Content uploaded by Paola Tubaro
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Paola Tubaro on Apr 21, 2014
Content may be subject to copyright.
1
Paola Tubaro
EconomiX, Université Paris X
Bât. K, Bureau K 131
200, avenue de la République
F - 92001 Nanterre cedex
Phone: +33 1 40 97 75 43
Fax: +33 1 40 97 70 57
E-mail: paola.tubaro@u-paris10.fr
Jules Dupuit’s Contribution to Mathematical Economics*
“So soon as it is realized […] that political economy is concerned with quantities susceptible of a more or a less,
it must also be recognized that it is in the realm of mathematics […]. Not only do the symbols and drawings of
mathematics give body and form to abstract ideas and thereby call the senses to the aid of man’s intellectual
power, but its formulae take hold of these ideas, modify them and transform them, and bring to light everything
that is true, right and precise in them, without forcing the mind to follow all the motions of a wheelwork the
course of which has been established once for all. They are machines which, at a certain stage, can think for us,
and there is as much advantage in using them as there is in using those which, in industry, labour for us”.
Jules Dupuit, 1844.
* First draft - please do not quote.
2
0. Introduction
Serving as a civil engineer for the State of France, in charge of the construction and
maintenance of roads, bridges and canals, Jules Dupuit1 was led from engineering questions
into his seminal contributions to economic theory. His articles “De la mesure de l’utilité des
travaux publics” (1844) and “De l’influence des péages sur l’utilité des voies de
communication” (1849) are now well-known, not only in the French-speaking world2. Key
features of subsequent neoclassical economics have been recognized in these works, and he
has been acknowledged as a pioneer of the intellectual tradition of microeconomic enquiry
(Ekelund and Hébert, 1999). Moreover, major surveys of the origins and early developments
of mathematical economics review his contributions (Theocharis 1993, pp. 50-55).
This paper focuses on the latter aspect, and aims to go deeper into Dupuit’s involvement
in the gradual progress of mathematical economics at the time, by taking into account the
state of advancement of the discipline in the middle of the 19th century. The use of
mathematics, including relatively advanced tools such as geometry, algebra, and calculus, was
rather uncommon in economic writings, although several attempts had already been made at
using them in the study of economic phenomena, as documented by Theocharis (1961, 1993)
and Baloglou (1995). What may seem striking to today’s readers, however, is that existing
work in mathematical economics mainly concerned the study of the supply side of the market
–calculations of costs of production, of profits, etc., while formal treatment of demand, utility,
and, more generally, consumers’ behavior was relatively infrequent. One reason for that is the
widespread influence of the classical school, placing emphasis on production rather than
consumption, on the economic thought of this period. At the same time, however, various
intellectuals did recognize utility as a key determinant of value –so why did they not
significantly inspire early mathematical economists? An intuitive explanation is that
estimating profits and costs only requires knowledge of easily accessible information, notably
input prices and available production techniques; by contrast, the utility of a good to a
consumer is dependent on subjective factors, of qualitative rather than quantitative nature, and
is therefore hard to translate into precise figures. Even a masterpiece such as Augustin
1 Trained at the École Nationale des Ponts et Chaussées in Paris, Arsène-Jules-Etienne-Juvenal Dupuit (1804 –
1866) was chief engineer in the Sarthe region, where he was in charge of roads and waterways, then in the
Marne and Maine-et-Loire regions. He was called back to Paris in 1850 to work for the municipal water system,
served as inspector-general of the Corps des Ingénieurs, and was then appointed to the Conseil Général des Ponts
et Chaussées.
2 An English translation of Dupuit’s 1844 article, entitled “On the Measurement of the Utility of Public Works”,
appeared in 1952, while only a section of the 1849 article has been translated, under the title “On Tolls and
Transport Charges” (1962).
3
Cournot’s 1838 Researches contains evaluations of firms’ profits and costs, as well as profit
maximization calculations, but no effort to express consumers’ viewpoint in mathematical
terms. His market demand function is not derived from an assessment of consumers’ wishes
or needs, on the grounds that the latter can hardly be evaluated on an objective basis:
“one should distinguish the abstract idea of wealth or exchangeable value, which can be
rigorously analyzed, from the accompanying ideas of utility, scarcity, adequacy to
man’s needs and pleasures, which the term wealth, in everyday language, calls to mind:
these ideas are by nature erratic and indefinite, thus one could not build any scientific
theory upon them” (Cournot 1838, p. 9, our translation).
At the heart of this paper is an effort to reinterpret Dupuit’s accomplishments in the
field of microeconomics, previously highlighted by Ekelund and Hébert (1999), by taking into
account this general context, in order to assess how his work innovated with respect to the
mathematical economics of his time. In this respect, the existing literature on Dupuit’s
achievements in pre-neoclassical economic theory actually provides some useful hints, since
the theoretical innovations that have been credited to him suggest that he was dealing
precisely with the problem of finding a way to apply some form of mathematical reasoning to
the study of utility, demand, and consumer behavior. The paper therefore asks whether he
succeeded in converting an apparently qualitative concept as utility into a numerical
magnitude that could be included into calculations and represented in diagrams. Insofar as this
question is answered in the affirmative, it will be possible to draw the conclusion that Dupuit
extended the field to which mathematics could be applied, by adding utility-related topics to
the evaluation of costs of production and to profit-maximization calculations. In this sense, it
can be said that his contribution opened the way to further developments in the
mathematization of economics.
Yet proving that Dupuit’s contribution to the study of utility can be reckoned as a step
forward in the advancement of mathematical economics, would be no evidence that the author
himself also played a major role in promoting the use of mathematical tools (especially
advanced ones) in economics. Admittedly, his praise of mathematics in the concluding
paragraph of his 1844 article indicates that he grasped the potential usefulness of mathematics
to the progress of economic theory:
“so soon as it is realized […] that political economy is concerned with quantities
susceptible of a more or a less, it must also be recognized that it is in the realm of
mathematics […]. Not only do the symbols and drawings of mathematics give body and
form to abstract ideas and thereby call the senses to the aid of man’s intellectual power,
but its formulae take hold of these ideas, modify them and transform them, and bring to
light everything that is true, right and precise in them […]. They are machines which, at
a certain stage, can think for us” (Dupuit 1844, pp. 109-110).
4
The problem, to date never addressed in the secondary literature on Dupuit, is that this
paragraph seems at odds with the approach he actually adopted, since he almost always used
simple numerical examples that only required knowledge of basic arithmetic to be understood.
Only in a short appendix to his 1844 article did he introduce advanced (by the standards of the
early decades of the 19th century) mathematical methods, by writing demand functions in the
general form y = f(x), stating their essential properties, and representing them graphically in
diagrams. Accordingly, another purpose of the present paper is to explain the seeming
inconsistency between Dupuit’s claims on the power of mathematics as a tool of economic
analysis and the fact that he made a very limited use of it. Clarity on this point may be of help
in assessing Dupuit’s contribution to mathematical economics in full.
Our study will be based on a closer examination of Dupuit’s 1844 article, although there
will be a few references to the 1849 paper as well. The first section highlights Dupuit’s
contribution to utility theory, by examining how he came to propose an operational definition
of the measure of utility. The second section goes deeper into the topic of the notion of utility
and the principle of utility maximization, and the third section scrutinizes Dupuit’s
mathematical treatment of demand and utility, as can be found in the 1844 appendix. In the
last section, we will sum up and draw some conclusions.
