Content uploaded by Peter Slezak
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Peter Slezak on Sep 20, 2015
Content may be subject to copyright.
PHILOSOPHICAL PSYCHOLOGY
,
VOL
.
15
,
NO
.
3
,
2002
The tripartite model of representation
P
ETER
S
LEZAK
A
BSTRACT
Robert Cummins [(1996) Representations, targets and attitudes, Cambridge, MA:
Bradford/MIT, p. 1] has characterized the vexed problem of mental representation as “the topic in
the philosophy of mind for some time now.” This remark is something of an understatement. The
same topic was central to the famous controversy between Nicolas Malebranche and Antoine Arnauld
in the 17th century and remained central to the entire philosophical tradition of “ideas” in the
writings of Locke, Berkeley, Hume, Reid and Kant. However, the scholarly, exegetical literature has
almost no overlap with that of contemporary cognitive science. I show that the recurrence of certain
deep perplexities about the mind is a systematic and pervasive pattern arising not only th roughout
history, but also in a number of independent domains today such as debates over visual imagery,
symbolic systems and others. Such historical and contemporary convergences suggest that the
fundamental issues cannot arise essentially from the theoretical guise they take in any particular case.
… if men had been born blind philosophy would be more perfect, because
it would lack many false assumptions that have been taken from th e sense
of sight. (Galileo Galilei, 1610)
Mental representation: “the topic for some time now”
Robert Cummins (1996, p. 1) has recently characterized the vexed problem of
mental representation as “the topic in the philosophy of mind for some time now.”
However, this remark is something of an understatement. In fact, the same topic was
central to the famous controversy between Antoine Arnauld and Nicolas Male-
branche in the 17th century, and also central to the entire philosophical tradition of
“ideas” in the writings of Locke, Berkeley, Hume, Reid and Kant. This pattern of
recurrence is a striking fact. However, the cognitive s cience lit erature has almost no
overlap with that of the history of early modern philosophy. This mutual neglect is
remarkable in view of the intimate connection of their c oncerns. I am c oncerned
here to reveal something of the rich and mutually illuminating connections between
these disjoint literatures. In principle, such mutual illumination can make a valuable
and perhaps novel contribution both to contemporary cognitive science and also to
the scholarship of early modern philosophy. The possibility of mutual bene!t is even
Peter Slezak, Program in Cognitive Science, School of History & Philoso phy of Science, University
of New South Wales, Sydney, NSW 2052, Australia, email: p.slezak@unsw.edu.au
ISSN 0951-5089/print/ISSN 1465-394X/online/0 2/030239–32
Ó
2002 Taylor & Francis Ltd
DOI: 10.1080/0951508021 000006085
240
P
.
SLEZAK
more evident when we notice that the parallels extend beyond merely having
common concerns. That is, not only the problems of the 17th century, but the same
solutions are being rehearsed today at the forefront of research in cognitive science.
Descartes’ de´ja` vu: Edelman’s Traite´ de l’homme
A preliminary indication of the modern relevance of early philosophy may be seen
in Edelman’s (1998) work on perception. Despite its concern with the latest theories
of perception, the central problem is stated in terms identical with that of the entire
tradition of writers on “ideas” since the 17th century. Edelman writes: “Advanced
perceptual systems are faced with the problem of securing a principled (ideally,
veridical) relationship be tween the world and its internal r epresentation.” Edelman’s
bold new solution “is a call for the representation of similarity instead of representa-
tion by similarity.” However, this might have been taken verbatim from Descartes’s
Traite´ de l’h omme (1662/1972) or Dioptrics (1637/1985) where he said “the problem
is to know simply how [images] can enable the soul to have sensory perceptions of
all the various qualities of th e objects to which they correspond—not to know how
they can resemble these objects” (Descartes, 1637/1985, pp. 1, 165). In the same
vein as Edelman, Meyering (1997) points out that, despite its advocates today
(Wright, 1993), resemblanc e cannot be analyzed without circularity. As we will see,
this issue arises inescapably as part of a deeper problem concerning the nature of
representation.
The tripartite schema
In a recent article, Bechtel (1998, p. 299) states the essentials of a modern theory of
representation: “There are … three interrelated components in a representational
story: what is represented, the representation, and the user of the representation.”
Z: System Using Y
®
Y: Representation
®
X: Thing Represented
Bechtel’s schema articulates a tripartite conception of ideas as representatives
intervening between the mind an d the world. As we will see, among the problematic
assumptions, Bechtel’s diagram (modi!ed here) and discussion crucially fail to
distinguish internal and externa l representations (see Abell & Currie, 1999). Impor-
tantly, Bechtel’s conception in this regard is not idiosyncr atic, but accurately re"ects
an almost universal conception in cognitive science (D ennett, 1978a; Lloyd, forth-
coming; Newell, 1986, p. 33; Rumelhart & Norman, 1983). As w e will note
presently, the same tripartite conception in the case of the pictorial t heory of images
inherently involves the same assimilation of internal and external representations,
and thereby encourages the illegitimate postulate of a user or external observer—the
notorious h omunculus. I will suggest that the same tacit assimilation of external and
internal representations is at the heart of Searle’s (1980) “refutation” of symbolic AI
and also leads to the doctrine that we think “in” language (Carruthers, 1996; Slezak,
2002). The assimilation just noted in Bechtel will also be seen in the seemingly
unrelated problem of consciousness and the mind–body p roblem (Place, 1956). The
THE TR IPARTITE MODEL OF REPRESENTATION
241
tripartite scheme appears obvious and innocuous enough, though it has been
remarkably fraught with dif!culties. Indeed, the inescapability and ubiquity of this
picture in one form or another is apparent from the fact that Bechtel’s diagram is a
variant of the scheme which we s ee throughout the long history of the subject.
“The vision of all things in God”
Thus, for example, nothing could seem more remote from mo dern theories in
cognitive science today than Malebranche’s (1712/1997) 17th century doctrine of
“the vision of all things in God ”—the theory that ideas are objects of our perception
that exist in God’s mind. On the contrary, however, despite the theological trap-
pings, it is instructive to recognize the profound af!nity of Malebranche’s views with
those at the very forefront of theorizing today in psycholog y and ar ti!cial intelli-
gence: Malebranche’s theory is just Bechtel’s tripartite model (Nadler, 1992), and
the modern problem of representation is h ow to avoid the notorious dif!culties
clearly articulated by his critic Arnauld (1683/1990).
Although these parallels need to be defended with detailed argument and
exegesis, it is signi!cant that Fodor has occasionally made the af!nities explicit.
Recently he suggests that his own Representational Theory of the Mind (RTM) may
be understood on the model of th e classical empiricist conception:
Just for the purposes of building intuitions, think of m ental representations
on the model of what Empiricist philosophers sometimes called “Ideas”.
That is, think of them as mental particulars endowed with causal powers
and susceptible of semantic evaluation. (Fodor, 1998 , p. 7)
In this light, it is hardly surprising that modern problems might be simply the
reinvention of old problems in a new guise. Fodor endorses the classical conception
of ideas though he rejects a conception of representation by means of resembling
images. He says “To a !rst approximation, … the idea that there are mental
representations is the idea that there are Ideas minus the idea that Ideas are image s”
(1998, p. 8). Despite such disclaimers, we will see that there is particular irony in the
fact that the problem for images may be, at a deeper level, the problem for Fodor’s
RTM as well.
Independently of Fodor’s explici t allusion, his conception of a representational
theory of mind has always been evocative of traditiona l acco unts. Thus, it may be
just a fac¸on de parler, but Fodor’s (1978) analysis of propositional att itudes has
consistently been expressed in terms of “relations between organisms and internal
representations” which are “sentence-like entities” (1978, p. 198), that is, “formulae
in an Internal Representational System” (1978, p. 194) and whose intentional
contents refer to things in the world. Fodor earlier explained this idiom by the same
analogy with traditional theories:
This is, quite generally, the way that representational theories of the mind
work. So in classical versions, thinking of John (construed opaquely) is a
242
P
.
SLEZAK
relation to an “idea”—viz., to an internal representation of John. (1978,
p. 200)
Fodor speaks of internal representations as the “immediate objects” of beliefs,
thereby revealing the close similarity of his theory with the classical Lockean theory
of ideas as the “immediate objects” o f perception. This conception of internal
representations as being in a relation to a person is an explicit tripartite scheme
which Fodor takes to specify “a priori” conditions on propositional attitudes. This
may be, at best, an awkward locution and, at worst, encouraging a notoriously
problematic theory.
