary
(or any other text). The conclusions yielded by the present discussion permit a less reductive and less
problematic understanding of the connections that may be established between protagonist and reader.
The fact that Emma’s psychology can be seen as so wholly ‘unrealistic’ (or even absent),
34
where the current analysis has shown at least one aspect of it to be highly realistic, begs the question
of whether the prime requirement of a Realist text is that it correspond to our assumptions about what
our experience of reality is. Are we reluctant to bestow the label ‘Realist’ unless our expectations
about psychology are met? If so, Realism is trapped in the paradox that we require it to ‘reflect
reality’ but in so doing require it to reflect our preconceptions about reality, which in the realm of
cognition often result less from reality than from the fitness for purpose of our cognitive faculties,
which creates certain sorts of illusion.
35
In the case of vision, for example, we have the impression of
taking in much more visual information than is actually the case because we can usually look again
33
See also Gregor and Nicholas (1962: 49): ‘Emma is no more fated to love Rodolphe than she is to
marry Charles -- the most we can say is that both episodes are credible, both entirely and depressingly
predictable.’
34
See also Cook (1973: 303): ‘It is a commonplace of contemporary criticism that Madame Bovary
has no psychology.’
35
Currie (2010) makes this argument for the reading of all literature, not just Realism: that we want
and enjoy wrong but familiar information about psychology, not unfamiliar truths about it.
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 29
when we need to, and because the information we do register is generally adequate to our current
needs.
36
In the case of memory, we retain sufficient details that ‘correspond’ in a straightforward way
that those which are distorted in order to ‘cohere’ are assumed also to correspond to the original
reality -- and by definition fit with our beliefs about ourselves and our past actions and reactions --,
while those which are suppressed for the sake of coherence by definition fail to alter this impression
most of the time. Only when comparison with someone else’s memories of the same event, or with an
objective record of that event, proves our ‘memories’ to have been inaccurate, or when a conflicting
memory resurfaces after a change in life circumstances, do we realize the extent to which our
memories serve our own changing psychological needs.
It could be argued that the whole of ‘consciousness’ is the subject of a ‘grand illusion’ (see
Noë ed. 2002), in that we acquire, by various cognitive means, the impression of the singularity,
coherence, and continuity of a self--in--the--head, which corresponds neither to the neural actuality of
multiple parallel pathways and centres of activation, nor to the fragmentary and ever--changing nature
of subjective experience and physical embodiment. If in general our beliefs about our own experience
are subject to illusions, it may be claimed that any fictional text which corresponds to those beliefs
(i.e. a traditional Realist one) will by definition be cognitively unrealistic: Realism (as epitomized in
the nineteenth century and still predominant in popular literature today) chimes with our assumptions
about cognition, whereas cognitive realism chimes with the facts (which may feel uncomfortable, as
well as compelling). Of course matters are complicated by the fact that a single text may be ‘Realist’
in some aspects and ‘cognitively realistic’ in others, but in broad terms the generalization may prove
valid. Only further in--depth work on a larger sample of Realist texts and the effects attributed to them
by both critics and ordinary readers will show whether the cognitively realistic aspects of a text tend
to be those experienced as non--Realist. In the case of Madame Bovary, however, understanding the
evocation of the protagonist’s memory allows us to claim that the text is cognitively realistic because
it is not quite a Realist text (and vice versa); or, as a more conciliatory way of phrasing the same
36
See e.g. O’Regan and Noë (2001) and Troscianko (2010a: 154-8).
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 30
conclusion, Madame Bovary makes Realism more realistic than we many often require -- or even
want -- Realism to be.
