Article

Hussearle's Representationalism and the “hypothesis of the Background”

Authors:
To read the full-text of this research, you can request a copy directly from the author.

Abstract

John Searle's “hypothesis of the Background” seems to conflict with his initial representationalism according to which each Intentional state contains a particular content that determines its conditions of satisfaction. In Section I of this essay I expose Searle's initial theory of Intentionality and relate it to Edmund Husserl's earlier phenomenology. In Section II I make it clear that Searle's introduction of the notion of Network, though indispensable, does not, by itself, force us to modify that initial theory. However, a comparison of this notion to the notion of “horizon” from Husserl's later phenomenology and an interpretation of Husserl's conception of the “determinable X” as providing a solution to the problem of perceptual misidentification lead me to conclude that in his discussion of 'twin examples' Searle had better modified his initial theory. Finally, I critically examine Searle's claim that “anyone who tries seriously to follow out the threads in the Network” will eventually reach a “bedrock” of non-Intentional capacities. In Section III I show in detail, partly in a rather Husserlian vein, that Searle's four official arguments for the Background thesis, though containing some very valuable contributions to a theory of linguistic skills, are not convincing at all if they are to be understood as going beyond the scope of (Hus)Searle's 'content-cum-Network' picture of Intentionality. The upshot of these considerations is that the Background thesis should be read as a thesis concerning the causal neurophysiological preconditions of human Intentionality rather than concerning the logical properties of Intentional states in general. Recently Searle himself has come to the same result, but he does not say for which reasons. The present essay makes it clear why Searle just had to arrive at this important result.

No full-text available

Request Full-text Paper PDF

To read the full-text of this research,
you can request a copy directly from the author.

