ArticlePDF Available

Abstract and Figures

Newly hatched domestic chicks were reared with five identical objects. On days 3 or 4, chicks underwent free-choice tests in which sets of three and two of the five original objects disappeared (either simultaneously or one by one), each behind one of two opaque identical screens. Chicks spontaneously inspected the screen occluding the larger set (experiment 1). Results were confirmed under conditions controlling for continuous variables (total surface area or contour length; experiment 2). In the third experiment, after the initial disappearance of the two sets (first event, FE), some of the objects were visibly transferred, one by one, from one screen to the other (second event, SE). Thus, computation of a series of subsequent additions or subtractions of elements that appeared and disappeared, one by one, was needed in order to perform the task successfully. Chicks spontaneously chose the screen, hiding the larger number of elements at the end of the SE, irrespective of the directional cues provided by the initial (FE) and final (SE) displacements. Results suggest impressive proto-arithmetic capacities in the young and relatively inexperienced chicks of this precocial species.
Content may be subject to copyright.
doi: 10.1098/rspb.2009.0044
, 2451-2460 first published online 1 April 2009276 2009 Proc. R. Soc. B
Rosa Rugani, Laura Fontanari, Eleonora Simoni, Lucia Regolin and Giorgio Vallortigara
Arithmetic in newborn chicks
References http://rspb.royalsocietypublishing.org/content/276/1666/2451.full.html#ref-list-1
This article cites 49 articles, 8 of which can be accessed free
Subject collections
(1061 articles)evolution (192 articles)cognition (770 articles)behaviour
Articles on similar topics can be found in the following collections
Email alerting service hereright-hand corner of the article or click
Receive free email alerts when new articles cite this article - sign up in the box at the top
http://rspb.royalsocietypublishing.org/subscriptions go to: Proc. R. Soc. BTo subscribe to
This journal is © 2009 The Royal Society
on 1 October 2009rspb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
Arithmetic in newborn chicks
Rosa Rugani
1,
*, Laura Fontanari
1
, Eleonora Simoni
2
, Lucia Regolin
2
and Giorgio Vallortigara
1
1
Center for Mind/Brain Sciences, University of Trento, Corso Bettini 31, 38068 Rovereto, Italy
2
Department of General Psychology, University of Padova, 35122 Padova, Italy
Newly hatched domestic chicks were reared with five identical objects. On days 3 or 4, chicks underwent
free-choice tests in which sets of three and two of the five original objects disappeared (either
simultaneously or one by one), each behind one of two opaque identical screens. Chicks spontaneously
inspected the screen occluding the larger set (experiment 1). Results were confirmed under conditions
controlling for continuous variables (total surface area or contour length; experiment 2). In the third
experiment, after the initial disappearance of the two sets (first event, FE), some of the objects were visibly
transferred, one by one, from one screen to the other (second event, SE). Thus, computation of a series of
subsequent additions or subtractions of elements that appeared and disappeared, one by one, was needed
in order to perform the task successfully. Chicks spontaneously chose the screen, hiding the larger number
of elements at the end of the SE, irrespective of the directional cues provided by the initial (FE) and final
(SE) displacements. Results suggest impressive proto-arithmetic capacities in the young and relatively
inexperienced chicks of this precocial species.
Keywords: number cognition; counting; number sense; arithmetic; addition; subtraction
1. INTRODUCTION
Only human adults would be considered capable of
counting if numerical and language abilities were
considered to be strictly correlated with one another
(Dehaene 1997;Butterworth 1999;Spelke & Dehaene
1999;Hauser & Spelke 2004). Although this is likely to be
correct for symbolic mathematical capacity (Carey 2004),
recent evidence from clinical neuropsychology suggests a
remarkable degree of independence of mathematical
cognition from language grammar in human adults
(Varley et al. 2005; see also Butterworth et al. 2008).
Moreover, numerical competences have recently been
demonstrated in a variety of species (for mammalian and
bird species, see Hauser et al. 2000;Hauser & Carey 2003;
Lyon 2003;Judge et al. 2005;Pepperberg & Gordon
2005;Beran et al.2006; Cantlon & Brannon 2006a,b,2007;
Pepperberg 2006;Addessi et al. 2008;Rugani et al. 2008).
Animals and human infants are even capable of some
simple arithmetic, such as addition and subtraction
(reviews in Gallistel 1990;Dehaene 1997;Spelke &
Dehaene 1999;Brannon & Roitman 2003).
Some of these studies employed choice paradigms
involving very little or no specific numerical training.
Chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) presented with two sets of
two food wells, each of which contained a number
of chocolates, selected the pair of quantities whose sum
was greater than the sum of the other pair (Rumbaugh
et al. 1987). To choose the sets of larger overall quantity,
the chimpanzees had to add up the number of chocolates
in each set and then compare the two resulting values.
Chimpanzees solved the task even when, on the critical
trial, the correct set of wells did not contain the larger
single value, demonstrating that performance was not
based on choosing the largest single amount (Rumbaugh
et al. 1988).
Other studies employed specific training on symbols
representing numbers. Washburn & Rumbaugh (1991)
trained two rhesus monkeys (Macaca mulatta) to choose
between two Arabic numbers presented on a touch-
sensitive screen. As a reward, the animals received the
corresponding number of pellets to the number they had
selected. Monkeys always chose the larger number even
when they were presented with new combinations of
numbers. A similar paradigm was used to test squirrel
monkeys (Saimiri sciureus) on tasks requiring them to
choose between pairs or triplets of Arabic numerals.
Monkeys chose the larger sum and their performance
could neither be attributed to choosing the largest single
value nor to avoiding the single smallest value (Olthof et al.
1997). Evidence on symbolic training has been reported
for apes, e.g. chimpanzees (P. troglodytes;Beran &
Rumbaugh 2001).
Using the methodology of the violation of expectancy,
Wynn (1992) showed that five-month-old infants can
solve some simple arithmetic operations. The idea was
that, if infants keep track of the numbers of toys they see
being placed behind a screen, they should look longer at
the screen that, once lowered, violates their expectations
revealing an unexpected outcome. For example, in the
1C1Z2 task, one object was placed on a stage, covered
by the screen, and then another object was introduced
behind the screen. When the screen was removed, infants
looked longer at the ‘impossible’ outcomes of either one
object or three objects, suggesting that infants expected to
see exactly two objects. In the original study, continuous
variables such as volume or surface area were not
controlled for, thus infants might well have attended to
Proc. R. Soc. B (2009) 276, 2451–2460
doi:10.1098/rspb.2009.0044
Published online 1 April 2009
*Author for correspondence (rosa.r ugani@unipd.it; rosa.rugani
@unitn.it.
Received 9 January 2009
Accepted 11 March 2009 2451 This journal is q2009 The Royal Society
on 1 October 2009rspb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
the volume, area or contour length of the objects rather
than to their actual number. Wynn’s results, however,
were then replicated by subsequent studies in which
continuous variables were at least partially controlled for.
Simon et al. (1995) replicated Wynn’s paradigm, but used
‘Elmo’ dolls in the initial phase of the trials and then
surreptitiously replaced ‘Elmo’ dolls with ‘Ernie’ dolls.
The infants’ expectations were not violated by this identity
switch. They looked longer only at the numerically
unexpected outcome and not at the identity of the
outcome. This indicates that, in some sense, infants
represent the number of objects stripped of their non-
numerical features. Moreover, they do so even across
sensory modalities. Five-month-old infants underwent
preliminary familiarization trials in which tones were
paired with objects, thereby, they learned to associate the
two events. At test, the infants were presented alternatively
with two types of arithmetic events: the expected, correct
outcome operations (one objectCone toneZtwo objects;
and one objectCtwo tonesZthree objects) or the
unexpected, incorrect ones (one objectCtwo tonesZtwo
objects; and one objectCone toneZthree objects). Infants
looked longer at the unexpected outcomes rather than at
the expected ones (Kobayashi et al. 2004).
Wynn’s paradigm was also adapted to test arithmetic
reasoning in rhesus monkeys (M. mulatta). Subjects
viewed food items. A screen was then raised to obscure
the items on the stage. Some items were then added or
removed from behind the screen. Finally, the screen was
lowered to reveal an expected or unexpected number of
objects and looking time was measured. Monkeys looked
longer when the unexpected outcome was revealed for
1C1Z1 or 2 and 2K1Z1 or 2 operations (Hauser et al.
1996), even when continuous variables, such as volume
and surface area were partially controlled for ( Hauser &
Carey 2003). Cotton-top tamarins (Saguinus oedipus) and
lemurs (Eulemur fulvus,Eulemur mongoz,Lemur catta and
Varecia rubra), if presented with the 1C1 operation,
looked longer at the unexpected outcome of 3 or 1
compared with the expected value of 2, demonstrating
that subjects expected ‘exactly 2’ (Uller et al. 2001;Santos
et al. 2005). Also, using a choice measure, expressed by
reaching rather than looking time, Sulkowski & Hauser
(2001) have shown that rhesus monkeys are remarkably
precise at calculating the outcome of subtraction
operations for small numbers up to 3. Even domestic
dogs have been shown to be capable of solving simple
additions such as 1C1Z2 rather than 1 or 3 ( West &
Young 2002). In all these studies, regardless of the
paradigm employed, participants were able to compute
the correct outcome of simple arithmetic operations
whenever both sets were small (upper limit of 4 for adult
rhesus monkeys and upper limit of 3 for human babies),
but failed whenever any of the sets exceeded such limit:
rhesus monkeys failed at three versus eight ( Hauser et al.