References
References in the text to page numbers alone refer to:
Flaubert, Gustave. 1971-75. Oeuvres complètes, 16 vols (Paris: Club de l’honnête homme), I:
Madame Bovary (1971)
Adolphs, Ralph, Natalie L. Denburg, and Daniel Tranel. 2001. ‘The Amygdala’s Role in Long-Term
Declarative Memory for Gist and Detail’, Behavioral Neuroscience, 115: 983-992
Aronson, Elliot, and Judson Mills. 1959. ‘The Effect of Severity of Initiation on Liking for a Group’,
Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 59: 177-181
Aronson, Elliot. 1969. ‘The Theory of Cognitive Dissonance: A Current Perspective’, in Advances in
Experimental Social Psychology (New York: Academic), IV, ed. by Leonard Berkowitz, pp. 2-
34
Auerbach, Erich. 1957. Mimesis: The Representation of Reality in Western Literature, trans. by
Willard R. Trask (Garden City, NY: Doubleday)
Baddeley, Alan. 2000. ‘The Episodic Buffer: A New Component of Working Memory?’, Trends in
Cognitive Science, 4: 417-423
--- 2003. ‘Working Memory: Looking Back and Looking Forward’, Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 4:
829-39
--- and Graham Hitch. 1974. ‘Working Memory’, in The Psychology of Learning and Motivation:
Advances in Research and Theory, ed. by Gordon. H. Bower (New York: Academic), VIII, 47-
89
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 31
Barash, David P., and Nanelle R. Barash. 2005. Madame Bovary’s Ovaries: A Darwinian Look at
Literature (New York: Delacorte)
Barclay, Craig R. 1986. ‘Schematization of Autobiographical Memory’, in Autobiographical Memory,
ed. by David C. Rubin (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 82-99
Beike, Denise R., and Shelly L. Landoll. 2000. ‘Striving for a Consistent Life Story: Cognitive
Reactions to Autobiographical Memories’, Social Cognition, 18: 292-318
Beizer, Janet. 1994. Ventriloquized Bodies: Narratives of Hysteria in Nineteenth-Century France
(Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press)
Berntsen, Dorthe. 2007. ‘Involuntary Autobiographical Memories: Speculations, Findings, and an
Attempt to Integrate Them’, in Involuntary Memory, ed. by John H. Mace (Malden, MA:
Blackwell), pp. 20-49
Bourgeois, André. 1968. ‘M. Homais, Instrument of Destin’, South Central Bulletin, 28: 124-126
Chapanis, N.P., and Alphonse Chapanis. 1964. ‘Cognitive Dissonance: Five Years Later’,
Psychological Bulletin, 61: 1-22
Chen, M. Keith, and Jane L. Risen. 2010. ‘How Choice Affects and Reflects Preferences: Revisiting
the Free-Choice Paradigm’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 99: 573-594
Christianson, Sven-Åke. 1992. ‘Emotional Stress and Eyewitness Memory: A Critical Review’,
Psychological Bulletin 112: 284-309
Conan Doyle, Arthur. 1999 [1887]. A Study in Scarlet (New York: Oxford University Press)
Conway, Martin A. 2005. ‘Memory and the Self’, Journal of Memory and Language, 53: 594-628
Cook, David A. 1973. ‘James and Flaubert: The Evolution of Perception’, Comparative Literature,
25: 289-307
Culler, Jonathon. 2006. Flaubert: The Uses of Uncertainty (Colorado: Davies Group)
Currie, Gregory. 2010. ‘Literature and the Psychology Lab’, Times Literary Supplement, forthcoming
Davison, Ian M., and Aidan Feeney. 2008. ‘Regret as Autobiographical Memory’, Cognitive
Psychology, 27: 385-403
Dickens, Charles. 1993 [1861]. Great Expectations (New York: Oxford University Press)
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 32
Dixon, Peter, Marisa Bortolussi, Leslie C. Twilley, and Alice Leung. 1993. ‘Literary Processing and
Interpretation: Towards Empirical Foundations’, Poetics, 22: 5-33
Draaisma, Douwe. 2000. Metaphors of Memory: A History of Ideas about the Mind, trans. by Paul
Vincent (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
