ArticlePDF Available

Inadequate Evidence for Multiple Intelligences, Mozart Effect, and Emotional Intelligence Theories

Taylor & Francis
Educational Psychologist
Authors:

Abstract

I (Waterhouse, 2006) argued that, because multiple intelligences, the Mozart effect, and emo- tional intelligence theories have inadequate empirical support and are not consistent with cog- nitive neuroscience findings, these theories should not be applied in education. Proponents countered that their theories had sufficient empirical support, were consistent with cognitive neuroscience findings, and should be applied in education (Cherniss, Extein, Goleman, & Weissberg, 2006; Gardner & Moran, 2006; Rauscher & Hinton, 2006). However, Gardner and Moran offered no validating evidence for multiple intelligences, Rauscher and Hinton con- cluded that "listening-to-Mozart" studies should be disregarded, and Cherniss, Extein, Goleman, and Weissberg agreed that emotional intelligence lacked a unitary empirically sup- ported construct. My reply addresses theory proponents' specific criticisms of my review and reasserts my original claims. In "Multiple Intelligences, the Mozart Effect, and Emotional Intelligence: A Critical Review" (Waterhouse, 2006), I ar- gued that "MI theory has no validating data … the Mozart ef- fect theory has more negative than positive findings, and EI theory lacks a unitary empirically supported construct." I also argued that these theories' brain system claims were not consistent with relevant cognitive neuroscience findings and concluded that until these theories have garnered reasonable evidentiary support they should not be applied in education. Theory proponents counterargued that their theories were
WATERHOUSEINADEQUATE EVIDENCE
Inadequate Evidence for Multiple Intelligences,
Mozart Effect, and Emotional Intelligence Theories
Lynn Waterhouse
Child Behavior Research
The College of New Jersey, Ewing
I (Waterhouse, 2006) argued that, because multiple intelligences, the Mozart effect, and emo
-
tional intelligence theories have inadequate empirical support and are not consistent with cog
-
nitive neuroscience findings, these theories should not be applied in education. Proponents
countered that their theories had sufficient empirical support, were consistent with cognitive
neuroscience findings, and should be applied in education (Cherniss, Extein, Goleman, &
Weissberg, 2006; Gardner & Moran, 2006; Rauscher & Hinton, 2006). However, Gardner and
Moran offered no validating evidence for multiple intelligences, Rauscher and Hinton con
-
cluded that “listening-to-Mozart” studies should be disregarded, and Cherniss, Extein,
Goleman, and Weissberg agreed that emotional intelligence lacked a unitary empirically sup-
ported construct. My reply addresses theory proponents’ specific criticisms of my review and
reasserts my original claims.
In “Multiple Intelligences, the Mozart Effect, and Emotional
Intelligence: A Critical Review” (Waterhouse, 2006), I ar-
gued that “MI theory has no validating data the Mozart ef-
fect theory has more negative than positive findings, and EI
theory lacks a unitary empirically supported construct. I
also argued that these theories’ brain system claims were not
consistent with relevant cognitive neuroscience findings and
concluded that until these theories have garnered reasonable
evidentiary support they should not be applied in education.
Theory proponents counterargued that their theories were
well supported by both behavioral research and cognitive
neuroscience findings and should continue to be applied in
education (Cherniss, Extein, Goleman, & Weissberg, 2006;
Gardner & Moran, 2006; Rauscher & Hinton, 2006).
Gardner and Moran (2006) affirmed the importance of
empirical evidence for multiple intelligences (MI) theory,
stating that “Theories such as evolution or plate tectonics or
MI develop through the continuing accumulation of evi
-
dence. They claimed that abundant empirical evidence for
MI theory existed in the studies Gardner relied on to develop
his theory, but this claim conflates theory generation and the
-
ory validation. They also claimed that evidence for cognitive
systems such as reasoning and natural kind categorization of
-
fered support for MI theory, but they provided no proof for
this assertion.
Rauscher and Hinton (2006) conceded that “listen-
ing-to-Mozart” studies do have too many negative findings to
warrant being applied to the classroom. They argued instead
that skills developed in playing a music instrument transfer to
spatial skills, and thus music instruction studies have find
-
ings that are important for education. However, the concept
of transfer lacks adequate empirical support (Barnett & Ceci,
2002; Mayer, 2004; Perruchet & Vinter, 2002).
Cherniss et al. (2006) agreed that “conflicting constructs
continue to characterize EI theory, but they viewed these
conflicts as a sign of vitality. Cherniss et al. also argued that
EI had significant predictive validity but they provided lim
-
ited evidence to support this claim.
In the discussions that follow I address theory proponents’
criticisms of my review and offer arguments to explain prob
-
lems I found in their criticisms.
MI THEORY LACKS VALIDATING
EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE
Gardner and Moran (2006) asserted that I erred in claiming
that MI theory lacked empirical support, that I misconstrued
the conceptual basis of MI, that I misunderstood the defini
-
tions of several intelligences, and that I had a naïve view of
science that limited my ability to value Gardner’s MI theory.
EDUCATIONAL PSYCHOLOGIST, 41(4), 247–255
Copyright © 2006, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.
Correspondence should be addressed to Lynn Waterhouse, Child Behav
-
ior Research, The College of New Jersey, 234 Bliss Hall, Ewing, NJ 08628.
E-mail: lynwater@tcnj.edu
The following discussions respond to these criticisms and
outline two important evidence problems that Gardner and
Moran failed to address.
Gardner and Moran’s Proposed Evidence Does
Not Validate MI Theory
Gardner and Moran (2006) offered four evidentiary claims
for MI theory. First, they claimed that MI theory was empiri
-
cally validated by the fact that “Gardner combined the empir
-
ical findings of hundreds of studies from a variety of disci
-
plines” to develop MI theory. However, theory validation is a
process distinct from theory generation. The studies Gardner
read that led him to hypothesize that there might be MI may
serve to warrant the reasonableness of his hypothesis, but the
studies he read cannot validate the existence of MI.
Second, Gardner and Moran (2006) argued that MI
subcomponents were supported by empirical evidence for
“manyspecificneuralsystems liketheoryofmind,recogni
-
tion of natural kinds, understanding of self, understanding of
others, andbyevidencefor “systems of numerical, linguistic,
and causal reasoning. Gardner and Moran further argued that
“modules identified by evolutionary psychologists, contrary
to Waterhouse’s argument that they refute MI theory, actually
align very well with Gardner’s intelligences and their
subcomponents.” However, Gardner and Moran did not sup-
plya crucialspecification:Whichmultiple intelligence is sup-
ported by what evidence for which neural system or adapted
cognition module? For example, Astuti, Solomon, and Carey
(2004) reported findings for studies of natural kind conceptu-
alization in Madagascar. Natural kind conceptualization in-
cludes, among other things, seeing objects, animals, and other
humans; labeling objects and individuals; grouping objects
and individuals;and conceptualizing categories of groupings.
Consequently, Astuti et al.s evidence for natural kind catego
-
rization“alignswith”atleast fourintelligences: thevisualspa
-
tial intelligence, the naturalistic intelligence, the linguistic in
-
telligence, and the interpersonal intelligence.
Examination of individual adapted cognition modules and
cognitive systems revealed that their specific behavioral
components aligned with more than one multiple intelli
-
gence (Waterhouse, 2006), thus cutting across the boundaries
of Gardner’s intelligences. Consequently this evidence does
not provide empirical support for the intelligences but, con
-
versely, argues against the framework of MI.
A related problem is that neither Gardner nor any of his
adherents has defined a set of testable psychological
subcomponents for each of the intelligences (Allix, 2000).
Gardner (2004) asserted that because his “basic paradigm
clashes with that of psychometrics” (p. 214), and because
testing “results may well be misused, he will not define
testable subcomponents for the intelligences. Without such
subcomponents, the intelligences are defined only by gen
-
eral descriptions (Gardner, 1983, 1999, 2004), and the gen
-
erality of these descriptions has prevented researchers from
conducting studies to explore the validity of the
intelligences (Allix, 2000).