2000); infants failed at 2 versus 4, 3 versus 6, 1 versus 4
and even 0 versus 4 (Feigenson & Carey 2005). Never-
theless, several other studies showed that animals succeed
when dealing with large as well as small sets. Rhesus
monkeys (Brannon & Terrace 1998,2000), socially
housed hamadryas baboons, socially housed squirrel
monkeys (Papio hamadnjas,Saimiri sciureus;Smith et al.
2003) and brown capuchin monkeys (Cebus apella;Judge
et al. 2005) trained to order numerosities from 1 to 4,
could then generalize to numbers from 5 to 9. Monkeys
trained to respond (in ascending or descending order) to
pairs of numerosities (1–9) spontaneously ordered in the
same direction new pairs of larger values (i.e. 10, 15, 20,
30; Cantlon & Brannon 2006b). Chimpanzees were able
to summate different sets of food items and to select the
larger quantities in the comparison 5 versus 8; 5 versus
10 and 6 versus 10 (Beran & Beran 2004) and 2C2C3
versus 3C4C1(Beran 2001). Monkeys could also sum
different numbers of dots and select the correct response
in a matching-to-sample task even when large numer-
osities were employed (Cantlon & Brannon 2007).
The present study aimed at extending comparative
research on the spontaneous representation of number to
very young birds, employing filial imprinting to familiarize
the animals with a certain number of elements (see
Vallortigara (2004,2006) for general reviews on the use of
imprinting as a tool for comparative cognitive investi-
gation). Thus, no specific numerical training was
performed and the results obtained allow some con-
clusions to be drawn on the spontaneous ability of animals
to deal with simple arithmetic tasks. Moreover, the use of
very young and inexperienced animals may enlighten us
with regard to core knowledge mechanisms (Spelke 2000,
2003) in the vertebrate brain, in particular, concerning the
extent to which arithmetic capacities depend on acquired
experience versus inborn predispositions (for similar
research in the domain of geometry cognition see
Vallortigara (in press a,b)).
2. EXPERIMENT 1
Chicks were required to identify the larger between a set
of two and a set of three elements (i.e. small balls, all
identical) by walking to the location where such sets had
been seen to disappear. Chicks have been shown capable
of rejoining a social goal (a single imprinting ball) in the
correct spatial location up to 180 s from its disappearance
(Vallortigara et al. 1998;Regolin et al. 2005a,b). Here,
chicks were expected to approach the larger set because,
in simultaneous free-choice tests when both choice
sets were visible, these birds have been shown to prefer
the larger set of imprinting objects, irrespective of the
number of elements that they had been exposed to during
imprinting (Rugani et al. submitted). Rugani and
colleagues tested chicks for their sensitivity to number
versus continuous extent of artificial objects they had
been reared with. When objects used during exposure
were all identical to each other and were also identical to
the objects used at test, chicks faced with choices between
different numerosities (i.e. 1 versus 2 or 2 versus 3
objects) chose the set of larger numerosity, irrespective of
the number of objects they had been reared with. When
chicks were reared with objects of different aspect
(colour, size and shape) and then tested with completely
novel objects (of different colour and shape but
controlled for continuous extent), they chose to associate
with the set of objects comprising the same number of
elements they had been reared with during imprinting.
Note,however,thatinthestudy presented here,
the choice could not be based on direct perceptual
cues associated with visible elements, but must have
relied on the memory of the disappeared sets and of
their spatial position.
2452 R. Rugani et al. Arithmetic in newborn chicks
Proc. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 1 October 2009rspb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
(a)Materials and methods
(i) Subjects and rearing conditions
Subjects were 17 female ‘hybro’ (a local variety derived
from the white leghorn breed) domestic chicks (Gallus
gallus), obtained weekly from a local commercial hatchery
(Agricola Berica, Montegalda, Vicenza, Italy) when they
were only a few hours old. On arrival at the laboratory,
chicks were immediately housed singly in standard metal
home cages (28 cm wide!32 cm long!40 cm high) at
controlled temperature (28–318C) and humidity (68%),
with food and water available ad libitum in transparent
glass jars (5 cm in diameter, 5 cm high) placed at each
corner of the home cage. The cages were constantly
(24 h d
K1
) lit by fluorescent lamps (36 W), located 45 cm
above each cage. Each chick was placed in one cage
together with a set of five identical rounded objects
made of yellow plastic. Each object was a ‘Kinder surprise’
capsule (Ferrero S.P.A. Alba, Cuneo, Italy) measuring
4!3!3 cm, which we will hereafter refer to as a ‘ball’.
Previous studies have shown that this kind of object is very
effective in producing social attachment through filial
imprinting in this strain of chicks ( Vallortigara & Andrew
1991). The five balls placed in each cage constituted the
chicks’ imprinting stimulus and were each suspended in
the centre of the cage by a fine thread, at approximately
4–5 cm from the floor, so that they were all located at
about chicks’ head height.
Chicks were reared in these conditions from the
morning (11.00) of the first day (i.e. Monday, the day of
their arrival, which was considered as day 1) to the third
day (Wednesday). All chicks underwent two testing
phases. In the morning (11.00) of day 3, chicks underwent
the training, and approximately 1 hour later, they took
part in the first testing session. A second testing session
took place in the morning (09.00) of day 4.
(ii) Apparatus
Training and testing took place in an experimental room
located near the rearing room. In the experimental room,
temperature and humidity were controlled (respectively,
at 258C and 70%). The room was kept dark, except for
the light coming from a 40 W lamp placed approximately
80 cm above the centre of the apparatus. The testing
apparatus (figure 1) consisted of a circular arena (95 cm
in diameter and 30 cm outer wall height) with the floor
uniformly covered by a white plastic sheet. Within
the arena, adjacent to the outer wall, was a holding box
(10!20!20 cm), in which each subject was confined
shortly before the beginning of each trial. The box was
made of opaque plastic sheets, with an open top allowing
the insertion of the chick before each trial. The side of the
holding box facing the centre of the arena consisted of
a removable clear glass partition (20!10 cm), in such a
way that the subjects, while confined, could see the centre
of the arena. During the training phase, a single opaque
cardboard screen (16!8 cm; with 3 cm sides bent back
to prevent the chicks from spotting the hidden ball) was
used, positioned in the centre of the arena, in front of and
35 cm away from the front of the holding box. During
testing, two opaque cardboard screens (16!8cm),
identical in colour and pattern (i.e. blue coloured with
a yellow ‘X’ on them), were positioned in the centre of
the arena, symmetrically with respect to the front of the
confining box (i.e. 35 cm away from it and 20 cm apart
from one another).
(iii) Procedure
Training
On day 3 of life, in the morning, chicks underwent a
preliminary training session. Each chick, together with
a single ball, identical to one of the five balls constituting
the chick’s imprinting object, was placed within the testing
arena, in front of one of the screens. The ball was held
from above by the experimenter (not visible to the chick),
via a fine thread, and kept between the holding box and the
screen. The chick was left free to move around and get
acquainted with the environment for approximately
5 min. Thereafter, the experimenter slowly moved the
ball towards the screen, and then behind it, until the ball
disappeared from the chick’s sight. This procedure was
repeated a few times, until the chick responded by
following and rejoining the ball behind the screen.
Thereafter, the chick was confined within the holding
box, from where it could see the ball being moved behind
the screen. As soon as the ball had completely disappeared
from sight, the chick was set free in the arena by lifting the
transparent frontal partition. Every time the chick rejoined
the ball, as a reward, it was allowed to spend a few seconds
with it. The whole procedure was restarted and the
training ended when the chick had rejoined the ball three
consecutive times. On average, approximately 15 min
were required to complete the training for each chick.
Testing
During testing, the chick was confined to the holding box,
behind the transparent partition, from where it could see
the two screens positioned in the arena. The chick was
shown two sets of elements, one made of three of the five
imprinting balls and the other made of two such balls
(placed at first at approx. 10 cm from the front of the
holding box containing the chick). Both sets disappeared,
each behind one of the two screens. Immediately after
the disappearance of both sets (with a delay of 5 s), the
transparent partition was removed and the chick was left
free to move around and search for its imprinting balls
within the arena. To prevent the chicks from seeing the
hidden balls before having circled almost completely
Figure 1. The test apparatus employed in all of the
experiments described. The holding box is visible to the left,
both screens are present, as during the test phase. One ball is
visible behind one of the screens.
Arithmetic in newborn chicks R. Rugani et al. 2453
Proc. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 1 October 2009rspb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
around the screen, the screens were provided with 3 cm
bent back edges on the two vertical sides. A choice was
defined as when the chick’s head had entered the area
behind one of the two screens (beyond the side edges),
only the choice for the first screen visited was scored and
thereafter the trial was considered over. At the end of each
trial, chicks were allowed to spend 1–2 s with their ‘social
companions’ behind the screen chosen by the chick. The
behaviour of the chicks was entirely video-recorded and it
was scored blind both online and later offline.
If the chick did not approach either screen within
3 min, the trial was considered null and void and it was
repeated immediately afterwards. After three consecutive
null trials, the chick was placed back within its own rearing
cage (in the presence of the imprinting balls) for
approximately 1 hour before being resubmitted to further
trials. After another three consecutive null trials, the same
procedure was repeated and if, once again, the chick
scored for the third time three consecutive null trials, it
was discarded from the experiment.