It is important to acknowledge that Fodor and Bechtel, like most theorists, are
fully aware of the fat al problem lurking here in principle. However, awareness of the
problem in principle does not necessarily preclude falling victim in practice. For
example, we will see that proponents of pictorial imagery have been repeatedly
charged with committing the homunculus error. Notwithstanding their advocates’
protestations of innocence [1] and full awareness of the hazards, there are grounds
for seeing pictorial theories as problematic in the traditional m anner. The charge is
that the representational format cannot be made to work without tacitly invoking the
very abilities it is supposed to explain (Pylyshyn, 1973, 1978, 1981, in press; Slezak,
1992, 1995, in press). The error is not con!ned to imagery and is made unwittingly
by failing to notice that the accessing mechanisms cannot perform their function on
their own in view of the particular properties ascribed to the representation. As
Bechtel (1998 , p. 299) no tes, a process which uses a representation as “stand in”
must be coordinated with the format of the representation. However, the nature of
the format may be such as to require a user which is not merely a process in an
innocuous sense. Speci!cally, taking internal representations to be too closely
modeled on our external representational artifacts clearly risks requiring the “user”
to share our relevant pe rceptual and cognitive abilities, thereby begging the question
in the traditional manner. We will see that the assimilation of internal and external
representations in just this way is frequently made as an explicit doctrine. Adverting
to the virtues of computational models which ultimately discharge their homunculi
and pay back their loan on intelligence (Dennett, 1978b) is not suf!cient as a plea
of innocence to these charges (Kosslyn et al., 1979). As Rorty (1979, p. 235) has put
it, there is no advance in replac ing the lit tle ma n in the head by a little machine in
the head. In particular, I will argue later that t he common appeal to an internal
symbolic language analogous to a formal sys tem appears to be guilty of the same
charge. The dispute, then, is about whether the theoretical models succeed in
avoiding the well-known dif!culty desp ite their authors’ int entions.
Thus, although rejecting the charge of being “ontologically promiscuous”
(1978, p. 179), Fodor’s locution may be symptomatic of the deep dif!culties which
pervade the problem of representation. Signi!cantly, Fodor says that his conception
corresponds precisely with the view that psychologists have independently arrived at.
To the extent that Fodor is correct in this observation, not only philosophers have
been prey to the deeply compelling mistakes of theorizing about the mind.
It is no accident that Gibson’s “ecological” approach, like the closely related
THE TR IPARTITE MODEL OF REPRESENTATION
243
“situated cognition,” are theories of direct realism which have been proposed as
alternatives to the representationalism of computational theories. This is merely one
form in which the Malebranche–Arnauld debate is being rehearsed today. This
celebrated debate is described by Nadler (1989) as a debate between an “o bject
theory” of ide as and an “act theory,” respectively. He explains
… the object theory of ideas involves a commitment to a representationalist
or indirect realist theory of perception, such as Malebranche (and, on the
traditional reading, Lo cke) put forth. An act theory of ideas, on th e other
hand, forms the c ore of Ar nauld’s perceptual direct realism. If ideas are
representational mental acts [rather than entitie s], then they can put the
mind in direct cognitive contact with the world—no intervening proxy, no
tertiu m quid, gets in the way. (1989, p. 6)
As Nadler (1989, p. 6) points out, Malebranche’s “vision in God” is a
“theo logization of cognition” according to which the contents of our own thoughts
are dependent upon their divine source in the mind of God. However, although
Malebranche’s theological and epistemological concerns are woven together, the
threads may be separated and his doctrine of ideas identi!ed as the familiar,
compelling and widely held theory until the present t ime. Although there is room for
scholarly dispute [2], most commentators share a reading of Malebranche according
to which ideas are intermediaries or proxie s representing external objects and
intervening between the mind and the world. This same “representative theory of
perception” has been more familiar as John Locke’s “veil of ideas” in the tradition
referred to as the “way of ideas.” On this view, ideas are internal mental objects of
some kind toward which the mind’ s operations are directed. Nadler ec hoes Bechtel,
describing Malebranche’s theory as assuming that there are three elements in the
normal perception or knowledge of the world (Nadler, 1989, p. 81). As Arnauld
explained in his critique, Malebranche “regards this representation as bein g act ually
distinct from our mind as well as from the object” (1683/1990, p. 63). A crucial and
frequently quoted passage from Malebranche himself explains:
Thus, it does not see them by themselves, and our mind’s immediate object
when it sees the sun, for example, is not the sun, but something that is
intimately joined to our soul, and this is w hat I call an idea. Thus, by the
word idea, I mean here nothing other than the immediate object, or the
objec t closest to the mind, when it perceives something, ie., that which
affects and modi!es t he mind with th e perception it has of an object.
(1712/1997, p. 217)
Situated cognition: the “canonical” cottage cheese case
Signi!cantly, John Yolton has expressed a hope that from the study of early thinkers
“we may be able to understand how we can have representation (cognitivity) and
realism too” (1996, p. x). This is, of course, a comment on the perennial problem
244
P
.
SLEZAK
posed by the tripartite scheme. Yolton’s remarks on earlier thinkers is apt to describe
the central problem of theories today:
The pivotal concept for the accounts of perceptual acquaintance in the
seventeenth and eighteenth centuries is that of objects present to the mind.
Depending on how that concept was interpreted, those accounts moved
between an indirec tness of knowledge (because only a representative, proxy
objec t can be present to the mind) and a strong direct realism where the
objec t known was, in some way, itself present to or in the mind. (1984,
p. 6)
Recent proponents of “situated cognition” have been complainin g of exactly the
same indirect, mediated conception in computational theories of cognition, recog-
nizing that these embody essentially the Locke–Malebranche’s scheme of represen-
tations intervening between mind and world. For example, Greeno (1989)
unknowingl y echoes Arnauld:
I am pe rsuaded … that in normal activity in physical and social settings, we
are connected directly with the environment , rather than connected in-
directly through cognitiv e representations.
… An individual in ordinary c ircumstances is considered as interacting
with the structures of situations directly, rather than constructing represen-
tations and interacting with the representations. (1989, p. 290)
Greeno cites the Weight Watcher who had studied calculus but nevertheless answers
a question about a daily allotment of cottage cheese by means of a simple, directly
physical, op eration dividing up a portion of cheese, rather than by any symbolic
computation such as a multiplication o n fractions. Ergo, reasoning is not symbolic
but “situated.” The Weight Watcher case is supposed to illustrate the th esis that the
person’s actions are somehow unmediated by mental representations [3]. The cause
for Greeno’s concern is the modern version of Locke’s view: “It is evident that the
mind knows not things immediately, but only by the intervention of the ideas it has
of them” (Locke, 1690, Book IV, Chapter IV).
Deux Carte´siens: plus c¸a change, plus c’est la meˆ me chose
It is amusing to notice ho w Malebranc he’s attempt to articulate this picture is
echoed today by Fodor. Malebranche wrote:
I think everyo ne agrees that we do not perceive objects external to us by
themselves. We see the sun, the stars and an in!nity of objects external to
us; and it is not likely that the soul should leave the body to stroll about the
heavens, as it were, in order to behold all these o bjects. (1712/1997,
p. 217)
Fodor writes in the same vein:
It is, to repeat, puzzling how thought could mediate between behavior and
THE TR IPARTITE MODEL OF REPRESENTATION
245
the world … The trouble isn’t—anyhow, it isn’t solely—thinking that
thoughts are somehow immaterial. It’s rather that thoughts need to be
in more places than seem s possible if they’re to do the job that
they’re assigned to. They have to be, as it were, “out there” so that
things in the world can interact with them, but they als o have to be,
as it were, “in here” so that they can proximally cause behavior.
… it’s hard to see how anything could be both. (Fodor, 1994a,
p. 83)
Malebranche and Arnauld are not chosen for mention here at random or merely
in retrospect for t heir current interest. As Gaukroger (1990) has noted,
Malebranche’s Search after truth was “the most in"uential philosophical treatise
of the second half of the seventeenth century, eclipsed only at the end o f that
century b y Locke’s Essay” (1690/1964, p. 1).
In particular, Malebranche’s doctrines were at the ce nter of a famous contro-
vers y with Antoine Arnauld whose treatise On true and false ideas (1683) was a
reply to Malebranche. Indeed, this debate was not only a major e´ve´nement
intellectuel of its time, as Moreau (1999) has recently described it, but one
whose echoes may be heard throughout the subsequent centuries of specu-
lation about the mind. Moreau’s (1999) recent book-length study in French
is perhaps the !rst devoted to the dispute as such, and attests to its importance
as an intellectual cause ce´le`bre in the 17th century [4]. N adler writes that, follow-
ing the !rst round w ith Arnauld’s critique of Malebranche,
For the next decade, until Arnauld’s death in 1694, these two men engaged
in a public debate that attracted the attention of intellectual circles
throughout Europe. Sides were taken in articles, reviews and letters in the
foremost journals of the day, and the issues were debated by others as hotly
as they were by the primary combatants themselves. … it remains … one of
the most interesting episodes in seventeenth-century intellectual history.
(1989, p. 2)
Nadler adds that the debate is indispensable for understanding the central
philosophical issues of the period, and this is especially true in relation to the
work of Descartes. As t he title of Moreau’s (1999) book indicates, Malebranche
and Arnauld were, despite their differences, !rst and foremost Deux Carte´siens.
Arnauld insisted that his conceptions were faithful to those of Descartes and,
as Nadler notes, “Arnauld would remain committed to la pense´e carte´sienne for
the rest of his life” (1989, p. 34). Though differing over the doctrine of ideas
and perceptual acquaintance, both accepted the fundamental principles of
Descartes’s philosophy (Nadler, 1989, p. 59). Arnauld’s view takes on special
interest today since h is crit ique of Malebranche constitutes a way out of
the analogous problematic conceptions of modern cognitive science.
246
P
.
SLEZAK
Precursors: pointless exercise ?
A
`
propos of historical re"ections, with some justice, Stephen Gaukroger (1996) in his
landmark intellectual biography of Descartes has described as a “pointless exercise”
the efforts to show the extent to which Descartes, for example, was a precursor of
modern cognitive science. However, in some cases we may discern so mething mor e
than fortuitous, independent reinvention. There is a more interesting kind of
recurrence wh ich deserves attention because it is a manifestation of deeper, and
therefore more illuminating, causes—a chronic malaise whose recurrence is symp-
tomatic of deep pathology.