1. Dupuit’s major achievement: quantifying the “utility” of a good to consumers
Dupuit first studied choice of technique problems, most prominently in his 1842 article
“Considérations sur les frais d'entretien des routes”, where he compared the costs of
production of different techniques of road construction and maintenance, so as to identify the
one that would minimize total expenses. His contribution was part of a wide-ranging debate,
involving a number of French engineers (Grall 2002, p. 64). However, being in charge of
public works such as roads and bridges, Dupuit soon realized that cost minimization was an
inappropriate choice criterion. In the case of public goods provision, one should not choose
the technique that is least expensive for the producer, but rather prefer the one that proves
most advantageous to the whole community of users. Accordingly, he tried in subsequent
works to replace choice models based on production costs evaluation with decision rules
founded on an assessment of the benefit that consumers get from a good or service.
5
This was, however, very difficult to do, owing to the fundamental asymmetry that exists
between producers and consumers: while it is relatively easy to calculate the gains that an
exchange yields to a producer, because one only needs to know the difference between market
price and cost of production for each unit sold, it is much harder to estimate the gain of a
consumer, which appears as a subjective, qualitative rather than quantitative notion. In order
to tackle this problem, Dupuit tried to create a method for quantifying consumers’ advantage,
by transforming it into a numerical magnitude that could be used in calculations. He first
outlined his solution in the above-mentioned 1844 article, and gave further details in later
papers. Let us briefly present its main features, by following the author’s own reasoning
closely, before commenting on its interest and novelty.
Consider a public work, for example a road. Since it is used by merchants in order to
transport goods from the place where they are produced to the location where they are to be
sold, it has an impact on the total cost of production of these goods, defined as “what it costs
to make an article available for consumption” (Dupuit 1844, p. 94), including both
manufacturing and transport costs. Hence, a new road is advantageous if it cuts the total cost
of production of goods, either by lowering their transportation cost, or by bringing to the
market new products, whose manufacturing costs are lower. For instance, suppose a town
uses 10,000 tons of stone each year for the construction and repair of its houses (Dupuit 1844,
p. 93). Each ton costs 20 francs, including 16 francs for extraction from the quarry and 4
francs for transport over a short distance, say 4 leagues. Now suppose a new means of
communication is established, e.g. a canal. It may happen that the cost of transporting the
stone is higher by the new route than by the old, on account of the new route being longer
(say 100 leagues), but that this extra cost can be compensated by other circumstances: for
example, the canal may pass by an easily worked quarry which had not formerly been
exploited, so that total costs of production now amount to 15 francs, including 2 francs for
extraction and 13 for transport over a long distance. Since the total cost of production of the
old stone exceeds the total cost of production of the new one, the inhabitants of the town will
purchase the latter instead of the former from now on.
Clearly, the canal proves to be beneficial to the inhabitants of the town, who can now
obtain the same good for a lower price. However, how can this benefit be precisely measured?
One might be tempted to believe that it equals 50,000 francs, i.e. the 5 francs reduction in the
unit cost of production multiplied by the 10,000 tons used. However, says Dupuit, such an
evaluation would underestimate the benefit, because the effect of the canal in having reduced
6
the cost of production and thus in having yielded benefits for buyers does not stop there.
Indeed, the fall in price will render the stone suitable to new uses: “in many buildings it will
replace brick and timber; streets will now be paved which were not so before, and so on”
(Dupuit 1844, p. 94). Consumption increases from 10,000 to, say, 30,000 tons each year.
The problem now is, how can the benefit produced by the 20,000 extra tons be
measured? The engineer Henri Navier, writing on this same topic a few years before (1832),
took the difference between the old cost of production and the new one (as for the first 10,000
tons) but such an evaluation is incorrect, because this additional quantity was not purchased at
the old price. In order to find a solution, Dupuit searched for a subjective notion of benefit
(“utility”, in his own wording), defined in such a way that, on the one hand, different
quantities of the same object yield different advantages to an individual, according to the
importance of the needs that they are meant to satisfy, and on the other hand, equal quantities
of the same object yield different benefits to different individuals. But, how to evaluate this
gain, which changes from one individual to another, and may vary for the same individual?
The way people react to a given price can provide a hint. If, at the initial price of 20 francs,
some individuals did buy a ton of stone, it is presumably because they believed that the
benefit they could obtain from the stone would exceed the benefit obtained by keeping the 20
francs. In a certain sense, it may be said that a ton of stone yields an advantage of at least 20
francs to them. If others did not buy at the price of 20 francs, it is apparent that they did not
attribute that much utility to the consumption of stone; if they buy at 15 francs, then they
attribute a utility at least equal to 15 francs (but certainly lower than 20 francs), to a ton of
stone. More precisely, among those who buy at 15 francs, some attach so little value to the
consumption of stone that they would give up if the price were to rise by as little as 1 franc.
For them, utility is therefore less than 16 franc. Others would cease to buy after a rise of 2
francs: for them, the utility of a ton of stone is between 16 and 17 francs, and so on. In short,
“in order to know the utility of each ton consumed it would be necessary for each
consumer to make known the strength of his desire in terms of the price which would
make him cease consuming” (Dupuit 1844, p. 94).
The problem is how to estimate the “strength of desire” of consumers, at first sight a
subjective and variable notion, difficult to quantify. Dupuit’s solution is a thought experiment,
using taxation as a tool capable of revealing apparently invisible benefits:
“it is beyond doubt that a tax can add nothing to the utility of a product; but when we
look at it from the consumer’s point of view we can say that its existence brings to light
undeniably that the product has a utility greater than the cost of production” (Dupuit
1844, p. 85).
7
A buyer pays a good on which a tax is imposed if he finds at least an equivalent utility in it:
“for, in spite of the tax, he is at perfect liberty to buy it or not to buy it. It is not within
the power of the state to make him pay, by means of the tax, anything more than the
utility which he derives from this purchase” (Dupuit 1844, p. 85).
The proposed thought experiment is as follows:
“Suppose that all those similar commodities of which we want to discover the utilities,
are all subjected to a tax which rises by small steps. Each successive increase will cause
a certain quantity of the commodity to disappear from consumption. This quantity,
multiplied by the rate of the tax, will give its utility expressed in money. By thus letting
the tax go up until there are no more consumers, and by adding together all the products
of this multiplication process, we will arrive at the total utility of the goods” (Dupuit
1844, p. 96).
If a tax of 1 franc imposed on stone deprives the canal of the carriage of 7,000 tons,
then we may say that the utility of this transport is 1 franc. If a new tax of 2 francs reduces
traffic by another 5,000 tons, the utility they yield may be evaluated at 2 francs at most, and
so on. Suppose that, by relating taxes with the amounts of traffic they cause to disappear, we
obtain the following result for the 20,000 new tons carried by the canal:
7,000 tons
1 fr.
7,000 fr.
5,000
2
10,000
4,000
3
12,000
3,000
4
12,000
1,000
5
5,000
Total : 20,000
46,000
Table 1.
In other words, the advantage (“relative utility”, in Dupuit’s terminology) derived from
the 20,000 extra tons that the canal allows to transport can be estimated at 46,000 francs. If to
these 46,000 francs of utility we add the 50,000 francs corresponding to the 10,000 tons of
initial consumption, we arrive at a figure of 96,000 francs for the total relative utility of this
type of transport. Notice that the calculation would be identical, except for the sign, if one had
to evaluate the loss to users that may be due to a rise in the price of the good, or to the
imposition of an indirect tax. Then Dupuit computes the “absolute utility”, equal to the sum of
the relative utility and of total cost of production, which in turn, is equal to the unit cost of
production, multiplied by the number of tons sold: in this case, it is 96,000 + 30,000 x 15 =
546,000 francs. Absolute and relative utility obviously coincide if costs of production are nil.
Dupuit claims that his own method of measurement is very general, in view of the fact that it
8
“is not peculiar to means of communication, but can be applied to everything, to any
working tools whatever and to their products; so that we can say in general that the
measure of the utility of a product is the tax which would prevent it being consumed”
(Dupuit 1844, p. 96).
