Content uploaded by Naomi Oreskes
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Naomi Oreskes on Apr 20, 2015
Content may be subject to copyright.
4
The Scientific Consensus on Climate
Change: How Do We Know We’re
Not Wrong?
Naomi Oreskes
In December 2004, Discover magazine ran an article on the top
science stories of the year. One of these was climate change,
and the story was the emergence of a scientific consensus over
the reality of global warming. National Geographic similarly
declared 2004 the year that global warming ‘‘got respect’’
(Roach 2004).
Many scientists felt that respect was overdue: as early as
1995, the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC)
had concluded that there was strong scientific evidence that
human activities were affecting global climate. By 2007, the
IPCC’s Fourth Assessment Report noted it is ‘‘extremely un-
likely that the global climate changes of the past fifty years can
be explained without invoking human activities’’ (Alley et al.
2007). Prominent scientists and major scientific organizations
have all ratified the IPCC conclusion. Today, all but a tiny
handful of climate scientists are convinced that earth’s climate
is heating up and that human activities are a significant cause.
Yet many Americans continue to wonder. A recent poll
reported in Time magazine (Americans see a climate problem
2006) found that only just over half (56 percent) of Americans
think that average global temperatures have risen despite the
fact that virtually all climate scientists think that they have.
1
More startlingly, a majority of Americans believe that scientists
are still divided about the issue. In some quarters, these doubts
have been invoked to justify the American refusal to join the
rest of the world in addressing the problem.
This book deals with the question of climate change and
its future impacts, and by definition predictions are uncertain.
People may wonder why we should spend time, effort, and
money addressing a problem that may not affect us for years
or decades to come. Several chapters in this book address that
question—explaining how some harmful effects are already
occurring, how we can assess the likely extent of future harms,
and why it is reasonable to act now to prevent a worst-case
scenario from coming true.
This chapter addresses a different question: might the scien-
tific consensus be wrong? If the history of science teaches any-
thing, it’s humility. There are numerous historical examples
where expert opinion turned out to be wrong. At the start
of the twentieth century, Max Planck was advised not to go
into physics because all the important questions had been
answered, medical doctors prescribed arsenic for stomach ail-
ments, and geophysicists were confident that continents could
not drift. Moreover, in any scientific community there are al-
ways some individuals who depart from generally accepted
views, and occasionally they turn out to be right. At present,
there is a scientific consensus on global warming, but how do
we know it’s not wrong?
The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change
Let’s start with a simple question: What is the scientific con-
sensus on climate change, and how do we know it exists?
Scientists do not vote on contested issues, and most scientific
66 Naomi Oreskes
questions are far too complex to be answered by a simple yes
or no, so how does anyone know what scientists think about
global warming?
Scientists glean their colleagues’ conclusions by reading their
results in published scientific literature, listening to presenta-
tions at scientific conferences, and discussing data and ideas in
the hallways of conference centers, university departments, re-
search institutes, and government agencies. For outsiders, this
information is difficult to access: scientific papers and confer-
ences are by experts for experts and are difficult for outsiders
to understand.
Climate science is a little different. Because of the political
importance of the topic, scientists have been unusually moti-
vated to explain their research results in accessible ways, and
explicit statements of the state of scientific knowledge are easy
to find.
An obvious place to start is the Intergovernmental Panel on
Climate Change (IPCC), already discussed in previous chap-
ters. Created in 1988 by the World Meteorological Organiza-
tion and the United Nations Environment Program, the IPCC
evaluates the state of climate science as a basis for informed
policy action, primarily on the basis of peer-reviewed and pub-
lished scientific literature (IPCC 2005). The IPCC has issued
four assessments. Already in 2001, the IPCC had stated un-
equivocally that the consensus of scientific opinion is that
earth’s climate is being affected by human activities. This view
is expressed throughout the report, but the clearest statement
is: ‘‘Human activities . . . are modifying the concentration of
atmospheric constituents ...that absorb or scatter radiant
energy. ...[M]ost of the observed warming over the last 50
years is likely to have been due to the increase in greenhouse
gas concentrations’’ (McCarthy et al. 2001, 21). The 2007
The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change 67
IPCC reports says ‘‘very likely’’ (Alley et al. 2007). The IPCC
is an unusual scientific organization: it was created not to
foster new research but to compile and assess existing knowl-
edge on a politically charged issue. Perhaps its conclusions
have been skewed by these political concerns, but the IPCC
is by no means alone it its conclusions, and its results have been
repeatedly ratified by other scientific organizations.
In the past several years, all of the major scientific bodies in
the United States whose membership’s expertise bears directly
on the matter have issued reports or statements that confirm
the IPCC conclusion. One is the National Academy of Sciences
report, Climate Change Science: An Analysis of Some Key
Questions (2001), which originated from a White House re-
quest. Here is how it opens: ‘‘Greenhouse gases are accumulat-
ing in Earth’s atmosphere as a result of human activities,
causing surface air temperatures and subsurface ocean temper-
atures to rise’’ (National Academy of Sciences 2001, 1). The re-
port explicitly addresses whether the IPCC assessment is a fair
summary of professional scientific thinking and answers yes:
‘‘The IPCC’s conclusion that most of the observed warming of
the last 50 years is likely to have been due to the increase in
greenhouse gas concentrations accurately reflects the current
thinking of the scientific community on this issue’’ (National
Academy of Sciences 2001, 3).
Other U.S. scientific groups agree. In February 2003, the
American Meteorological Society adopted the following state-
ment on climate change: ‘‘There is now clear evidence that the
mean annual temperature at the Earth’s surface, averaged over
the entire globe, has been increasing in the past 200 years.
There is also clear evidence that the abundance of greenhouse
gases has increased over the same period. . . . Because human
activities are contributing to climate change, we have a col-
68 Naomi Oreskes
lective responsibility to develop and undertake carefully con-
sidered response actions’’ (American Meteorological Society
2003). So too says the American Geophysical Union: ‘‘Scien-
tific evidence strongly indicates that natural influences cannot
explain the rapid increase in global near-surface temperatures
observed during the second half of the 20th century’’ (Ameri-
can Geophysical Union Council 2003). Likewise the American
Association for the Advancement of Science: ‘‘The world is
warming up. Average temperatures are half a degree centigrade
higher than a century ago. The nine warmest years this century
have all occurred since 1980, and the 1990s were probably the
warmest decade of the second millennium. Pollution from
‘greenhouse gases’ such as carbon dioxide (CO2) and methane
is at least partly to blame’’ (Harrison and Pearce 2000). Cli-
mate scientists agree that global warming is real and substan-
tially attributable to human activities.