Noting anticipations o f c urrent theories is likely to be re vealing in both direc-
tions: precursors of cognitive science provide an independent, extensive source of
insight into contemporary issues and, conversely, are t hemselves elucidated in novel
ways unavailable to traditional scholarship. (For preliminary steps in this direction,
see Yolton, 1984, 1996, 2000; Slezak, 1999, 2000.) Thus, beyond merely noting the
parallels, I would like to offer some preliminary diagnosis of the malaise and its
etiology along the lines of Arnauld’s defense of Descartes’ view against Male-
branche.
Tables & chairs: bumping into things
From Yolton’s statement of earlier concerns, we can see their relevance to contem-
porary issues:
From the scholastics’ intelligible species, through th e Cartesian’s objective
reality, to Berkeley’s and Hume’s talk of ideas as the very things them-
selves, we see writers on perception striving for some way to sa y that we
perceive physical ob jects. … One of the ways in which some of the writers
tried to preserve the accuracy, if not the directness, of perceptual awareness
was by talking of a conformity or agreement between ideas and objects;
otherwise they said ideas represent objects. (1996, pp. 1–2)
This is, of course, just the modern problem of intentionality or “psychosemantics”
which Cummins describes as just that of saying “in some illuminating way, what it
is for something in the mind to represent something” (1996, p. 1). Despite the
seeming simplicity o f the phenomenon, the burgeoning liter ature attests to the fact
that there is a c onsensus, at least, on Fodor’s judgment that “of the semanticity of
mental representations w e have, as things now stand, no adequate account” (1985b,
p. 28). Typic ally, Stalnaker, too, says, “There is lit tle agreement about how to do
semantics, o r even about the questions that de!ne the subject of semantics” (1991,
p. 229). Likewise, B.C. Smith confesses, “It should be admitted that how this all
works—how symbols ‘reach out and touch someone’—remains an almost total
mystery” (1987, p. 215).
In a report on the state and prospects of interdisciplinary cognitive science,
Fodor (1985a) joked that philosophers are notorious for having been prey to absurd,
eccentric worries such as the “fear that there is something fundamentally unsound
THE TR IPARTITE MODEL OF REPRESENTATION
247
about tables and chairs.” Nevertheless, he optimistically contrasted such “mere”
philosophical worries with those that occasionally turn out to be “real,” as with the
representational character of cognition. Triumphantly, Fodor points to the fact that
today, unlike other proprietary concerns, this problem is no longer just a philoso-
phers’ preoccupation because its solution has become of general importance as a
precondition of progress in several disciplines of cognitiv e science. However, there
is an acute unintended irony in Fodor’s contrast, because the problem of represen-
tation at th e forefront of cognitive science today is, in fact, identical with the
philosophical anxiety about tables and chairs. In various more or less independent
domains, cognitive scientists have simply rediscovere d the very same sterile conun-
drums which have kept philosophers busy since Descartes.
We see a revealing clue to this commonality in Jackendoff’s (1992, p. 161)
question which is a reductio ad absurdum of contemporary symbolic, computational
theories: In view of the “internalism” and “narrow” syntactic character of computa-
tional symbols, Jackendoff asks facetiously: “Why, if our understanding has no direct
access to the real world, aren’t we always bumping into things?” Jackendoff’s satire
is evocative of Samuel Johnson’s famous response to Berkeley’s “ingenious
sophistry”: “I refute it thus,” he said, that is, by kicking a stone. In both cases,
appealing to bumping into things, the responses bring into relief the way in which
classical and modern theories entail a disc onnection of the mind and the world. The
suggestive parallel between Jackendoff and Johnson is no accident. Jackendoff
captures precisely the paradox charged against Locke and also Malebranche, who
Nadler (1992, p. 7) say s “is often portrayed by his critics as enclosing the mind in
a ‘palace of ideas,’ forever cut off from any kind of cognitive or perceptual contact
with the material world.” Of course, Berkeley’s idealism is just the worry about the
reality of tables and c hairs, and Berkeley’s reaction to Locke’s “ideas” is analogous
to Fodor’s reaction to Simon’s symbols—“m ethodological solipsism.” Seemingly
isolating thought in a realm of its own, the representations intervene between mind
and world—two items whose systematic connections with each other become
mysterious. The traditional problem, rediscovered in cognitive science, is how to
make sense of the relation between these three elements—mind, representation and
world—seemingly essent ial to any model of cognition.
The “philosophick topick” of ideas
In his recent book, Yolton (1996, p. 43) mentions the anonymous author of a
pamphlet written in 1705 titled Philosophick essay concerning ideas who says, “There
is hardly any Topick we shall meet with that the Learned have differed more about
than that of Ideas.” It is a remarkable fact that little has changed in this regard
concerning the “Topick” in dispute, the underlying reasons for the problem and th e
solutions adopted [5]. Although the ter minology of ef"uvia, essences, modes and
substances has been replaced by information processing jargon, the essential issues
are unchanged. Thus, Palmer’s (1978) article on “Fundamental aspects of cognitive
representation” says “Anyone who has attempted to read the literature related to
cognitive representation quickly becomes confused—and w ith good reason. The
248
P
.
SLEZAK
!eld is obtuse, poorly de!ned, and embarrassingly disorganized.” After enumerating
a dozen distinct conceptions Palmer adds “These are not c haracteristics of a
scienti!c !eld with a deep understanding of its problem, much less its solution”
(1978, p. 259). The situation does not appear to have improved in the two decades
since Palmer wrote. It is no accide nt that Palmer’s lament and his litany echo
Yolton’s anonymous author because th e theoretical disarray, like the doctrines
themselves, are not unrelated. Suf! cient evidence of this is the fact that the 18th
century auth or’s analysis of the problem and its causes remains appropriate today.
… in considering the Mind, some men do not suf!ciently abstract their
Thoughts from Matter, but make use of such Terms as can prope rly relate
to Matter only, and apply them to the Mind in the same Sense as t hey are
spoken of Matter, such as Images and Signatures, Marks, and Impressions,
Characters and Notes of Things, and Seeds of Thoughts and Knowledge.
(quoted in Yolton, 1956/1993, p. 96)
Translated into current terminology, this is an insightful diagnosis of the latest
disputes concerning representation in cognitive science today. It is, in fact, a
re-statement of Arnauld’s orthodox Cartesian view which insists that mental repre-
sentations cannot be properly characterized in terms taken too directly from those
apt for our e xternal, material representations—the problem of “original” versus
“derived” intentionality.
“Malebranchean Theatre”?
Dennett’s (1991) reference to a “Cartesian Theater” has given wide currency to this
term and thereby served to draw attention to the supposed provenance of a
conception which is, indeed, at the heart of philosophical puzzles about the mind
and consciousness . Indeed, the related mistakes of the “Theater” and the homun-
culus are at the heart of much theorizin g in cognitive science. However, fully
acknowledging the value of Dennett’s analysis, it remains t hat his terminology, at
least, perpetuates an historical solecism. Conceding that Dennett was not concerned
with exegetical, scholarly niceties, it remains important to correct a serious error of
misattribution. The “Theater” in question is more appropriately ascribed to Male-
branche than to Descartes. Although “Malebranchean Theater” does not have the
same pleasing sonority, th ere is good philosophical reason to correct the usage
besides mere historical pedantry. It is important to recognize that a commitment to
the picture of an inner perso n observing a scene on the stage of consciousness is
independent of, and does not follow directly from, dualism. Dennet t recognizes this
in his talk of “Cartesian materialism” (1991, p. 107) which he says is “the view yo u
arrive at when you discard Descartes’ dualism but fail to disc ard the imagery of a
central (but material) Theater where ‘it all comes together’.” However, Dennett
seems to blame Descartes for holding this “Theater” conception together with, or
directly as a consequence of, his dualism. Nevertheless, contrary to Dennett’s
implication , while undeniably a Cartesian dualist, Descartes was emphatically no t a
Cartesian materialist as well. That is, he was not guilty of the Theater fallacy in this
THE TR IPARTITE MODEL OF REPRESENTATION
249
sense. On the contrary, despite positing the anatomica l convergence of nerve
!laments in the pinea l gland, Descartes did not subscribe to the picture of an
observer in the problematic “Theater” because he explicitly argued against positing
concomitant representations of a kind which would require the notorious homun-
culus. Descartes’ “ghost in the machine” is not this observer, but a posit based on
entirely different, independent considerations—namely, the “Cogito” argument and
the lim itation s of machines (Discourse V). The rationale for Descartes’ immaterial
soul is quite different and independent of the “Theater” conception which he
explicitly repudiates in his Dioptrics (1637) and Trea tise of ma n (1662).
Quite apart from the evidence of Descartes’ own texts, ample support for these
ascriptions is found in Arnauld’s writings which articulate an act-theory as an
alternative to Malebranche’s representative “veil of ideas” (see Nadler, 1989, pp. 34,
118, 126, fo otnote 36). Arnauld saw this “direct perception” view as faithful to
Descartes, and Descartes says in correspondence that Arnauld “has entered further
than anyone else into the sense of what I have written” (AT III, 331). Thus,
Arnauld’s Cartesian position adopts precisely Dennett’s stance against the
“Malebr anchean Theater.”