In order to fully appreciate the interest and novelty of the measurement procedure
Dupuit proposed in his 1844 article, it is helpful to relate it to the state of mathematical
economics at the time –specifically, to the fact that the subjective nature of concepts such as
utility, satisfaction, and need, prevented most early mathematical economists from
considering them in their work. In spite of these difficulties, Dupuit set out to conceive a
method to provide an operational definition of consumers’ point of view that could be subject
to mathematical treatment. He seems to have realized that measurability is not an intrinsic
property of phenomena, but can be assigned to them, by bringing about measurement
procedures, founded on theoretical or empirical arguments.
Dupuit’s definition is not meant to be a rigorous measure of “the quality which things
have of being able to satisfy men’s needs” (Dupuit 1844, p. 89, italics in the original). It
would be difficult (or even impossible) to assess human needs or wishes as such, but his
method allows him at least to take account of the intensity of needs and wishes through their
monetary expressions. It is based on individuals’ decisions to buy or not to buy a good, given
their incomes and the price of the good: “political economy only bakes bread for those who
can buy it” (Dupuit 1844, p. 89). This method has the merit of allowing for an assessment of
the total quantity that a number of different individuals wish to buy at a given price, without
requiring interpersonal comparisons of needs and wishes, which would be problematic:
“it would be difficult to say whose hunger was the greater –the rich man’s, who would
be willing to give a million for a kilogramme of bread, or the poor man’s, who, having
nothing else to give, would risk his life for it”, Dupuit, 1844, p. 89).
Dupuit’s first and foremost contribution to mathematical economics consists in his
effort to provide an operational definition that permits to include a measure of consumers’
satisfaction into economic calculations. Although he only used simple arithmetic in his
reasoning, as the above cited quotations confirm, his work can be reckoned as a progress for
mathematical economics, which was hardly capable of including utility-related arguments up
to that time. This advance was indispensable to enhance mathematical economics at this stage
of its historical development, by enlarging its field of application from the study of the profit-
maximizing (or cost-minimizing) behavior of producers to the study of the utility-oriented
9
behavior of consumers. In this sense, Dupuit’s contribution constitutes a step forward with
respect to Cournot’s, who believed that no rigorous study of utility would ever be possible.
2. Demand, utility, and utility maximization in Dupuit
After claiming that Dupuit’s contribution helped to include consumers’ satisfaction into
mathematical economics in some sense, it may now be interesting to go deeper into the
meaning he attached to the concept of utility, in order to better assess its novelty and interest.
2.1 Utility and demand
Let us first examine the basic characteristics of the relationship between price and the quantity
of objects consumed at each price, as Dupuit conceived it. He never called it “demand”; he
did not label it in any particular way in the 1844 article, but as we shall see later, he used the
expression “curve of consumption” in the mathematical note at the end of this article, and
“law of consumption” in the 1849 paper. Be that as it may, his reasoning is based on the
intuition that an individual attaches a different utility to different quantities of the same good.
Take the example of stone which we referred to earlier: at a price of 20 francs per ton, buyers
use it to build or to repair their houses but, if price falls to 15 francs, they may not only buy
the quantity that they need for necessary construction or renovation work, but they may also
increase their consumption, by using stone for other, less urgent needs, e.g. they may be
willing to replace brick and timber in some buildings. It is thus clear that, in general, the
consumption of each individual increases as price falls. Consequently, at the system level, the
sum of the quantities consumed by many different individuals also increases as price falls.
This is, according to Dupuit, the first “general law” (Dupuit 1844, p. 103) to which the
relationship between price and (aggregate) demanded quantity “remains constantly subject”
(Dupuit 1844, p. 103). This law is always valid, in his opinion, despite the fact that the exact
shape of the relationship between price and quantity may not be known for any commodity,
and that “it can even be said that it will never be known since it depends on the volatile will of
human beings; it is today no longer what it was yesterday” (Dupuit 1844, p. 103).
The second general law states that:
“the increase in consumption due to a price fall will be the greater, the lower the initial
price. If a fall in the price of an article from 100 to 95 francs brings in another thousand
consumers a further fall from 95 to 90 will bring in more than a thousand” (Dupuit
1844, p. 103).
10
This particular aspect (which obviously concerns aggregate but not individual demand
functions) depends on the income distribution that prevails in modern societies, according to
an argument already found in Germain Garnier (1796, pp. 195-6) and Jean-Baptiste Say
(1828-29, p. 358):
“this property reflects the structure of society which, if it is divided into groups
according to income, and these groups are placed one on top of the other starting with
the poorest, has a shape similar to one of those pyramids of cannon-balls which are to
be seen in parks of artillery –the lower the layer, the more balls it contains. Thus, as the
price of an article falls, its use spreads to more and more consumers, quite apart from
the fact that existing consumers purchase it in greater quantities” (Dupuit 1844, p. 103).
Thus Dupuit’s justification of the two “laws” relies on individual evaluations
(depending on the tastes, needs and available resources of each buyer), as well as on
information supposedly derived from the empirical observation of the structure of society at a
given moment in time. But what about “utility”, to which Dupuit constantly referred, starting
from the very title of his paper? Indeed, the question arises whether he envisaged the whole
chain of derivations from utility maximization to demand functions, similarly to neoclassical
economists, who first introduce a utility function, conditional on the needs, tastes or
preferences of an individual, and a budget constraint, depending on the prevailing market
conditions, summarized by current prices; then maximization of each individual’s utility
function subject to his or her own budget constraint gives rise to individual demand functions
and ultimately to aggregate demand functions.
It does not seem possible to answer this question in the affirmative. As a matter of fact,
Dupuit never thinks in terms of utility functions independently of market conditions, as a
necessary presupposition of demand analysis, and never explicitly distinguishes utility
considerations and budget constraints as two separate determinants of demand. His thought
experiment leads him to build his demand function directly, so to speak, as the individuals he
pictures would be unable to determine the maximum sacrifice they would be willing to make
in order to acquire a given good without knowing prices. His measurement criterion takes into
account, at the same time, the personal tastes or needs of the individual concerned and the
prevailing market conditions. The lack of a separate, preliminary treatment of utility in his
work is also plainly revealed by a few passages, such as “utility and everything that can be
said about it derive from the law of consumption” Dupuit 1849, p. 7). Together with the
absence of a clear-cut distinction between utility and demand considerations, this is probably
one reason why his approach did not make much sense to some later neoclassical writers,
11
including Léon Walras, who claimed that “Mr. Dupuit’s theory consists in an utter confusion
between utility curves and demand curves” (Jaffé 1965, vol. I, p. 535, our translation).
In fact, what Dupuit calls “utility” –more precisely, “relative utility”- is a concept
similar to Alfred Marshall’s consumer surplus. Both approaches provide practical ways to
compare monetary with non-monetary magnitudes, so as to build money measures of a
person’s satisfaction, in terms of the amount of money s/he would be willing to pay for an
object rather than renounce to it. Both measures have the appeal of seeming scientific
objectivity, in that they enable to calculate costs and benefits from the observed behaviour of
individuals, i.e. their actions of buying or not buying the object, with a minimum of subjective
judgements.
It is beyond the scope of this paper to discuss the merits and the shortcomings of
consumer surplus arguments in detail. It is enough to recall the controversies that the use of
measurable utility indexes has aroused, especially since the discoveries by Fisher and Pareto,
that all the propositions regarding equilibrium of the consumer in competitive markets can be
derived without them. Though Paul Samuelson (1974) has shown how a “money-metric
utility function” can be defined in a rigorous manner, the use of consumer surplus analysis as
a tool of investigation in a rigorously acceptable way comes with a cost, in that it is necessary
to make stringent assumptions about consumer preferences (Chipman and Moore, 1976).