These kinds of reports and statements are drafted through a
careful process involving many opportunities for comment,
criticism, and revision, so it is unlikely that they would diverge
greatly from the opinions of the societies’ memberships. Never-
theless, it could be the case that they downplay dissenting
opinions.
2
One way to test that hypothesis is by analyzing the contents
of published scientific papers, which contain the views that are
considered sufficiently supported by evidence that they merit
publication in expert journals. After all, any one can say any-
thing, but not anyone can get research results published in a
refereed journal.
3
Papers published in scientific journals must
pass the scrutiny of critical, expert colleagues. They must be
supported by sufficient evidence to convince others who know
the subject well. So one must turn to the scientific literature to
be certain of what scientists really think.
The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change 69
Before the twentieth century, this would have been a trivial
task. The number of scientists directly involved in any given
debate was usually small. A handful, a dozen, perhaps a hun-
dred, at most, participated—in part because the total number
of scientists in the world was very small (Price 1986). More-
over, because professional science was a limited activity, many
scientists used language that was accessible to scientists in
other disciplines as well as to serious amateurs. It was rela-
tively easy for an educated person in the nineteenth or early
twentieth century to read a scientific book or paper and under-
stand what the scientist was trying to say. One did not have to
be a scientist to read The Principles of Geology or The Origin
of Species.
Our contemporary world is different. Today, hundreds of
thousands of scientists publish over a million scientific papers
each year.
4
The American Geophysical Union has 41,000
members in 130 countries, and the American Meteorological
Society has 11,000. The IPCC reports involved the partici-
pation of many hundreds of scientists from scores of countries
(Houghton, Jenkins, and Ephraums 1990; Alley et al. 2007).
No individual could possibly read all the scientific papers on a
subject without making a full-time career of it.
Fortunately, the growth of science has been accompanied
by the growth of tools to manage scientific information. One
of the most important of these is the database of the Institute
for Scientific Information (ISI). In its Web of Science, the ISI
indexes all papers published in refereed scientific journals every
year—over 8,500 journals. Using a key word or phrase, one
can sample the scientific literature on any subject and get an
unbiased view of the state of knowledge.
Figure 4.1 shows the results of an analysis of 928 abstracts,
published in refereed journals during the period 1993 to 2003,
70 Naomi Oreskes
produced by a Web of Science search using the keyword phrase
‘‘global climate change.’’
5
After a first reading to determine ap-
propriate categories of analysis, the papers were divided as fol-
lows: (1) those explicitly endorsing the consensus position, (2)
those explicitly refuting the consensus position, (3) those dis-
cussing methods and techniques for measuring, monitoring,
or predicting climate change, (4) those discussing potential or
documenting actual impacts of climate change, (5) those deal-
ing with paleoclimate change, and (6) those proposing mitiga-
tion strategies. How many fell into category 2—that is, how
many of these papers present evidence that refutes the state-
ment: ‘‘Global climate change is occurring, and human activ-
ities are at least part of the reason why’’? The answer is
remarkable: none.
Figure 4.1
A Web of Science analysis of 928 abstracts using the keywords
‘‘global climate change.’’ No papers in the sample provided scientific
data to refute the consensus position on global climate change.
The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change 71
A few comments are in order. First, often it is challenging to
determine exactly what the authors of a paper do think about
global climate change. This is a consequence of experts writing
for experts: many elements are implicit. If a conclusion is
widely accepted, then it is not necessary to reiterate it within
the context of expert discussion. Scientists generally focus their
discussions on questions that are still disputed or unanswered
rather than on matters about which everyone agrees.
This is clearly the case with the largest portion of the papers
examined (approximately half of the total)—those dealing with
impacts of climate change. The authors evidently accept the
premise that climate change is real and want to track, evaluate,
and understand its impacts. Nevertheless, such impacts could,
at least in some cases, be the results of natural variability
rather than human activities. Strikingly, none of the papers
used that possibility to argue against the consensus position.
Roughly 15 percent of the papers dealt with methods, and
slightly less than 10 percent dealt with paleoclimate change.
The most notable trend in the data is the recent increase
in such papers; concerns about global climate change have
given a boost to research in paleoclimatology and to the devel-
opment of methods for measuring and evaluating global tem-
perature and climate. Such papers are essentially neutral:
developing better methods and understanding historic climate
change are important tools for evaluating current effects, but
they do not commit their authors to any particular opinion
about those effects. Perhaps some of these authors are in fact
skeptical of the current consensus, and this could be a motiva-
tion to work on a better understanding of the natural climate
variability of the past. But again, none of the papers used that
motivation to argue openly against the consensus, and it would
be illogical if they did because a skeptical motivation does not
72 Naomi Oreskes
constitute scientific evidence. Finally, approximately 20 percent
of the papers explicitly endorsed the consensus position, and
an additional 5 percent proposed mitigation strategies. In
short, the basic reality of anthropogenic global climate change
is no longer a subject of scientific debate.
6
Some readers will be surprised by this result and wonder
about the reliability of a study that failed to find any argu-
ments against the consensus position when such arguments
clearly exist. After all, anyone who watches the evening news
or trolls the Internet knows that there is enormous debate
about climate change, right? Well, no.
First, let’s make clear what the scientific consensus is. It is
over the reality of human-induced climate change. Scientists
predicted a long time ago that increasing greenhouse gas emis-
sions could change the climate, and now there is overwhelming
evidence that it is changing the climate and that these changes
are in addition to natural variability. Therefore, when contra-
rians try to shift the focus of attention to natural climate vari-
ability, they are misrepresenting the situation. No one denies
the fact of natural variability, but natural variability alone
does not explain what we are now experiencing. Scientists
have also documented that some of the changes that are now
occurring are clearly deleterious to both human commu-
nities and ecosystems (Arctic Council 2004). Because of global
warming, humans are losing their homes and hunting grounds,
and plants and animals are losing their habitats (e.g., Kolbert
2006; Flannery 2006).
Second, to say that global warming is real and happening
now is not the same as agreeing about what will happen in
the future. Much of the continuing debate in the scientific com-
munity involves the likely rate of future change. A good anal-
ogy is evolution. In the early twentieth century, paleontologist
The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change 73
George Gaylord Simpson introduced the concept of ‘‘tempo
and mode’’ to describe questions about the manner of evolu-
tion—how fast and in what manner evolution proceeded. Biol-
ogists by the mid-twentieth century agreed about the reality of
evolution, but there were extensive debates about its tempo
and mode. So it is now with climate change. Virtually all pro-
fessional climate scientists agree on the reality of human-
induced climate change, but debate continues on tempo and
mode.