Each chick underwent two complete testing sessions of
20 valid trials each. The two test sessions differed in the
procedure by which the balls were made to disappear
behind the two screens:
Simultaneous disappearance test (SDT ). Both sets of
three and two elements were placed in the arena in front
of the chick confined in the holding box. After approxi-
mately 3 s, both sets were simultaneously made to slowly
move and disappear each behind one different screen
(the whole procedure took approx. 8–10 s).
Consecutive disappearance test (CDT ). For each trial,
each of the balls of the first set was placed singly in front of
the confined chick and then made to disappear before the
next ball was introduced in the arena. In this way, all balls
of the first set were made to disappear one by one behind
one screen, and then the same procedure was employed
for the second set. For both sets, each ball was kept for
approximately 3 s in front of the chick before making it
move and disappear behind either screen (the whole
procedure took approx. 50 s). During the disappearance
phase, the speed of motion of the items of each set was
manipulated so that it took the same total time to
disappear for the set of three and for the set of two.
Disappearance of each whole set took approximately 18 s
(i.e. 6 s for each element in the set of three and 9 s for each
element in the set of two).
For both the SDT and the CDT, the order (3–2 versus
2–3) as well as the direction (left–right) of disappearance
of the two sets was counterbalanced within each chick’s
20 test session trials.
The number of trials in which each chick chose the
screen hiding three balls (correct choice) was considered
and percentages were computed as: number of correct
choices/20!100. Parametric paired t-tests (to compare
different conditions) or one-sample t-tests (to assess
significant departures from chance level, i.e. 50%) were
used. Non-parametric statistics were performed employ-
ing the binomial test.
(b)Results and discussion
All chicks took part in the first test administered (whether
SDT or CDT), but four chicks were discarded from the
second test (two chicks did not take part in the SDT, and
two did not take part in the CDT) due to unsatisfactory
health condition. Chicks preferentially chose the screen
hiding three balls over the screen hiding two balls both
in the SDT (nZ15; meanZ65.000, s.e.m.Z2.536;
one-sample t-test: t
14
Z5.915; p!0.001) and in the
CDT (nZ15; meanZ70.000, s.e.m.Z3.047; one-sample
t-test: t
14
Z6.564; p!0.001) trials (figure 2). There was
no statistically significant difference between correct
choices in the two testing conditions (two-sample t-test:
t
28
Z1.261; pZ0.218).
In order to assess whether the overall performance
depended on learning, occurring during testing, the
first five trials of each session were considered. Since
there was no difference between the two groups (two-
sample t-test: t
28
Z1.684, pZ0.103; SDT: nZ15, meanZ
58.667, s.e.m.Z4.563;CDT: nZ15, meanZ70.667,
s.e.m.Z5.474), data were merged and overall, chicks
preferentially chose the larger set (nZ30; meanZ64.667,
s.e.m.Z3.674; one-sample t-test: t
29
Z3.992, p!0.001).
We also performed a non-parametric (binomial)
analysis on chicks’ initial performance. As this was
the chicks’ behaviour in the very first trial affected by the
response to the novelty of the situation (e.g. two screens
were present in the arena), the first three trials were
considered. Twenty-three chicks were considered success-
ful as they scored at least two correct trials within the first
three, and seven chicks were considered as unsuccessful
(they scored at least two mistaken trials out of three). The
difference (23 versus 7) was significant (binomial test, one
tail, pZ0.0026).
Chicks’ performance could not be based on the average
presentation time of the two sets of stimuli, because this
was identical in the SDT, and was equalized in the CDT.
Results confirmed that, in the absence of any specific
training, chicks spontaneously discriminated between sets
of two and three elements, preferring the larger set
(Rugani et al. submitted), and did so even when such a
discrimination must have been based on the memory of
the disappeared sets and of their relative spatial position.
3. EXPERIMENT 2
Experiment 1 showed that chicks spontaneously master
the discrimination of two versus three identical elements
after these had been hidden from view. In experiment 2,
a similar procedure was employed using new stimuli
allowing us to control for continuous variables, such as
overall area and contour length. Our hypothesis predicted
that chicks should be able to discriminate 2 versus
3 independently of the use of such variables, since such
0
10
20
30
40
50
60
70
80
90
100
SDT CDT
correct responses (%)
Figure 2. Results of experiment 1. Percentage of correct
responses (group meansCs.e.m.) scored by chicks that
underwent the SDT or the CDT. The dashed line ( yZ50)
represents chance level.
2454 R. Rugani et al. Arithmetic in newborn chicks
Proc. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 1 October 2009rspb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
discrimination would still be possible when operating
within a system computing small numerosities (Hauser &
Spelke 2004). However, some doubt has been raised
recently as to whether human infants and non-human
animals really compute numerosity: when number is
pitted against continuous dimensions correlating with
number (e.g. area and contour length), infants sometimes
respond to continuous physical dimensions (Feigenson
et al. 2002a,b). Nevertheless, it has been shown that
monkeys are able to compute number rather than other
dimensions in a matching-to-sample numerical task
(Cantlon & Brannon 2007). That is not to say that
preverbal infants cannot respond to number themselves,
but that they do so only sometimes. For instance, when
objects to be discriminated belong to a domain in
which the continuous extent is especially relevant, such
as food, infants indeed tend to respond to the overall
amount rather than to number ( Feigenson et al. 2002a,b).
But, when the task requires reaching for individual
objects, number encoding prevails over physical extent
(Feigenson 2005). Using conditioning procedures, even
newborn chicks are able to discriminate small sets of
elements on the basis of number when both area and
contour length are controlled for (Rugani et al. 2008).
(a)Materials and methods
(i) Subjects
Subjects were a new group of 16 female domestic chicks.
Rearing conditions were identical to those described for
the first experiment.
(ii) Stimuli
Imprinting stimuli were identical for all chicks and
consisted of a set of five identical, two-dimensional
(approx. 1 mm thick), red plastic squares (4!4 cm).
Test stimuli also consisted of red squares, identical in
material and colour to those used for imprinting, but
differing in their dimensions in each of three control
groups. In the two-dimensional stimuli control group
(nZ7), the original dimensions of the stimuli were
maintained, so that the single squares were all identical
in the sets of three and two elements. This control was
aimed at determining whether chicks responded to two-
dimensional imprinting stimuli in the same way as they did
to the solid objects in experiment 1. Both in the contour
length (nZ5) and in the area (nZ4) control groups, the
set of two elements comprised squares of dimensions
identical to those used during imprinting, while the set of
three elements comprised smaller sized squares. The
dimensions of each square in the set of three elements
were computed in order to equate the overall contour
length (with squares measuring 2.66!2.66 cm each) or
the overall area (with squares measuring 3.26!3.26 cm
each) in the two sets. The overall time of disappearance
of the two sets was equalized as detailed in §2a(iii).
(iii) Procedure
The apparatus, the general training and testing procedures
were identical to those described in the CDT of the
previous experiment, with each chick undergoing 20 test
trials on day 3.
(b)Results and discussion
No difference (F
2,13
Z1.824; pZ0.200) emerged at an
analysis of variance (ANOVA) comparing the percentage
of correct responses emitted by the three groups of chicks
(two-dimensional stimuli control group: nZ7, meanZ
67.143, s.e.m.Z1.844; contour length control group:
nZ5, meanZ62.000, s.e.m.Z2.000; and area control
group: nZ4, meanZ63.750, s.e.m.Z3.750). Data were
therefore merged, and the resulting mean (nZ16,
meanZ64.688, s.e.m.Z1.405) was significantly above
chance level (one-sample t-test: t
15
Z10.454, p!0.001).
When analysing chicks’ initial performance (consid-
ering the first three trials, as described for the data of
experiment 1), a statistically significant difference was
found as 13 chicks out of 16 were successful (binomial
test, one tail, pZ0.0106).
Chicks preferentially chose the screen hiding the set
of three elements in all conditions.
Results confirmed the ability of chicks to discriminate
sets of 2 versus 3 elements selectively preferring the
larger set even when such discrimination must be based on
the actual number of the non-visible sets of objects and
was not based on differences in continuous variables, such
as contour length, area or time of disappearance.
4. EXPERIMENT 3
In the third experiment, we checked whether chicks can
also update their representation of the sets of stimuli by
processing subsequent events. After the initial disap-
pearance of the two sets of elements (similarly to the
previous experiments), some of the elements were visibly
transferred from behind one screen to behind the other
one. Such condition should represent a more challenging
task than those of the previous experiments, since
the chicks’ final choice would now depend on correctly
taking into account a series of subsequent displacements.
The possible cues provided by the order of disappear-
ance of stimuli in guiding chicks’ discrimination were
controlled for.
(a)Materials and methods
(i) Subjects
Subjects were a new group of 19 female domestic chicks.
Rearing conditions were identical to those described for
the previous experiments.
(ii) Procedure
Apparatus, general training and testing procedures were
the same described for the previous experiments. At test,
one ball at a time was placed in the arena and was slowly
moved towards and behind one screen. The procedure
was repeated for all five balls in such a way that a different
number of them (depending on the experimental con-
dition, see below) was eventually concealed behind either
screen. This disappearance phase constituted the first
event (FE). Approximately 5 s after the last ball had
disappeared, and while the chick was still confined to the
holding box, some of the concealed balls were slowly and
visibly moved (one ball at a time) from one screen towards
and behind the other screen (second event, SE). After a
delay of 5 s from the end of the SE, the chick was released
in the arena. Regardless of the balls position after the FE,
all four tests provided, as a result of the SE, a final
Arithmetic in newborn chicks R. Rugani et al. 2455
Proc. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 1 October 2009rspb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
comparison of two versus three balls. Chicks performed a
correct choice when approaching the screen hiding the
three elements.