2.2 Utility or profit maximization?
If Dupuit’s writings are somewhat confused about the distinction between utility and demand,
what about the principle of utility maximization? In a sense, Ekelund and Hébert’s suggestion
that Dupuit contributed to place utility maximization at the heart of economic theory (2000) is
well documented by his whole work. The idea that “the purchaser never pays more for the
product than the value he places on its utility” (Dupuit 1844, p. 89), on which Dupuit insists
in his writings, and which actually underlies most of his numerical examples, clearly hints
that consumers do behave rationally, in that they always choose the alternative they value
most between an object and the monetary equivalent of its price. At a time in which it was
relatively uncommon to interpret consumers’ behaviour in this light, Dupuit’s emphasis on
their ability to make consistent choices between different alternatives can be seen as a
significant change, opening the way to later efforts to found explanations of consumer
behaviour on maximization models. Despite the novelty of this insight, and its implications
for subsequent theoretical developments, however, the principle of utility maximization seems
to be rather underdeveloped in Dupuit’s work. The aforementioned absence of clearly
12
distinguishable utility functions, similar to the ones neoclassical theory has accustomed us to,
obviously implies that there are no utility maximization calculations that take into account the
preferences of an individual over a range of different goods. More to the point, there are some
ambiguities in the way Dupuit depicts consumers’ behaviour. On the one hand, his idea that
“no one is ever a dupe except in relation to the cost of production” (Dupuit 1844, p. 89)
emphasizes buyers’ ability never to pay more than what they think is the value of an object;
on the other hand, it does not necessarily imply that they maximize their utility, insofar as
consumers would accept to pay any price lower than the utility they attach to an object, but
this price may be above the cost of production -hence even a small decrease in price would
increase their satisfaction. Sometimes, Dupuit even characterizes consumers’ behaviour in
much more unfavourable terms, for example by evoking their “vanity” and “credulity”, which
have enabled merchants to “set traps” for them, and to conceive “devices for taking in dupes”
(Dupuit 1844, p. 89).
By contrast, the principle of profit maximization is clearly present and recognizable in
Dupuit’s economic thought. An example in his 1849 article is telling in this respect. Suppose
the table below gives the number of crossings over a bridge corresponding to each toll rate,
with tariffs in the first column and number of crossings, i.e. demanded quantity, in the second
one. The number of crossings is at its maximum, taken to be 100, when price is zero,
decreases gradually as the tariff rises, and falls to zero for a toll rate of 12. The third column
gives the reduction in demand due to each unit increase in tariff. Column four gives the
(marginal) loss of utility due to a unit increase in the toll, calculated as the product of the
reduction of crossings (column 3) and the toll rate (column 1), while column five indicates the
total loss of utility, i.e. the sum of the marginal losses for each toll rate from 0 up to the level
considered. The total loss corresponding to the maximum toll rate, equal to 445 in this case,
obviously equals the total utility of a zero rate; hence, Dupuit re-writes this same amount in
the first line of column six, which represents total utility. The following lines of column 6 are
obtained by subtracting the sum of partial utilities lost, taken from column 4, from the total
utility of 445. In the last column, Dupuit shows the yield of the toll for each rate.
Since demand decreases as the toll rate increases, the yield of the toll is nil for a zero
rate, then grows with the toll, reaches a maximum (here, for a toll rate of 5), and falls again
back to zero. Dupuit insists, both in his 1844 and in his 1849 articles, that two entirely
different toll rates, one below and one above that which brings in the maximum revenue, may
yield more or less the same revenue to the supplier of the good or service, while bringing
about considerably different losses of utility. In this particular case, toll rates equal to 1 and 9
13
correspond approximately to the same yield, i.e. 80 and 81 francs, respectively, but the loss of
utility is only 20 for a unit toll rate, and is equal to 346 if the toll rate increases to 9. The
reason of this is that the toll is not only a burden to those who pay it, but also to those who
cannot cross the bridge because they cannot afford it.
Utility
Toll
rate
Number of
crossings
Reduction of
crossings due
to rate increase
lost by rate
increase
lost by toll
corresponding
to toll
Yield of
toll
0
100
0
0
445
0
0
1
80
20
20
425
20
80
2
63
17
34
391
54
126
3
50
13
39
352
93
150
4
41
9
36
316
129
164
5
33
8
40
276
169
165
6
26
7
42
234
211
156
7
20
6
42
192
253
140
8
14
6
48
144
301
112
9
9
5
45
99
346
81
10
6
3
30
69
376
60
11
3
3
33
36
409
33
12
0
3
36
0
445
0
Totals
100
445
Table 2
On this basis, Dupuit explained how to choose a toll rate in the 0-12 range.
Interestingly, he claimed that this choice will be different according to whether the bridge
belongs to a private company or the government, because the purpose in view is not the same
in these two cases. If the bridge is a public property, the government “will want to recover
from the toll merely a fixed sum representing interest on the capital spent for construction,
maintenance cost and perhaps amortization” (Dupuit 1849, p. 11). Suppose that the bridge
costs 150,000 francs to build and that the figures shown in the above table are one-hundredth
of the real traffic figures. Yearly proceeds of 8,000 are enough to cover interest on the capital
spent for construction, at a rate of 4%, and to leave about 2,000 francs for maintenance and
amortization. The government will thus choose toll rate 1, yielding a revenue of 8,000 each
year. On the contrary, a private company « has only one aim, and that is to get the largest
possible income from the toll » (Dupuit 1849, p. 11). Accordingly, the company will charge 5,
i.e. the toll rate that corresponds to the maximum yield (165,000 francs). The differences
between the results of private and public operation are shown in the table below:
14
Type of operation
Utility (fr.)
Crossings
Toll yield
(fr.)
Public
42,500
80
8,000
Private
27,600
33
16,500
Difference
14,900
47
8,500
Table 3
The extra 8,500 francs that the private company charges the users of the bridge are
profit for its shareholders, who gain just as much as users lose. It is a redistribution of wealth
from consumers to producers, but from the point of view of society as a whole, it is not a loss.
On the contrary, the difference of 14,900 francs is an additional utility that consumers gain in
the case of public operation, and a dead loss for everybody in the case of private operation:
“those who have not crossed the bridge have been deprived of a service which they value at
14,900 francs and which would have cost the company nothing” (Dupuit 1849, p. 12).
Nevertheless, it is possible to reduce the disadvantages associated with private
operation, by differentiating tariffs in order to make all users of the bridge pay a toll
proportionate to the utility they derive from the passage. Suppose for example “that the toll
for a bridge is so arranged that every user pays half the price which would stop him from
crossing” (Dupuit 1849, p. 16). In this way, nobody would be deprived of the service, and
hardly any utility would be lost to society. Furthermore, he argues, the yield would at any rate
be sufficient to allow the company make some profit, after covering its costs: price
differentiation is more profitable for the producer than fixing a single rate at the lowest level
that demand conditions allow for, which corresponds to the same quantity purchased (number
of crossings in this case), but would yield a lower revenue. Hence, both producers and
consumers would benefit from such a tariff scheme (it can thus be reminded in passing that
Dupuit is acknowledged as one of the first advocates of price discrimination).
Of course, such a price policy is not easy to enforce, because users are not willing to
declare the true utility they attach to the bridge, in the hope that they be charged less:
“I need hardly say that I do not believe it possible that such a tariff should be applied
voluntarily, because it would come up against the unsurmountable obstacle of the
general public’s universal dishonesty” (Dupuit 1849, p. 16).
The ability of a company manager thus consists in trying
“to guess the needs of the consumers as well as the sacrifices they are prepared to make
to satisfy these needs, and then to define the general characteristics by which consumers
may be classified in the tariff schedule” (Dupuit 1849, p. 16).