Reinventions: synchronic and diachronic
If Malebranche and Arnauld anticipate d contemporary concerns about representa-
tion in cognitive sc ience, then it is clear that the current theoretical problem has
nothing to do with t he theoretical framework of symbolic, computational approaches
as universally assumed. It is particularly signi!cant, then, that the recurrences of
interest here are found not only throughout history but in seemingly unrelated
domains of cognitive science today. This recurrence of essentially the same dispute
in widely varying contexts con!rms that the underlying problem does not arise
essentially from the special features o f any one of them. Given a seductive mistake
concerning representation as such, multiple, seemingly independent, reinventions
are just what we would expect to !nd. I will presently suggest that we may discern
the same underlying problem at the heart of notorious disputes such as the “Imagery
Debate,” Searle’s Chinese Room conundrum, the thinking-in-languag e debate and
a numbe r of others which have been prominent and recalcitrant.
No representations?
The “cognitive revolution” of the 1960s was characterized by a renewed recognition
of the indispensability of internal representations following their repudiation by
Skinnerian behaviorism. There is considerable irony in recent approaches which
appear to reject internal representations once again (Brooks, 1991; Clark & Tor ibio,
1994; Freeman & Skarda, 1990; Greeno, 1989; van Gelder, 1998). Notwithstandin g
Eliasmith’s (1996) claim, these views are not plausibly s een as a return to behav-
iorism since, strictly speaking, they do not reject internal representations at all (see
Markman & Dietrich , 2000). Nevertheless, these approaches and their rhetoric are
symptoms of the profound dif!culties posed by the phenomena. Particularly in view
250
P
.
SLEZAK
of the revolutionary hype associated with the latest fashions, it is sobering to notice
that Arnauld’s (1683/1990) critique of Malebranche exactly pre!gures these recent
attacks on representational theories. It is no coincidence that Arnauld’s treatise On
true and false ideas is concerned to repudiate what he describes as “imaginary
representations,” saying, “I can, I believe, show the falsity o f the hypothesis of
representations” (1683/1990, p. 77) for “one must not make use of alleged entities of
which we have no clear and distinct idea in order to explain the effects of nature,
whether corporeal or spiritual” (1683/1990, p. 65).
Illusions & misrepresentation: “curious and melancholy fact”
In seeking t o understand the per sistence and recalcitrance of the problems of
intentionality, it is instructive to examin e one facet of the issue which reveals the
seductiveness of the mistake. The problem of misrepresentation h as arisen fo r causal
or co-variation th eories of intentional content (Dretske, 1986; Fodor, 1994a) since
these theories seem to be unable to capture t he way a mismatch might arise between
a representation and the world. If a mentalese token “mouse” might be caused not
only by mic e but also by shrews, then the symbol must ipso facto mean “shrew” and
cannot be in error. It seems not to have been noticed that this modern philosophical
problem of mis representation is a var iant of the well-known classical “Argument
from Illusion” (Reynolds, 2000) which was employed in support of Locke’s “ideas”
and A.J. Ayer’s (1940) sense-data as the immediate objects of per ception. The
parallel s hould not be surprising s ince, after all, an illusion in the relevant sense (that
is, an hallucination) is precisely a misrepresentation. The problem of misrepresen-
tation, then, appears to be one of the loose threads which may be pulled to unravel
the rest of the tangled ball (see Slezak, forthcoming).
Responding to Ayer (1940), Austin (1962, p. 61) remarked on the “curious”
and “melancholy fact” that Ayer’s position on sense-data echoes that of Berkeley. It
is an even more melancholy fact today that Fodor’s “real” problems of representa-
tion also echo Berkeley. Q uestions of veridicality for Locke’s ideas and Ayer’s
sense-data arose from precisely the same assumptions as Fodor’s—namely, the
assumption of being able to compare representations and the world.
The earlier Fodorian passage from Malebranche is followed by a paragraph that
explicitly articulates the “Argument from Illusion”:
It should be c arefully noted that for the mind to perceive an object, it is
absolutely necessary for the idea of that object to be actually present to
it—and about this there can be no doubt; bu t there need not be any
external thing like t hat idea. For it often happens that we perceive things
that do not exist, and that even have never existed—thus our min d often
has real ideas of th ings that have never existed. When, for example, a m an
imagines a golden mountain, it is absolutely necessary that the idea of this
mountain really be present to his mind. When a madman or someone
asleep or in a high fever sees some animal before his eyes, it is certain that
what he sees is not nothing, and that therefore the idea of this animal really
THE TR IPARTITE MODEL OF REPRESENTATION
251
does exist, though the golden mountain and the animal have never existed.
(1712, p. 217)
Illusions in this sense are cases in which the correspondence between represen-
tations and world fails—misrepresentations of exactly the sort relevant to the
contemporary puzzle for symbolic, computational accounts of c ognition. In the
modern case, as posed by Fodor (1994a) and Dretske (1986), the problem is, given
causation between these elements, how to explain the possibility of illusion; in the
classical case the problem is, given illusion, how to explain causation. The modern
problem of misrepresentation arises because causal or correlational theories don’t
appear to permit a distinction between true and false representations. If a dog causes
a representation of “cat” in mentalese, on the causal account it must ipso facto count
as meaning “dog” and is, therefore, not a mistaken representation of cat. Con-
versely, the classica l Argument from Illusion, starts from the other end, as it were.
Beginning with the distinction between true and false representations, the Argument
recognizes that these cannot both be correlated with an external reality, and
concludes that in both veridical and non-veridical cases there must be some other
object of direct perception, the “idea” or sense-datum (see Reynolds , 2000). In view
of these analogies, therefore, I suggest it is no coincidence that Fodor’s (1980)
“meth odological solipsism” is st rongly evocative of a Berkeleyan idealism.
The Malebranche–Locke argument for representative ideas recognizes that
illusions cannot be caused in the usual way by external objects—essentially Fodor’s
puzzle expressed in reverse: Fodor argues that, if ideas are caused by external
objects, we can’t have illusions. The parallels h ere appear to be more than super!cial
or terminological [6]. My claim is not that the problem of misrepresentation and the
Argument from Illusion are directed towards the same ends, but only that they arise
from an identical conceptual scheme and are mirror-images of one another: The
classical argument asse rts: if there are illusions, then there is no direct connection or
correlation with the external world (i.e. there must be intermediate objects of
perception); conversely, Fodor’s argument asserts: If there is a direct connection
(i.e. c ausal correlation) with the external world, then there can be no illusions.
These are eq uivalent co ntrapositives: if we take “I”
5
illusion, “C”
5
correlation,
then the Malebranche–Locke proposition is [I
® ,
C] and the Fodor–Dretske
propositio n is [C
® ,
I].
In passing, we may note that a degree of confusio n ha s been intro duced in these
discussions by the failure to distinguish crucially different kinds of “illusion.” An
illusion in the sense rele vant to the argument concerning ideas, sense-data or
representations is, strictly speaking , hallucination. Ho wever, certain other phenom-
ena commonly referred to as “illusions” in this context such as mirages or bent sticks
in water are not illusory at all in an important sense. These are veridical perceptions
of the light patterns entering the eye unlike cognitive errors such as the Mu¨ ller–Lyer
illusion. Richard Gregory (1997), for example, has explicitly assimilated these
phenomena , but no theory of cognitive processes could explain the “illusion” in the
case of mirages and seemingly bent sticks due to refracted light. Gregory’s mistake
in this regard is interesting and perhaps no mere mistake . Assuming that our
252
P
.
SLEZAK
knowledge of the actual conditions in the world must be use d in characterizing
mental representations is precisely the seductive error which I am concerned to
expose in its various guises. A stick appearing bent in water is a case of “the world
gone wrong” in just the sense of this felicitous phrase used by Fodor, as we will see
presently,
Truth conditions as explanatory?
In both the case of misrepresentation and t hat of illusion the puzzle arises from a
commitment to the tripartite conception in w hich representations intervene between
the mind and the world and are somehow correlated with it. In particular, the
questions of veridicality for Locke’s ideas arose from the impossibility of any
comparison between representations and the world, except from the perspective of
an independent outside observer. As Berkeley recognized, the very distinction
between true and false ideas cannot be made without comparing representations and
the world. Of course, this perspective is unavailable to the mind itself. Correspond-
ingly, an explanatory theory cannot make tacit appeal to such a perspective without
committing the homunculus error. This means that the veridicality or otherwise of
mental representation does not serve an explanatory role and is, therefore, not a
legitimate part of a theory o f m ind. In Berkeley’s idealist response to this problem
we can see the precursor to F odor’s problem arising from a commitment to truth
conditions for mental representations. Securing the veridical connection between
representations and the world through causation simply binds them in such a way as
to preclude error and thus causation functions for Fodor in the way that a mysteri-
ou s correspondence worked for Locke .
Of course the problem of explaining error and that of explaining truth are two
sides of the same coin. Accordingly , t he puzzl e of misrepresentation is symptomatic
of fundamental problems in the conception of mental representations as semanti-
cally evaluable. Fodor is emphatic about the centrality of truth preservation for the
computational RTM . Regarding the fact that mental processes tend to preserve
semantic properties like truth Fodor says
This is, in my view, the most important fact we know about minds; no
doubt it’s why God bothered to give us any. A psychology that can’t make
sense of such facts as that mental processes are typically truth preserving is
ipso facto dead in the water. (Fodor, 1994a, p. 9)
Fodor’s dilemma arises from the fact that content doesn’t ap pear to supervene on
mental processes and, therefore, “semantics isn’t part of psychology” (Fodo r,
1994a, p. 38).