Third, there is the question of what kind of dissent still
exists. The analysis of the published literature presented here
was done by sampling, using a keyword phrase that was in-
tended to be fair, accurate, and neutral: ‘‘global climate
change’’ (as opposed to, for example, ‘‘global warming,’’
which might be viewed as biased). The total number of papers
published over the last ten years having anything at all to do
with climate change is probably over ten thousand, and no
doubt some of the authors of the other over nine thousand
papers have expressed skeptical or dissenting views. But the
fact that the sample turned up no dissenting papers at all dem-
onstrates that any remaining professional dissent is now ex-
ceedingly minor.
This suggests something discussed elsewhere in this book—
that the mass media have paid a great deal of attention to a
handful of dissenters in a manner that is greatly disproportion-
ate with their representation in the scientific community. The
number of climate scientists who actively do research in the
field but disagree with the consensus position is evidently very
small.
This is not to say that there are not a significant number of
contrarians but to point out that most of them are not climate
scientists and therefore have little (or no) basis to claim to be
74 Naomi Oreskes
experts on the subjects on which they boldly pronounce. Some
contrarians, like the physicist Frederick Seitz, were once active
scientific researchers but have long since retired (and Seitz
never actually did research in climate science; he was a solid-
state physicist). Others, like the novelist Michael Crichton, are
not scientists at all. What Seitz and Crichton have in common,
along with most other contrarians, is that they do no new sci-
entific research. They are not producing new evidence or new
arguments. They are simply attacking the work of others and
mostly doing so in the court of public opinion and in the mass
media rather than in the halls of science.
This latter point is crucial and merits underscoring: the vast
majority of materials denying the reality of global warming do
not pass the most basic test for what it takes to be counted as
scientific—namely, being published in a peer-reviewed journal.
Contrarian views have been published in books and pamphlets
issued by politically motivated think-tanks and widely spread
across the Internet, but so have views promoting the reality of
UFOs or the claim that Lee Harvey Oswald was an agent of
the Soviet Union.
Moreover, some contrarian arguments are frankly disin-
genuous, giving the impression of refuting the scientific consen-
sus when their own data do no such thing. One example will
illustrate the point. In 2001, Willie Soon, a physicist at the
Harvard-Smithsonian Center for Astrophysics, along with
several colleagues, published a paper entitled ‘‘Modeling Cli-
matic Effects of Anthropogenic Carbon Dioxide Emissions:
Unknowns and Uncertainties’’ (Soon et al. 2001). This paper
has been widely cited by contrarians as an important example
of a legitimate dissenting scientific view published in a peer-
review journal.
7
But the issue actually under discussion in the
paper is how well models can predict the future—in other
The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change 75
words, tempo and mode. The paper does not refute the consen-
sus position, and the authors acknowledge this: ‘‘The purpose
of [our] review of the deficiencies of climate model physics and
the use of GCMs is to illuminate areas for improvement. Our
review does not disprove a significant anthropogenic influence
on global climate’’ (Soon et al. 2001, 259; see also Soon et al.
2002).
The authors needed to make this disclaimer because many
contrarians do try to create the impression that arguments
about tempo and mode undermine the whole picture of global
climate change. But they don’t. Indeed, one could reject all cli-
mate models and still accept the consensus position because
models are only one part of the argument—one line of evi-
dence among many.
Is there disagreement over the details of climate change? Yes.
Are all the aspects of climate past and present well understood?
No, but who has ever claimed that they were? Does climate
science tell us what policy to pursue? Definitely not, but it does
identify the problem, explain why it matters, and give society
insights that can help to frame an efficacious policy response
(e.g., Smith 2002).
So why does the public have the impression of disagreement
among scientists? If the scientific community has forged a
consensus, then why do so many Americans have the impres-
sion that there is serious scientific uncertainty about climate
change?
8
There are several reasons. First, it is important to dis-
tinguish between scientific and political uncertainties. There are
reasonable differences of opinion about how best to respond to
climate change and even about how serious global warming is
relative to other environmental and social issues. Some people
have confused—or deliberately conflated—these two issues.
76 Naomi Oreskes
Scientists are in agreement about the reality of global climate
change, but this does not tell us what to do about it.
Second, climate science involves prediction of future effects,
which by definition is uncertain. It is important to distinguish
among what is known to be happening now, what is likely to
happen based on current scientific understanding, and what
might happen in a worst-case scenario. This is not always easy
to do, and scientists have not always been effective in making
these distinctions. Uncertainties about the future are easily con-
flated with uncertainties about the current state of scientific
knowledge.
Third, scientists have evidently not managed well enough to
explain their arguments and evidence beyond their own expert
communities. The scientific societies have tried to communicate
to the public through their statements and reports on climate
change, but what average citizen knows that the American Me-
teorological Society even exists or visits its home page to look
for its climate-change statement?
There is also a deeper problem. Scientists are finely honed
specialists trained to create new knowledge, but they have little
training in how to communicate to broad audiences and even
less in how to defend scientific work against determined and
well-financed contrarians. Moreover, until recently, most scien-
tists have not been particularly anxious to take the time to
communicate their message broadly. Most scientists consider
their ‘‘real’’ work to be the production of knowledge, not its
dissemination, and often view these two activities as mutually
exclusive. Some even sneer at colleagues who communicate to
broader audiences, dismissing them as ‘‘popularizers.’’
If scientists do jump into the fray on a politically contested
issue, they may be accused of ‘‘politicizing’’ the science and
The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change 77
compromising their objectivity.
9
This places scientists in a
double bind: the demands of objectivity suggest that they
should keep aloof from contested issues, but if they don’t get
involved, no one will know what an objective view of the mat-
ter looks like. Scientists’ reluctance to present their results to
broad audiences has left scientific knowledge open to misrepre-
sentation, and recent events show that there are plenty of peo-
ple ready and willing to misrepresent it.
It’s no secret that politically motivated think-tanks such as
the American Enterprise Institute and the George Marshall In-
stitute have been active for some time in trying to communicate
a message that is at odds with the consensus scientific view
(e.g., Gelbspan 1997, 2004). These organizations have success-
fully garnered a great deal of media attention for the tiny num-
ber of scientists who disagree with the mainstream view and
for nonscientists, like novelist Michael Crichton, who pro-
nounce loudly on scientific issues (Boykoff and Boykoff 2004).
This message of scientific uncertainty has been reinforced by
the public relations campaigns of certain corporations with a
large stake in the issue.
10
The most well known example
is ExxonMobil, which in 2004 ran a highly visible advertis-
ing campaign on the op-ed page of the New York Times.