Gardner and Moran’s (2006) third evidentiary claim was
that Gardner, Feldman, and Krechevsky (1998) reported em
-
pirical evidence for multiple intelligence profiles in pre
-
school children. However, this 1998 report is inadequate as
support for MI theory. No formal data analysis was pre
-
sented, and the half-page discussion of findings is too brief
and too vague to be used by other researchers:
Assessments did identify distinctive profiles for a majority of
children every child exhibited at least one strength
there was little correlation between the children’s perfor
-
mances on the different activities because of the small
sample size (39 subjects), our results must be regarded as ten
-
tative. (Gardner et al., 1998, p. 27)
Fourth, Gardner and Moran (2006) claimed that MI theory
will ultimately accrue evidence comparable to that for evolu
-
tionary theory and plate tectonics theory. Even though only
23 years have elapsed since Gardner first proposed MI
(1983), Gardner and Moran’s claim can already be seen to be
mistaken. Unlike MI theory, evolutionary theory and plate
tectonics theory accrued important validating empirical find-
ings quite soon after they were proposed. In the 23 years fol-
lowing Darwin’s publication of Origin of Species in 1859
(Appleman, 2000), other scientists presented an array of fos-
sil and faunal evidence in support of Darwin’s theory
(Bowler, 1986). In the 23 years following the emergence of
plate tectonics theory in the 1960s, data collected from ocean
floor mapping, magnetic rock record measurement, radio-
metric dating of the Earth’s magnetic pole reversal history,
and precise location of earthquake sites provided strong vali
-
dating empirical evidence for plate tectonics theory
(Oreskes, 2003). MI theory has accrued no such validating
empirical evidence in the 23 years since it was proposed.
The Multiple Levels of MI
Gardner and Moran (2006) argued that I misconstrued the
intelligences as skills because I failed to “encompass the
several levels on which MI theory examines intelligences.
Gardner and Moran proposed (a) the finer level of neuro
-
logical subcomponents of each intelligence, (b) the middle
road level of the intelligences, and (c) the broader level of
skills that use the intelligences “to produce proficient
and/or expert behavior.
Contrary to Gardner and Moran’s (2006) claim, I did un
-
derstand these levels. My review outlined cognitive systems
of the same explanatory scope (middle road level) as MI
whose findings countered the nature and boundaries of MI
(Waterhouse, 2006). In their response Gardner and Moran re
-
defined the “What is it?” and “Where is it?” cognitive sys
-
tems down from middle road level to finer level neurological
subcomponents of the intelligences. They also redefined
248
WATERHOUSE
Kahneman’s decision-making processes up from middle
road level to broader level skills that would deploy Gardner’s
intelligences. These down-a-level and up-a-level
redefinitions had the effect of side-stepping the evidence
against MI theory that these systems provide. Moreover,
Gardner and Moran’s redefinitions were inaccurate.
What is it and where is it processing streams could
not be MI subcomponents.
The brain’s primary visual
cortex sends visual information along both the ventral (what
is it) and dorsal (where is it) processing streams, wherein
neurons further downstream to learn to respond to increas
-
ingly organized sets of features (Deco & Rolls, 2005). These
two streams begin with shared visual information, but the
dorsal stream moves to incorporate body-in-space process
-
ing, and the ventral stream moves to incorporate auditory
processing. Thus, each stream’s mixed content processing
precludes it from being construed as a subcomponent of any
individual multiple intelligence.
Kahneman’s systems could not be domain skills
deploying the intelligences.
Briefly, in Kahneman’s
(2003) prospect theory, Systems I and II governdecision mak-
ing by predicting utility value (Will this decision be good or
bad?). System I is spontaneous but rigid and is probably based
in limbic and basal ganglia neural circuits, whereas System II
is effortful but flexible and is probably based in frontal lobe
functions (Trepel,Fox,& Poldrack, 2005). System II operates
at the concept level, and System I operates both at the percept
and concept level (Kahneman, 2003). Because the percept
level is the same as Gardner and Moran’s finer level, and the
conceptlevelisthesameasGardner andMoran’smiddlelevel,
therefore neither System I nor System II could be interpreted
as broader level skills deploying the intelligences.
Understanding Definitions of
Specific Intelligences
Gardner and Moran (2006) were correct in stating that I be
-
lieved Gardner (2004) had proposed two additional types of
intelligence. Although Gardner may have intended some
-
thing different, nonetheless both the content and parallel
structure of his published text argue that there are two MI
profiles, each yielding a separate form of intelligence. The
text posits that individuals with high IQs have a mental
searchlight” (intelligence), whereas individuals with jagged
MI profiles have a laser-form of intelligence” (Gardner,
2004, p. 217).
Gardner and Moran (2006) argued that I was wrong to
state that intrapersonal and interpersonal intelligences were
combined into a personal intelligence. However, Gardner
(1983, 1999) did treat these two intelligences as part of a
larger whole of “personal intelligence” (1983, chapter 10;
1999, p. 43). For example, Gardner (1983) stated that “it is
important not to gloss over differences between the personal
and other forms of intelligence” (p. 240).
Gardner and Moran (2006) further argued that I was
wrong to include empathy for natural things as part of the
naturalist intelligence. However, Gardner (1999) proposed
that the naturalist intelligence involved biophilia, wherein
the naturalist “may well possess the talent of caring for, tam
-
ing, or interacting subtly with various living creatures” (p.
49). The word empathy does not seem to me to be wide of the
mark as a summary incorporating “biophilia” and “caring
for” and “interacting subtly.
My View of Science is Based on the
Practice of Science
Gardner and Moran (2006) argued that I had a naïve view of
science” that prevented me from being able to “acknowledge
or understand the enterprise in which Gardner has been en
-
gaged.” My view of science is exemplified in my practice of
science. For example, our research group synthesized neuro
-
science and behavioral findings on attachment to theorize
that abnormalities in the neurohormone oxytocin might con
-
tribute to attachment impairments found in autism (Modahl,
Fein, Waterhouse, & Newton, 1992; Waterhouse, Fein, &
Modahl, 1996). Our group then conducted empirical studies
of this hypothesis in which we did find evidence for abnor-
malities in oxytocin in autistic individuals (Green et al.,
2001; Modahl et al., 1998). Since that time other researchers
have conducted a wide range of related research, and genetic
evidence has linked an oxytocin receptor gene with autism
(Wu et al., 2005).
In fact, Gardner and Moran (2006) argued that my view of
science is naïve because I do not view Gardner’s synthesis of
research findings as validating evidence for MI theory. Syn
-
theses are important because they can summarize the current
state of research, can identify studies that should be con
-
ducted, and can yield new theories. However, if a new theory,
such as MI theory, is generated by the synthesis of existing
findings, then that new theory requires empirical validation.
MI Theory Problems That
Gardner and Moran Failed to Address
Gardner and Moran’s (2006) response failed to address two
problems for MI theory outlined in my review. Gardner
claimed that the successful application of MI theory in edu
-
cation provided empirical support for MI theory (Gardner,
2004, p. 214; Gardner & Connell, 2000, p. 292). However,
applying MI cannot provide evidence to validate the
intelligences because the act of applying MI theory assumes
the validity of the intelligences. Gardner and Moran offered
no response to this problem.
Second, Gardner (1999) asserted that MI theory depends
on each intelligence having its own neural processing circuit,
arguing that if “musical and spatial processing were identi
-
INADEQUATE EVIDENCE 249
cally represented” in neural circuits “that fact would suggest
the presence of one intelligence, and not two separate
intelligences” (p. 99). My review outlined evidence for
shared neural circuits for the processing of many different
types of content (Waterhouse, 2006). Gardner and Moran
(2006) offered no response to this evidence.
In summary, Gardner and Moran (2006) provided no vali
-
dating research evidence for MI theory, and they sidestepped
the problem that neuroscience findings for other cognitive
systems cut across MI boundaries. They were mistaken in
their claim that a theory based on a synthesis of research re
-
quires no empirical validation, and they did not address the
problem that application research cannot validate MI theory.