Each chick underwent only one of two different
test conditions:
FE controlled (FEC )(nZ8). In order to choose the
screen hiding the larger amount, i.e. the three balls,
the chicks entering this condition would need to
choose against the cue provided by the initial
displacement of the balls. In fact, at the end of the
FE, the larger set was located behind the screen
which hid two balls at the end of the SE (i.e. the
wrong one). This was obtained in two different
manners: ‘(4K2) versus (1C2)’ and ‘(5K3) versus
(0C3)’ (the names refer to the events taking place at
the correct screen).
—(4K2) versus (1C2). The chicks (nZ4) saw four
balls disappearing behind one screen and the
remaining one disappearing behind the other
screen. Subsequently, two balls moved from the
screen hiding four balls to the other screen. At
the end, the screen initially hiding one ball only,
hid three balls and represented the correct choice
(figure 3a).
—(5K3) versus (0C3). In front of the chicks (nZ4),
five balls disappeared behind one screen and none
disappeared behind the other screen. Then, the
chick saw three balls that moved from the screen
hiding the group of five, to the other screen.
Therefore, the screen initially hiding no balls,
at the end hid three balls and constituted the
correct choice.
Last event controlled (LEC )(nZ11). The SE now
involved a movement from the screen that was to be
considered as correct (hiding the larger number of
elements) to the wrong screen (hiding the smaller
number of elements). Therefore, in order to choose
the correct screen chicks would need to choose
against the directional cue provided by the final visible
displacement. This was obtained in two different
manners: ‘(4K1) versus (1C1)’ and ‘(5K2) versus
(0C2)’ (again, the names refer to the events taking
place at the correct screen).
—(4K1) versus (1C1). Chicks (nZ7) saw four balls
disappear behind one screen and the remaining
one behind the other screen. Then, one ball moved
from the group of four to the other screen.
Therefore, the screen initially hiding four balls
now hid three balls and represented the correct
choice (figure 3b).
—(5K2) versus (0C2). Chicks (nZ4) saw five balls
disappear behind one screen and none behind the
other. Two balls were then moved from the group
(a)
(i) (ii) (i) (ii)
(iii)
(v) (v)
(iv) (iii) (iv)
(b)
Figure 3. Schematic representing, from the perspective of the confined chick, the events occurring in experiment 3 within:
(a) one possible trial of the FEC test (in the ‘(4K2) versus (1C2)’ condition, see text); (b) one possible trial of the last event
controlled test (in the ‘(4K1) versus (1C1)’ condition, see text). (a(i)) FE: one ball is hidden behind one screen. (ii) Four balls
are hidden—one by one—behind the other screen. The sequence of events and the directions were randomized between trials.
(iii) At the end of the first displacement either four or one ball(s) are hidden behind each screen. (iv) SE: two balls move—one by
one—from the screen hiding four to the one hiding a single ball. (v) Test: the chick is released in the arena and should rejoin the
larger number of imprinting balls, which is NOT behind the screen where the larger number of balls had initially disappeared.
(b(i)) FE: one ball is hidden behind one screen. (ii) Four balls are hidden—one by one—behind the other screen. The sequence
of events and the directions were randomized between trials. (iii) At the end of the first displacement either four or one ball(s) are
hidden behind each screen. (iv) SE: one ball moves from the screen hiding four to the one hiding a single ball. (v) Test: the chick
is released in the arena and should rejoin the larger number of imprinting balls, which is NOT behind the screen where the final
hiding of balls has been observed.
2456 R. Rugani et al. Arithmetic in newborn chicks
Proc. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 1 October 2009rspb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
of five to the other screen. Therefore, the screen
initially hiding five balls now hid three balls and
constituted the correct choice.
For both conditions (FEC and LEC), whenever the
initial displacement involved two hiding events (i.e. four
balls going behind one screen and one (or two) ball(s)
going behind the other screen), the order of such events
(i.e. which one occurred before and which after the other)
was counterbalanced throughout the 20 testing trials
administered to each chick, as well as the left–right
direction of the disappearance of the two sets. Sets’
disappearance times could not be equalized in this
experiment due to procedural contingencies (e.g. one
set disappeared in one direction and no elements
disappeared in the opposite direction).
Each chick underwent one single testing session
(20 trials). For each chick and for each group, the mean
percentage of choices of the screen hiding three elements
were computed. Non-parametric statistics were per-
formed employing the binomial test.
(b)Results and discussion
Results are represented in figure 4.
(i) FE controlled
No significant difference (two-sample t-test: t
6
Z0.785;
pZ0.463) was found between the groups: (4K2) versus
(1C2) (nZ4, meanZ78.750, s.e.m.Z3.750) and (5K3)
versus (0C3) (nZ4, meanZ73.750, s.e.m.Z5.154).
Overall (nZ8, meanZ76.250, s.e.m.Z3.098) chicks
significantly chose the screen hiding the larger number
of elements (one-sample t-test: t
7
Z8.473, p!0.001).
When limiting the analysis to the first five test trials, no
statistically significant difference was found between the
two conditions (two-sample t-test: t
6
Z0.522, pZ0.620).
Overall, chicks significantly approached, from the very
beginning of the test, the screen hiding the larger set at
the end of the SE (nZ8, meanZ77.500, s.e.m.Z4.531;
one-sample t-test: t
7
Z6.069, p!0.001).
(ii) LE controlled
No significant difference (two-sample t-test: t
10
Z1.053;
pZ0.317) was found between the (4K1) versus (1C1)
(nZ7, meanZ76.586, s.e.m.Z2.978) and the (5K2)
versus (0C2) (nZ5, meanZ71.556, s.e.m.Z3.826)
conditions. Overall, chicks preferentially chose the correct
screen (nZ12, meanZ74.490, s.e.m.Z2.366; one-
sample t-test: t
11
Z10.347, p!0.001).
When limiting the analysis to the first five test trials,
no difference was found (two-sample t-test: t
10
Z0.078;
pZ0.938) between the two test conditions. Overall, chicks
significantly preferred the correct screen even within the
first five test trials (nZ12, meanZ76.667, s.e.m.Z4.820;
one-sample t-test: t
11
Z5.533; p!0.001).
There was no difference between FEC and LEC
conditions (two-sample t-test: t
18
Z0.458; pZ0.652).
Chicks selectively approached the screen hiding the
larger number of elements (nZ20, meanZ75.194,
s.e.m.Z1.843; one-sample t-test: t
19
Z13.667;
p!0.001). Their response was based neither on the first
site, where the larger number of objects had been seen to
disappear, nor on the most recent directional cue provided
by the very last displacement.
When chicks’ initial performance was analysed with
non-parametric statistics (considering the first three trials,
as described for the data of experiment 1), the difference
between successful and unsuccessful chicks (i.e. 13 out
of 19) was marginally non-significant (binomial test, one
tail, pZ0.0835). We expected chicks’ performance to be
worse in experiment 3, as the conditions were much
harder than those of the previous experiments. Never-
theless, when analysing chicks’ overall scores in the 20
trials, and considering successful any chick that took at
least 14 out of 20 (binomial test, one tail, pZ0.0577)
correct trials, then overall 14 out of 19 chicks were
successful (binomial test, one tail, pZ0.0318).
It should be pointed out that, although chicks were
choosing against the initial or the final events, they must
have properly computed such events in order to make a
correct final choice.
5. GENERAL DISCUSSION
The results of experiments 1 and 2 showed that, in the
absence of any specific training, chicks spontaneously
discriminated between two and three, in both cases
preferring the larger stimulus set. The discrimination
was based on the memory of the spatial position of the
disappeared objects, since any direct assessment of
the sensory stimuli associated with the two sets was not
possible at the time when chicks were allowed to choose
between the two screens. Hence chicks’ behaviour seemed
to indicate an ability to perform additions, i.e. combining
two or more quantitative representations (addends) to
form a new representation (i.e. the sum).
Quite interestingly, the discrimination held for both
the simultaneous disappearance of all the elements of a
set of stimuli as well as for the one-by-one (i.e. sequential)
disappearance of the single elements of the set. Indeed,
the performance tended to be slightly better in the latter
case, although this difference could not be due to cues
provided by differences in the time of disappearance of
the two sets as this variable had been equalized in the
first two experiments.
The results of experiment 2 showed that discrimination
was based on the number, and not on the continuous
physical variables that may covary with number, such as
area, contour length or time of disappearance during
stimuli presentation. Evidence has been reported that
when the number is pitted against continuous dimensions
that correlate with number (e.g. area and contour length),
infants sometimes seem to respond to continuous physical
dimensions (Feigenson et al. 2002a,b). Nonetheless,
0
10
20
30
40
50
60
70
80
90
100
FEC LEC
correct responses (%)
Figure 4. Results of experiment 3. Percentage of correct
responses (group meansCs.e.m.) shown by chicks that
underwent the FEC or the LEC conditions. The dashed
line ( yZ50) represents chance level.
Arithmetic in newborn chicks R. Rugani et al. 2457
Proc. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 1 October 2009rspb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
evidence has been collected showing that human infants
also encode discrete numbers as well as continuous extent
(Feigenson & Carey 2003). It seems that when the objects
in an array differ in their individual characteristics (such as
colour, shape, texture), infants rely on the number rather
than spatial extent, whereas the reverse is true for sets of
homogeneous objects ( Feigenson 2005). Somewhat
similar results were obtained in the study by Rugani
et al.(submitted; see §2) in which chicks, were directly
facing the two sets of objects while choosing between them
at test, so that encoding them as a homogeneous or
heterogeneous array of elements was perceptually appa-
rent. In the task studied here, by contrast, summation and
subtraction required an updating of stored memory
representations of small arrays that were no longer visible.