There are examples of business people succeeding in structuring their tariff schedule in
15
such a way that consumers are led to pay according to the sacrifice they are ready to make to
satisfy their needs. The two or three-class tariff policies of most railway companies are ways
to leave passengers to classify themselves, according to their willingness to pay:
“there is a presumption that those who are willing to make the largest sacrifice for their
journey are also those who value their comfort most and who have their carriages
luxuriously appointed inside and out. So this is the treatment the company gives them. It
also tries to guard against their avarice, which might induce them to travel in a lower
class, by differentiating as much as possible the comfort provided for passengers”
(Dupuit 1849, p. 24).
It is not against the poor that the war is being conducted, he concluded, but against the
likely avarice of the rich. In short, business people have already made good progress in this
direction “by just going ahead at random”; the problem Dupuit is trying to deal with “is
merely one of according scientific treatment” to this question (Dupuit 1849, p. 16).
The above remarks show that Dupuit attributed a high degree of rationality to
producers. He explicitly described their purpose in terms of profit maximization, and
performed the necessary calculations to determine the tariff level that yields the greatest gain.
He also seems to believe that most producers or merchants of goods and services have some
intuitive knowledge of the relationship between price and demanded quantity, and try to use it
to their own advantage. Of course, he was aware that the exact price / quantity relationship is
normally unknown, but he believed that this is “no obstacle to the rational calculation of toll
rates” (Dupuit 1849, p. 12). All business calculations turn on conjectures, after all:
“if the law of consumption were fully known […] then these calculations would have to
do only with perfectly determined problems soluble by the simplest arithmetic. But in
the producer’s uncertain world the solution depends both on his skill in guessing the
needs of the consumers and on his imagination in devising a method of making them
pay as much as possible” (Dupuit 1849, p. 12).
These abilities constitute what he called the “business talent” that “lets one merchant or
one manufacturer make a fortune in an industry which ruins his neighbour” (Dupuit 1849, p.
26). In an uncertain environment, scientific knowledge can be of help in providing “general
principles which might serve as a guide” (Dupuit 1849, p. 26). The author understood his own
study as a means to improve merchants and producers’ performance, by helping them to grasp
the general characteristics of consumers’ behavior, so that they no longer have to guess “at
random”, but only to work out the specific characteristics of the particular demand behaviour
of their customers.
In sum, there seems to be a gap between the behaviour of producers and merchants, who
16
are supposed capable of using all the possible means to maximize their profits, and
consumers, whose utility-maximizing behaviour is depicted in much paler shades. Besides,
Dupuit acknowledged that the well-being of society as a whole depends on producers’
behavior: if they are able to guess consumers’ needs and wishes so as to fix different prices
for different degrees of their willingness to pay, everybody will gain. Thus, although Dupuit’s
contribution does reduce the gap between producers and consumers in the economic thinking
of his time, it does not entirely eliminate it: there is still a significant degree of asymmetry
between the two sides of the market. Beside the technical obstacles to the development of
utility maximization calculations, one reason for this is, presumably, that the general vision
underlying most economic theories of the time was still one that put greater emphasis on the
production / supply rather on than the consumption / demand side of the market, as in
classical economic thought. In this sense, there is much to gain by interpreting Dupuit’s
contribution not only in the light of later developments in neoclassical microeconomics, but
also in relation to the thinking that prevailed in early 19th century economics.
3. Dupuit’s line of reasoning in the appendix: mathematics
Although Dupuit mainly used numerical examples in his reasoning, he attached a note to the
1844 article, in which he presented some of the general principles of his theory, and some of
their most significant implications, in mathematical form. Let us now have a closer look at
this attempt, in order to compare Dupuit’s mathematical arguments with the numerical
examples used elsewhere in his writings, in order to assess their usefulness and relevance.
3.1 Fig. 1: a novel formulation of Dupuit’s basic principle
In fig. 1, the lengths Op, Op’, Op’’, represent various prices for a good, and the verticals Or,
Or’, Or’’, indicate the number of articles consumed at these prices. Let ON represent the
quantity consumed when the price is zero, and OP the price at which consumption falls to
zero. By relating prices and quantities, it is possible to construct the curve Nnn’n’’P –i.e.
aggregate demand, or the “curve of consumption”, as Dupuit calls it in the appendix. It
appears as a real function defined on the positive half-line, monotonically decreasing, convex,
continuous, and probably differentiable (it may be useful to recall that at the time, the
existence of continuous but non-differentiable functions was not known). It follows that the
first derivative must be negative and increasing, and second derivative positive.
17
Two of these properties are explicitly recognized by the author in the first, non-
mathematical part of the article. The curve is monotonically decreasing because consumption
expands when price falls, and convex because the increase in consumption due to a price fall
will be the greater, the lower the initial price (see par. 2.1). These two properties also
characterize the laws of consumption Dupuit used elsewhere in his articles, represented by
two columns of figures showing the number of articles consumed corresponding to each
market price from zero (at which consumption is largest) up to the price which causes all
consumption to cease. By contrast, continuity and differentiability do not apply to the
numerical examples previously used, which refer to changes in demand due to discrete
changes in prices. Does the introduction of these two additional assumptions change anything,
with respect to Dupuit’s arithmetical arguments?
To answer this question, let us refer to what Dupuit himself suggested in a footnote in
the first part of his article:
“for convenience of exposition we have used calculated differences instead of using the
differential calculus. Those who are familiar with the elements of the calculus will see
later how precision may be substituted for approximation” (Dupuit 1844, p. 95).
Indeed, most of the calculations performed in the first part in order to measure the
changes in the quantity purchased due to a series of changes in price, are based on discrete
price variations, arbitrarily chosen by the observer. Consequently, they are necessarily
approximate. Still, improvements are possible, by evaluating changes in demand due to
smaller and smaller price changes. In this respect, the introduction of a continuous
relationship between prices and quantities in the appendix can be seen as an attempt to make
Dupuit’s method more accurate, by taking into account small differences in price levels and
their effects on consumption.
18
Dupuit uses this relationship to give visual form to his concepts of relative and
absolute utility. Since pn represents the number of articles consumed at price Op, the area of
the rectangle Ornp expresses the costs of production of these articles. The “utility” of each of
the pn articles is at least Op and for almost all of them it is greater than Op. Indeed, by raising
a perpendicular from p’ it can be seen that for each of p’n’ articles the utility is at least Op’,
since they are bought at that price. Of the pn articles there are therefore only qn = pn – p’n’
for which utility is really Op (or rather, between Op and Op’), for the others it is at least Op’.
The same argument, applied to another price level Op’’, leads to the conclusion that the utility
of the quantity q’n’ = p’n’ – p’’n’’ is between Op’ and Op’’, while the utility of the
remaining p’’n’’ articles is at least equal to Op’’. By continuing to apply the same argument
an indefinite number of times, and by taking smaller and smaller price differences each time,
it can be shown that the absolute utility of the pn articles to the consumer is the mixtilinear
trapezium OrnP. Relative utility can be calculated by subtracting the cost of production from
absolute utility: in graphical terms, it is the mixtilinear triangle npP.