My point, then, is of course not that solipsism is true; it’s just that truth
reference and the rest of the semantic notions aren’t psychological cate-
gories. (1980, p. 253)
It seems that we can’t do psychology with the semantic notions, but we can’t do
THE TR IPARTITE MODEL OF REPRESENTATION
253
psychology without them either. This formulation of Fodor’s dilemma is reminiscent
of a remark by Dennett in a quite different context in which he explained:
… psychology without homunculi is impossible. But psychology with ho-
muncul i is doomed to circ ularity or in!nite regress, so psychology is
impossible. (Dennett, 1978b, p. 123)
My suggestion is that Fodor’s and Dennett’s dilemmas appear to be the same
because at root the puzzle of semantics is a version of the homunculus problem. Just
as Dennett (1978a, p. 122) pointed out that nothing is intrinsically a representation
of anything but only for someone who is the interpreter , so nothing is a misrepresen-
tation for the same reason. That is, Fodor’s current problem of misrepresentation
might be accounted for by noting that it arises from the demand for tacitly adopting
the stance of external interpreter: The very problem itself cannot be cohere ntly
formulated except in terms of judgments which are not part of the explanatory
enterprise. The veridicality of representations is not a property which can play any
role in the functioning of representations or the explanation of them. Like the
picture on a jigsaw puzzle , the meaning of representations conceived as semantically
evaluable in this way is for our own bene!t and not intrinsic to the arrangements of
interlocking components. The sense in which a mental representation does its work
is not one which requires judgment of its truth-value since this is only possible from
the point of view of an observer, the theorist, for whom the representation is
construed as an external symbol.
The very concern with misrepresentation arises from tacitly adopting a ques-
tionable assumption endorsed by Davidson (1975) that having a belief requires also
having the concept of belief, including the concept of error. Davidson says “someone
cannot have a belief unless he understands the possibility of being mistaken, and this
requires grasping the contrast between truth and error—true and false belief” (1975,
p. 22). However, it seems that animals might have beliefs even if they are unable to
know that they have th em and re"ect on their truth-value. A cat can surely be
correct in thinking that a mouse is in a certain hole without having the concepts of
belief and truth.
The judgment of truth or error in a belief must be distinguished from merely
having a belie f which is true or false. We as theorists may judge true and false beliefs
(just as we may judge pictorial resemblance) since these are meta-linguistic or
second-order beliefs, but truth and error are not intrinsic properties of representa-
tion s as such, only to the judgments made about them. Cat psychology must be
possible without invoking cat epistemology.
It is not a big leap from misrepresentation and illusion to notice that images are
a species of the same genus. Imagery involves illusory or non-veridical experiences
of exactly the sort required for the classical argument for sense-data. The proverbial
Pink Elephant of inebriated apprehension is a visual image par excellence, not
relevantly diff erent from Malebranche’s golden mountain or subjects’ imaginings in
the celebrated experiments of Shepard and Metzler (1971) and K osslyn (1994). As
we will see presently, of course, if my conjectured parallel is warranted, it is perhaps
no surprise that the image ry debate has been among the most persistently intractable
254
P
.
SLEZAK
disputes in cognitive science also arising from the theorist doing the work of the
theory.
Twin Earth
Putnam’s (1975) Twin Earth puzzles, too, seem to be an unnoticed variant on the
problem of misrepresentation we sa w earlier. In the familiar scenario, instead of my
Twin Earth double, we may substitute myself after having been unknowingly
transported to Twin Earth. There, like my twin in the original story, I will refer to
XYZ as “water.” However, on this variation of t he original scenario my term
“water” now fails to refer correctly rather than being a correct reference with a term
having a different meaning. Since my twin and I are identic al, the two scenarios
must also be indistinguishable. That is, the problem of “wide” and “narrow”
meaning is just the p roblem o f misrep resentation in another guise.
Instead o f th inking of Twin Earth, then, we may imagine alternatively that on
this earth, Go d might have switched all H
2
O to XYZ without my knowledge. Instead
of taking the original Twin Earth story as showing that my twin must mean
something other than “water,” we may equally conclude that my use of the term is
simply in error when the worlds have been surreptitiously switched. The Twin Earth
scenario is, indeed, simply another wa y of tellin g Dretske’s (1986) story of the
magnetic micro-organisms which are fooled into “thinking” that up is down. Or, in
a different case, as Fodor (in Millikan, 1991, p. 161) has put it, “it’s not the frog but
the world that has gone wrong when a frog snaps at a bee-bee.” Undoubtedly, if the
world is suf!ciently perverse, or it is contrived to alter things in certain ways, our
concepts may accidentally “fail” to refer in the usual manner. It is not clear why such
possibilities should be of interest to a theory of representation for their description
depends on knowledge from a “God’s Eye” p erspective available to the theorist.
Whether the liquid substance is really XYZ or H
2
O is known only to the external
omniscience of the theorist and has no explanatory role in a theory of representation.
In this sense, the philosophical concern with misrepresentation is analogous to the
spurious assimilation of m irages and seemingl y bent sticks to genuine cognit ive
illusions, as noted earlier. In both cases, the actua l truth about the world is invoked
irrelevantly to explain cognition.
Philosophers as three-year-olds?
Ironically, the mistak e I am indicating is not unknown in cognitive science: In the
cases of interest here, philosophers are like the three-year-olds an d autistics in the
much-discussed “false belief task” o f Wimmer and Perner (1983) (see Carruthers &
Smith, 1996; Davies & Stone, 1995a,b ). Like three-year-olds, philos ophers fail to
discount what they know to be the truth about the world in their “theory of mind.”
The surreptitious switching of XYZ for H
2
O, bee-bees for " ies or magnetic “up ” for
“down” ar e ways of making “the world go wrong” precisely analogous to switching
the candy while the child is looking in the “false belief” paradigm. Knowing how the
world really is, philosophers truly ascribe false be lief, just as the three-year-olds
THE TR IPARTITE MODEL OF REPRESENTATION
255
falsely ascribe true belief. I n both cases, belief at tributions are independent of any
facts about the believer, depending instead on irrelevant ext ernal facts about the
world. In these cases, the believer’s state of mind can remain !xed and yet the beliefs
can be made to change from true to false by manipulating the world. The child, like
the philosopher naively takes this po ssibility to be relevant to a “theory of mind” in
ascribing mental representations.
Justi!ed true belief?
In case the foregoing analogy may be thought far-fetched or merely whimsical, it is
perhaps worth noting en passant that yet another notorious philosophical puzzle may
be seen to be merely a version of the same problem. Gettier (1963) paradoxes may
be seen as a species of misrepresentation in which the world conspires to make a
propositio n true for reasons which are entirely independent of a person’s grounds for
believing it. In these cases the problem can only be described because the theorist
knows the truth about circumstances which make a belie f accidentally true, even
though the actual circumstances are irrelevant to the agent’s own reasons for
believing the proposition. The Gettier cases are structurally identical with those of
misrepresentation and Twin Earth because the truth or falsity of the mental
representation (i.e. the state of the world) is varied independently of the agent’s
belief-!xing mechanisms. Such considerations in all cases should be irrelevan t to the
problem of understanding mental representation. The moral of the Gettier cases,
like th at of misrepresentation, is that the only sensible, and perhaps the only
possible, theory of knowledge is one that invokes justi!cations and not truth from a
“God’s Eye” perspective [7]. Any adequate, or even complete, account of a person’s
psychology would have to invoke only the relation of beliefs to available evidence
and not their actual, ultimate truth-value. The world can mislead us in various ways,
giving us good reasons for things that may be false, bad reasons for things that may
be true and good reasons for things that may be true fo r other reasons. None of this
should occasion philosophical anxieties for those interested in psychology. Does the
speedometer of a bicycle misrepresent when the bike is ridden on rollers and not
moving? Once again, it is the w orld that h as gone wrong, known to us as external
observers. However, psychology has no obligation to explain why the world may go
wrong. Thus, conceivably, one might contrive things so that Cabernet Sauvignon
replaced the usual liquid in someone’s veins. However, such a p ossibility is of no
more theoretical concern for medical sc ience than Dretske’s (1986) disoriented
microbes are of interest to cognitive science.
Idea-objects
Bechtel’s (1998, p. 299) re-statement of the tripartite model in Malebranche’s terms
makes explicit the widely he ld assumptions which are the potential source of the
dif!culties in understanding representation [8]. In particular, Bechtel’s assimilation
of internal and external representations is acknowledged where he lists the sorts of
“high-level” representations which have been postulated by cognitive scientists.
256
P
.
SLEZAK
These include “concepts that might designate objects in the world or linguistic
symbols, !gures and diagrams which we can use in reasoning and problem solving”
(1998, p. 305). Bechtel suggests that if cognition does require such higher-level
representations, “the most plausible analysis is that such rep resentations ar e built
upon these low-level representations and perhaps inherit their content from them”
(Bechtel, 1998, p. 306). However, the dif!culty is that the distinction between
!gures or diagrams, on the one hand, and representations operating in the frog’s
retina, for example, is not simply a matter of higher and lower “levels” in an
unproblematic sense. Linguistic symbols, !gures and diagrams which we use in
reasoning and problem solving, as Bechtel says, are obviously “used” in a sense
which is different and precisely inappropriate for internal mental representations.