Updating of stored representations by chicks is
particularly impressive in experiment 3. Here, after the
initial disappearance of the two sets of objects behind both
screens, some of the objects were again visibly transferred
from one screen to the other before the chick was allowed
to search. Thus, an initial addition and a subsequent
subtraction of elements were needed in order to determine
the screen hiding the larger number of elements at the end
of the two events. Chicks correctly chose the screen hiding
the larger number of elements irrespective of the
directional cues provided by the initial or final movement
of the elements.
Human infants seem to show a failure when an exact
numerical representation has to include more than three
objects (review in Hauser & Spelke 2004). A signature
limit similar to that described for young infants has been
reported for adult monkeys ( Hauser & Spelke 2004), and
it was also observed in chicks, although in a different
task and on animals a few days older than those used here
(Rugani et al. 2008). In the present study, however,
chicks seem to go beyond such a limit, for, in order
to perform the arithmetic discriminations described in
experiment 3, they must have represented five distinct
individuals exactly.
It can be speculated that altricial and precocial species
may differ in signature limits (or in their timing of
appearance in life) in exact numerical representations.
Moreover, the signature limit may be task specific, in
the sense that it is shaped by the specific demands of the
ecological conditions in which a certain numerical
computation has evolved. If so, we could perhaps expect
that chicks’ signature limits would be defined by their
typical brood size (i.e. approx. 8–10 siblings).
The capacities exhibited by young chicks appear to
be really noteworthy, particularly considering that, in
the very brief period of rearing that preceded testing, the
animals had no possibility to experience the sorts of events
they were faced with at test, since the chicks were reared
singly with the suspended balls (and without any
experience of occluding surfaces in their home cage). We
cannot exclude of course that, over their first days of life,
chicks experience (in their home cage) would contribute to
some familiarization with quantity manipulation. Besides
the imprinting objects, chicks in their home cages were
exposed to food, water and the dishes. For example, chicks
may learn that the level of chicks’ starter food decreases
over the time spent eating. Nevertheless, we regard it
unlikely for the chicks to experience precise computation
of actual subtraction of food elements (we see no possible
way for them to experience additions) while eating, as
their food (i.e. standard chicks’ starter crumbs) was not
made of discrete elements (as would occur, for example, if
the chicks were fed seeds), but rather of clumped
aggregate of grain flour. Moreover, although food amount
in the dish could somewhat diminish daily, new food was
constantly added so that its level was kept constant.
Chicks could apparently maintain a record of the
number of hidden objects comprising two distinct sets,
updated by arithmetic operations of addition and
subtraction computed on the basis of only the sequential
visual appearance and disappearance of single separate
objects. Models based on the idea of an operating
‘accumulator’ are common in the theoretical analyses of
how animals can perform counting in the absence of verbal
tags (Meck & Church 1983). However, to the best of our
knowledge, this is the first evidence showing that
sequential addition and subtraction can be successfully
performed by animals on the same sets.
We believe that the findings presented here provide
striking support to the ‘core knowledge’ hypothesis ( Pica
et al. 2004;Dehaene et al. 2006;Spelke & Kinzler 2007)
according to which mental representations of number (as
well as other basic representations such as those of
physical objects, animate objects and geometry) would
be in place at birth and shared among vertebrates.
All procedures were in accordance with the Italian
and European Community laws on animal research
and treatment.
The authors wish to thank Paola De Martini Di Valle Aperta
for the help provided with animal care and testing. This study
was supported by grants ‘Intellat’ and MIPAF ‘Benolat’
(to G.V.).
REFERENCES
Addessi, E., Crescimbene, L. & Visalberghi, E. 2008 Food
and token quantity discrimination in capuchin monkeys
(Cebus apella). Anim. Cogn. 11, 275–282. (doi:10.1007/
s10071-007-0111-6)
Beran, M. J. 2001 Summation and numerousness judgments
of sequentially presented sets of items by chimpanzees
(Pan troglodytes). J. Comp. Psychol. 115, 181–191. (doi:10.
1037/0735-7036.115.2.181)
Beran, M. J. & Beran, M. M. 2004 Chimpanzees remember
the results of one-by-one addition of food items to sets over
extended time periods. Psychol. Sci. 15, 94–99. (doi:10.
1111/j.0963-7214.2004.01502004.x)
Beran, M. J. & Rumbaugh, D. M. 2001 ‘Constructive’
enumeration by chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes)ona
computerized task. Anim. Cogn. 4, 81–89. (doi:10.1007/
s100710100098)
Beran, M. J., Smith, J. D., Redford, J. S. & Washburn, D. A.
2006 Rhesus macaques (Macaca mulatta) monitor uncer-
tainty during numerosity judgments. J. Exp. Psychol.
Anim. B 32, 111–119. (doi:10.1037/0097-7403.32.2.111)
Brannon, E. M. & Roitman, J. D. 2003 Nonverbal
representations of time and number in animals and
human infants. In Functional and neural mechanism of
interval timing (ed. W. H. Meck), pp. 143–182. Boca
Raton, FL: CRC Press.
Brannon, E. M. & Terrace, H. S. 1998 Ordering of the
numerosities 1–9 by monkeys. Science 282, 746–749.
(doi:10.1126/science.282.5389.746)
2458 R. Rugani et al. Arithmetic in newborn chicks
Proc. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 1 October 2009rspb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
Brannon, E. M. & Terrace, H. S. 2000 Representation of the
numerosities 1–9 by rhesus monkeys (Macaca mulatta).
J. Exp. Psychol. Anim. B 26, 31–49. (doi:10.1037/0097-
7403.26.1.31)
Butterworth, B. 1999 A head for figures. Science 284,
928–929. (doi:10.1126/science.284.5416.928)
Butterworth, B., Reeve, R., Reynolds, F. & Lloyd, D. 2008
Numerical thought with and without words: evidence
from indigenous Australian children. Proc. Natl Acad.
Sci. USA 105, 13 179–13 184. (doi:10.1073/pnas.
0806045105)
Cantlon, J. F. & Brannon, E. M. 2006aThe effect of
heterogeneity on numerical ordering in rhesus monkeys.
Infancy 9, 173–189. (doi:10.1207/s15327078in0902_5)
Cantlon, J. F. & Brannon, E. M. 2006bShared system for
ordering small and large numbers in monkeys and
humans. Psychol. Sci. 17, 401–406. (doi:10.1111/j.1467-
9280.2006.01719.x)
Cantlon, J. F. & Brannon, E. M. 2007 How much does
number matter to a monkey? J. Exp. Psychol. Anim. B 33,
32–41. (doi:10.1037/0097-7403.33.1.32)
Carey, S. 2004 Bootstrapping and the origins of concepts.
Daedalus 133, 59–68. (doi:10.1162/00115260477274
6701)
Dehaene, S. 1997 The number sense. New York, NY: Oxford
University Press.
Dehaene, S., Izard, V., Pica, P. & Spelke, E. S. 2006 Core
knowledge of geometry in an Amazonian indigene group.
Science 311, 381–384. (doi:10.1126/science.1121739)
Feigenson, L. 2005 A double dissociation in infants’
representation of object arrays. Cognition 95, B37–B48.
(doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2004.07.006)
Feigenson, L. & Carey, S. 2003 Tracking individuals via
object-files: evidence from infants’ manual search. Dev.
Sci. 6, 568–584. (doi:10.1111/1467-7687.00313)
Feigenson, L. & Carey, S. 2005 On the limits of infants’
quantification of small object arrays. Cognition 97,
295–313. (doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2004.09.010)
Feigenson, L., Carey, S. & Spelke, E. 2002aInfant’s
discrimination of number versus continous extent. Cogn.
Pychol. 44, 33–66. (doi:10.1006/cogp.2001.0760)
Feigenson, L., Carey, S. & Hauser, M. D. 2002bThe
representations underlying infants’ choice of more: object
file versus analogue magnitudes. Psychol. Sci. 13, 150–156.
(doi:10.1111/1467-9280.00427)
Gallistel, C. R. 1990 The organization of learning. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Hauser, M. D. & Carey, S. 2003 Spontaneous represen-
tations of small numbers of objects by rhesus macaques:
examinations of content and format. Cogn. Psychol. 35,
367–401. (doi:10.1016/S0010-0285(03)00050-1)
Hauser, M. D. & Spelke, E. 2004 Evolutionary and
developmental foundations of human knowledge.
In The cognitive neurosciences, III (ed. M. Gazzaniga &
sub-section ed. N. Logothetis), pp. 853–864. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Hauser, M. D., MacNeilage, P. & Ware, M. 1996 Numerical
representation in primates. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 93,
1514–1517. (doi:10.1073/pnas.93.4.1514)
Hauser, M. D., Carey, S. & Hauser, L. B. 2000 Spontaneous
number representation in semi-free-ranging rhesus mon-
keys. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B 267, 829–833. (doi:10.1098/
rspb.2000.1078)
Judge, P. G., Evans, T. A. & Vyas, D. K. 2005 Ordinal
representation of numerical quantities by brown capuchin
monkeys (Cebus apella). J. Exp. Psychol. Anim. B 31,
79–94. (doi:10.1037/0097-7403.31.1.79)
Kobayashi, T., Hiraki, K., Mugitani, R. & Hasegawa, T. 2004
Baby arithmetic: one object plus one tone. Cognition 91,
B23–B34. (doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2003.09.004)
Lyon, B. E. 2003 Egg recognition and counting reduce costs
of avian conspecific brood parasitism. Nature 422,
495–499, Letter. (doi:10.1038/32878)
Meck, W. & Church, R. 1983 A mode control model of
counting and timing processes. J. Exp. Psychol. Anim. B 9,
320–334. (doi:10.1037/0097-7403.9.3.320)
Olthof, A., Iden, C. M. & Roberts, W. A. 1997 Judgments of
ordinality and summation of number symbols by squirrel
monkeys (Saimiri sciureus). J. Exp. Psychol. Anim. B 23,
325–333. (doi:10.1037/0097-7403.23.3.325)
Pepperberg, I. M. 2006 Gray parrot (Psittacus erithacus)
numerical abilities: addition and further experiments on a
zero-like concept. J. Com. Psychol. 120, 1–11. (doi:10.