... 18 17 It is not accidental that the central notions of Searle's theory are very similar to the corresponding notions of Husserl. There are philosophers who maintain that Searle's theory contains many points that are known to us from Husserl's works (see Beyer (1997), McIntyre (1984)). 18 The noema consists of two important parts -thetic part and noematic Sinn -which correlate with parts of a concrete intentional state. ...
... 28 See e.g. Beyer (1997), 338. According to Beyer, D. Føllesdal thinks along similar lines. ...
... Similar accounts of these issues, maybe in different idioms, emerged almost in every phenomenological theory of intentionality (see, for example,Twardovski (1982),Husserl (2001). SeeBeyer (1997) for a comparison of Searle's theory with Husserl's). ...
Thesis
Full-text available
My aim in this research is to study the philosophical problems of intentionality and perception by critically analyzing the relevant ideas from John Searle’s works, and also to attempt to give solutions to some of these problems. I try to elucidate Searle's theory of intentionality and his way of assimilating the problems of perception into this theory, and investigate the plausibility of his corresponding ideas in the context of ongoing debates.
... On the other hand, it provokes further questions regarding how, precisely, one is aware of the table. For example, does the table 13 Or "Hussearle", as Beyer (1997) puts it. More specific areas of overlap include the structure of intentionality, the relation of mind to language, Searle's concept of the background, and his more recent work on social ontology (Beyer 1997;McIntyre 1984). ...
... For example, does the table 13 Or "Hussearle", as Beyer (1997) puts it. More specific areas of overlap include the structure of intentionality, the relation of mind to language, Searle's concept of the background, and his more recent work on social ontology (Beyer 1997;McIntyre 1984). Searle has responded to the claim that his work is similar to Husserl's, acknowledging that he read some Husserl and assimilated phenomenological ideas via Dreyfus, but denying substantive influence (Searle 2005). ...
... . Husserl discusses what are in effect Twin Earth cases as well in the 1911 Beilage XIX of VB. For helpful discussions, seeBeyer 1997, Alweiss 2009, Erhard 2011, and Szanto 2012. Beyer's piece contains English translations of sizeable portions of Husserl's text.24 ...
Article
In the 21st century Philosophy of mind is naturally understood in terms of a certain historical progression. After rejecting introspection as unreliable, some behaviorists sought to understand the mind strictly in terms of widely available data. Nevertheless, behaviorism cannot account for certain inner feelings and states, so the identity theory emerged as a viable physicalist alternative. The identity theory posits a strict, reductive identity between brain states and mental states. However, the one-to-one link between psychological terms and corresponding physical terms was problematic, since terms like “pain” seem to have many relations to physical kinds. To address this issue functionalists described mental states in terms of a kind of finite machine or probabilistic mechanism, defined by a pattern of relationships between inputs, outputs, and other internal states. These structures have the attractive feature that they can multiply and be realized in different physical systems. Consequently, contemporary philosophy of mind has rediscovered phenomenology, notwithstanding in a fairly impoverished form. Contemporary philosophers of mind often address the “phenomenology” of a particular form of experience by inquiring whether “there is something that it is like” to undergo it. The phrase is suggestive, but it has led to a severe phenomenology, an account of the “small mental residue” that materialist theories leave unexplained. On the other hand, this narrow conception of phenomenology has been expanding. “Liberal” accounts of phenomenal character include emotional-affective, agentive, and cognitive experience. Intentionality has been pursued in an increasingly phenomenological way. These and related projects come closer to phenomenology as historically conceived, which was extremely rich in terms of its method, scope, and conceptual apparatus. In this article we give an overview of the phenomenological tradition. In addition, we survey some of the many ways phenomenology overlaps philosophy of mind, how they have shared historical origins in Brentano, Frege and Husserl; the areas of numerous thematic overlaps and the active collaborations. Finally, we shall argue about how phenomenology and philosophy mind can interact.
Chapter
Brentano’s lectures attracted a large number of very gifted students who became fascinated with the idea of intentionality and developed it further in several different directions. Brentano followed up Aristotle’s view on our mind taking on the form of the object and he was particularly influenced by Thomas Aquinas’ approach. His students struggled with how to deal with acts without objects, for example hallucinations, and proposed different solutions. Husserl tried to agree with his teacher as far as he could. He even regarded agreement with one’s teacher as a duty, which could only be forsaken for very good reasons. But he thought he had such reasons. These led him to phenomenology, which is briefly presented in this paper. In a short appendix I use the connection between Aristotle and Husserl to examine the controversy between two prominent Aristotle scholars, Myles Burnyeat (1992) and Richard Sorabji (1974, 1992), and their many followers on both sides concerning the interpretation of Aristotle’s theory of perception. The appendix was presented in lectures at conferences in 1995 and 1996, but never sent off for publication. It was published in Greek translation in 1997. In the following years, Burnyeat, who died on September 20, 2019, modified his view, probably without knowing about my criticism. As far as I know, Sorabji stands by his view.
Chapter
From Descartes and Cartesian mind-body dualism in the 17th century though to 21st-century concerns about artificial intelligence programming, The Bloomsbury Companion to the Philosophy of Consciousness presents a compelling history and up-to-date overview of this burgeoning subject area. Acknowledging that many of the original concepts of consciousness studies are found in writings of past thinkers, it begins with introductory overviews to the thought of Descartes through to Kant, covering Brentano’s restoration of empiricism to philosophical psychology and the major figures of the late 19th and early 20th centuries: Russell, Wittgenstein, Ryle and James. These opening chapters on the forces in the history of consciousness lay the groundwork needed to understand how influential contemporary thinkers in the philosophy of mind interpret the concept of consciousness. Featuring leading figures in the field, Part II discusses current issues in a range of topics progressing from the so-called hard problem of understanding the nature of consciousness, to the methodology of invoking the possibility of philosophical zombies and the prospects of reductivism in philosophy of mind. Part III is dedicated to new research directions in the philosophy of consciousness, including chapters on experiment objections to functionalism and the scope and limits of artificial intelligence. Equipped with practical research resources including an annotated bibliography, a research guide and a glossary, The Bloomsbury Companion to the Philosophy of Consciousness is an authoritative guide for studying the past, present and future of consciousness.
Article
Levinas is usually discussed as a philosopher wrestling with the nature of our experience of others, ethical obligation, and the divine. Unlike other phenomenologists, such as Husserl and Heidegger, he is not often mentioned in discussions about issues in philosophy of mind. His work in that area, especially on perception, is underappreciated. He gives an account of the nature of perceptual experience that is remarkable both in how it departs from that of others in the phenomenological tradition and for how it fits in among presently available views about the nature of perceptual experience, namely, as a form of naïve realism.
Article
A couple of years ago, the Cuban philosopher, Pablo Guadarrama, wrote an article titled: “Criticism of epistemological reductionisms in the social sciences.” The aim of this paper will be to show how the reading made by this philosopher can lead to a misunderstanding of phenomenology. Instead of indicating some omissions about phenomenology made by Guadarrama, this text tries to explain how phenomenology, instead of being an epistemological reductionism, could facilitate some “integral investigations” in social science. To fulfill this objective, the article starts with a succinct presentation of Guadarrama’s thesis; later, some aspects that do not correspond with an informed interpretation of phenomenology are pointed out. Finally, the article presents some arguments about the importance of phenomenology in the social science framework. The possibilities of phenomenology for “real” research in social sciences are noted.
Article
Introduction: Acquaintance and Intentionality.- One: The Experience of Acquaintance.- I: Perceptual Awareness.- II: Consciousness and Self-Awareness.- III: Empathy and Other-Awareness.- Two: The Relation of Acquaintance.- IV: Content in Context.- V: A Sense of Presence.- VI: Grounds of Acquaintance.- Index of Names.- Index of Topics.
Book
The abstract for this document is available on CSA Illumina.To view the Abstract, click the Abstract button above the document title.
Part-Whole The Cambridge Companion to Husserl
  • K Fine
Husserl's Notion of Intentionality The Logical Foundations of Cognition
  • D Føllesdal
Die Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie
  • M Heidegger
Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy, Nijhoff, The Hague, German original: 1913, Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie
  • E Husserl
Im übertragenen Sinne” – Zur Theorie der Metapher
  • W Künne
Meaning and Language The Cambridge Companion to Husserl
  • P Simons
The Background of Thought
  • B Stroud