Easterbrook, J.A. 1959. ‘The Effect of Emotion on Cue Utilization and the Organization of Behavior’,
Psychological Review, 66: 183-201
Eliot, George. 1996 [1874]. Middlemarch (New York: Oxford University Press)
Ferguson, Frances. 2002. ‘Emma, or Happiness (or Sex Work)’, Critical Inquiry, 28: 749-779
Festinger, Leon. 1957. A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance (Evanson, IL: Row, Peterson)
Flaubert, Gustave. 1971-1975. Oeuvres complètes, 16 vols (Paris: Club de l’honnête homme), XIII:
Correspondance 1850-1859 (1974)
Fleming, Bruce E. 1989. ‘An Essay in Seduction, or The Trouble with Bovary’, French Review, 62:
764-773
Förster, Jens, Nira Liberman, and E. Tory Higgins. 2005. ‘Accessibility from Active and Fulfilled
Goals’, Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 41: 220-239
Foster, Jonathon K. 2009. Memory: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
Frijda, Nico H. 2007. The Laws of Emotion (Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum)
Gilovich, Thomas, and Victoria Husted Medvec. 1995. ‘The Experience of Regret: What, When, and
Why’, Psychological Review, 102: 379-395
Goldstein, Jan. 1991. ‘The Uses of Male Hysteria: Medical and Literary Discourse in Nineteenth-
Century France’, Representations, 34: 134-165
Greenwald, Anthony G. 1980. ‘The Totalitarian Ego: Fabrication and Revision of Personal History’,
American Psychologist, 35: 603-618
Gregor, Ian, and Brian Nicholas. 1962. The Moral and the Story (London: Faber and Faber)
Herz, Rachel S., and Jonathon W. Schooler. 2002. ‘A Naturalistic Study of Autobiographical
Memories Evoked by Olfactory and Visual Cues: Testing the Proustian Hypothesis’, The
American Journal of Psychology, 115: 21-32
Hjort, Mette, and Sue Laver (eds). 1997. Emotion and the Arts (New York: Oxford University Press)
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 33
Holmes, David S. 1970. ‘Differential Change in Affective Intensity and the Forgetting of Unpleasant
Personal Experiences’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 15: 234-239
James, Henry. 1919 [1878]. ‘Charles de Bernard and Gustave Flaubert’, in French Poets and
Novelists, by Henry James (London: Macmillan), pp. 186-210
--- 1995 [1881]. The Portrait of a Lady (New York: Oxford University Press)
Kensinger, E.A. 2004. ‘Remembering Emotional Experiences: The Contribution of Valence and
Arousal’, Reviews in the Neurosciences, 15: 241-251
Kintsch, Walter, and Praful Mangalath. 2010. ‘The Construction of Meaning’, Topics in Cognitive
Science, 1-25, doi: 10.1111/j.1756-8765.2010.01107.x
Knight, Deborah. 1997. ‘Does Tom Think Squire Allworthy Is Real?’, Philosophy and Literature, 21:
433-443
Knight, David. 1981. Ordering the World: A History of Classifying Man (London: Burnett)
Leboe, Jason P., and Tamara L. Ansons. 2006. ‘On Misattributing Good Remembering to a Happy
Past: An Investigation into the Cognitive Roots of Nostalgia’, Emotion, 6: 596-610
Levine, Linda J., and David A. Pizarro. 2004. ‘Emotion and Memory Research: A Grumpy
Overview’, Social Cognition, 22: 530-554
Marder, Elissa. 1997. ‘Trauma, Addiction, and Temporal Bulimia in “Madame Bovary”’, Diacritics,
27.3: 49-64
McNally, Richard J. 2003. Remembering Trauma (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard
University Press)
Miller, George A., Eugene Galanter, and Karl H. Pribram. 1960. Plans and the Structure of Behavior
(New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston)
Noë, Alva (ed.). 2002. ‘Is the Visual World a Grand Illusion?’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 9.5-
6
Ochsner, Kevin N. 2000. ‘Are Affective Events Richly Recollected or Simply Familiar? The
Experience and Process of Recognizing Feelings Past’, Journal of Experimental Psychology.