1037/0735-7036.120.1.1)
Pepperberg, I. M. & Gordon, J. D. 2005 Number compre-
hension by a gray parrot (Psittacus erithacus), including a
zero-like concept. J. Comp. Psychol. 119, 197–209. (doi:10.
1037/0735-7036.119.2.197)
Pica, P., Lemer, C., Izard, V. & Dehaene, S. 2004 Exact and
approximate arithmetic in an Amazonian indigene group.
Science 306, 499–503. (doi:10.1126/science.1102085)
Regolin, L., Garzotto, B., Rugani, R., Pagni, P. &
Vallortigara, G. 2005aWorking memory in the chick:
parallel and lateralized mechanisms for encoding of
object- and position-specific information. Behav. Brain
Res. 157, 1–9. (doi:10.1016/j.bbr.2004.06.012)
Regolin, L., Rugani, R., Pagni, P. & Vallortigara, G. 2005b
Delayed search for a social and a non-social goal object by
the young domestic chick (Gallus gallus). Anim. Behav. 70,
855–864. (doi:10.1016/j.anbehav.2005.01.014)
Rugani, R., Regolin, L. & Vallortigara, G. 2008 Discrimi-
nation of small numerosities in young chicks. J. Exp.
Psychol. Anim. B 34, 388–399. (doi:10.1037/0097-7403.
34.3.388)
Rugani, R., Regolin, L. & Vallortigara, G. Submitted.
Imprinted numbers: newborn chicks’ sensitivity to
number vs. continuous extent of objects they have been
reared with. Dev. Sci.
Rumbaugh, D. M., Savage-Rumbaugh, E. S. & Hegel, M. T.
1987 Summation in the chimpanzee (Pan troglodytes).
J. Exp. Psychol. Anim. B 13, 107–115. (doi:10.1037/0097-
7403.13.2.107)
Rumbaugh, D. M., Savage-Rumbaugh, E. S. & Pate, J. L.
1988 Addendum to ‘Summation in the chimpanzee
(Pan troglodytes)’. J. Exp. Psychol. Anim. B 14, 118–120.
(doi:10.1037/0097-7403.14.1.118)
Santos, L. R., Barnes, J. & Mahajan, N. 2005 Expectations
about numerical events in four lemur species (Eulemur
fulvus,Eulemur mongoz,Lemur catta and Varecia rubra).
Anim. Cogn. 8, 253–262. (doi:10.1007/s10071-005-
0252-4)
Simon, T. J., Hespos, S. J. & Rochat, P. 1995 Do infants
understand simple arithmetic? A replication of Wynn
(1992). Cogn. Dev. 10, 253–269. (doi:10.1016/0885-
2014(95)90011-X)
Smith, B. R., Piel, A. K. & Candland, D. K. 2003 Numerity
of a socially-housed hamadyras baboon (Papio hamadryas)
and a socially housed squirrel monkey (Saimiri sciureus).
J. Comp. Psychol. 17, 217–225. (doi:10.1037/0735-7036.
117.2.217)
Spelke, E. S. 2000 Core knowledge. Am. Psychol. 55,
1233–1243. (doi:10.1037/0003-066X.55.11.1233)
Spelke, E. S. 2003 What makes us smart? Core knowl-
edge and natural language. In Language in mind: advances in
the investigation of language and thought (eds D. Gentner &
S. Goldin-Meadow), pp. 277–311. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Spelke, E. S. & Dehaene, S. 1999 Biological foundations of
numerical thinking. Trends in Cogn. Sci. 3, 365–366.
(doi:10.1016/S1364-6613(99)01385-6)
Arithmetic in newborn chicks R. Rugani et al. 2459
Proc. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 1 October 2009rspb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
Spelke, E. S. & Kinzler, K. D. 2007 Core knowledge. Dev.
Sci. 10, 89–96. (doi:10.1111/j.1467-7687.2007.00569.x)
Sulkowski, G. & Hauser, M. D. 2001 Can rhesus monkeys
spontaneously subtract? Cognition 79, 239–262. (doi:10.
1016/S0010-0277(00)00112-8)
Uller, C., Hauser, M. & Carey, S. 2001 Spontaneous
representation of number in cotton-top tamarins.
J. Comp. Psychol. 115, 248–257. (doi:10.1037/0735-
7036.115.3.248)
Vallortigara, G. 2004 Visual cognition and representation in
birds and primates. In Vertebrate comparative cognition: are
primates superior to non-primates? (eds L J. Rogers &
G. Kaplan), pp. 57–94. New York, NY: Kluwer Academic/
Plenum Publishers.
Vallortigara, G. 2006 The cognitive chicken: visual and
spatial cognition in a non-mammalian brain. In Compara-
tive cognition: experimental explorations of animal intelligence
(eds E. A. Wasserman & T. R. Zentall), pp. 41–58. Oxford,
UK: Oxford University Press.
Vallortigara, G. In press a. Animals as natural geometers. In
Cognitive biology: evolutionary and developmental perspectives
on mind, brain and behavior (eds L. Tommasi, L. Nadel &
M. Peterson). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Vallortigara, G. In press b. Original knowledge and the two
cultures. In The two cultures: shared problems (eds E. Carafoli,
G. A. Danieli & G. O. Longo). Berlin, Germany: Springer.
Vallortigara, G. & Andrew, R. J. 1991 Lateralization of
response by chicks to change in model partner. Anim.
Behav. 41, 187–194. (doi:10.1016/S0003-3472(05)
80470-1)
Vallortigara, G., Regolin, L., Rigoni, M. & Zanforlin, M.
1998 Delayed search for a concealed imprinted object in
the domestic chick. Anim. Cogn. 1, 17–24. (doi:10.1007/
s100710050003)
Varley, R. A., Klessinger, N. J. C., Romanowski, C. A. J. &
Siegal, M. 2005 Agrammatic but numerate. Proc. Natl
Acad. Sci. USA 102, 3519–3524. (doi:10.1073/pnas.
0407470102)
Washburn, D. A. & Rumbaugh, D. M. 1991 Ordinal
judgments of Arabic symbols by macaques (Macaca
mulatta). Psychol. Sci. 2, 190–193. (doi:10.1111/j.1467-
9280.1991.tb00130.x)
West, R. E. & Young, R. J. 2002 Do domestic dogs show any
evidence of being able to count ? Anim. Cogn. 5, 183–186.
(doi:10.1007/s10071-002-0140-0)
Wynn, K. 1992 Addition and subtraction by human infants.
Nature 358, 749–750. (doi:10.1038/358749a0)
2460 R. Rugani et al. Arithmetic in newborn chicks
Proc. R. Soc. B (2009)
on 1 October 2009rspb.royalsocietypublishing.orgDownloaded from
... p = 0.01), with a higher choice for congruent combinations at the beginning of the test-starting from about 0.7 in trial 1-that progressively decreases until reaching chance level (figure 2). This is an expected outcome, as animals progressively extinguish responses to unrewarded tests [13,28,29]. Since we found a significant decrease of crossmodal associations with time, we analysed the initial 12 and final 12 trials separately [13,28,29] (figure 2b,c). ...
... This is an expected outcome, as animals progressively extinguish responses to unrewarded tests [13,28,29]. Since we found a significant decrease of crossmodal associations with time, we analysed the initial 12 and final 12 trials separately [13,28,29] (figure 2b,c). This analysis confirmed a significant crossmodal association in the initial part of the test and no significant association in the second part of the test. ...
Article
Full-text available
Humans spontaneously match information coming from different senses, in what we call crossmodal associations. For instance, high-pitched sounds are preferentially associated with small objects, and low-pitched sounds with larger ones. Although previous studies reported crossmodal associations in mammalian species, evidence for other taxa is scarce, hindering an evolutionary understanding of this phenomenon. Here, we provide evidence of pitch-size correspondence in a reptile, the tortoise Testudo hermanni. Tortoises showed a spontaneous preference to associate a small disc (i.e. visual information about size) with a high-pitch sound (i.e. auditory information) and a larger disc to a low-pitched sound. These results suggest that crossmodal associations may be an evolutionary ancient phenomenon, potentially an organizing principle of the vertebrate brain.
... This experiment has been replicated for different variables (e.g., Simon et al. 1995) and it is generally accepted that infants are indeed sensitive to numerosity, rather than another variable, such as visible surface area. Similar explicit claims of innate arithmetical ability have been made for non-human animals, such as newborn chicks (e.g., Rugani et al. 2009;Agrillo 2015). ...