Finally, although Gardner (1999) claimed that MI theory
would be nullified if the neural processing circuits for differ
-
ent contents were found to be shared (p. 99), Gardner and
Moran offered no response to evidence that neural process
-
ing circuits for different contents are shared.
THE MOZART EFFECT AND
MUSIC LESSON TRANSFER
Rauscher and Hinton (2006) argued that I misconstrued the
concept of transfer and misrepresented the contents of a re-
view article by Schellenberg (2003). Their major criticism,
however, was that I was wrong to lump listening-to-Mozart
studies together with music instruction studies because “in-
struction studies, unlike the listening studies, have profound
implications for educational practice. The following sections
address these criticisms.
Transfer From Instrument Practice to
Spatial Skills is “For Free” Learning
I argued that Rauscher’s (2002) claim that music will lead to
improvement in spatial cognition (p. 276) meant that spatial
skill improvement occurred for free. Rauscher and Hinton
countered that because I lumped listening and lesson studies
together I failed to understand that improved spatial cogni
-
tion transferred via music lessons was not for free but was,
instead, effortful, because children expended effort in prac
-
ticing their instruments. Contrary to Rauscher and Hinton’s
claim, however, transfer is not effortful, it is for free learning.
For example, if a student practiced the violin daily, and with
-
out any practice in origami paper folding, showed enhanced
origami folding skills, then no matter how effortful the violin
practice was, the paper folding skill improvement is for free
because no effort was expended in practicing origami.
More important, Barnett and Ceci (2002) reviewed re
-
search on transfer and concluded that, despite 100 years of
research, no clear evidence has emerged, and many re
-
searchers believe there is no experimental design that can
determine whether or not transfer exists (p. 634). Mayer
(2004) also reviewed transfer research and concluded that
there was no evidence for general learning transfer, and no
evidence for specific skill transfer, but there was some evi
-
dence for specific transfer of general knowledge (pp.
217–218). Perruchet and Vinter (2002) reported that “to
-
tally negative results are certainly the most frequent out
-
come” in transfer research (p. 319).
Schellenberg’s (2003) Claims Concerning Music
Lesson Effects
Rauscher and Hinton (2006) argued that I misrepresented
Schellenberg (2003) by citing his article as support for the
claim that transfer from music to spatial skill had not been
demonstrated. Rauscher and Hinton argued that
Schellenberg’s (2003) statement that “positive transfer ef
-
fects to nonmusical domains, such as language, mathematics,
or spatial reasoning could be similarly unique for individuals
who take music lessons” (p. 444) meant that transfer from
music to spatial skills had been demonstrated. However,
Schellenberg’s statement (2003, p. 444) was hypothetical, as
framed by this preceding statement: “If we suspend our dis
-
belief, however, and assume that music education affects
abilities how could we account for this influence?” (p.
443). In fact, Schellenberg (2003) proposed that “music les-
sons may confer benefits by providing close and extended
contact with an adult other than a parent or teacher” and that
“similar effects should be evident with chess and draw-
ing” lessons (p. 444).
Music Instruction Studies Do Not Have
“Profound Implications” for Education
Rauscher and Hinton (2006) are to be commended as scien
-
tists for their forthright review of the evidence for their own
and others listening-to-Mozart studies. They concluded that
“Given the contradictory findings of the studies on children,
we agree with Waterhouse that educational practice should
not be influenced by this area of research.
Rauscher and Hinton (2006) argued that music instruction
studies, by contrast, have clearly demonstrated that skills de
-
veloped in playing a musical instrument do enhance spatial
skills. They cited two published studies (Rauscher et al.,
1997; Rauscher & Zupan, 2000) and a review (Hetland,
2000). Rauscher et al. (1997) reported that, unlike the control
group, 34 young children given piano keyboard lessons
showed spatial reasoning improvement that lasted for 1 day,
and Rauscher and Zupan (2000) reported that 34 young chil
-
dren given 8 months of keyboard lessons did significantly
better in creating an object from pieces than did controls.
Hetland (2000) reviewed 15 studies of music instruction’s as
-
sociation with improved spatial skills. However, only 6 of the
15 studies were published, and 2 of these 6 were the
Rauscher studies discussed previously (Rauscher et al.,
1997; Rauscher & Zupan, 2000). Moreover, 1 of the remain
-
ing 4 published studies was not directly relevant because it
250
WATERHOUSE
used music and spatial training to enhance math skills
(Graziano, Peterson, & Shaw, 1999). Of the 3 remaining pub
-
lished studies Hetland reviewed, only 1 reported an effect
with a p value of .05 or below (Costa-Giomi, 1999).
Thus, Rauscher and Hinton (2006) claimed “profound im
-
plications for educational practice” based on three published
studies that linked music instruction to spatial skill enhance
-
ment—two of which are from Rauscher’s own group. These
studies are promising, but insufficient at present to hold “pro
-
found implications” for education.
All Forms of Music’s Effect on
Spatial Skills Should Be Considered Together
Rauscher and Hinton (2006) stated that “Waterhouse’s con
-
flating listening studies with the music instruction studies
will lead to greater misinterpretation of the research by edu
-
cators, politicians, and laypeople. I have no wish to add to
misinterpretation of current findings, but I believe it is of
value to try to establish a comprehensive understanding of all
reported music effects on spatial cognition.
Rauscher and Hinton (2006) proposed three brain mecha
-
nisms for music’s ability to cause improved spatial cognition:
transfer, cortical arousal, and synaptic plasticity. Rauscher
and Hinton argued that music lessons provided spatial skill
transfer and cortical arousal, each of which separately con-
tributed to spatial skill improvement. They also proposed that
because rats exposed to a Mozart sonata demonstrated im-
proved maze learning and exhibited changes in brain synap-
ses (Chikahisa et al., 2006), therefore, synaptic changes
could be the cause of skill transfer.
Although current research findings do not support the no-
tion of transfer, neuroscience findings do suggest functional
connections among synaptic change, cortical arousal, repeti
-
tion, and overlapping neural circuits for different forms of
content. Brief repetition and cortical arousal confer
short-term enhancement of neural circuit activity, but
long-term motor skills, perceptual skills, and content memo
-
ries depend on synaptic and other neural changes that occur
when there has been extended repetition of in the circuitry
underwriting those skills and memories and when there has
been associated cortical arousal (Phelps, 2006; Squire &
Kandel, 2000). If there are general cross-content processing
neural circuits, formed by generalist genes (Kovas & Plomin,
2006), there may be cross-content enhancement of memory.
Consequently, from what is known, the following specu
-
lative model could be proposed. Short-term exposure to mu
-
sic provides general cortical arousal, as well as some specific
(priming) repetition of shared or overlapping circuits for mu
-
sic and spatial processing, which together may contribute to a
brief enhancement of spatial skills. Longer term exposure to
music, whether through extensive auditory exposure only (as
in the rat studies) or through extensive auditory exposure as
part of instrument practice, provides repeated and extended
cortical arousal and extensive repetition of the firing of
shared and overlapping neural circuits for music and spatial
skills. These extended effects, in turn, cause changes in gene
expression, and these changes in gene expression may lead to
reorganization of synaptic structures (and other forms of re
-
modeling of neural circuits). The structural changes may
support durative enhanced spatial skills.
This speculative model is consistent with neuroscience
findings and offers a coherent account of results from the dif
-
ferent types of music effect studies. It also provides an expla
-
nation for the fact that spatial skills are not the only cognitive
skills be found to be enhanced by music experience
(Schellenberg, 2004). Equally important, the model accounts
for spatial skill enhancement through music exposure or mu
-
sic instruction without invoking the unsupported notion of
transfer, and without resorting to a claim for a novel, previ
-
ously undiscovered cognitive process.