The above remarks are sufficient to highlight some of the advantages of this method,
compared to the numerical examples used elsewhere. Consider one of the earliest criticisms
against Dupuit, raised by his colleague, the engineer Louis Bordas, in a 1847 comment to the
1844 article we are examining here3. Among other, Bordas stressed the possibility of income
effects that may make Dupuit’s measure inadequate. Suppose, he suggested, that the
introduction of a new technique lowers the cost of production of a pair of stockings from 6 to
3 francs. A consumer who used to buy four pairs of stockings each year, for a total
expenditure of 24 francs, is now able to buy eight pairs of stockings for the same amount of
money. Before the technical innovation, he would have needed 48 francs to purchase eight
pairs, i.e. he would have had to cut his other expenses by 24 francs. Hence in his perception, a
technical change in the production of stockings is equivalent to a 24-francs increase in his
annual income. If, instead of using all his extra income to purchase stockings, he decided to
buy only seven pairs, and to use the remaining 3 francs to buy some other product, his relative
gain measured by Dupuit’s criterion would be only 21 francs –i.e. the change in price
multiplied by the quantity formerly consumed, plus the new price multiplied by the additional
3 In fact, the first three sections of Dupuit’s above mentioned 1849 article are a reply to Bordas’s criticism.
19
quantity purchased. In other words, Dupuit’s method of measurement underestimates the
advantage of the consumer (Bordas 1847, pp. 77 – 78).
A possible solution may consist in considering Dupuit’s measure of the advantage of
consumers as an approximate rather than an exact measurement procedure, which would be
acceptable insofar as the price variation is so small that the resulting change in the
individual’s income is negligible. Most of the numerical examples that Dupuit used in the
main part of his article are based on discrete (hence, relatively large) price variations, and thus
hardly permit to solve the problem; conversely, the use of real instead of integer numbers and
the assumption of continuity introduced in the appendix make the study of such small changes
possible. In this sense, the mathematical presentation of the note turns out to be superior to the
simple arithmetic initially used by Dupuit. The author himself, however, does not seem to be
aware of this, in that he does not rely on this point in his 1849 reply to Bordas’s critique.
3.2 Fig 2: the effects of a change in methods of production
Dupuit used the general principles outlined above to illustrate some of the most important
implications of his theory. To begin with, he considered the effects of an improvement in the
production technique, which reduces the cost of production from Op to Op’ (fig. 2). The
increase in consumers’ utility is represented by the surface of the mixtilinear trapezium
n’p’pn. Navier’s mistake, mentioned earlier (par. 1.1), was to overestimate the increase in
utility, by taking, instead, the rectangle n’p’pq, i.e. the product of the price difference and the
quantity purchased at the new price.
In most cases, a technical change not only reduces costs, but also brings about a
modification in the quality of the product. Before giving details on how Dupuit dealt with this
topic in the appendix, with the help of fig. 2, it is useful to briefly recall how he treated it in
the first, non-mathematical part of the article, so as to be able later to compare the strengths
and the weaknesses of the two methods. The non-mathematical argument is as follows:
qualities have a value which must be taken into account in the calculation of utility. Suppose,
as Navier did, that transporting goods by a newly built canal costs 0.87 francs less than by the
old road. The advantage of the canal cannot be valued at 0.87, even if the transported goods
come by canal in the same quantities in which they formerly came by the road, because
“carriage by road being quicker, more reliable and less subject to loss or damage, it
possesses advantages to which business men often attach a considerable value.
However, it may well be that the saving of 0.87 induces the merchant to use the canal;
he can buy warehouses and increase his floating capital in order to have a sufficient
supply of goods on hand to protect himself against the slowness and irregularity of the
20
canal, and if all told the saving of 0.87 francs in transport gives him an advantage of a
few centimes, he will decide in favour of the new route. But the advantage of the new
route to him will only be precisely these few centimes, and if a toll of the same amount
is established on the canal, then goods will no longer be moved by this route” (Dupuit
1844, p. 100).
Let us now look at the way Dupuit presented these concepts in his mathematical note.
With a change in the quality of the product, the curve of consumption would move, to the
right in case of an improvement in quality, and to the left in the case of deterioration. Ekelund
and Hébert draw the conclusion that quality is a parameter that remains constant along a
consumption curve (Ekelund and Hébert, 1999, p. 139). Fig. 2 illustrates the effects of a
change for the worse in quality, moving the curve from NP to NS: in this particular case, the
change in utility is represented by the difference between the two triangles mp’S and npP.
Are the two methods equivalent, or is one of them better than the other? Notice, first,
that in his numerical example, Dupuit took into account a rather simple state of affairs, in
which a technical change brings about both a fall in price and a deterioration in quality, while
the quantity does not change. The lower quality of the product is equivalent to an increase in
costs, which offsets to some extent the favorable effects of the initial price decrease –so that
in this particular case, the advantage diminishes from 0.87 francs to “a few centimes”.
Fig. 2 illustrates a more complex situation, in which the fall in price and in quality are
accompanied by an increase in quantity. It becomes more difficult in this case to compare the
two different situations; however, the graphical method gives some general guidance, by
providing a visual representation of consumers’ satisfaction in the two different cases, which
may be of help in establishing which situation is preferable. If the equations of the two curves
were known, it would also be possible to calculate the areas representing utility in the two
21
cases, by integrating under the curves of consumption over the relevant intervals. On the
contrary, numerical examples would not be of great help in this case –they provide no general
guidance as to whether the previous or the novel method of production is preferable, so that it
would be more difficult to draw general conclusions from them. Hence it can be said that, as
this type of problem is concerned, the mathematical method outlined in the appendix to
Dupuit’s 1844 article provides a slightly better, and certainly a more general, analytical tool.
3.3 Fig. 3: how demand theory provides guidance to policy-makers
Let us now have a look at fig. 3, which illustrates the effects of the imposition of a tax on an
article. His purpose is to advise the government on how to raise a given sum by means of
taxation, while minimizing the loss of utility to society. Similarly to the yield of a toll (par.
2.2), the revenue the government obtains from taxes is nil for a zero tax rate, then increases as
the tax rate rises, reaches a maximum, and then falls to zero again. On the other hand, the loss
of utility to society increases steadily as the tax rate rises. In particular, Dupuit argued, the
dead loss due to an increase in a tax increases as the square of the tax. As before, let us first
briefly recall how he treated this question in the non-mathematical part of the article, so as to
be able to compare the two methods afterwards. In that section, Dupuit explained this
principle by taking, again, the example of stone, and supposing that, starting from a price of
15 francs, the government imposes a 5-francs tax. Since the introduction of this tax is
equivalent to an increase in price from 15 to 20 francs, table 1 above shows that consumption
will fall to 10,000, so that the yield of the tax will be 50,000. How to calculate the amount of
utility lost? First, Dupuit calculates that, if quantity decreases in a uniform manner as price
rises, that is to say 2,000 by the rise from 15 francs to 16, 2,000 by the rise from 16 to 17, etc.,
the average loss of utility would be 2.50 francs per ton. Since, however, each successive rise
in price prevents less and less numerous consumers from buying stone, the average loss will
be somewhat lower. Hence, says Dupuit, “the utility lost or gained through a change in price
has for its upper limit the amount by which the quantity consumed changes, multiplied by half
the change in price” (Dupuit 1844, p. 104). Specifically, if a tax of 5 francs reduces
consumption from 30,000 to 10,000, the utility lost is below 20,000 x 5 x
2
1
= 50,000 (in this
particular case, we know from the calculations presented earlier that the loss is equal to
46,000). The second step of Dupuit’s reasoning consists in saying that “the smaller the tax the
nearer does this limit approach the actual figure”, and thus
“it is permissible, where a tax is small relative to the cost of manufacture, to suppose a
22
uniform rate of decrease. Thus a tax of 1 franc on a thing worth 100 francs will cause
the number of consumers to fall to an extent not markedly different from a tax of 2, 3, 4,
5 or 6 francs; for the relations between the numbers 100, 101, 102, 103, 104, 105 and
106 are little different” (Dupuit 1844, p. 104).
In this case, the utility lost as result of a tax of 1 franc will be the change in quantity
multiplied by
2
1
of 1; raising the tax to 2 francs will double the change in quantity, so that the
utility lost will be twice this number multiplied by
2
1
of 2; for 3 francs,
2
1
3 x 3. It may thus
be said, concludes Dupuit, that “the loss of utility is proportional to the square of the tax”
(Dupuit 1844, p. 104). It is still an approximation, though a better one.