Its carefully worded advertisements—written and formatted
to look like newspaper columns and called op-ed pieces by
ExxonMobil—suggested that climate science was far too un-
certain to warrant action on it.
11
One advertisement concluded
that the uncertainties and complexities of climate and weather
means that ‘‘there is an ongoing need to support scientific re-
search to inform decisions and guide policies’’ (Environmental
Defense 2005). Not many would argue with this commonsense
conclusion. But our scientists have concluded that existing re-
search warrants that decisions and policies be made today.
12
78 Naomi Oreskes
In any scientific debate, past or present, one can always find
intellectual outliers who diverge from the consensus view. Even
after plate tectonics was resoundingly accepted by earth scien-
tists in the late 1960s, a handful of persistent resisters clung to
the older views, and some idiosyncratics held to alternative the-
oretical positions, such as earth expansion. Some of these men
were otherwise respected scientists, including Sir Harold Jef-
freys, one of Britain’s leading geophysicists, and Gordon J. F.
MacDonald, a one-time science adviser to Presidents Lyndon
Johnson and Richard Nixon; they both continued to reject
plate tectonics until their dying day, which for MacDonald
was in 2002. Does that mean that scientists should reject plate
tectonics, that disaster-preparedness campaigns should not use
plate-tectonics theory to estimate regional earthquake risk, or
that schoolteachers should give equal time in science class-
rooms to the theory of earth expansion? Of course not. That
would be silly and a waste of time.
No scientific conclusion can ever be proven, and new evi-
dence may lead scientists to change their views, but it is no
more a ‘‘belief’’ to say that earth is heating up than to say that
continents move, that germs cause disease, that DNA carries
hereditary information, and that HIV causes AIDS. You can al-
ways find someone, somewhere, to disagree, but these conclu-
sions represent our best current understandings and therefore
our best basis for reasoned action (Oreskes 2004).
How Do We Know We’re Not Wrong?
Might the consensus on climate change be wrong? Yes, it could
be, and if scientific research continues, it is almost certain that
some aspects of the current understanding will be modified,
perhaps in significant ways. This possibility can’t be denied.
The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change 79
The relevant question for us as citizens is not whether this sci-
entific consensus might be mistaken but rather whether there is
any reason to think that it is mistaken.
How can outsiders evaluate the robustness of any particular
body of scientific knowledge? Many people expect a simple an-
swer to this question. Perhaps they were taught in school that
scientists follow ‘‘the scientific method’’ to get correct answers,
and they have heard some climate-change deniers suggesting
that climate scientists do not follow the scientific method (be-
cause they rely on models, rather than laboratory experiments)
so their results are suspect. These views are wrong.
Contrary to popular opinion, there is no scientific method
(singular). Despite heroic efforts by historians, philosophers,
and sociologists, there is no answer to what the methods and
standards of science really are (or even what they should be).
There is no methodological litmus test for scientific reliability
and no single method that guarantees valid conclusions that
will stand up to all future scrutiny.
A positive way of saying this is that scientists have used a va-
riety of methods and standards to good effect and that philoso-
phers have proposed various helpful criteria for evaluating the
methods used by scientists. None is a magic bullet, but each
can be useful for thinking about what makes scientific informa-
tion a reliable basis for action.
13
How does current scientific
knowledge about climate stand up to these diverse models of
scientific reliability?
The Inductive and Deductive Models of Science
The most widely cited models for understanding scientific rea-
soning are induction and deduction. Induction is the process of
generalizing from specific examples. If I see 100 swans and
they are all white, I might conclude that all swans are white. If
80 Naomi Oreskes
I saw 1,000 white swans or 10,000, I would surely think that
all swans were white, yet a black one might still be lurking
somewhere. As David Hume famously put it, even though the
sun has risen thousands of times before, we have no way to
prove that it will rise again tomorrow.
Nevertheless, common sense tells us that the sun is extremely
likely to rise again tomorrow, even if we can’t logically prove
that it’s so. Common sense similarly tells us that if we had seen
ten thousand white swans, then our conclusion that all swans
were white would be more robust than if we had seen only
ten. Other things being equal, the more we know about a sub-
ject, and the longer we have studied it, the more likely our con-
clusions about it are to be true.
How does climate science stand up to the inductive model?
Does climate science rest on a strong inductive base? Yes.
Humans have been making temperature records consistently
for over 150 years, and nearly all scientists who have looked
carefully at these records see an overall increase since the
industrial revolution about 0.6to 0.7C (1.1to 1.3F)
(Houghton, Jenkins, and Ephraums 1990; Bruce et al. 1996;
Watson et al. 1996; McCarthy et al. 2001; Houghton et al.
2001; Metz et al. 2001; Watson 2001; Weart 2003). The em-
pirical signal is clear, even if not all the details are clear.
How reliable are the early records? How do you average the
data to be representative of the globe as a whole, even though
much of the early data comes from only a few places, mostly
in Europe? Scientists have spent quite a bit of time addressing
these questions; most have satisfied themselves that the empiri-
cal signal is clear. But even if scientists doubted the older
records, the more recent data show a strong increase in tem-
peratures over the past thirty to forty years, just when the
amount of carbon dioxide and other greenhouses gases in the
The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change 81
atmosphere was growing dramatically (McCarthy et al. 2001;
Houghton 2001; Metz et al. 2001; Watson 2001).
Moreover these records—based on measurements with
instruments, such as thermometers—are corroborated by inde-
pendent evidence from tree rings, ice cores, and coral reefs. A
recent paper by Jan Esper at the Swiss Federal Research Center
and colleagues at Columbia University, shows, for example,
that tree rings can provide a reliable, long-term record of tem-
perature variability that largely agrees with the instrumental
records over the past 150 years (Esper, Cook, and Schweing-
ruber 2003).
While many scientists are happy simply to obtain consistent
results—often no trivial task—others may deem it important
to find some means to test whether their conclusions are right.
This has led to the view that the core of scientific method is
testing theories through logical deductions.
Deduction is drawing logical inferences from a set of
premises—the stock-in-trade of Sherlock Holmes. In science,
deduction is generally presumed to work as part of what
has come to be known as the hypothetico-deductive model—
the model you will find in most textbooks that claim to
teach the scientific method. In this view, scientists develop
hypotheses and then test them. Every hypothesis has logical
consequences—deductions—and one can try to determine
whether the deductions are correct. If they are, they support
the hypothesis. If they are not, then the hypothesis must be
revised or rejected. It’s especially good if the prediction is
something that would otherwise be quite unexpected because
that would suggest that it didn’t just happen by chance.