CONFLICTING CONSTRUCTS, FINDINGS,
AND CLAIMS FOR EMOTIONAL
INTELLIGENCE (EI)
Cherniss et al. (2006) argued that I was wrong to view multi-
ple conflicting EI measures and constructs as a problem,
wrong to argue that EI has limited predictive validity, wrong
to assert that Goleman claimed that EI accounts for more
than 80% of success, wrong to propose that EI was unlikely
to have a discrete neural system, and wrong to argue that EI
should not be applied in education. The following sections
address these five criticisms.
Lack of a Validated Unitary EI Construct
Remains a Problem
Cherniss et al. (2006) argued that the many conflicting EI
constructs are not a stumbling block for EI research. How
-
ever, the competing EI constructs demonstrate that EI is
poorly understood and make generalization across studies
extremely difficult. Van Rooy and Viswesvaran (2004) re
-
ported that studies of EI “have not used the same, or even a
few of the same, measures of EI” (p. 74). Moreover, efforts to
reconcile measures have been unsuccessful. For example,
Gignac, Palmer, Manocha, and Stough (2005) reported that a
confirmatory factor analysis could not even reconcile an off
-
spring measure of EI with its parent measure. Goldenberg,
Matheson, and Mantler (2006) could not demonstrate con
-
vergence of two measures of EI, the Mayer-Salovey-Caruso
Emotional Intelligence Test (MSCEIT) and SREIS, in a com
-
munity sample of 223 individuals. Correlations between
scores from the two EI measures for their three comparable
subscales (perceiving emotion, r = –.03; using emotions, r =
–.02; managing emotions, r = .04) were essentially zero
(Goldenberg, Matheson, & Mantler, 2006, p. 39).
Murphy (2006) reviewed the state of research on mea
-
sures of EI and concluded that not only are existing measures
INADEQUATE EVIDENCE 251
of EI inconsistent with one another but current constructs of
EI for which there are, as yet, no measures are so conceptu
-
ally unclear that these constructs will not be able to be trans
-
lated into measures.
EI Has Limited Predictive Validity
Cherniss et al. (2006) argued that, contrary to my review, five
published studies reported that EI has significant predictive
validity for a variety of life outcomes. However, these five
studies do not provide strong support for EI. One study as
-
sumed that attitudes, job skill, and leadership factors that dif
-
ferentiated better collection agents were subserved by EI
(Bachman, Stein, Campbell, & Sitarenios, 2000), and an
-
other reported only modest correlations for EI and leadership
(Rosete, & Ciarrochi, 2005). Lopes, Salovey, and Straus
(2003) expressed doubt about EI, concluding that “it is un
-
clear to what extent we are truly assessing skill, rather than
conformity or adjustment to social norms” (p. 655). Lopes,
Salovey, Côté, and Beers (2005) reported that only one of
four self-report EI subscales, emotional regulation, was asso
-
ciated with social adaptation (p. 5) and concluded that EI
skills “are likely to have only a modest impact on the quality
of social interactions” (p. 4). Moreover, the fifth study was a
meta-analysis of EI studies that revealed that EI did not have
predictive validity beyond that found for general intelligence,
but general intelligence did “significantly predict perfor-
mance beyond that explained by EI” (Van Rooy and
Viswesvaran, 2004, p. 87). Van Rooy and Viswesvaran
(2004) concluded that “the claims that EI can be a more im-
portant predictor than cognitive ability (e.g., Goleman, 1995)
are apparently more rhetoric than fact” (p. 87).
Van Rooy and Viswesvaran’s (2004) meta-analysis deter
-
mined that the correlation between EI and work performance
was .24 and between EI and academic performance was .10
(p. 86). Thus, EI predicted only 1% of the variance in aca
-
demic performance and only 8% of job performance vari
-
ance. Similarly, Bastian, Burns, and Nettelbeck (2005) re
-
ported that only 6% of the variance in life skills could be
predicted by EI (p. 1143).
Cherniss et al. (2006) cited Judge, Colbert, and Ilies
(2004) to argue that “IQ and other tests of cognitive ability
account for no more than about 25 percent of the variance in
outcomes. However, Deary, Strand, Smith, and Fernandes
(2006) reported that intelligence scores predicted 48% of the
variance of performance on General Certificate of Secondary
Education exams, and Rindermann and Neubauer (2004)
similarly found that intelligence scores predicted 43% of the
variance in academic achievement. Schmidt and Hunter’s
(1998) meta-analysis found that general intelligence “g” is
the most valid predictor of job performance, and Gottfredson
(1997) reviewed meta-analyses of the predictive validity of
intelligence measures for job performance and reported a
range of predictive validity from 23% to 65%. Thus, contrary
to Cherniss et al.s claim, studies have reported that general
intelligence accounts for more than 25% of the variance in
academic and job performance.
As noted by Cherniss et al. (2006), Van Rooy and
Viswesvaran (2004) found that EI had incremental predictive
validity in relation to personality factors (p. 86). However,
the EI basis for this increment is unclear, and the increment is
small. Gannon and Ranzijn (2005) found that EI added only
1.3% beyond the 34.2% of variance in life satisfaction ac
-
counted for by personality. Personality dimensions, in gen
-
eral, have been reported to have high predictive validity for
job performance. Hogan and Holland (2003), for example,
found that emotional stability predicted 43%, extraversion
35%, agreeableness 34%, conscientiousness 43%, and open
-
ness to experience 34% of variation in job performance.
No Ambiguity in Goleman’s Claim That EI
Accounts for More Than 80% of Success
Cherniss et al. (2006) offered no rebuttal of my claim that
Goleman’s 80% figure is a subjective judgment mistakenly
presented as “recent studies” (Waterhouse, 2006). Goleman
examined a list of 21 job skills that hegot from an unpublished
privately commissioned study (Goleman, 1998, p. 31) and de-
cided that 18 of the 21 skills were EI skills; thus, as 18 equals
85.7%of21,he judged that EI explainedmorethan80%oflife
success (Pool, 1997, p. 12) or more than 80% of job skill com-
petencies of superior workers (Goleman, 1998, p. 320).
In place of a direct rebuttal, Cherniss et al. (2006) sug-
gested that I had misunderstood the ambiguities in
Goleman’s work. However, Pool’s (1997) lecture report and
Goleman’s (1998) published statements are not ambiguous.
Pool did state that Goleman told members of the Associa-
tion for Supervision and Curriculum Development that “IQ
predicts only a small part of career performance—ranging
from 4 to 20 percent. But recent studies have shown that
emotional intelligence predicts about 80 percent of a per
-
son’s success in life” (p. 12). Goleman (1998) did claim
that “IQ alone at best leaves 75 percent of job success un
-
explained, and at worst 96 percent” (p. 19), and Goleman
(1998) did claim that “more than 80 percent of general
competencies that set apart superior from average perform
-
ers depend on emotional intelligence” (p. 320).
No Evidence for Neural Circuits for EI
Although at present no research has identified neural bases
for EI, Cherniss et al. (2006) argued that EI and IQ neural cir
-
cuits are separate, that EI depends on subcortical systems and
IQ on prefrontal cortex, and that EI includes discrete brain
systems for mindsight (recognizing that others have their
own thoughts) and for face recognition.
Cherniss et al.s (2006) brain claims for EI ignore the fact
that behavioral studies have consistently reported significant
correlations between EI and IQ and between EI and personal
-
ity(Schulte, Ree, & Carretta, 2004; Van Rooy& Viswesvaran,
252
WATERHOUSE
2004). Consequently, theorizingabout the brain circuits for EI
shouldinclude consideration oftheevidencefor structural and
neurochemical brain bases for general intelligence (Shaw et
al., 2006) and for personality (Paris, 2005). Moreover, instead
of considering only mindsight and face recognition, specula
-
tive models should address the full range of existing evidence
for neural bases for EI component behaviors such as attach
-
ment, empathy, face and emotion recognition, emotional sen
-
sation, emotional expression, the mirror neuron system, lan
-
guage skills, personality components, working memory,
long-term memory, reasoning, decision making, and others
(Waterhouse, 2006).