Article
Full-text available
Hutto and Myin have proposed an account of radically enactive (or embodied) cognition (REC) as an explanation of cognitive phenomena, one that does not include mental representations or mental content in basic minds. Recently, Zahidi and Myin have presented an account of arithmetical cognition that is consistent with the REC view. In this paper, I first evaluate the feasibility of that account by focusing on the evolutionarily developed proto-arithmetical abilities and whether empirical data on them support the radical enactivist view. I argue that although more research is needed, it is at least possible to develop the REC position consistently with the state-of-the-art empirical research on the development of arithmetical cognition. After this, I move the focus to the question whether the radical enactivist account can explain the objectivity of arithmetical knowledge. Against the realist view suggested by Hutto, I argue that objectivity is best explained through analyzing the way universal proto-arithmetical abilities determine the development of arithmetical cognition.
... 27 When discriminating between multiple relational magnitudes, the AMS presents itself via the distance and magnitude effects, whereby discrimination improves with an increasing distance between two values and, at a given numerical distance, worsens with an increasing difference in ratio difference, respectively. Indeed, the AMS has already been well established in numerical discrimination tasks in birds, [14][15][16]28,29 primates, [30][31][32][33][34] and even elephants 35 and fish. 36,37 Most of the previous statistical inference literature has used only two reward (outcome) probabilities and has therefore been unable to examine the relationship between the AMS and statistical inference abilities. ...
Article
Statistical inference, the ability to use limited information to draw conclusions about the likelihood of an event, is critical for decision-making during uncertainty. The ability to make statistical inferences was thought to be a uniquely human skill requiring verbal instruction and mathematical reasoning.1 However, basic inferences have been demonstrated in both preliterate and pre-numerate individuals,2,3,4,5,6,7 as well as non-human primates.8 More recently, the ability to make statistical inferences has been extended to members outside of the primate lineage in birds.9,10 True statistical inference requires subjects use relative rather than absolute frequency of previously experienced events. Here, we show that crows can relate memorized reward probabilities to infer reward-maximizing decisions. Two crows were trained to associate multiple reward probabilities ranging from 10% to 90% to arbitrary stimuli. When later faced with the choice between various stimulus combinations, crows retrieved the reward probabilities associated with individual stimuli from memory and used them to gain maximum reward. The crows showed behavioral distance and size effects when judging reward values, indicating that the crows represented probabilities as abstract magnitudes. When controlling for absolute reward frequency, crows still made reward-maximizing choices, which is the signature of true statistical inference. Our study provides compelling evidence of decision-making by relative reward frequency in a statistical inference task.
... We argue that these qualitative conditions are preverbal psychological intuitions that shape our perception of the world. They are biologically based, reflecting our shared evolutionary history with nonhumans, and likely related to (or part of) "core knowledge systems" that have been studied in developmental science (Rugani et al., 2009;Spelke, 2017;Spelke & Kinzler, 2007;Spelke & Lee, 2012;Vallortigara, 2012Vallortigara, , 2017. This is fundamentally a Kantian view. ...
Article
Full-text available
Where does arithmetic come from, and why are addition and multiplication its fundamental operations? Although we know that arithmetic is true, no explanation that meets standards of scientific rigor is available from philosophy, mathematical logic, or the cognitive sciences. We propose a new approach based on the assumption that arithmetic has a biological origin: Many examples of adaptive behavior such as spatial navigation suggest that organisms can perform arithmetic-like operations on represented magnitudes. If so, these operations-nonsymbolic precursors of addition and multiplication-might be optimal due to evolution and thus identifiable according to an appropriate criterion. We frame this as a metamathematical question, and using an order-theoretic criterion, prove that four qualitative conditions-monotonicity, convexity, continuity, and isomorphism-are sufficient to identify addition and multiplication over the real numbers uniquely from the uncountably infinite class of possible operations. Our results show that numbers and algebraic structure emerge from purely qualitative conditions, and as a construction of arithmetic, provide a rigorous explanation for why addition and multiplication are its fundamental operations. We argue that these conditions are preverbal psychological intuitions or principles of perceptual organization that are biologically based and shape how humans and nonhumans alike perceive the world. This is a Kantian view and suggests that arithmetic need not be regarded as an immutable truth of the universe but rather as a natural consequence of our perception. Algebraic structure may be inherent in the representations of the world formed by our perceptual system. (PsycInfo Database Record (c) 2023 APA, all rights reserved).
... For instance, subcortical computations to support reflexive orienting of attention (exogenous) can be used to develop an endogenous system, one that can operate on symbolic inputs (Carrasco 2011;Klein and Lawrence 2011). Similarly, subcortical non-symbolic numerical computations of quantity can be exploited for the emergence of symbolic arithmetic procedures such as counting (Rugani et al. 2009;Lorenzi et al. 2021). ...
Article
Full-text available
Researchers often attribute higher cognition to the enlargement of cortical regions throughout evolution, reflecting the belief that humans sit at the top of the cognitive pyramid. Implicitly, this approach assumes that the subcortex is of secondary importance for higher-order cognition. While it is now recognized that subcortical regions can be involved in various cognitive domains, it remains unclear how they contribute to computations essential for higher-level cognitive processes such as endogenous attention and numerical cognition. Herein, we identify three models of subcortical–cortical relations in these cognitive processes: (i) subcortical regions are not involved in higher cognition; (ii) subcortical computations support elemental forms of higher cognition mainly in species without a developed cortex; and (iii) higher cognition depends on a whole-brain dynamic network, requiring integrated cortical and subcortical computations. Based on evolutionary theories and recent data, we propose the SEED hypothesis: the Subcortex is Essential for the Early Development of higher cognition. According to the five principles of the SEED hypothesis, subcortical computations are essential for the emergence of cognitive abilities that enable organisms to adapt to an ever-changing environment. We examine the implications of the SEED hypothesis from a multidisciplinary perspective to understand how the subcortex contributes to various forms of higher cognition.
... It has been proposed that this mechanism underlies the process of estimation of large sets of elements (Anobile et al., 2014;Burr & Ross, 2008;Dehaene, 2011). The ANS is also believed to be the building block for numerical development in general (Dehaene, 2009;Piazza, 2010), but is not unique to humans (Cantlon & Brannon, 2006;Rugani et al., 2009). ...
Article
Full-text available
Ponzo is a familiar name in psychology because of the illusion that takes his name. He had a long and productive career in Italy, and some of his work was translated for international journals already in his lifetime. However, few of these papers are available in English. We provide a commentary that considers how his name came to be associated with an illusion he did not discover. We explain the content of several papers, some of which are often cited in a wrong context in the literature (i.e., papers on touch mentioned in relation to the Ponzo illusion). More importantly, we discuss his contribution to the study of perceived numerosity, and provide a full translation of his important 1928 paper, including a redrawing of its 28 illustrations.
... Newborn chicks preferentially move toward larger sets of objects hidden behind screens. If objects are visibly transferred from behind one screen to the other, the chicks can keep track of which screen hides more of them, showing a kind of sensitivity to both addition and subtraction (Rugani, Fontanari, Simoni, Regolin, & Vallortigara, 2009). Similar abilities have been shown in vervet monkeys (Tsutsumi, Ushitani, & Fujita, 2011), and even in bees (Cepelewicz, 2021a;Dyer, 2019a and. ...
Book
Full-text available
This book argues that there is a joint in nature between seeing and thinking, perception, and cognition. Perception is constitutively iconic, nonconceptual, and nonpropositional, whereas cognition does not have these properties constitutively. The book does not appeal to “intuitions,” as is common in philosophy, but to empirical evidence, including experiments in neuroscience and psychology. The book argues that cognition affects perception, i.e., that perception is cognitively penetrable, but that this does not impugn the joint in nature. A key part of the argument is that we perceive not only low-level properties like colors, shapes, and textures but also high-level properties such as faces and causation. Along the way, the book explains the difference between perception and perceptual memory, the differences between format and content, and whether perception is probabilistic despite our lack of awareness of probabilistic properties. The book argues for perceptual categories that are not concepts, that perception need not be singular, that perceptual attribution and perceptual discrimination are equally fundamental, and that basic features of the mind known as “core cognition” are not a third category in between perception and cognition. The chapter on consciousness leverages these results to argue against some of the most widely accepted theories of consciousness. Although only one chapter is about consciousness, much of the rest of the book repurposes work on consciousness to isolate the scientific basis of perception.
Article
The ability to compare quantities of visual objects with two distinct measures, proportion and difference, is observed even in newborn animals. However, how this function originates in the brain, even before visual experience, remains unknown. Here, we propose a model in which neuronal tuning for quantity comparisons can arise spontaneously in completely untrained neural circuits. Using a biologically inspired model neural network, we find that single units selective to proportions and differences between visual quantities emerge in randomly initialized feedforward wirings and that they enable the network to perform quantity comparison tasks. Notably, we find that two distinct tunings to proportion and difference originate from a random summation of monotonic, nonlinear neural activities and that a slight difference in the nonlinear response function determines the type of measure. Our results suggest that visual quantity comparisons are primitive types of functions that can emerge spontaneously before learning in young brains.
Article
Preference tests remain a useful tool in the assessment of laying hen welfare and have been used to establish what types of resources and enrichments are most likely to meet the birds' needs. Evidence on the underlying structure of bird preference suggests that hens make stable and reliable choices across time and context. This means that their preferences can also be used as a benchmark in the validation of other welfare indicators. Hens have sophisticated cognitive abilities. They are quick to form associations between events and they are flexible in how they apply their knowledge in different contexts. However, they may not form expectations about the world in the same way as some mammalian species. Limited research in this area to date seems to show that hens judge situations in absolute terms rather than evaluating how a situation may be improving or deteriorating. The proportion of hens housed in cage-free systems is increasing globally, providing birds with greater behavioural freedom. Many of the problems associated with cage-free systems, such as keel bone fractures, mortality and injurious pecking, are slowly reducing due to improved experience and appropriate changes in rearing practices, diet, housing design and alignment of breeding goals. However, much remains to be done. The design and performance of veranda-based systems which provide hens with fresh air and natural light is a promising avenue for future research aimed at optimising hen welfare and improving sustainability.