The most famous example of successful deduction in the his-
tory of science is the case of Ignaz Semmelweis, who in the
1840s deduced the importance of hand washing to prevent the
spread of infection (Gillispie 1975; Hempel 1965). Semmelweis
82 Naomi Oreskes
had noticed that many women were dying of fever after giving
birth at his Viennese hospital. Surprisingly, women who had
their infants on the way to the hospital—seemingly under
more adverse conditions—rarely died of fever. Nor did women
who gave birth at another hospital clinic where they were
attended by midwives. Semmelweis was deeply troubled by
this.
In 1847, a friend of Semmelweis, Jakob Kolletschka, cut his
finger while doing an autopsy and soon died. Autopsy revealed
a pathology very similar to the women who had died after
childbirth; something in the cadaver had apparently caused his
death. Semmelweis knew that many of the doctors at his clinic
routinely went directly from conducting autopsies to attending
births, but midwives did not perform autopsies, so he hypothe-
sized that the doctors were carrying cadaveric material on their
hands, which was infecting the women (and killed his friend).
He deduced that if physicians washed their hands before
attending the women, then the infection rate would decline.
They did so, and the infection rate did decline, demonstrating
the power of the hypothetico-deductive method.
How does climate science stand up to this standard? Have
climate scientists made predictions that have come true? Abso-
lutely. The most obvious is the fact of global warming itself. As
already has been noted in previous chapters, scientific concern
over the effects of increased atmospheric carbon dioxide is
based on physics—the fact that CO2is a greenhouse gas. In
the early twentieth century, Swedish chemist Svante Arrhenius
predicted that increasing carbon dioxide from the burning of
fossil fuels would lead to global warming, and by midcentury,
a number of other scientists, including G. S. Callendar, Roger
Revelle, and Hans Suess, concluded that the effect might soon
be quite noticeable, leading to sea level rise and other global
changes. In 1965, Revelle and his colleagues wrote, ‘‘By the
The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change 83
year 2000, the increase in atmospheric CO2. . . may be suffi-
cient to produce measurable and perhaps marked change in cli-
mate, and will almost certainly cause significant changes in the
temperature and other properties of the stratosphere’’ (Revelle
1965, 9). This prediction has come true (Fleming 1998; Weart
2003; McCarthy et al. 2001; Houghton et al. 2001; Metz et al.
2001; Watson 2001).
Another prediction fits the category of something unusual
that you might not even think of without the relevant theory.
In 1980, climatologist Suki Manabe predicted that the effects
of global warming would be strongest first in the polar regions.
Polar amplification was not an induction from observations
but a deduction from theoretical principles: the notion of ice-
albedo feedback. The reflectivity of a material is called its
albedo. Ice has a high albedo. It reflects sunlight back into
space much more effectively than grass, dirt, or water, and
one reason polar regions are as cold as they are is that snow
and ice are very effective in reflecting solar radiation back into
space. But if the snow starts to melt and bare ground (or water)
is exposed, the reflection effect diminishes. Less ice means less
reflection, which means more solar heat is absorbed, leading
to yet more melting in a positive feedback loop. So once warm-
ing begins, its effects are more pronounced in polar regions
than in temperate ones. The Arctic Climate Impact Assessment
concluded in 2004 that this prediction has also come true
(Manabe and Stouffer 1980, 1994; Holland and Bitz 2003;
Arctic Council 2004).
Falsificationism
Ignaz Semmelweis is among the famous figures in the history of
science because his work in the 1840s foreshadows the germ
84 Naomi Oreskes
theory of disease and the saving of millions of human lives. But
the story has a twist because Semmelweis was right for the
wrong reason. Cadaveric matter was not the cause of the infec-
tions: germs were. In later years, this would be demonstrated
by James Lister, Robert Koch, and Louis Pasteur, who realized
that hand washing was effective not because it removed the
cadaveric material but because it removed the germs associated
with that material.
The story illustrates the fundamental logical flaw with the
hypothetico-deductive model—the fallacy of affirming the con-
sequent. If I make a prediction, and it comes true, it does not
prove that my hypothesis was correct; my prediction may
have come true for other reasons. The other reasons may be re-
lated to the hypothesis—germs were associated with cadaveric
matter—but in other cases the connection may be entirely co-
incidental. I can convince myself that I have proved my theory
right, but this would be self-deception. This realization led the
twentieth-century philosopher Karl Popper to suggest that you
can never prove a theory true but you can prove it false—a
view known as falsificationism (Popper 1959).
How does climate science hold up to this modification?
Can climate models be refuted? Falsification is a bit of a prob-
lem for all models—not just climate models—because many
models are built to forecast the future and the results will
not be known for some time. By the time we find out whether
the long-term predictions of a model are right or wrong, that
knowledge won’t be of much use. For this reason, many mod-
els are tested by seeing if they can accurately reproduce past
events. In principle, this should be an excellent test—a climate
model that failed to reproduce past temperature records might
be considered falsified—but in reality, it doesn’t work quite
that way.
The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change 85
Climate models are complex, and they involve many
variables—some that are well measured and others that are
not. If a model does not reproduce past data very well, most
modelers assume that one or more of the model parameters
are not quite right, and they make adjustments in an attempt
to obtain a better fit. This is generally referred to as model cal-
ibration, and many modelers consider it an essential part of the
process of building a good model. But the problem is that cali-
bration can make models refutation-proof: the model doesn’t
get rejected; it gets revised. If model results were the only basis
for current scientific understanding, they would be grounds for
some healthy skepticism. Models are therefore best viewed as
heuristic devices: a means to explore what-if scenarios. This is,
indeed, how most modelers use them: to answer questions like
‘‘If we double the amount of CO2in the atmosphere, what is
the most likely outcome?’’
One way in which modelers address the fact that a
model can’t be proved right or wrong is to make lots of
different models that explore diverse possible outcomes—
what modelers call ensembles. An example of this is
hclimateprediction.neti, a Web-based mass-participation ex-
periment that enlists members of the public to run climate
models on their home computers to explore the range of likely
and possible climate outcomes under a variety of plausible
conditions.
Over ninety thousand participants from over 140 countries
have produced tens of thousands of runs of a general circula-
tion model produced by the Hadley Centre for Climate Pre-
diction and Research. Figure 4.2 presents some initial results,
published in the journal Nature in 2005, for a steady-state
model in which atmospheric carbon dioxide is doubled relative
to preindustrial levels and the model earth is allowed to adjust.
86 Naomi Oreskes
The results in black are the climateprediction.net’s mass-
participation runs; the results in grey come from runs made by
professional climate scientists at the Hadley Centre on a super-
computer (Stainforth et al. 2005).
What does an ensemble like this show? For one thing, no
matter how many times you run the model, you almost always
get the same qualitative result: the earth will warm. The unan-
swered question is how much and how fast—in other words,
tempo and mode.