EI Is Not a Basis for Moral Conduct
Cherniss et al. (2006) claimed that programs such as social
emotional learning (SEL) could be used to “enhance posi
-
tive youth development and mental health, reduce sub
-
stance use and antisocial behavior, and improve educational
outcomes. However, because no one yet knows what EI
represents, beyond general mental ability and personality
components already identified as part of EI, and because
there is no empirically validated unitary construct of EI
(Murphy, 2006), therefore it remains premature to apply EI
to education. Furthermore, a review has suggested that
there is insufficient evidence for the beneficial effects of
SEL programs (Kristjannson, 2006).
Another problem of significance is that EI training has
been implied to be moral education. For example, Cherniss et
al. (2006) argued that EI/SEL training can reduce discipline
problems as well as make students more caring and responsi-
ble. However, in fact, nothing in any EI construct precludes
someone with high EI from being an immoral person.
Kristjannson (2006) analyzed whether or not components of
EI reflected moral principles, and he concluded that “EI lacks
moral depth and does not exclude the possibility that a calcu
-
lated Machiavellian personality can be deemed emotionally
intelligent” (p. 17).
In summary, none of Cherniss et al.s (2006) five criti
-
cisms survived close examination. Researchers do not yet
know what the conflicting measures for EI are actually
measuring. The five studies published in academic journals
that Cherniss et al. outlined as evidence for EI did not pro
-
vide strong empirical support for EI, and one of the five, a
meta-analysis of EI studies (Van Rooy & Viswesvaran,
2004), found that EI predicted only 1% of the variance in
academic performance and only 8% of the variance in
workplace performance. Goleman did claim that EI pre
-
dicted 80% of life and work performance. No research has,
as yet, provided evidence for the possibility that there are
unique brain circuits for the two core domains of EI.
Finally, as EI components contain no moral principles, pro
-
ponents should desist from implying that EI school pro
-
grams can provide moral education.
CONCLUSION: PERSISTING WITHOUT
ADEQUATE EVIDENCE
Although Gardner and Moran (2006), Rauscher and Hinton
(2006), and Cherniss et al. (2006) claimed that there was a
wealth of empirical support for their theories, Gardner and
Moran offered no research evidence to validate MI, Rauscher
and Hinton included only three published music instruction
studies with significant positive findings for spatial skill en
-
hancement, and Cherniss et al. provided five published stud
-
ies whose findings did not provide strong support for the pre
-
dictive validity of EI.
Despite their inadequate empirical bases, these theories
have wide currency and, unfortunately, may continue to be
applied in education because they tell “good news” stories.
Gardner’s MI theory tells us the story that we each have
eight forms of intelligence, so there is likely to be one in
which we can shine. Rauscher’s music transfer theory of
-
fers spatial skill improvement through music lessons—a
cognitive bonus for keeping music in the curriculum.
Goleman’s EI theory tells the story that job and life success
depends much more on our EI than our IQ, with the good
news that we can increase our EI.
Tilly (2006) argued that there are four modes of explana-
tion: conventions (accepted reasons for events and actions),
stories (simple cause and effect accounts), codes (sets of
rules such as legal judgments), and technical accounts (sys-
tematic discipline-based empirical explanations). Gardner
and Moran (2006), Rauscher and Hinton (2006), and
Cherniss et al. (2006) argued that MI, the music instruction
effect, and EI were validated technical accounts of brain
systems. In the absence of adequate validating empirical
support, and in the absence of concord with neuroscience
findings, these three theories are not validated technical ac
-
counts. Therefore, at present, despite their appeal, they
should not be applied in education.
REFERENCES
Allix, N. M. (2000). The theory of multiple intelligences: A case of missing
cognitive matter. Australian Journal of Education, 44, 272–288.
Appleman, P. (Ed.). (2000). Darwin Third Edition. New York: Norton.
Astuti, R., Solomon, G. E., & Carey, S. (2004). Constraints on conceptual
development: A case study of the acquisition of folkbiological and
folksociological knowledge in Madagascar. Monographs for the Society
for Research in Child Development, 69(3), 1–135.
Bachman, J., Stein, S., Campbell, K., & Sitarenios, G. (2000). Emotional in
-
telligence in the collection of debt. International Journal of Selection and
Assessment, 8, 176–182.
Barnett, S. M., & Ceci, S. J. (2002). When and where do we apply what we
learn? A taxonomy for far transfer. Psychological Bulletin, 128, 612–637.
Bastian, V. A., Burns, N. R., & Nettelbeck, T. (2005). Emotional intelligence
predicts life skills, but not as well as personality and cognitive abilities.
Personality and Individual Differences, 39, 1135–1145.
Bowler, P. J. (1986). Theories of human evolution: A century of debate,
1844–1944. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
INADEQUATE EVIDENCE
253
Cherniss, C., Extein, M., Goleman, D., & Weissberg, R. P. (2006). Emo
-
tional intelligence: What does the research really indicate? Educational
Psychologist, 41, 239–245.
Chikahisa, S., Sei, H., Morishima, M., Sano, A., Kitaoka, K., Nakaya, Y., et
al. (2006). Exposure to music in the perinatal period enhances learning
performance and alters BDNF/TrkB signaling in mice as adults. Behav
-
ioural Brain Research, 169, 312–319.
Costa-Giomi, E. (1999). The effects of three years of piano instruction on
children’s cognitive development. Journal of Research in Music Educa
-
tion, 47, 198–212.
Deary, I. J., Strand, S., Smith, P., & Fernandes, C. (in press). Intelligence and
educational achievement. Intelligence.
Deco, G., & Rolls, E. T. (2005). Attention, short-term memory, and action
selection: A unifying theory. Progress in Neurobiology, 76, 236–256.
Gannon, N., & Ranzijn, R. (2005). Does emotional intelligence predict
unique variance in life satisfaction beyond IQ and personality? Personal
-
ity and Individual Differences, 38, 1353–1364.
Gardner, H. (1983). Frames of mind: The theory of multiple intelligences.
New York: Basic Books.
Gardner, H. (1999). Intelligence reframed. New York: Basic Books.
Gardner, H. (2004). Audiences for the theory of multiple intelligences.
Teachers College Record, 106, 212–220.
Gardner, H., & Connell, M. (2000). Response to Nicholas Allix. Australian
Journal of Education, 44, 288–293.
Gardner, H., Feldman, D. H., & Krechevsky, M. (Eds.). (1998). Project Zero
frameworks for early childhood education: Volume 1, Building on chil
-
dren’s strengths: The experience of project spectrum. New York: Teachers
College Press.
Gardner, H., & Moran, S. (2006). The science in multiple intelligences:
A response to Lynn Waterhouse. Educational Psychologist, 41,
227–232.
Gignac, G. E., Palmer, B. R., Manocha, R., & Stough, C. (2005). An exami-
nation of the factor structure of the Schutte self-report emotional intelli-
gence (SSREI) scale via confirmatory factor analysis. Personality and In-
dividual Differences, 39, 1029–1042.
Goldenberg, I., Matheson, K., & Mantler, J. (2006). The assessment of emo-
tional intelligence: A comparison of performance-based and self-report
methodologies. Journal of Personality Assessment, 86, 33–45.
Goleman, D. (1995). Emotional intelligence. New York: Bantam.
Goleman, D. (1998). Working with emotional intelligence. New York: Ban
-
tam.
Goleman, D. (2001). Emotional intelligence: Issues in paradigm building. In
C. Cherniss & D. Goleman (Eds.), The emotionally intelligent workplace
(pp. 13–26). San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
Gottfredson, L. S. (1997). Why g matters: The complexity of everyday life.
Intelligence, 24, 79–132.
Graziano, A. B., Peterson, M., & Shaw, G. L. (1999). Enhanced learning of
proportional math through music training and spatial-temporal training.
Neurological Research, 21, 139–152.
Green, L., Fein, D., Modahl, C., Feinstein, C., Waterhouse, L., & Morris, M.
(2001). Oxytocin and autistic disorder: Alterations in peptide forms. Bio
-
logical Psychiatry, 50, 609–613.
Hetland, L. (2000). Learning to make music enhances spatial reasoning.
Journal of Aesthetic Education, 34, 179–238.