“Higher” concepts of this kind could no t inherit their content from low-level
concepts mentioned because t he difference here is not one of level, but of a kind
which precisely de!nes the distinction between original and derived intentionality.
In this regar d Bechte l’s account accurately re"ects the assumption s built in to
the foundational notion of symbolic computation, as Allan Newell explains:
The idea is that there is a class of systems which manipulate symbols, and
the de!nition of these systems is what’s behind the programs in AI. The
argument is very simple. We see humans using symbols all the time. They
use symbol systems like books, they use !sh as a symbol for Christianity,
so there is a whole range of symbolic activity, and that clearly appears to be
essential to the exercise of mind. (1986, p. 33)
This passage is striking for the explicitness with which Newell assimilates internal
mental representations with our external communicative symbols. The assimilation
of representations of radically different kinds appears, then, to be among the
foundational assumptions of cognitive science. It was self-consciously articulated in
Dennett’s (1978a) review of Fodor’s (1975) important work The language of thought
which was the philosophical manifesto for the classical symbolic approach to
cognition:
What is needed is nothing less than a completely general t heory of repre-
sentation, with which we can explain how words, thoughts, thinkers,
pictures, computers, animals, sentences, mechanisms, states, functions ,
nerve impulses, an d formal models (inter alia) can be said to represent one
thing or another. (1978, p. 91)
The hoped-for uni!cation is to be achieved by showing that these seemingly
heterogeneous items are all, in f act, variants of a common, underlying scheme.
Dennett makes this explicit, explaining:
It will not do to divide and conquer here—by saying that these various
things do not represent in the same sense. Of course that is true, but what
is important is that there is something that binds them all together, and we
need a theory that can unify the variety. (1978a, p. 91) .
The pictorial account of imagery is perhaps the clearest example of taking our
THE TR IPARTITE MODEL OF REPRESENTATION
257
external artifacts as the model for internal representations. More generally, the
dif!culties arise from an equivocation on the notion of “understanding” w hich can
mean interpreting a meaningful representation as intelligible, or explaining it as in
science. We will see presently that this con"ation is evidently at th e heart of Searle’s
(1980) Chinese Room scenario, for Searle asks whet her he, as homunculus in the
system, can unde rstand the symbols. This criterion should be irrelevan t to the
question of whether a system ha s “original” intentionality, but Searle’s mistake is
no t his alone. That is, the Chinese Room scenario accurately captures the orthodox
assumptions of the Simon–Newell “physical symbol system hypothesis.” Searle’s
argument is, therefore, best understood, not as a refutation of “strong” AI, but as a
reductio ad absurdum of the widely held assumptions on which AI and cognitive
science are based. I will suggest that this standard formalist or logicist view
conceived on the model of an uninterpreted logical calculus is problematic as an
account of the way an intelligent system is related to the external world by
depending on the intentions of the external user who supplies the interpretation of
the meaningless formal symbols (see Birnb aum, 1991; Rosenschein, 1985). Embrac-
ing this conception, Nilsson (1987, 1991), like Newell above, explicitly invokes our
external symbolic artifacts such as books to defend his view against the
“proc eduralist” position that representations are to be used by the system itself
rather than understood or ascribed meaning by the designer. Undoubtedly recogniz-
ing the problems with invoking an intelligent user or understander, most theorists
would not knowingly embrace such an account, but their intentions may be
inconsistent with the actual properties of their model by virtue of assimilating
external and internal representations [9]. It is not dif!cult to !nd leading theorists
explicitly endorsing this assimilation. Thus, Rumelhart and Norman (1983) wrote:
We de!ne a symbol to be an arbitrary entity that stands for or represents
something else. By “entity” we mean anything that can be manipulated and
examined … Humans also use external devices as symbols, such as the
symbols of writing and printing, electronic displays or speech waves.
(p. 78)
In a recent statement for an encyclopaedi a entry on rep resentation Dan L loyd
explains:
Humans are representing animals, and we have built a world crammed
with representations of many kinds. Consider, for examp le, the number
and variety of pictorial representation: paintings, photographs, moving
pictures, line drawings, caricatures, diagrams, icons, charts, graphs, and
Maps. Add the variety of linguistic representations in signs, titles, texts of
all kinds, and especially spoken words and sentences … Human life, in
short, is largely a cycle of making and interpreting representations. (Lloyd,
forthcoming)
By contrast, Block (1986) recognizes that “The representation on the page must be
read or heard to be understood, but not so for the representation in the brain”
(p. 83). However, despite making this distinction, Block’s discus sion appears to
258
P
.
SLEZAK
lapse into the characteristic error. Block asks “what it is to grasp or understand
meaning? ” (p. 82). Of course, we don’t grasp or understand the meaning of our own
mental representations, we just have them. In Dennett’s (1978b) felicitous phrase,
the representations must understand themselves. Arnauld’s words appear to directly
address theorists today:
To say that our ideas and our perceptions (taking these to be the same
thing) represent to us the things that we conceive and that they are their
images, is t o say something completely different from saying that pictures
represent their originals and are the images of them, or that spoken or
written words are the images of our thoughts. For in the case of ideas we
mean that the things we conceive are objectively in our mind and in our
thought. And this way of being objectively in the mind is so peculiar to the
mind and to thought, since it is what speci!cally gives them their nature,
that one seeks in vain anything similar outside the min d and thought. As
I have already remarked, what has thrown the question of ideas into
confusion is the att empt to explain the way in which objects are repre-
sented by ideas by analogy with corporeal things, but there can be no real
comparison between bodies and minds on this question. (Arnauld, 1683/
1990, p. 66)
Symbols & Searle: the meaning of meaning
I have been suggesting that a crucial equivocation on distinct meanings of
“meaning” has led to the postulation of symbols having me aning in an observer-rel-
ative sense in which a representat ion is necessarily apprehended and understood by
someone. Cummins (1996) clearly points to this mistake of construing int ernal
representations as if they may function through being understood. The question of
meaning of mental representations is regularly confused between whether represen-
tations are intelligible and whether they are explainable. Searle (1980) trades directly
on this confusion by asking whether an intelligent understander can interpret the
symbols which are the sub strate of thought. But however we might explain inten-
tionality, it cannot depend on whether anyone can “understand” the goings-on in a
machine or a head in the sense of apprehending them. The only sense in which these
goings-on are to be understood is the quite different sense o f scienti!c explanation .
It is no accident that the same pernicious equivocation has bedeviled longstanding
disputes in the social sciences b etween subjectivist advocates of verstehen as a
method and “positivist” advocates of erkla¨ ren (Slezak, 1990; Winch, 1957). How-
ever, understanding qua participant is not the same as understanding qua scientist
[10]. Undeniably, Searle’s (1980 ) Chinese Room demonstrates that computational
symbols are meaningless in the former sense, but this is no more problematic than
the meaninglessness, in this sense, of action potentials or synapti c activations.
Predictably, the problem may be seen arisin g in debates over connectionist systems
where, in this case, it is the alleged absence of “explicit” symbols in dispute.
THE TR IPARTITE MODEL OF REPRESENTATION
259
However, the criterion is taken to be whether symbols may be “directly read off” or
“immediately grasped” (Ramsey et al., 1991). The obvious question is: by whom?
Searle’s conundrum is remarkably evoked by Glanvill’s response in 1661 to
Descartes’ own version of a coding or information processing theory of perception.
“But how is it, and by what Art doth the soul read that such an image or stroke in
matter … signi !es such an object? Did we learn such an Alphabet in our Embryo-
state?” (quoted in Yolton, 1984, p. 28). Echoing Searle, Glanvill suggests that the
“motio ns of the ! laments of nerves” learn the quality of objects by analogy with the
wa y in which a person learns to understand a language, for otherwise “the soul
would be like an infant who hears sounds or sees lips move but has no understanding
of what the sounds or movements signify, or like an illiterate pe rson who sees letters
but “knows not w hat they mean” (1984, p. 28). It is signi!cant that, unknowingly,
Yolton also evokes Searle in the Chinese Room when discussing Locke’s conception
in terms of a “perspective box” or camera obscura. Yolton asks “Was there some
temptation to think of our awareness being like the face at the perspective box
scanning the images on the wall of the box?” (1984, p. 127).
Arnauld’s act-theory of direct realism
Arnauld proposed a “direct perception” account against Malebranche’s indirect,
object-mediated theory. For Arnauld, combating the tripartite view means that ideas
are not dis tinct entities but just those very activities of the mind which are essentially
representative p er se.
Since God desired our mind should know bodies, and that bodies should
be known by ou r mind, it was undoubtedly simpler for him to render our
mind capable of knowing bodies immediately, that is, without representa-
tive entities distinct from perceptions … and bodies capable of being
known immediately by our mind, rather than leaving the soul powerless to
see them otherwise than by means of certain representative entities. (VFI,
222–3, quoted in Nadler, 1989, p. 97)
Arnauld insists that enclosing the mind in a “palace of ideas” as Berkeley was
to do is an ab surd conclusion to draw from the representative t heory. Speci!cally,
as we have seen, Arnauld diagnoses the absurdity as due to a mistake o r false analogy
between “being present to the mind” in the sense of having ideas, thinking or
perceiving, on the one hand, and being present to the eyes in seeing. Of course, this
is the assimilation of internal and external representations we have seen. That is,
“seeing” with the mind or sou l is confused wit h seeing with the eyes or body.