General, 129: 242-261
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 34
O’Regan, Kevin, and Alva Noë. 2001. ‘A Sensorimotor Account of Vision and Visual
Consciousness’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24: 939-1011
Orr, Mary. 2000. Flaubert: Writing the Masculine (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
Palermo Di Stefano, Rosa Maria. 2003. Le Corset moral (Naples: Edizioni Scientifiche Italiane)
Paskow, Jacqueline Merriam. 2005. ‘Rethinking Madame Bovary’s Motives for Committing Suicide’,
Modern Language Review, 100: 323-339
Plato. 1975. Philebus, trans. by J.C.B. Gosling (Oxford: Clarendon)
--- 1973. Theaetetus, trans. by John McDowell (Oxford: Clarendon)
Radford, C. (1975) ‘How Can We Be Moved by the Fate of Anna Karenina?’, Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 49: 67-80
Riffaterre, Michael. 1981. ‘Flaubert’s Presuppositions’, Diacritics, 11.4: 2-11
Sabiston, Elizabeth. 1973. ‘The Prison of Womanhood’, Comparative Literature, 25: 336-351
Safer, Martin A., Linda J. Levine, and Amy L. Drapalski. 2002. ‘Distortion in Memory for Emotions:
The Contributions of Personality and Post-Event Knowledge’, Personality and Social
Psychology Bulletin, 28: 1495-1507
Savitsky, Kenneth, Victoria Husted Medvec, and Thomas Gilovich. 1997. ‘Remembering and
Regretting: The Zeigarnik Effect and the Cognitive Availability of Regrettable Actions and
Inactions’, Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 23: 248-257
Tanner, Tony. 1979. Adultery in the Novel: Contract and Transgression (Baltimore, MD: Johns
Hopkins University Press)
Tillett, Margaret. 1966. ‘On Reading Madame Bovary’, in Madame Bovary and the Critics: A
Collection of Essays, ed. by B.F. Bart (New York: New York University Press), pp. 1-25
Troscianko, Emily. 2010a. ‘Kafkaesque Worlds in Real Time’, Language and Literature, 19: 151-171
--- 2010b. The Literary Science of the ‘Kafkaesque’ (unpublished doctoral thesis, University of
Oxford)
Vermeule, Blakey. 2009. Why Do We Care About Literary Characters? (Baltimore, MD: Johns
Hopkins University Press)
E.T. Troscianko, Cognitive Realism in Flaubert 35
Williams, David Anthony. 1973. Psychological Determinism in ‘Madame Bovary’ (Hull: University
of Hull)
Affiliation: Junior Research Fellow in Modern Languages, St John’s College, University of Oxford
Name as it is to be printed: Dr Emily T. Troscianko
Name and postal address for correspondence: Dr Emily Troscianko, St John’s College, Oxford, OX1
3JP, England
Email address: emily.troscianko@sjc.ox.ac.uk
... Beyond modeling the general processes of interpretation, secondgeneration cognitive analyses have mostly focused on matters of emotion, embodiment, and enaction as key factors in our engagement with literary works and their meaningfulness. Some have used cognitive theory to ask how narrative style and form correspond to, or diverge from, aspects of the embodied mind and so shape real readers' interpretations (e.g., identifying examples of "cognitive realism" in literary Modernism [ Troscianko 2014] or Realism [Troscianko 2012]). Others have focused on particular experiential dimensions of the reading experience (e.g., Kuzmičová [2014] on mental imagery) or have sought dialogue with earlier narratological models of the reader; Karin Kukkonen (2014), for instance, complements Wolfgang Iser's (1972) propositional account of the reader's engagement with the temporal dynamics of plot using an embodied-cognitive approach based on Bayesian (2014) has explored how the reader's interpretive activity is shaped by inferences about authorial intention that the extended-cognition paradigm allows us to understand as emerging in writing as well as being retrospectively recoverable when reading. ...
... Many forms of cognitive realismfor example, in texts that evoke memory or hearing in ways that correspond to the cognitive realitiesmay induce effects of ambivalence, if we hypothesize that folk psychology and cognitive realities tend to be systematically discrepant. 24 However, this is a question for empirical investigation and for another time. ...