Hogan, J., & Holland, B. (2003). Using theory to evaluate personality and
job-performance relations: A socioanalytic perspective.
Journal of Ap
-
plied Psychology, 88, 100–112.
Judge, T. A., Colbert, A. E., & Ilies, R. (2004). Intelligence and leadership:
A quantitative review and test of theoretical propositions. Journal of Ap
-
plied Psychology, 89, 542–552.
Kahneman, D. (2003). A perspective on judgment and choice: Mapping
bounded rationality. American Psychologist, 58, 697–720.
Kovas, Y., & Plomin, R. (in press). Generalist genes: Implications for the
cognitive sciences. Trends in Cognitive Science.
Kristjannson, K. (2006). “Emotional intelligence” in the classroom? An Ar
-
istotelian critique. Educational Theory, 56, 39–56.
Lieberman, P. (2002). On the nature and evolution of the neural bases of
human language. American Journal of Physical Anthropology, 235,
36–62.
Lopes, P. N., Salovey, P., Côté, S., & Beers, M. (2005). Emotion regulation
abilities and the quality of social interaction. Emotion, 5, 113–118.
Lopes, P. N., Salovey, P., & Straus, R. (2003). Emotional intelligence, per
-
sonality, and the perceived quality of social relationships. Personality and
Individual Differences, 35, 641–658.
Mayer, R. E. (2004). Teaching of subject matter. Annual Review of Psychol
-
ogy, 55, 715–744.
Modahl, C., Fein, D., Waterhouse, L., & Newton, N. (1992). Does oxytocin
deficiency mediate social deficits in autism? Journal of Autism and Devel
-
opmental Disorders, 22, 449–551.
Modahl, C., Green, L., Fein, D., Morris, M., Waterhouse, L., Feinstein, C, et
al. (1998). Plasma oxytocin levels in autistic children. Biological Psychia
-
try, 43, 270–277.
Murphy, K. (Ed.). (2006). Critique of emotional intelligence: What are the
problems and how can they be fixed? Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
Associates, Inc.
Oreskes, N. (Ed.). (2003). Plate tectonics: An insider’s history of the modern
theory of the Earth. Boulder, CO: Westview.
Paris, J. (2005). Neurobiological dimensional models of personality: A re
-
view of the models of Cloninger, Depue, and Siever. Journal of Personal
-
ity Disorders, 19, 156–170.
Perruchet, P., & Vinter, A. (2002). The self-organizing consciousness. Be
-
havioral and Brain Sciences, 25, 297–388.
Phelps, E. A. (2006). Emotion and cognition: Insights from studies of the hu
-
man amygdala. Annual Review of Psychology, 57, 27–53.
Pool, C. R. (1997). Up with emotional health. Educational Leadership, 54,
12–14.
Rauscher, F. H. (2002). Mozart and the mind: Factual and fictional effects of
musical enrichment. In J. Aronson (Ed.), Improving academic achieve-
ment: Impact of psychological factors on education (pp. 269–278). New
York: Academic.
Rauscher, F. H., & Hinton, S. C. (2006). The Mozart effect: Music listening
is not music instruction. Educational Psychologist, 41, 233–238.
Rauscher, F. H., Shaw, G. L., Levine, L .J., Wright, E. L., Dennis, W. R., &
Newcomb, R. (1997). Music training causes long-term enhancement of
preschool children’s spatial-temporal reasoning abilities. Neurological
Research, 19, 1–8.
Rauscher, F. H., & Zupan, M. A. (2000). Classroom keyboard instruction
improves kindergarten children’s spatial-temporal performance: A field
experiment. Early Childhood Research Quarterly, 15, 215–228.
Rindermann, H., & Neubauer, A. C. (2004). Processing speed, intelligence,
creativity, and school performance: Testing of causal hypotheses using
structural equation models. Intelligence, 32, 573–589.
Rosete, D., & Ciarrochi, J. (2005). Emotional intelligence and its relation
-
ship to workplace performance outcomes of leadership effectiveness.
Leadership and Organization Development Journal, 26, 388–399.
Schellenberg, E. G. (2003). Does exposure to music have beneficial side ef
-
fects? In I. Peretz & R. Zatorre (Eds.), The cognitive neuroscience of mu
-
sic (pp. 430–448). New York: Oxford University Press.
Schellenberg, E. G. (2004). Music lessons enhance IQ. Psychological Sci
-
ence, 15, 511–514.
Schmidt, F. L., & Hunter, J. E. (1998). The validity and utility of selection
methods in personnel psychology: Practical and theoretical implica
-
tions of 85 years of research findings. Psychological Bulletin, 124,
262–274.
Schulte, M. J., Ree, M. J., & Carretta, T. R. (2004). Emotional intelligence:
not much more than “g” and personality. Personality and Individual Dif
-
ferences, 37, 1059–1068.
Shaw, P., Greenstein, D., Lerch, J., Clasen, J., Lenroot, R., Gogtay, N., et al.
(2006). Intellectual ability and cortical development in children and ado
-
lescents. Nature, 440, 676–679.
Squire, L. R., & Kandel, E. R. (2000). Memory: From mind to molecules.
New York: Freeman.
254 WATERHOUSE
Tilly, C. (2006). Why? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Trepel, C., Fox, C. R., & Poldrack, R. A. (2005). Prospect theory on the
brain? Toward a cognitive neuroscience of decision under risk. Cognitive
Brain Research, 23, 34–50.
Van Rooy, D. L., & Viswesvaran, C. (2004). Emotional intelligence: A
meta-analytic investigation of predictive validity and nomological net.
Journal of Vocational Behavior, 65, 1–95.
Waterhouse, L. (2006). Multiple intelligences, the Mozart effect, and emotional
intelligence: A critical review. Educational Psychologist, 41, 207–225.
Waterhouse, L., Fein, D., & Modahl, C. (1996). Neurofunctional mecha
-
nisms in autism. Psychological Review, 103, 457–489.
Wu, S., Jia, M., Ruan, Y., Liu, J., Guo, Y., Shuang, M., et al. (2005). Positive
association of the oxytocin receptor gene (OXTR) with autism in the Chi
-
nese Han population. Biological Psychiatry, 58, 74–77.
INADEQUATE EVIDENCE
255
... However, Gardner (1999) also argues that there is no hierarchy between the domains of intelligence, although it is the reality that in some societies linguistic and mathematical intelligence are more valued and prioritised (Visser et al., 2006). However, Waterhouse (2006) emphasised the limitations of the theory, claiming that there is insufficient empirical evidence of distinct and independent intelligences, and that the theory relies heavily on anecdotal observations and case studies. According to Waterhouse (2006), the evidence provided for the theory is subjective and lacks scientific rigour. ...
... However, Waterhouse (2006) emphasised the limitations of the theory, claiming that there is insufficient empirical evidence of distinct and independent intelligences, and that the theory relies heavily on anecdotal observations and case studies. According to Waterhouse (2006), the evidence provided for the theory is subjective and lacks scientific rigour. Despite these criticisms, Gardner's (1983Gardner's ( , 1999 rejection of a single, dominant intelligence can be considered consistent with the 2E paradigm, which acknowledges that intelligence is multifaceted and cannot be summarised by a single criterion, but rather involves a unique interplay of strengths and weaknesses. ...
... While Gardner's theory has led to important discussions about the diversity of human abilities and the need for varied instructional approaches, it is essential to critically evaluate its limitations and consider alternative perspectives to develop a comprehensive understanding of intelligence and education. Accordingly, Waterhouse (2006) criticised Gardner's theory as there is a lack of empirical evidence to support the existence of distinct and independent intelligence, arguing that the evidence provided for the theory is often subjective and lacks the empirical rigour necessary to validate the theory. Waterhouse (2006) also suggests that the theory also relies heavily on anecdotal observations and case studies rather than rigorous scientific research. ...