Figure 4.2
Changes in global mean surface temperature (C) after carbon dioxide
values in the atmosphere are doubled. The black lines show the results
of 2,579 fifteen-year simulations by members of the general public
using their own personal computers. The grey lines show comparable
results from 127 thirty-year simulations completed by Hadley Centre
scientists on the Met Office’s supercomputer (hwww.metoffive.gov
.uki). Figure prepared by Ben Sanderson with help from the
hclimateprediction.netiproject team.
Source: Reproduced by permission from
hhttp://www.climateprediction.net/science/results_cop10.phpi.
The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change 87
The models vary quite a bit in their tempo and mode, but
nearly all fall within a temperature range of 2to 8C(4
to
14F) within fifteen years after the earth’s atmosphere reaches
a doubling of atmospheric CO2. Moreover, most of the runs
are still warming at that point. The model runs were stopped
at year 15 for practicality, but most of them had not yet
reached equilibrium: model temperatures were still rising. Look
again at figure 4.2. If the general-public model runs had been
allowed to continue out to thirty years, as the Hadley Centre
scientists’ model runs do, many of them would apparently
have reached still higher temperatures, perhaps as high as 12C.
How soon will our atmosphere reach a CO2level of twice
the preindustrial level? The answer depends largely on how
much carbon dioxide we humans put into the atmosphere—a
parameter that cannot be predicted by a climate model. Note
also that in these models CO2does not continue to rise: it is
fixed at twice preindustrial levels. Most experts believe that
unless major steps are taken quickly, atmospheric CO2levels
will go well above that level. If CO2triples or quadruples, then
the expected temperature increase will also increase. No one
can say precisely when earth’s temperature will increase by
any specific value, but the models indicate that it almost surely
will increase. With very few exceptions, the models show the
earth warming, and some of them show the earth warming
very quickly.
Is it possible that all these model runs are wrong? Yes,
because they are variations on a theme. If the basic model
conceptualization was wrong in some way, then all the models
runs would be wrong. Perhaps there is a negative feedback
loop that we have not yet recognized. Perhaps the oceans can
absorb more CO2than we think, or we have missed some
other carbon sink (Smith 2002). This is one reason that con-
88 Naomi Oreskes
tinued scientific investigation is warranted. But note that
Svante Arrhenius and Guy Callendar predicted global warming
before anyone ever built a global circulation model (or even
had a digital computer). Climate models give us a tool for
exploring scenarios and interactions, but you don’t need a cli-
mate model to know that global warming is a real problem.
If climate science stands with or without climate models,
then is there any information that would show that climate
science is wrong? Sure. Scientists might discover a mistake
in their basic physical understanding that showed they had
misconceptualized the whole issue. They could discover that
they had overestimated the significance of carbon dioxide and
underestimated the significance of some other parameter. But if
such mistakes are found, there is no guarantee that correcting
them will lead to a more optimistic scenario. It could well be
the case that scientists discover neglected factors that show
that the problem is even worse than we’d supposed.
Moreover, there is another way to think about this issue.
Contrarians have put inordinate amounts of effort into trying
to find something that is wrong with climate science, and de-
spite all this effort, they have come up empty-handed. Year
after year, the evidence that global warming is real and serious
has only strengthened.
14
Perhaps that is the strongest argument
of all. Contrarians have repeatedly tried to falsify the consen-
sus, and they have repeatedly failed.
Consilience of Evidence
Most philosophers and historians of science agree that there is
no iron-clad means to prove a scientific theory. But if science
does not provide proof, then what is the purpose of induction,
hypothesis testing, and falsification? Most would answer that,
The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change 89
in various ways, these activities provide warrant for our views.
Do they?
An older view, which has come back into fashion of late, is
that scientists look for consilience of evidence. Consilience
means ‘‘coming together,’’ and its use is generally credited to
the English philosopher William Whewell, who defined it as
the process by which sets of data—independently derived—
coincided and came to be understood as explicable by the
same theoretical account (Gillispie 1981; Wilson 1998). The
idea is not so different from what happens in a legal case.
To prove a defendant guilty beyond a reasonable doubt, a
prosecutor must present a variety of evidence that holds to-
gether in a consistent story. The defense, in contrast, might
need to show only that some element of the story is at odds
with another to sow reasonable doubt in the minds of the
jurors. In other words, scientists are more like lawyers than
they might like to admit. They look for independent lines of ev-
idence that hold together.
Do climate scientists have a consilience of evidence? Again
the answer is yes. Instrumental records, tree rings, ice cores,
borehole data, and coral reefs all point to the same conclusion:
things are getting warmer overall. Keith Briffa and Timothy
Osborn of the Climate Research Unit of the University of East
Anglia compared Esper’s tree-ring analysis with six other
reconstructions of global temperature between the years 1000
and 2000 (Briffa and Osborn 2002). All seven analyses agree:
temperatures increased dramatically in the late twentieth cen-
tury relative to the entire record of the previous millennium.
Temperatures vary naturally, of course, but the absolute mag-
nitude of global temperatures in the late twentieth century was
higher than any known temperatures in the previous one thou-
90 Naomi Oreskes
sand years, and many different lines of evidence point in this
direction.
Inference to the Best Explanation
The various problems in trying to develop an account of how
and why scientific knowledge is reliable have led some philoso-
phers to conclude that the purpose of science is not proof, but
explanation. Not just any explanation will do, however; the
best explanation is the one that is consistent with the evidence
(e.g., Lipton 1991). Certainly, it is possible that a malicious
or mischievous deity placed fossils throughout the geological
record to trick us into believing organic evolution, but to a sci-
entist this is not the best explanation because it invokes super-
natural effects, and the supernatural is beyond the scope of
scientific explanation. (It might not be the best explanation to
a theologian, either, if that theologian was committed to heav-
enly benevolence.) Similarly, I might try to explain the drift of
the continents through the theory of the expanding earth—as
some scientists did in the 1950s—but this would not be the
best explanation because it fails to explain why the earth has
conspicuous zones of compression as well as tension. The phi-
losopher of science Peter Lipton has put it this way: every set of
facts has a diversity of possible explanations, but ‘‘we cannot
infer something simply because it is a possible explanation. It
must somehow be the best of competing explanations’’ (Lipton
2004, 56).