Arnauld argues that philosophers have t ried to explain how we think or p erceive with
the mind—mental vision or la vue spirituelle—by analogy with optical vision or true
seeing [11] with the eye—la vue corporelle. This is the same insight expressed in the
epigraph from Galileo. As Nadler points out, Arnauld insists that the problem with
this analogy is that it rests on false assumptions and “One must not base one’s
reasoning about the mental act of perception or observations on, or beliefs about,
the physiological processes which constitute bodily seeing. ”
260
P
.
SLEZAK
Nadler (1989, p. 93) construes Arnauld’s distinction between mental
seeing and bodily vision as arising from an adherence to a strict Cartesian
dualism. However, Nadler appears to be making a similar mistake to the
on e we have already noted by Dennett in his diagnosis of the “Cartesian
Theater.” Arnauld, like Descartes, avoids the problems inherent in represent-
ative ideas qua intervening, apprehended e ntities because he has a better
theory of perceptual an d intellectual activity—namely, in terms o f mental
processes which are themselves inherently referential . This is to avoid the
necessity of any central observing homunculus and the Theater by avoiding
a conception of representative entities which require an intelligent perceiver
to contemplate them. Contrary to Nadler, this conception is entirely indepen-
dent of dualism “which rules out any such analogies” between mental and
corporeal vision. Arnauld’s view is more subtle. The analogy is ruled out not
because of any dualism but becaus e Arnauld conceives mental activity as
itself essentially representative and thereby dispenses with ideas as surrogat e
objects to be observed by the mind’ s eye: “… I do not see any need for this
alleged ‘representative entity’ in order to know any object, be it present or absent”
(VFI, 221, quoted in Nadler, 1989, p. 96).
Not much of a revolution?
By contrast with the usual hype, Chomsky recently expressed skepticism regard-
ing th e radical novelty of the so-called Cognitive Revolution saying “it wasn’t all
that muc h of a revolution in my opinion” (1996, p. 1). Chomsky suggests that
the same convergence of disciplinary interests had taken place in the 17th century
in what he calls “ ‘the !rst cognitive revolution,’ perhaps the only real one” (p. 1).
Chomsky (1966) began his Cartesian linguistics by quoting Whitehead, who said that
the recent history of intellectual life may be accurately described as “living upon
the accumulated capital o f ideas provided … by the genius of the seventeenth
century.” Chomsky was concerned to show that a return to classical concerns and
appreciation of their parallels with contemporary developments is valuable in help-
ing to advance the study of language [12]. I hav e been suggesting that, with some
interesting differences, Chomsky’s point ho lds for recent speculation about the min d
outside of linguistics as well. Indeed, Nadler (1992, p. 73) notes th at it is both
“strange an d no t a little embarrassing” that the Malebranche–Arnauld debate should
remain largely ignored or misunderstood by philosophers and historians alike. The
same goes for cognitive scientists. Thus, Chomsky’s example may be usefully
followed in relation to these different issues such as the hotly contested represent-
ational theories of the mind. However, the differences f rom the case of linguistics are
revealing. Though equally neglected in cognitive science, not only the good ideas of
the 17th century are being rediscovered: We are not only reinventing the same
theories and reliving the same debates, but also rehearsin g the same notorious
mistakes.
THE TR IPARTITE MODEL OF REPRESENTATION
261
Imagery: the pictorial theory
The “I magery Debate” is perhaps the most remarkable modern duplication of 17th
century cont roversies. In this re-enactment, among the dramatis personae Pylyshyn
plays Arnauld against Kosslyn’s Malebranche. Kosslyn (1994) c laims to have
resolved the debate in favor of his “pictorial” theory, but there remain grounds for
skepticism. The mise-en-sce`ne is faithful even to the extent of the acrimony of the
disputes. More importantly, the central error identi!ed by Arnauld of ascribing
corporeal properties to mental ones is exactly the one charged by Pylyshyn (1973,
1978, 1981, in press) against Kosslyn.
Despite its computational and neuroscience trappings, Kosslyn’s (1994) picto-
rial account of image ry takes mental images to represent by virtue of a relation of
resemblance to their objects and by virtue of actually having spatial properties which
they r epresent. Furthermore, “depictive” representations in a “visual buffer” are
taken to have the spec i!c function of permitting a re-inspection of images by the
higher visual apparatus. There is said to be an “equivalence” between imagery and
perception according to which the “higher” cognitive processing apparatus for visual
perception is simply applied to an alternative input other than the retina—namely,
the visual buffer. Thus, on the pictorial account, a mental image is conceived to be
a “surrogate percept” (Pinker & Finke, 1980). In this way, an image may be
“repro cessed as if it were perceptual input … thereby accomplishing the purposes of
imagery that paralle l those of perception” (Kosslyn 1987, p. 155). Of course this is
an implicit endorsement of the tripartite conception of mental representation in
imagery.
Dennett (1991) takes this pictorial theory of imagery to be a paradigm example
of the “Theater” misconception and, not surprisingly, t his “quasi-perceptual” model
has been repeatedly charged with the error of importing an “homunculus.” The
charge is vigorously rejected on the grounds that “the theory is realized in a
computer program” (Kosslyn et al., 1979, p. 574), but undischarged homunculi can
lurk in computational models just as easily as in traditional discursive theories (see
Slezak, 1995, in press).
Thus, Kosslyn et al. (1989) offer a diagram of the visual imagery system which
is a profusion of interconnected boxes and arrows. The box labeled “visual buffer”
contains another box labeled “attention window” which is lef t unexplained. This
box is, in fact, the observer in the “theater” which is the source of the traditional
problem. The elaborate diagram is reducible to the same tripartite schema we have
seen in Malebranche. Signi!cantly, following D escartes, Arnauld explicitly p ointed
to the seductive error of taking pictures as an appropriate model of mental represen-
tation (Arnauld, 1683/1990, p. 67), and he cites the camera obscura as an erroneous
model for imagery.
In a revealing misunderst anding, Kosslyn (1980, p. 30) has charged alternative
propositional or “tac it knowledge” theories (Pylyshyn, 1973) as being “no imagery”
accounts, but denying pictorial images is not to deny imagery per se. Rather, in an
Arnauldian spirit, the denial of pictorial format for representations is actually to
deny the problematic homunculus an d its pseudo-explanation. In effect, as we see,
262
P
.
SLEZAK
the debate between Malebranche and Arnauld is being replayed throughout the
history of speculation o f the mind and contemporary cognitive science. Thus, one
need not go back as far as the 17th and 18th centuries to discover the same
concerns. F.C. Bartlett’s (1932) theory of schemata in his book Remembering, was a
reaction to theories of “!xed, lifeless and fragmentary traces” or images which are
merely “reduplicative,” capable only of being re-excited. Reminiscent of Arnauld’s
rejection of “super"uous entities” and his view “that idea and perception are the same
thing,” Bartlett wishes to substitute a cognitive process for objects which are
pictorial or “reduplicative traces” (1932, p. 215) [13].
Phenomenological fallacy
Kosslyn claims to have clinched the debate about imagery by app ealing to the
!ndings of neurophysiology and neuroanatomy [14]. Topographically organized
regions of cortex or “retinotopic mapping” are said to “support depictive represen-
tations,” that is, pictures in some sense. Thus, for example, a monkey may be given
a visual stimulus like a dartboard to look at. If the brain tissue is treated in a certain
way, it can be shown to have a likeness of the dartboard “etched” on the cortex. The
result was anticipated and p erfectly understood by one psychologist 30 years before:
At some point the organism must do more than create duplicates … The
need for something beyond and quite different from copying is not widely
understood. Suppose someone were to coat the occipital lobes of the brain
with a special photographic emulsion which, when developed, yielded a
reasonable copy o f a current visual stimulus In many quarters this woul d be
regarded as a triumph in the physiology of vision. Yet nothing could be
more disastrous … (Skinner, 1963, p. 285)
Skinner was acutely sensitive to the source of homunculi pseudo-explanations even
if his behaviorist remedy is no longer attractive.
Kosslyn’s TV screen metaphor reveals the link between seemingly unrelated
problems in cognitiv e science. For example, in the classic statement of materialism,
U.T. Place (1956) argued that the implausibility and rejection of materialism as a
solution to the mind–body problem is based on the qualitative features of subjective
experience. Although these features have recently been supposed to constitute the
“hard” problem of consciousness (Chalmers, 1996), Place suggested that they are
the source of the “p henomenological fallacy.” Anticipating Dennett (1991), Place
wrote, this is “the mistake of supposing that when the subject describes his experi-
ence, how things look, sound, smell, taste, or feel to him, he is describing the literal
properties of objects and events on a particular s ort of internal cinema or television
screen.”
Thinking in language
On the face of it, the persistent doctrine that we think “in” language is not obviously
connected with the others we have considered such as pictorial imagery. Neverthe-
THE TR IPARTITE MODEL OF REPRESENTATION
263
less, these two theories are variat ions on the same theme. Symptomatic is the fact
that both depend on a deep intuitive, introsp ective appeal. Just as w e seem to be
looking at pictures when w e imagine visually, so we appear to talk to ourselves when
we think. Indeed, Carruthers (1996), who seeks to revive what he acknowledges to
be an unfashionable doctrine, explicitly bases his argument against Fodor’s Lan-
guage of thought on such evidence of introspection. This is the evidence that we
sometimes !nd ourselves in a silent monologue, talking to ourselves in our natural
language, sotto voce, as it were.