Article
Full-text available
I argue that understanding cognition as enactive-that is, as constituted of physical interaction between embodied minds and the environment-can illuminate the opening of Kafka's novel Der Proceβ (The Trial), revealing it as cognitively realistic in this respect. I show how enactivism is relevant to this passage in several ways: in terms of enactive vision and imagination (based on the sensorimotor account of vision), enactive language (with a focus on basic-level categorization and readers' motor responses), and enactive emotion (drawing on appraisal theory). I also suggest that these cognitively realistic features might result in ambivalent reactions on the reader's part.
... Where realities and expectations converge, Proust evokes cognition accordingly; where they diverge, he follows folk psychology rather than cognitive reality. This means that we nowhere find cognitive realism contradicting expectations, entailing the ambivalent response – both compelled and unsettled – that seems to occur when, for example, Kafka evokes vision counter to our pictorialist assumptions (Troscianko, 2010) or when Flaubert evokes memory counter to our understanding of it as static storage (Troscianko, forthcoming 2012). Even the border case of vacillation between evoking the effort to remember as searching/finding or creating leaves us free to choose the interpretation we prefer, rather than imposing a counterintuitive one upon us. ...
Article
Full-text available
The famous ‘madeleine episode’ of Proust’s In Search of Lost Time is investigated with reference to cognitive realism in the evocation of memory, by asking how this literary memory experience compares with the conceptualization of memory in current cognitive science. Furthermore, what does close reading of the episode informed by current scientific findings and debates on memory and agency tell us about Proust’s categorization of this memory event as involuntary memory, and his presentation of voluntary and involuntary memory as a distinct opposition? I show that the madeleine episode (1) corresponds partly to cognitive realities as documented by recent science and partly to prevalent expectations about cognition or its narration, and (2) undermines the neat voluntary/involuntary distinction it initially seems to illustrate. I suggest how these qualities may affect readers’ responses to Proust’s famously evocative object.
Article
Literary realism has produced some of the most famous deaths in literary fiction. Psychological insight into the characters’ experiences and the mental states that induced their deaths helps readers to engage the protagonists not as victims of society, martyrs of fate, or wicked characters but, rather, as pathological human beings. Their psychological dualities bring affirmations of identity as well as breakdowns of identity, hence transforming readers’ judgments on their morality with new understanding.
Article
We investigated the effects of narrative perspective on mental imagery by comparing responses to an English translation of Franz Kafka’s Das Schloß ( The Castle ) in the published version (narrated in the third person) versus an earlier (first-person) draft. We analysed participants’ pencil drawings of their imaginative experience for presence/absence of specific features (K. and the castle) and for image entropy (a proxy for image unpredictability). We also used word embeddings to perform cluster analysis of participants’ verbal free-response testimony, generating thematic clusters independently of experimenter expectations. We found no effects of text version on feature presence or overall entropy, but an effect on entropy variance, which was higher in the third-person condition. There was also an effect of text version on free responses: Readers of the third-person version were more likely to use words associated with mood and atmosphere. We offer conclusions on “Kafkaesque” aesthetics, cognitive realism, and the future of experimental literary studies.
Chapter
Realism is an artistic, intellectual, and literary movement that began in the nineteenth century. Often presented as a foil to romanticism, it was closely related to Enlightenment ideas of rationalism and scientific observation. According to many critics, if the romantic movement emphasized the fantastic and ideal, realism emphasized the everyday and banal. However, the overlap between the two philosophies can hardly be overlooked. Major players in both movements, from authors to artists, created works that exhibited both realist and romantic traits. Clearly, realism relied on and developed parallel to romanticism, even as it rejected it.