Article
Full-text available
Numerical competence in 5-month-old infants is investigated using a violation-of-expectation paradigm. An experiment is reported which replicates the findings of Wynn (1992). In additional conditions, 5-month-olds are shown to be sensitive to impossible outcomes following addition or subtraction operations on small sets of objects, regardless of identity changes. Results support Wynn's interpretation that infants' responses are based on arithmetical ability. An alternative explanation, that infants' responses are based on their knowledge of the principles of physical object behavior, is also discussed.
Article
Summation and numerousness judgments by 2 chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) were investigated when 2 quantities of M&Ms were presented sequentially, and the quantities were never viewed in their totality. Each M&M was visible only before placement in 1 of 2 cups. In Experiment 1, sets of 1 to 9 M&Ms were presented. In Experiment 2, the quantities in each cup were presented as 2 smaller sets (e.g., 2 + 2 vs. 4 + 1). In Experiment 3, the quantities were presented as 3 smaller sets (e.g., 2 + 2 + 3 vs. 3 + 4 + 1). In Experiment 4, an M&M was removed from 1 set before the chimpanzees' selection. In Experiments 1 and 2, the chimpanzees selected the larger quantity on significantly more trials than would be predicted by chance. In Experiments 3 and 4, 1 chimpanzee performed at a level significantly better than chance. Therefore, chimpanzees mentally represent quantity and successfully combine and compare nonvisible, sequentially presented sets of items.
Chapter
Scientists from many disciplines have been intrigued by the topic of how the mind represents number because of the question’s relevance to controversial topics such as thought without language, the evolution of cognition, modularity of mind, and nature vs. nurture. Number is an abstract and emergent property of sets of discrete entities; two people and two airplanes look nothing alike, and yet the numerosity of the set is the same. Some researchers believe that the abstract nature of numerical representation makes it an unlikely candidate for a cognitive capacity held by nonhuman animals and human infants. However, a growing body of data suggests that both nonverbal animals and preverbal human infants represent number and even perform operations on these representations. In fact, a new synthesis of the data on numerical abilities in animals and infants suggests that there is an evolutionarily and developmentally primitive system for representing number as mental magnitudes with scalar variability (Gallistel and Gelman, 1992, 2000; see also Dehaene, 1997; Wynn, 1995). Furthermore, there is abundant evidence that adult humans also represent number nonverbally as analog magnitudes (Cordes et al., 2001; Dehaene, 1997; Dehaene et al., 1998; Moyer and Landauer, 1967; Whalen et al., 1999). For these reasons, numerical cognition has become an exciting area of research and an exemplary model of a crossdisciplinary field where comparative and developmental studies have influenced current conceptions of adult human numerical processing (e.g., Dehaene, 1997).
Article
This chapter reviews studies over the past 20 years using non-mammalian species (mainly the domestic chicken), addressing issues that were largely inspired by the European Gestalt tradition rather than by the psychology of animal learning, which has provided the typical background of most contemporary comparative psychology. Chicks possess quite remarkable cognitive abilities that can be revealed using as tools those forms of early learning that have been the concern of classic ethologists and early comparative psychologists. This evidence, together with reasonable knowledge of the chick's neuroanatomy, can allow investigators of the brain-mind relationship to proceed a step further, moving from investigation of the neural basis of simple basic learning abilities (imprinting, passive avoidance learning) to cognitive phenomena that have direct counterparts in humans, such as completion of partly occluded objects, biological motion perception, and object and spatial representations.
Article
This chapter discusses how animals deal with natural geometry, particularly on spatial reorientation mechanisms. It examines the ability of animals, such as birds and fish, to integrate landmark and geometric information in environments of different spatial scale. We thus tried to explore a different avenue. The solution of the blue-wall task encompasses the combined use of two sources of information, geometric information provided by the shape of the room (the arrangements of surfaces as surfaces) and nongeometric, landmark information provided by the blue wall. However, geometric information actually has two aspects, which have not been considered separately in previous work, namely, metric information and sense. Metric information refers to the distinction between a short and a long wall, irrespective of any other nongeometric property associated with the walls’ surfaces, such as color, brightness, or scent. In geometry, sense refers to the distinction between left and right. Note, in fact, that even the simple use of purely geometric infor mation does require an ability to combine different sources of information, i.e., metric information and sense. In fact, modularistic hypotheses based on the idea that animals lack a true ability to conjoin outputs of different modules in the absence of a language medium refers to the ability to conjoin information between (e.g., geometric and landmark information) and not (p.91) within (e.g., metric properties and sense) different modules (see Spelke 2000, 2003; Spelke and Tsivkin 2001). The important point to stress is that in certain conditions animals might make use of a combination of nongeometric information and sense in order to reorient, without making any use of metric properties of the environment.
Article
We investigated how within-stimulus heterogeneity affects the ability of rhesus monkeys to order pairs of the numerosities 1 through 9. Two rhesus monkeys were tested in a touch screen task where the variability of elements within each visual array was systematically varied by allowing elements to vary in color, size, shape, or any combination of these dimensions. We found no evidence of a cost (or benefit) in accuracy or reaction time when monkeys were tested with stimuli that were hetero- geneous in color, size, or shape. This was true even though both monkeys experi- enced extended initial training with arrays that were homogeneous in the color, shape, and size of elements. The implications of this finding for the mechanisms that monkeys use to represent and compare numerosities are discussed. Adult humans possess rich and profoundly abstract number concepts. We recog- nize the numerical equivalence between sets as diverse as four painters and four strokes of a brush, three musicians and three saxophone notes, or two books and two ideas. Such examples illustrate that, as adult humans, we form numerical rep- resentations when perceiving simultaneously occurring visual stimuli (e.g., two books), successively occurring visual events (e.g., strokes of a brush), successively occurring auditory events (e.g., three saxophone notes), or when thinking about sets as intangible as an author's ideas. In addition to abstracting number across varying stimulus formats (e.g., successive vs. simultaneously occurring objects or events) and across different stimulus modalities (e.g., auditory or visual), adult human number representations are also abstract in that they are independent of perceptual aspects of the stimuli (e.g., size, shape, color). For example, two
Article
What are the brain and cognitive systems that allow humans to play baseball, compute square roots, cook souffl茅s, or navigate the Tokyo subways? It may seem that studies of human infants and of non-human animals will tell us little about these abilities, because only educated, enculturated human adults engage in organized games, formal mathematics, gourmet cooking, or map-reading. In this chapter, we argue against this seemingly sensible conclusion. When human adults exhibit complex, uniquely human, culture-specific skills, they draw on a set of psychological and neural mechanisms with two distinctive properties: they evolved before humanity and thus are shared with other animals, and they emerge early in human development and thus are common to infants, children, and adults. These core knowledge systems form the building blocks for uniquely human skills. Without them we wouldn't be able to learn about different kinds of games, mathematics, cooking, or maps. To understand what is special about human intelligence, therefore, we must study both the core knowledge systems on which it rests and the mechanisms by which these systems are orchestrated to permit new kinds of concepts and cognitive processes. What is core knowledge? A wealth of research on non-human primates and on human infants suggests that a system of core knowledge is characterized by four properties (Hauser, 2000; Spelke, 2000). First, it is domain-specific: each system functions to represent particular kinds of entities such as conspecific agents, manipulable objects, places in the environmental layout, and numerosities. Second, it is task-specific: each system uses its representations to address specific questions about the world, such as "who is this?" [face recognition], "what does this do?" [categorization of artifacts], "where am I?" [spatial orientation], and "how many are here?" [enumeration]. Third, it is relatively encapsulated: each uses only a subset of the information delivered by an animal's input systems and sends information only to a subset of the animal's output systems. Finally, the system is relatively automatic and impervious to explicitly held beliefs and goals,. In this chapter, we use the domain of number to illustrate how core knowledge systems are assembled to permit uniquely human cognitive advances. We consider first two lines of research that elucidate core knowledge systems: comparative evolutionary studies and studies of human development. These studies provide evidence for two core knowledge systems that
Article
Reply by the current author to the comments made by T. J. Simon (see record 2006-00313-001) on the original article (see record 1999-05057-002). Simon's remarks bear on two theoretical issues. First, what is the specificity of the cerebral circuits for number processing? Second, how do numerical abilities emerge in the course of development? The answers are clear-cut: the brain's cerebral circuits are 'non-numerical', and the developmental foundations of numerical processing are to be found in 'a brain without numbers' which constructs itself through unspecified mechanisms of 'open-ended plasticity'. We disagree on all counts. Although those important issues are still open to scientific inquiry, there is already strong evidence that the numerical abilities of the human brain rest in part on specialized cerebral processes and follow a specific developmental time course that hints at an initial specialization. We share with him, the hypothesis that some mathematical abilities, particularly those that are evidently late cultural acquisitions, such as multiplication tables, do not rely on specific cerebral substrates. The unique and culture-specific features of human number knowledge nevertheless appear to build on a dedicated neural and cognitive system: a number sense that emerged early in vertebrate evolution, is present and functional early in human development, and resides in dedicated neural circuitry. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2012 APA, all rights reserved)