Best is a term of judgment, so it doesn’t entirely solve our
problem, but it gets us thinking about what it means for a
scientific explanation to be the best available—or even just
a good one. It also invites us to ask the question, ‘‘Best for
The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change 91
what purpose?’’ For philosophers, best generally means that an
explanation is consistent with all the available evidence (not
just selected portions of it), that the explanation is consistent
with other known laws of nature and other bodies of accepted
evidence (and not in conflict with them), and that the explana-
tion does not invoke supernatural events or causes that virtu-
ally by definition cannot be refuted. In other words, best can
be judged in terms of the various criterion invoked by all the
models of science discussed above: Is there an inductive basis?
Does the theory pass deductive tests? Do the various elements
of the theory fit with each other and with other established sci-
entific information? And is the explanation scientific in the
sense of being potentially refutable and not invoking unknown,
inexplicable, or supernatural causes?
Contrarians have tried to suggest that the climate effects we
are experiencing are simply natural variability. Climate does
vary, so this is a possible explanation. No one denies that. But
is it the best explanation for what is happening now? Most cli-
mate scientists would say that it’s not the best explanation. In
fact, it’s not even a good explanation—because it is inconsis-
tent with much of what we know.
Should we believe that the global increase in atmospheric
carbon dioxide has had a negligible effect even though basic
physics indicates otherwise? Should we believe that the correla-
tion between increased CO2and increased temperature is just a
weird coincidence? If there were no theoretical reason to relate
them and if Arrhenius, Callendar, Suess, and Revelle had not
predicted that all this would all happen, then one might well
conclude that rising CO2and rising temperature were merely
coincidental. But we have every reason to believe that there is
a causal connection and no good reason to believe that it is a
coincidence. Indeed, the only reason we might think otherwise
92 Naomi Oreskes
is to avoid committing to action: if this is just a natural cycle in
which humans have played no role, then maybe global warm-
ing will go away on its own in due course.
And that sums up the problem. To deny that global warming
is real is precisely to deny that humans have become geological
agents, changing the most basic physical processes of the earth.
For centuries, scientists thought that earth processes were so
large and powerful that nothing we could do would change
them. This was a basic tenet of geological science: that human
chronologies were insignificant compared with the vastness of
geological time; that human activities were insignificant com-
pared with the force of geological processes. And once they
were. But no more. There are now so many of us cutting down
so many trees and burning so many billions of tons of fossil
fuels that we have indeed become geological agents. We have
changed the chemistry of our atmosphere, causing sea level to
rise, ice to melt, and climate to change. There is no reason to
think otherwise.
Notes
1. Contrast this with the results of the Intergovernmental Panel on
Climate Change’s Third and Fourth Assessment Reports, which state
unequivocally that average global temperatures have risen (Houghton
et al. 2001; Alley et al. 2007).
2. It must be acknowledged that in any area of human endeavor,
leadership may diverge from the views of the led. For example, many
Catholic priests endorse the idea that priests should be permitted to
marry (Watkin 2004).
3. In recent years, climate-change deniers have increasingly turned to
nonscientific literature as a way to promulgate views that are rejected
by most scientists (see, for example, Deming 2005).
4. An e-mail inquiry to the Thomson Scientific Customer Technical
Help Desk produced this reply: ‘‘We index the following number of
The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change 93
papers in Science Citation Index—2004, 1,057,061 papers; 2003,
1,111,398 papers.’’
5. The analysis begins in 1993 because that is the first year for which
the database consistently published abstracts. Some abstracts initially
compiled were deleted from our analysis because the authors of those
papers had put ‘‘global climate change’’ in their key words, but their
papers were not actually on the subject.
6. This is consistent with the analysis of historian Spencer Weart,
who concluded that scientists achieved consensus in 1995 (see Weart
2003).
7. In e-mails that I received after publishing my essay in Science
(Oreskes 2004), this paper was frequently invoked.
8. And we do. According to Time magazine, a recent Gallup poll
reported that ‘‘64 percent of Americans think scientists disagree with
one another about global warming’’ (Americans see a climate problem
2006).
9. Objectivity certainly can be compromised when scientists address
charged issues. This is not an abstract concern. It has been demon-
strated that scientists who accept research funds from the tobacco in-
dustry are much more likely to publish research results that deny or
downplay the hazards of smoking than those who get their funds
from the National Institutes of Health, the American Cancer Society,
or other nonprofit agencies (Bero 2003). On the other hand, there is a
large difference between accepting funds from a patron with a clearly
vested interest in a particular epistemic outcome and simply trying
one’s best to communicate the results of one’s research clearly and in
plain English.
10. Some petroleum companies, such as BP and Shell, have refrained
from participating in misinformation campaigns (see Browne 1997).
Browne began his 1997 lecture by focusing on what he accepted as
‘‘two stark facts. The concentration of carbon dioxide in the atmo-
sphere is rising, and the temperature of the Earth’s surface is increas-
ing.’’ For an analysis of diverse corporate responses, see Van den
Hove et al. (2003).
11. For an analysis of one ad, ‘‘Weather and Climate,’’ see Environ-
mental Defense (2005). An interesting development in 2003 was that
Institutional Shareholders Services advised ExxonMobil shareholders
to ask the company to explain its stance on climate-change issues and
94 Naomi Oreskes
to divulge financial risks that could be associated with it (see ISS in fa-
vor of ExxonMobil 2003).
12. These efforts to generate an aura of uncertainty and disagreement
have had an effect. This issue has been studied in detail by academic
researchers (see, for example, Boykoff and Boykoff 2004).
13. Reliable is a term of judgment. By reliable basis for action, I mean
that it will not lead us far astray in pursuing our goals, or if it does
lead us astray, at least we will be able to look back and say honestly
that we did the best we could given what we knew at the time.
14. This is evident when the three IPCC assessments —1990, 1995,
2001—are compared (Houghton et al. 1990; Bruce et al. 1996; Wat-
son et al. 1996; Houghton et al. 2001; Metz et al. 2001; Watson
2001; see also Weart 2003).
References
Alley, Richard et al. 2007. Climate change 2007: The physical science
basis: Summary for policymakers. Intergovernmental Panel on Cli-
mate Change. Geneva: IPCC Secretariat. hhttp://www.ipcc.ch/
SPM2feb07.pdfi(accessed March 31, 2007).
American Geophysical Union Council. 2003. Human impacts of
climate. American Geophysical Union, Washington, DC. hwww.agu
.org/sci_soc/policy/climate_change_position.htmli(accessed March 1,
2005).
American Meteorological Society. 2003. Climate change research:
Issues for the atmospheric and related sciences. Bulletin of the Amer-
ican Meteorological Society 84. hhttp://www.ametsoc.org/policy/
climatechangeresearch_2003.htmli(accessed May 1, 2006).
Americans see a climate problem. Time.com, March 26. hhttp://
www.time.com/time/nation/article/0,8599,1176967,00.htmli(ac-
cessed May 1, 2006).