Chapter
Autobiographical memory is a major form of human memory. it is the basis of most psycotherapies, an important repository of legal, historical, and literary information, and, in some views, the source of the concept of self. When it fails, it is the focus of serious complaints in many neurological disorders. This timely book brings together and integrates the best contemporary work on the cognitive psychology of autobiographical memory. Introductory chapters place the study of autobiographical memory in its historical, methodological, and theoretical contexts; chapters reporting original research probe the recollections people have for substantial portions of their lives. Topics include the schematic and temporal organization of autobiographical memory, the temporal distribution of autobiographical memories, and the failures of autobiographical memory in various forms of amnesia. Autobiographical Memory constitutes the first tutorial in this exciting new area of research. Cognitive psychologists, clinicians, researchers in artificial intelligence, and their students - indeed, anyone interested in the processes that preserve and distort autobiography - will find it a useful resource.
Book
This book offers a new approach to Flaubert's major writing and to gender studies as a whole. Through a combination of close reading with a knowledge of current gender studies and particular attention to the sociohistorical and legal contexts of 19th-century France, it examines the masculine in the six very different literary contexts that are Flaubert's fictions. His characters, male and female, are reassessed for their masculinity: Baudelaire's famous view of Emma Bovary as 'masculine', like other critical idées recues that have propped up a canonical Flaubert, finds a new interpretation within the wider discussion of the book, as does the term 'masculine' itself. While it is mostly Flaubert's men, both those who conform to patriarchy's models and the non-conformists, who offer new insights into masculine identities in crisis, the structures of society that endorse male status - legal, social, institutional, and literary-critical - also come under scrutiny. The book challenges the primacy of gendered terms over sex, and provides various methodological resources to further scholarship in French Studies, Gender Studies, and masculinities theory, arguing strongly for the adroitness of literature to formulate representations that are as relevant today as in Flaubert's time.
Article
Flaubert's references to himself as hysterical, of which several more instances could be cited, raise the issue of the gender of hysteria in the nineteenth century. Clearly these references depend for their arresting force upon the audience's automatic association of hysteria with women, an association indelibly imprinted on the term by its ancient Greek etymology ("uterus") and its long, subsequent social development. But at the same time Flaubert's self-depictions violate and sever the association they assume. They suggest that if nineteenth-century hysteria was a conceptual space for the conventional, stereotypical definition of femininity, it was also, by that same token, potentially a conceptual space for the subversion of gender stereotypes. Through partaking of the pathological condition "hysteria," the man Flaubert might also lay claim to the attributes of femininity it had come to epitomize-here, nervous hypersensitivity, vulnerability,
Article
Unlike most nineteenth-century novels of female adultery in which the heroine's unhappy end is a function of her having broken social taboos, Gustave Flaubert's Madame Bovary presents us with a heroine whose suicide, contrary to the reader's expectation, cannot be explained in terms of any social or personal havoc caused by her adulteries. By contesting the expected motives for her suicide indeed viewing them as so many red herrings laid by Flaubert-this article re-poses and seeks to re-answer the question of what Madame Bovary is ultimately about.
Article
Blakey Vermeule wonders how readers become involved in the lives of fictional characters, people they know do not exist. Vermeule examines the ways in which readers' experiences of literature are affected by the emotional attachments they form to fictional characters and how those experiences then influence their social relationships in real life. She focuses on a range of topics, from intimate articulations of sexual desire, gender identity, ambition, and rivalry to larger issues brought on by rapid historical and economic change. Vermeule discusses the phenomenon of emotional attachment to literary characters primarily in terms of 18th-century British fiction but also considers the postmodern work of Thomas Mann, J. M. Coetzee, Ian McEwan, and Chinua Achebe. From the perspective of cognitive science, Vermeule finds that caring about literary characters is not all that different from caring about other people, especially strangers. The tools used by literary authors to sharpen and focus reader interest tap into evolved neural mechanisms that trigger a caring response. This book contributes to the emerging field of evolutionary literary criticism. Vermeule draws upon recent research in cognitive science to understand the mental processes underlying human social interactions without sacrificing solid literary criticism. People interested in literary theory, in cognitive analyses of the arts, and in Darwinian approaches to human culture will find much to ponder in Why Do We Care about Literary Characters? © 2010 The Johns Hopkins University Press. All rights reserved.