Thesis
Twice-exceptionality (2E) refers to individuals who possess both exceptional intellectual abilities and disabilities. This qualitative exploratory study primarily investigated the experiences of 2E learners and teachers who have previously taught, or currently teach, students with twice-exceptionality. The study examined such lived experiences with reference to philosophical, sociological and socio-cultural theoretical concepts. A combination of interviews and self-administered questionnaires was utilised for data collection following a protracted recruitment process in COVID-19 pandemic and post-pandemic conditions which, it was assumed, had limited consent to participate to seven teachers and five students based primarily in Plymouth. An indicative content analysis of the students` data and reflexive thematic analysis of teachers` data illustrated the importance of acknowledging of paradoxical combinations of ability and disability with additional conditions (e.g., eating disorders and depression). Socialisation difficulties in 2E students with autism and organisational skill problems in high potential students with ADHD were identified. Some teachers observed different characteristics in 2E students such as overconfidence and creative writing skills. However, it was also found that participating teachers were unaware of aspects of 2E and tended to avoid classifying their students as 2E or gifted. Thus, the generation of data on the lack of awareness of 2E provided an additional benefit and contribution to knowledge. The study emphasised the importance of tailored support and inclusive practices, intending to ensure that the voices of 2E students and teachers are heard and to determine their needs. With reference to empirical data and the existing literature, it will contribute the recognition and broader understanding of twice exceptionality, offering valuable insights for educational practitioners, policymakers, and researchers. Further research into this complex intersection of issues in diversity, inclusion, and twice-exceptionality is encouraged to enhance inclusivity and educational systems for 2E individuals.
... The lack of consensus around the conceptualization and measurement tools is a common criticism of EI (Grewal & Salovey, 2005;MacCann et al., 2020;Rooy et al., 2005;Waterhouse, 2006;Zeidner et al., 2008Zeidner et al., , 2013. However, Keefer et al. (2018) make the case for "the multiplicity of EI models as a healthy indicator of a relatively new and generative research area" (p. 6). ...
... Supporters of the Mayer and Salovey (1997) EI model object to the use of the term intelligence to refer to competencies, skills, behaviours, or traits that do not literally refer to emotions and intelligence, such as the competency of teamwork (Brackett & Mayer, 2003). Goleman has also been criticized for using anecdotal evidence (Ashkanasy & Daus, 2005) and over-stating the importance of EI in relation to performance (Waterhouse, 2006). However, an analysis of college course syllabi found that when EI is taught, 35% teach Goleman's model, compared to 3% for the Mayer and Salovey (1997) model (Joseph et al., 2019), so this curriculum focused on the Goleman model, despite the criticisms. ...
Article
Full-text available
Research suggests that developing undergraduates’ emotional intelligence (EI) may improve current academic and future work performance, as well as health and well-being. Curriculum to help undergraduate business management students improve their EI competencies was designed and implemented in a 4-credit course taught over 18 days. During 3-hour class periods, students participated in activities such as mindful walks, journaling, and guided meditations designed to improve self-awareness and self-management competencies. The steps in the Multiple Approaches to Understanding instructional design model are explained and illustrated with the entry points, analogies, and activities of the EI curriculum.
... The Catalog bases itself on many theoretical references, including the heavily criticized "Multiple Intelligences Theory" (MI), coined by Gardner (1983). The main criticism comes from Waterhouse (2006), who argues that, although there is sufficient evidence for the Multiple Intelligences to be offered as a reasonable hypothesis, Gardner still hasn't offered the specific parameters to be evaluated in order to validate his hypothesis, nor the empirical data after-the-fact to properly back it up. Other more recent authors also offer valid criticisms to the hypothesis, however, that is not entirely relevant for the purposes of the project or this article. ...
... The MI model was embraced by educational professionals, yet was not without criticism for its lack of empirical support (Gottfredson, 2004;Waterhouse, 2006), its failure to provide practical applications for practitioners (Collins, 1998), and Gardner's seemingly selective literature review to support the theory (Jensen, 1998). Gardner, various other systemic models of giftedness have emerged that offer alternative perspectives on intelligence and talent. ...
Thesis
Full-text available
The study assessed the quality and effectiveness of Integrated or Regular School, Gifted School, and Dedicated Classroom approaches in Saudi Arabia. By gathering survey data from 300 gifted secondary students in grades 10-12 and their parents, the study assessed and compared the quality and effectiveness of Integrated or Regular School, Gifted School, and Dedicated Classroom approaches in Saudi Arabia. The research questions explored stakeholder views regarding the provision of gifted education and perceptions of gifted teachers across these approaches. The data were analysed using both descriptive and inferential statistics. Additionally, a content analysis was conducted on open-ended responses from the participants to gain deeper insights into their perceptions and suggestions for improvement regarding gifted education in Saudi Arabia. The findings suggest that full-time gifted programs, such as those implemented through gifted schools, may be most effective in meeting the needs of these students. Furthermore, the study identifies the social and emotional needs of gifted students as an area requiring greater attention in gifted education programs across Saudi Arabia. The participants provided improvement suggestions that varied by approach. Students in gifted schools emphasised the need for improved instructional strategies and extracurricular activities, those in dedicated classes called for a better school environment and more academic enrichment opportunities, and students in regular schools believed that teachers needed more training. The study also found that personal characteristics were more highly valued by gifted students across the three approaches, which may relate to the students’ perceived unmet social and emotional needs. The study highlights the importance of tailoring gifted education to the 3 | Page unique needs of students and their families and provides insights into effective approaches to support their academic, social, and emotional growth.
... Esta evolução tornou-a uma prática indispensável no cenário educativo contemporâneo. Na Grécia Antiga, por exemplo, a educação era individualizada, com filósofos como Sócrates a adotarem um método dialético que se adaptava às necessidades individuais dos aprendizes (Waterhouse, 2005). No entanto, a Revolução Industrial trouxe consigo a institucionalização da educação e o desafio de ensinar um grande número de alunos de maneira padronizada (Tyack, 1974). ...
Thesis
Full-text available
O presente trabalho de projeto analisa a influência que a implementação do Ecossistema TI-Nspire™ STEM pode ter nas aprendizagens dos alunos e na prática letiva docente. O estudo de caso foi realizado num Agrupamento TEIP, inserido na zona da Área Metropolitana de Lisboa, e no qual participaram 21 alunos, 13 raparigas e nove rapazes, inscritos numa turma do 11º ano de escolaridade, do Curso Ciências e Tecnologias, sem qualquer tipo de experiência na utilização de calculadoras gráficas e sensores em anos anteriores. Participaram neste projeto as disciplinas de Matemática A, Físico-Química A, Biologia e Geologia e respetivas quatro docentes, que implementaram as atividades com recurso ao referido Ecossistema TI-Nspire™ STEM. Para analisar o impacto do projeto recorreu-se a uma metodologia mista, que incluiu a aplicação de um inquérito por questionário aos alunos, enquanto que às docentes foram realizadas entrevistas semiestrturadas. Os resultados sugerem que a introdução do Ecossistema TI-Nspire™ CX, com suas ferramentas pedagógicas TI-Nspire™ STEM, contribui positivamente para a melhoria das aprendizagens dos alunos, promovendo não apenas a compreensão do conteúdo e o desenvolvimento de competências, mas também o envolvimento e a motivação para aprender, assim como estimula práticas pedagógicas que cultivam a autonomia e o interesse dos alunos, promovendo uma reflexão estratégica sobre a melhoria e a continuidade das práticas educativas. This project work analyses the influence that the implementation of the TI-Nspire™ STEM Ecosystem can have on student learning and teaching practice. The case study was carried out in a TEIP Grouping, located in the Lisbon Metropolitan Area, and involved 21 students, 13 girls and nine boys, enrolled in an 11th grade Science and Technology class, with no experience of using graphing calculators and sensors in previous years. The Maths A, Physics and Chemistry A, Biology and Geology subjects and their four teachers took part in this project and implemented the activities using the TI-Nspire™ STEM Ecosystem. A mixed methodology was used to analyse the impact of the project, including a questionnaire survey for the students and semi-structured interviews for the teachers. The results suggest that the introduction of the TI-Nspire™ CX Ecosystem, with its TI-Nspire™ STEM pedagogical tools, contributes positively to improving student learning, promoting not only content understanding and skills development, but also engagement and motivation to learn, as well as stimulating pedagogical practices that cultivate student autonomy and interest, promoting strategic reflection on the improvement and continuity of educational practices.