Fig. 3 provides an alternative proof of this same proposition. Let Op be the initial price
of an article “which is cheap and consumed in large quantities” (Dupuit 1844, p. 107), and
suppose a small tax of pp’ is imposed. The government’s revenue from the tax will be pp’n’q,
and the utility lost is equal to the triangle nqn’. If the tax is doubled, its yield of pp’’n’’q’ is
smaller than the double of the rectangle pp’n’q, yet the loss of utility nq’n’’ is four times the
loss represented by the triangle nqn’, since both its base and height have been doubled.
Similarly, says Dupuit, if the tax is trebled, the loss of utility increases nine-fold, and so on.
Therefore “The loss of utility increases as the square of the tax” (Dupuit, 1844, p. 107, italics
in the original). Furthermore, suppose that the level pM is the one for which the yield for the
government is at a maximum, pMTQ. Beyond this level, the yield diminishes and equals that
given by a much lower rate of tax, while the loss of utility increases further: “the higher the
tax, the less it yields relatively” (Dupuit 1844, p. 107). Specifically, a tax of pP will bring
nothing into the treasury, but will do society the greatest harm.
23
Note that Dupuit’s argument concerns the elastic part of the demand curve, where the
demanded quantity reacts most to changes in price. More to the point, he treats the imposition
of the tax as a small increase in price, so as to be able to use a linear approximation of the
demand function. His argument may be thought of as an application of Taylor’s formula,
which enables to replace a function in the vicinity of a given point by the straight line which
is tangent to the function at that point. Under these conditions, despite the convexity of the
curve, the square of the tax is a good estimate of the loss of utility due to the tax. By making it
possible to take smaller variations in the tax rate (i.e. smaller than the ones that Dupuit
envisaged in his numerical example), giving rise to small reductions in demanded quantity,
the continuity of the demand curve makes it possible to obtain a better approximation of the
total utility lost. Specifically, it is an improvement with respect to the numerical example
previously used. In this sense, introducing the assumption of continuity makes Dupuit’s
argument on the whole more convincing than the one he used in the first part of his article,
based on rougher calculations.
3.4 Fig. 4: producers’ behaviour and price discrimination
This same framework may be useful to study not only the effects of taxation, but also
producers’ behavior –i.e. how they fix prices or tolls for a good or service they provide, say a
bridge. A general way of reasoning consists in writing the curve of consumption y = f(x),
where the variables y and x stand for demanded quantity and price, respectively. If it is wished
by means of a toll (or price) to raise a sum A representing what is needed to repay the capital
advanced (as in the case of public operation, mentioned above), then “we must solve the
equation xy = A” (Dupuit 1844, p. 107). If it is wished to raise the greatest revenue (as in the
case of private operation), “we must solve the equation
0=
dx
dxy
” (Dupuit 1844, p. 108).
The mathematical expression of the curve of consumption and the equations that
determine the toll rate according to the purpose of the provider of the service considered,
permit to go deeper into the meaning and the implications of the assumption that prices and
quantities are real numbers. In fig. 1-4, a price may be represented by any point between O
and P, and a quantity by any point between O and N. Some of these points correspond to
rational numbers, which may result from dividing the units of measure of prices or quantities
into smaller and smaller parts; they may thus result from the application of Dupuit’s method
of assessing the changes in the quantity purchased due to a series of (small) changes in price.
But other points on lines ON and OP correspond to irrational numbers, which by definition
24
cannot be obtained in this way. They may only result from certain calculations, or from
solving certain algebraic equations, such as
0=
dx
dxy
. They make sense in an appropriate
theoretical framework, but never result from the direct measurement of a magnitude. Strictly
speaking, the methodology consisting in imposing a tax on a good, increasing it gradually and
measuring the reduction in demand it causes at each step, until the tax is so high that demand
falls to zero, does not lead to the diagrams of the note. This conclusion would remain valid
even if it were possible to estimate the changes in demand due to very small price variations.
In this sense, the curves of consumption that Dupuit draws in his note represent more than a
mere extension of the method of measurement he proposed in the first part of his article.
Rather, they hint at a different conception of the relationship between price and the demanded
quantity of a good. Instead of the direct measurement procedure that Dupuit illustrated with
the device of a gradually rising fictive tax, the method he proposed in his mathematical note
consists in assuming a general law that associates any price level on segment OP to a quantity
level belonging to interval ON, and in indicating the main characteristics of this law, i.e.
monotony, convexity, continuity, and differentiability. It is no longer a method of
measurement, but an abstraction, which permits to determine the quantity corresponding to
any price between O and P (and the other way round), while the former method typically
takes into account integer or rational numbers only. This may be another reason why the
model outlined in Dupuit’s note is characterized by “precision”, while the other one is a mere
“approximation” (Dupuit 1844, p. 95).
Let us now consider the way Dupuit uses this method to re-prove his conclusions about
the desirability of price discrimination. Suppose that the value of x derived from equation
0=
dx
dxy
is OM, corresponding to the maximum revenue to the producer, graphically
represented by rectangle OMTR (fig. 4). The utility of the good to consumers is the triangle
TMP, and the loss of utility is RTN. If consumers can be placed in several categories each of
which attributes a different utility to the same service, it is possible, by an appropriate
combination of different prices, to increase the producer’s revenue and to diminish the loss of
utility. If from among the initial pn articles sold you can distinguish the consumers that would
buy pq at price OM, and among the latter, those who would buy Mq’ at Op’, then the revenue
is the sum of the three rectangles Ornp + pqTM + Mq’n’p’, the utility to consumers is nqT +
Tq’n’ + n’p’P, while the loss of utility shrinks to Nrn.
25
Although the use of diagrams and the continuity assumption do not lead Dupuit to new
results on price discrimination, they enable him to shorten his argument, to rely on the general
characteristics of the curve of consumption instead of the specific aspects of a particular
numerical example, and even to make his idea clearer, by providing an image of it –thus
confirming his point that “the symbols and drawings of mathematics give body and form to
abstract ideas and thereby call the senses to the aid of man’s intellectual power” (Dupuit
1844, p. 110).
On the whole, the mathematical note at the end of Dupuit’s 1844 article does not lead to
any significantly new findings, and may even be skipped on a first reading. Nonetheless, it
provides a better analytical tool than the method of measurement outlined in the first part of
the paper. Diagrams, functions and calculus enable to take into account any level of price and
quantity in a given range of possible (real) values, and to express the essential features of the
relationships between relevant magnitudes in the general form y = f(x), which can then be
adapted to examine each particular case. They provide a general theoretical framework for the
study of economic phenomena, which enables to write equations such as
0=
dx
dxy
or xy = A,
aimed at developing principles of universal validity. Furthermore, the use of continuous and
differentiable functions makes Dupuit’s reasoning more precise, by taking into account
smaller price and quantity variations, and in some cases, improves his proofs, notably by
giving a better argument in support of Dupuit’ conclusion about the loss of utility due to a tax,
and by giving reasons to neglect the income effects that might have invalidated his method.
In light of the above remarks it can be said that, although Dupuit does not make the
most of mathematics as a tool of investigation in his own work, since he only used it in the
26
1844 appendix, he seems to have grasped its potential usefulness in making economic
analysis more general as well as more accurate. In this sense, the aim of his appendix seems to
be precisely to hint at the opportunities for the future development of economic theory that the
use of mathematics may provide:
“in presenting, in this note, some of the principles of our science in this particular form,
it was our wish to try and make clear how great would be the advantages of an alliance
with mathematics, despite the anathema which economists of all times have pronounced
against the latter” (Dupuit 1844, pp. 109).