However, in a neglected article, Ryle (1968) suggested that the very idea that
we might think “in” language is unintelligible, and the undeniable experience of
talking to ourselves cannot supp ort any claim about the vehicles of thought. It is
signi!cant that Ryle mentions en passant among the equally problematical cases, that
in which we claim to see things in our “mind’s eye”—taken to involve mental
pictures of some kind. Ryle’s compariso n and his warning is unwittingly con!rmed
by Carruthers (1996, 1998), who exp licitly invokes Kosslyn’s pictorial account of
imagery as support for his own analogous theory. In doing so, however, Carruthers
only brings into relief the notorious dif!culties o f his own model which relies on a
representational format—sentences of natural language—which is, like pictures,
paradigmatically the kind requiring an external intelligent observer (see Slezak,
2002).
Still more processing: triadic or dyadic?
As we have seen, the traditional dif!culty, rediscovered in various forms today, arises
from the problematic three-part relation between world, ideas and consciousness.
Cognition without these basic features seems inconceivable, and yet they le ad to
seemingly intractable dif!culties. In its essentials, the Malebranche–Locke account
may be captured in the following schematic diagram:
External World
®
Ideas
®
Consciousness
The commonality between this schema and modern ones is clearly revealed in a
diagram of Ulric Neisser (1976 ). In its essentials the diagram may be represented as
follows:
Storage Storage St o rage
¯! ¯! ¯!
External
®
Retinal
®
Processing
®
M ore processing
®
Still m o re processing
®
Consciousness
W orld image
Neisser’s schema obviously abstracts from the details of any speci!c account, but
despite its mildly whimsical character, it purports to be a serious generic sketch of
information processing theories. For example, the welter of boxes and arrows in
Kosslyn’s diagram reduces to Neisser’s picture which has the virtue of not disguising
its essential commitment to the problematic third element “consciousness.”
One early attempt to avoid the dif!culties inherent in this account is in the
reactions of Locke’s critic John Sergeant:
264
P
.
SLEZAK
He never found a satisfactory answer to the question of the nature of ideas,
but he was convinced that t hey functioned to deny the mind direct access
to things by restricting it to some kind of third entity. Cognition was thus
made to consist in a triadic relation involving the knowing mind, the object
or referent, and the ideas by means of which the mind came to know
things. Sergeant wished to reduce the process of knowing to a dyadic
relation consisting only of the knowing mind and the object known.
(quoted in Yolton, 1956/1993, p. 103)
No ideas?
However, given a p roblematic three-part relation, there are only a few ways to ge t
a dyadic relation. First, eliminating the middle term, ideas or representations,
permits two construals. On one view, which Yolton describes as “wildly impossible”
but which has nonetheless been explicitly held, an object is itself somehow literally
present to, or in, the mind. Thi s is t he view we saw parodied by Malebranche saying
that the soul does not stroll in the heavens among the stars.
External World
®
Consciousness
No external world?
Of course, a dyadic relation can also be obtained by dropping one of the other relata
instead of the middle one. Thus, we might eliminate the external world to get
Berkeley’ s idealism.
Ideas
®
Consciousness
Berkeley’ s strategy has not been popular recently among cognitive scientists, though
it is precisely the paradox of Fodor’s “methodological solipsism.”
No consciousness?
Of course, we have another choice besides getting rid of the world or getting rid of
the representations. We can get rid of consciousness! Securing a direct connection
between cognition and the world can also be achieved by dispensing with the agent
[15].
External World
®
Ideas
Despite its counter-intuitiveness, in some respects this option is preferable to the
others. Of c ourse, the agent as an element in models of perception is the locus of the
potential homunculus. The paradoxical rejection of consciousness is equivalent to
the !rst of these three options, being the same as rejecting representations when
these are conceived in ce rtain ways. Therefore, expressed less paradoxically, the
Gibsonian or “situated” case against representations may be best understood, not as
an outright rejection of an internal mental medium as such, but rather as the
THE TR IPARTITE MODEL OF REPRESENTATION
265
Arnauldian rejection o f a certain particular conception of representations which are
explanatorily question-begging.
Conclusion
Thirty years ago in his book Psychological explanation, Fodor (1968 , p. vii) remarked:
“I think many philosophers secretly harbor the view that there is something dee ply
(i.e. conceptually) wrong with psychology, but that a philosopher with a little
training in the techniques of linguistic analysis and a free afternoon could straighten
it out.” Today , the suspicion of deep conceptual problems at the heart of cognitive
science is perhaps more clearly seen to be justi!ed, although Fodor’s joke was
intended to re"ect as much upon philosophy as upon psychology. Notoriously, deep
conceptual problems at the heart of philosophy have been no more dispelled than
those in psychology. I have been suggesting that by adopting a broader perspective
we may see why the sorry fortunes of the two disciplines have been inextricably
linked.
Acknowledgements
This paper has bene!ted greatly by the most helpful comments and criticisms of the
editor, W. Bechtel, and two anonymous referees of Philosophical Psychology. Versions
of the material have be en presented at the Department of Philosophy, University of
Sydney, the Sixteenth Annual Me eting of the J apanese Cognitive Science Society,
Tokyo, August 1999, the Annual Meeting of the Australasian Association for
History, Philosophy & Social Studies of Science, Melbourne, June 2001, and the
Twenty Third Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, Edinburgh,
August 2001. I am particularly grateful for the comments of Stephen Gaukroger,
Ron Giere, Pat Langley, Robert Nola, Zenon Pylyshyn and John Sutton.
Notes
[1] Kosslyn writes with evident annoyance: “Once and for all, the ‘homunculus problem’ is simply
not a problem. We thought this would be obviou s given that the theory is realized in a computer
program, but it seems necessary to address this complaint again ” (Kosslyn et al., 1979, p. 574).
[2] The scholarly, exegetical niceties need not concern us here. However, Nadler (1992, p. 8) points
out that th e standard reading presented here is mistaken and even a caricature, though it has been
almost universally held among commentators including Arnauld, Locke, Leibniz, Berkeley and
Reid.
[3] The “situated” critique confuses conscious calculation with the “sub-personal” use of symbols
and their purely causal, functional role in cognition (see Slezak, 1999). As Pasnau says: “Surely,
any modern direct-realist theory of perception will allow causal interme diaries between object and
percipient: no one would dream of denying the title of direct realism to a theory of percepti on
merely because it tole rates causal intermediaries” (Pasnau, 1997, p. 300).
[4] Above all, Moreau expresses irritation at the view which has been widely held, especially among
“nos contemporains anglo-saxons,” that this affair is at base nothing other than one of opposing
temperaments—“Arnauld-la-teigne ” against “Malebranche-le-grognon”—that is, Arnauld-the-nuis-
266
P
.
SLEZAK
ance against Malebranche-the-grouch (1999, p. 16). In fact, numerous great !gures of the time
became embroiled in the debate, such as Leibniz who followed it closely (see Nadler, 1989, p. 5).
[5] In his earlier work on Locke and the way of ideas, Yolton (1956/1993) gives a longer passage from
the same author which is worth repeating here as testimony to the curious persistence of the
puzzle of ideas, albeit in different guises: “… like Men blundering in the dark, they feel after them
to !nd them; some catch at them under one Appearance, some under another; some make them
to be Material, others Spiritual; some will have them to be Ef!uvia, from the Bodies they
Represent, others Totally Distinct Essences; some hold them to be Modes, others Substances; some
assert them All to be Innate; others None: So that one would think there must needs be a very great
Intricacy in that which has given Rise, not only to such a Variety but also such a Contradiction of
Opinions” (quoted in Yolton, 1956/1993, p. 96).
[6] I am grateful to an anonymous referee for criticisms which have helped me to try clarifying this
argument.
[7] This moral seems to extend in an obvious way to the broader concern with knowledge in
philosophy of science. Although it cannot be pursued here, another deep parallel may be seen in
the more or less distinct literatures of perceptual realism and scienti!c realism. Here too the
problem of truth and error arises for realism in the form of the so-called “pessimistic meta-induc-
tion” from history—analogous to the Argume nt from Illusion. It is no accident that Mach’s
instrumentalism was harshly criticized in Lenin’s (1927) Materialism and empirio-criticism as
betraying science by deserting to a Berkeleyan idealism. See also Popper (1963a,b) on Berkeley
as precursor to Mach and Einstein. See also Zahar (1981).
[8] Among the few explicit attempts to articulate the relevant distinctions here, see Cummins (1996,
p. 87) on the distinction between “meaning” and “meaningfor”—the latter described by Cum-
mins as “a three-place relation between a representation, a concept, and a cognitive system.” See
discussion on p. 130.
[9] Conversely, it may be that researchers’ actual theories or programs are exemplary and free of
problems, but only their “meta-theoretical” analyses suffer from the fatal "aws. I am grateful to
Pat Langley and Ron Giere for this point.
[10] Chomsk y (1962) has drawn attention to the way in which traditional grammars produce an
illusion of explanatory completeness while, in fact, they have serious limitations fro m a scienti!c,
explanatory point of view. The apparent success