... Subsequently, other theoretical models of intelligence were developed, such as those of Cattell, Vernon, Thurstone, Guilford and Sternberg, among others. The theory of multiple intelligences has generated a great deal of debate both pedagogically and academically (Ferrero et al., 2021;Geake, 2008;Howard-Jones, 2014;Jarrett, 2014;Waterhouse, 2006;Gardner, 2020). Even so, the author of MI theory himself, Howard Gardner, after receiving the Prince of Asturias Award in 2011, argued that the concept of multiple intelligences can be reinterpreted as "talent" (Gardner, 2020). ...
Article
Full-text available
Neuromyths are misconceptions arising from misinterpreted or biased data, often lacking scientific evidence and presenting unverified claims. Examples include the Mozart effect, Brain Gym, the idea that some people predominantly use one hemisphere of the brain, the belief that women are inherently better at multitasking, the notion that reggaeton benefits brain function, and the theory of multiple intelligences. Despite their initial popularity, these myths lack solid evidence. The main objective of this article is to select the most relevant neuromyths about movement that have had the greatest impact on education and society in order to demonstrate their inconsistencies and lack of scientific rigor, and then to show the most relevant academic literature that disproves them. To do so, we will refer to numerous meta-analyses, as well as quantitative and longitudinal studies. However, research on the relationship between movement and brain function has significantly expanded over the past decade. Validated tests and large sample studies provide strong evidence of the physical and cognitive benefits of movement, as thoroughly documented in numerous systematic reviews and bibliometric analyses. Nevertheless, certain educational and academic circles still promote information about movement and the brain that lacks scientific support and has questionable efficacy. Examples include claims about the relationship between crossed laterality and learning, learning styles, kinesthetic intelligence, and the notion that walking 10,000 steps a day is essential for fitness. Despite their widespread presence in some sectors, these claims have no scientific basis. This article aims to highlight neuromyths related to movement and reference high-impact publications that disprove these myths, demonstrating their inaccuracy.
... Note that the theory of multiple intelligences has been subject to strong critique due to its limited empirical support(Waterhouse, 2006); this also applies to allied concepts such as 'learning styles'(Kirschner & van Merriënboer, 2013). ...
Technical Report
Full-text available
The use of disciplinary categories and subject areas to structure primary school curricula is common in education systems worldwide. Increasing attention has been afforded to the potential offered by blurring or removing these disciplinary boundaries through integrated curriculum frameworks. While no one definition of curriculum integration exists, shared across all definitions is a focus on connections. Exactly what is connected varies from scholar to scholar, researcher to researcher and teacher to teacher. Proponents of curriculum integration cite the need to break down subject boundaries in pursuit of a more holistic education that reflects children’s experiences and supports skills such as critical thinking. Nevertheless, the rationale and evidence base for integration has been the subject of extensive critique. Key among these criticisms is a distinct ambiguity about what is meant by the term ‘curriculum integration’. The current review provides an extensive analysis of the theoretical, conceptual, curricular, and empirical literature to better address what curriculum integration is and what it looks like when implemented.
Chapter
Based on the theory of Multiple Intelligences (MI) (Gardner, 1983, 2011) the MI educational philosophy emphasizes the use of learners’ strengths to maximize both academic achievement and success in life. The eight multiple intelligences included in MI theory (linguistic, logical-mathematical, visual-spatial, musical, kinesthetic, naturalist, interpersonal, and intrapersonal) are described in relationship to traditional conceptions of general intelligence (IQ, unitary intelligence) (Kovacs, 2019) and learning styles (Kolb, 2005). MI theory can be used to address issues in second language acquisition, such as memorization, verbal skills, motivation, engagement, and learning attitude. This chapter describes how MI theory has inspired educational psychologists, teachers, and school administrators to devise creative lesson plans and curricula to enhance language instruction for students of all ages and ability levels. It reviews the foundations of MI theory rooted in neuroscience evidence along with guiding principles of educational neuroscience (Shearer, 2019). The chapter also highlights how models of instruction for second language acquisition, such as Basic Interpersonal Communication Skills (BICS) and Cognitive Academic Language Proficiency (CALP) (Cummins, 2000), Cognitive Academic Language Learning Approach (CALLA) (Chamot & Robbins, 2005), and Total Physical Response (Asher, 1969) practices can be implemented based on the eight intelligences. Sample lesson plans, learning outcomes, and the potential benefits of Artificial Intelligence in language instruction are briefly discussed (Eslit, 2024). This chapter closes with an outline for an action research project to facilitate the development of multiple intelligences-inspired language instruction and curriculum.
Chapter
Contemporary social science research is at a pivotal juncture amidst the era of transformative change. The exponential advancement of the new generation of information technologies represented by artificial intelligence has engendered in education, a pivotal domain within the realm of social sciences, the emergence of an entirely novel research paradigm. From the perspective of scientific history and philosophy, this article endeavors to elucidate the transformative influence of “computational pedagogy” as an emerging interdisciplinary field and scrutinize how artificial intelligence has revolutionized the landscape of educational research. In light of this inquiry, it becomes evident that artificial intelligence has profoundly expanded and refined the purview of educational research, through both large and small. Furthermore, it has pioneered methodological innovations within educational research by leveraging modeling and simulation. In addition, AI has galvanized the underpinnings of ethical reconstruction by supporting and empowering learning, thus positing human development as an intrinsic and cardinal value metric. Nonetheless, in the epoch of technological advancements, educational research must underscore the potency of intellectual acumen to avert the peril of “abundance-induced destitution” in the realm of computational pedagogy.
Article
Full-text available
This article summarizes the practical and theoretical implications of 85 years of research in personnel selection. On the basis of meta-analytic findings, this article presents the validity of 19 selection procedures for predicting job performance and training performance and the validity of paired combinations of general mental ability (GMA) and the 18 other selection procedures. Overall, the 3 combinations with the highest multivariate validity and utility for job performance were GMA plus a work sample test (mean validity of .63), GMA plus an integrity test (mean validity of .65), and GMA plus a structured interview (mean validity of .63). A further advantage of the latter 2 combinations is that they can be used for both entry level selection and selection of experienced employees. The practical utility implications of these summary findings are substantial. The implications of these research findings for the development of theories of job performance are discussed.
Article
Despite a century's worth of research, arguments surrounding the question of whether far transfer occurs have made little progress toward resolution. The authors argue the reason for this confusion is a failure to specify various dimensions along which transfer can occur, resulting in comparisons of "apples and oranges." They provide a framework that describes 9 relevant dimensions and show that the literature can productively be classified along these dimensions, with each study situated at the intersection of Various dimensions. Estimation of a single effect size for far transfer is misguided in view of this complexity. The past 100 years of research shows that evidence for transfer under some conditions is substantial, but critical conditions for many key questions are untested.
Article
Personnel selection research provides much evidence that intelligence (g) is an important predictor of performance in training and on the job, especially in higher level work. This article provides evidence that g has pervasive utility in work settings because it is essentially the ability to deal with cognitive complexity, in particular, with complex information processing. The more complex a work task, the greater the advantages that higher g confers in performing it well. Everyday tasks, like job duties, also differ in their level of complexity. The importance of intelligence therefore differs systematically across different arenas of social life as well as economic endeavor. Data from the National Adult Literacy Survey are used to show how higher levels of cognitive ability systematically improve individual's odds of dealing successfully with the ordinary demands of modern life (such as banking, using maps and transportation schedules, reading and understanding forms, interpreting news articles). These and other data are summarized to illustrate how the advantages of higher g, even when they are small, cumulate to affect the overall life chances of individuals at different ranges of the IQ bell curve. The article concludes by suggesting ways to reduce the risks for low-IQ individuals of being left behind by an increasingly complex postindustrial economy.