4. Concluding remarks
Our attempt at reading Dupuit’s 1844 article in the light of the difficulties that made the
mathematical study of utility difficult at the time, has emphasized the novelty and interest of
his contribution. His effort to provide an operational definition of the measure of utility,
transforming it into a “quantity” that could be subject to mathematical and geometrical
treatment, succeeded in extending the domain of application of mathematics. In this sense, his
contribution is to be thought of as a considerable achievement, and a move ahead in the
development of mathematical economics (in spite of the criticisms that have been addressed
to consumer surplus arguments many years later).
On this basis, Dupuit was able to develop a fairly satisfactory analysis of market
demand, useful to gain a better understanding of the market mechanism, especially of the
principles determining prices. Nonetheless, we have shown that his notion of utility is still far
from the neoclassical one, that it is somewhat confused with demand, and that the principle of
utility maximization is underdeveloped in his writings. By contrast, the principle of profit
maximization is clearly stated and well developed in Dupuit’s writings –in a way that
reminds, to some extent, of Cournot’s Researches. Interestingly, despite the fact that Dupuit is
essentially remembered for his seminal contribution to the study of demand and consumption,
there is still a significant asymmetry between the producer and the consumer in his work. One
possible reason is the strong influence of the classical school, placing emphasis on the
production rather than the consumption side of the market.
Dupuit was also a pioneer in using advanced mathematics, including analytical
geometry and calculus, to study utility-related questions. Only Cournot had drawn demand
curves before –without, however, using them to analyse consumers’ utility and satisfaction.
Our examination of Dupuit’s text has stressed the advantages of using advanced mathematical
27
tools, instead of numerical examples, for discovery and proof in economics. It has been
shown that the use of mathematics makes Dupuit’s arguments more general, provides a broad
theoretical framework capable of dealing with a number of different particular cases,
improves his reasoning, and gives more accurate proofs of some of his main results. His work
gives a hint of the opportunities that the application of mathematical tools may provide for the
development of economic analysis, and in a sense, it prefigures the flourishing of
mathematical economics a few decades later. Interestingly, Dupuit’s praise of mathematics in
the last paragraph of his 1844 article indicates that, at least to some extent, he was aware of
the potential usefulness of mathematics as a tool of economic analysis.
Yet Dupuit used geometry and calculus only in the appendix to his 1844 article. He had
used numerical examples in the first part of the article, and switched back to them in
subsequent papers. Presumably, he did not change his mind as to the power of mathematics as
a tool of analysis, and was still aware of the weaknesses of numerical examples, which have
“the disadvantage of leaving some initial doubt about the general validity of the principles to
be developed” (Dupuit 1849, p. 7). He seems to have relied on them in the hope to make
himself understood in a simpler way, as well as in an effort to hint at the possible practical
application of his ideas to real-life cases: indeed, he ascribed to numerical examples “the
advantage of being much clearer and of showing up much better the applications of which the
theory is susceptible in practice” (Dupuit 1849, p. 7). Ironically, he may have been led to this
methodological choice by his very engineering background, which had provided him with the
mathematical knowledge necessary to perform the calculations and to conceive the proofs
outlined in the 1844 article. His duties as engineer in charge of public works may have led
him to give priority to the applied part of his work, so that he eventually preferred imperfect,
but practically more useful tools of analysis as numerical examples, to theoretically sounder,
but apparently more difficult to communicate, mathematical investigations.
28
References
Baloglou, Ch.P. (1995) Die Vertreter der mathematischen Nationalökonomie in Deutschland
zwischen 1838 und 1871, Marburg, Metropolis.
Bordas, L. (1847) “De la mesure de l’utilité des travaux publics. Réponse à l’article de M.
l’ingénieur en chef Dupuit”, in J. Dupuit, De l’utilité et de sa mesure. Ecrits choisis et
republiés par Mario de Bernardi (1934), Turin, La riforma sociale, and Paris, Marcel Giard,
pp. 67-96.
Chipman, J. S. and Moore, J.C. (1976) “The Scope of Consumer’s Surplus Arguments”, in
A.M. Tang, F.M. Westfield, J.S. Worley, eds., Evolution, Welfare, and Time in Economics,
Lexington, Mass., D.C. Heath & Company, pp. 69 – 123.
Cournot, A.-A. (1838) Recherches sur les principes mathématiques de la théorie des
richesses, Paris, Dunod, 2001.
Dupuit, J. (1842) “Considérations sur les frais d’entretien des routes”, Annales des Ponts et
Chaussées, s. II, t. III, pp. 1 – 90.
Dupuit, J. (1844) “De la mesure de l’utilité des travaux publics”, Annales des Ponts et
Chaussées, s. II, 2nd semester, pp. 332 – 375 ; English translation “On the Measurement of the
Utility of Public Works”, by R.H. Barback, International Economic Papers (1952), n. 2, pp.
83-110.
Dupuit, J. (1849) “De l’influence des péages sur l’utilité des voies de communication”,
Annales des Ponts et Chaussées, s. II, 1st semester, pp. 170-248 ; English translation of the
last section “On Tolls and Transport Charges”, by E. Henderson, International Economic
Papers (1962), n. 11, pp. 7-31.
Ekelund, R.B. Jr. and R.F. Hébert (1999) Secret Origins of Modern Microeconomics. Dupuit
and the Engineers, Chicago and London, The University of Chicago Press.
Ekelund, R.B. Jr. And R.F. Hébert (2000) “Jules Dupuit, Engineer and Economist”, An
Address to Faculty, Staff and Students at the University of Montréal, 2000.
Etner, F. (1987) Histoire du calcul économique en France, Paris, Economica.
Garnier, G. (1796) Abrégé élémentaire des principes de l’économie politique, 2nd edition
(1846), Paris, H. Agasse.
Grall, B. (2002) “De l’entretien des routes à la mesure de l’utilité : le calcul de substitution
chez Dupuit (1842 – 1844)”, in J.-P. Simonin and F. Vatin, eds., L’œuvre multiple de Jules
Dupuit (1804 – 1866). Calcul d’ingénieur, analyse économique et pensée sociale, Angers,
Presses Universitaires d’Angers, pp. 61 - 70.
Grall, B. (2003) Economie de forces et production d’utilités. L’émergence du calcul
économique chez les ingénieurs des Ponts et Chaussées (1831 – 1891), F. Vatin, ed., Rennes,
Presses Universitaires de Rennes.
29
Grall, B. and F. Vatin (2002) “La machine et l’impôt : Jules Dupuit, l’économie politique et la
mécanique industrielle”, in J.-P. Simonin and F. Vatin, eds., L’œuvre multiple de Jules Dupuit
(1804 – 1866). Calcul d’ingénieur, analyse économique et pensée sociale, Angers, Presses
Universitaires d’Angers, pp. 39 - 60.
Jaffé, W. (1965) Correspondence of Léon Walras and Related Papers, Amsterdam, North
Holland Publishing.
Marshall, A. (1890) Principles of Economics, London, Macmillan.
Navier, H. (1832) “De l’exécution des travaux publics et particulièrement des concessions”,
Annales des Ponts et Chaussées, s. I, 1st semester, n. XXXV, pp. 1 – 31.
Samuelson, P.A. (1974) “Complementarity – An Essay on the 40th Anniversary of the Hicks-
Allen Revolution in Demand Theory”, Journal of Economic Literature, vol. 12, n. 4, pp.
1255-89.
Say, J.-B. (1828 - 29) Cours complet d’économie politique pratique, 3rd edition (1852), Paris,
Guillaumin.
Theocaris, R.D. (1961) Early Developments in Mathematical Economics, London, St.
Martin's Press, 2nd ed. 1983.
Theocharis, R.D. (1993) The Development of Mathematical Economics: the Years of
Transition, from Cournot to Jevons, London, Macmillan.