Arctic Council. 2004. Arctic climate impact assessment. Arctic Council,
Oslo, Norway. hhttp://www.acia.uaf.edui(accessed March 14, 2005).
Bero L. 2003. Implications of the tobacco industry documents for
public health and policy. Annual Review of Public Health 24: 267–
88.
The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change 95
Boykoff, M. T., and J. M. Boykoff. 2004. Balance as bias: Global
warming and the U.S. prestige press. Global Environmental Change
14: 125–36.
Briffa, K. R., and T. J. Osborn. 2002. Blowing hot and cold. Science
295: 2227–28.
Browne, E. J. P. 1997. Climate change: The new agenda. Paper pre-
sented at Stanford University, May 19, Group Media and Publica-
tions, British Petroleum Company.
Bruce, James P., Hoesung Lee, and Erik F. Haites, eds. 1996. Climate
change 1995: Economic and social dimensions of climate change.
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Deming, David. 2005. How ‘‘consensus’’ on global warming is used
to justify draconian reform. Investor’s Business Daily, March 18, A16.
Environmental Defense. 2005. Too slick: Stop ExxonMobil’s
global warming misinformation campaign. hhttp://actionnetwork.org/
campaign/exxonmobil?source=edac2i(accessed March 14, 2005).
Esper, J., E. R. Cook, and F. H. Schweingruber. 2003. Low-frequency
signals in long tree-ring chronologies for reconstructing past tempera-
ture variability. Science 295: 2250–53.
Flannery, Tim. 2006. The weather makers: How man is changing the
climate and what it means for life on earth. New York: Atlantic
Monthly Press.
Fleming, James Rodger. 1998. Historical Perspectives on Climate
Change. New York: Oxford University Press.
Gelbspan, Ross. 1997. The heat is on: The high stakes battle over
earth’s threatened climate. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Gelbspan, Ross. 2004. Boiling point: How politicians, big oil and
coal, journalists, and activists are fueling the climate crisis—and
what we can do to avert disaster. New York: Basic Books.
Gillispie, Charles C., ed. 1975. Semmelweis. In Dictionary of scientific
biography. Vol. 12. New York: Scribner.
Gillispie, Charles C., ed. 1981. Dictionary of scientific biography. Vol.
12. New York: Scribner.
Harrison, Paul, and Fred Pearce. 2000. AAAS atlas of population and
environment. Berkeley: University of California Press. hhttp://www
.ourplanet.com/aaas/pages/atmos02.htmli(accessed May 1, 2006).
96 Naomi Oreskes
Hempel, Carl. 1965. Aspects of scientific explanation, and other
essays in the philosophy of science. New York: Free Press.
Holland, M. M., and C. M. Bitz. 2003. Polar amplification of climate
change in coupled models. Climate Dynamics 21: 221–32.
Houghton, J. T., G. J. Jenkins, and J. J. Ephraums, eds. 1990.
Scientific assessment of climate change: Report of Working Group I.
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Houghton, J. T., Y. Ding, D. J. Griggs, M. Noguer, P. J. van der Lin-
den, X. Dai, K. Maskell, and C. A. Johnson, eds. 2001. Climate
change 2001: The scientific basis (Third Assessment Report). Intergov-
ernmental Panel on Climate Change. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press.
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC). 2005. About
IPCC, February 7. hhttp://www.ipcc.ch/about/about.htmi(accessed
March 1, 2005).
ISS in favor of ExxonMobil global warming proposals. Planet
Ark, May 19. hhttp://www.planetark.com/dailynewsstory.cfm/newsid/
20824/story.htmi(accessed March 14, 2005).
Kolbert, Elizabeth. 2006. Field notes from a catastrophe. New York:
Bloomsbury.
Lipton, Peter. 1991. Inference to the best explanation. Oxford:
Routledge.
Lipton, Peter. 2004. Inference to the best explanation. 2nd ed. Ox-
ford: Routledge.
Manabe, S., and R. J. Stouffer. 1980. Sensitivity of a global climate
model to an increase of CO2concentration in the atmosphere. Journal
of Geophysical Research 85(C10): 5529–54.
Manabe, S., and R. J. Stouffer. 1994. Multiple-century response of a
coupled ocean-atmosphere model to an increase of atmospheric car-
bon dioxide. Journal of Climate 7(1): 5–23.
McCarthy, James J., Osvaldo F. Canziani, Neil A. Leary, David
J. Dokken, and Kasey S. White, eds. 2001. Climate change 2001:
Impacts, adaptation and vulnerability. Intergovernmental Panel on
Climate Change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Metz, Bert, Ogunlade Davidson, Rob Swart, and Jiahua Pan, eds.
2001. Climate change 2001: Mitigation. Intergovernmental Panel on
Climate Change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change 97
National Academy of Sciences, Committee on the Science of Climate
Change. 2001. Climate change science: An analysis of some key ques-
tions. Washington, DC: National Academy Press.
Oreskes, N. 2004. Beyond the ivory tower: The scientific consensus on
climate change. Science 306(5702): 1686.
Popper, K. R. 1959. The logic of scientific discovery. London:
Hutchinson.
Price, Derek de Solla. 1986. Little science, big science—and beyond.
New York: Columbia University Press.
Revelle, Roger. 1965. Atmospheric carbon dioxide. In Restoring the
quality of our environment: A report of the Environmental Pollution
Panel, 111–33. Washington, DC: President’s Science Advisory Com-
mittee.
Roach, John. 2004. The year global warming got respect. National
Geographic, December 29. hhttp://news.nationalgeographic.com/
news/2004/12/1229_041229_climate_change_consensus.htmli(ac-
cessed February 24, 2005).
Smith, Leonard A. 2002. What might we learn from climate forecasts?
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 99 (suppl. 1): 2487–
92.
Soon, W., S. Baliunas, S. B. Idso, K. Y. Kondratyev, and E. S. Pos-
mentier. 2001. Modeling climatic effects of anthropogenic carbon di-
oxide emissions: Unknowns and uncertainties. Climate Research 18:
259–75.
Soon, W., S. Baliunas, S. B. Idso, K. Y. Kondratyev, and E. S. Pos-
mentier. 2002. Modeling climatic effects of anthropogenic carbon di-
oxide emissions: Unknowns and uncertainties, reply to Risbey. Climate
Research 22: 187–88.
Stainforth, D., T. Aina, C. Christensen, M. Collins, N. Faull, D. J.
Frame, J. A. Kettleborough, S. Knight, A. Martin, J. M. Murphy, C.
Piani, D. Sexton, L. A. Smith, R. A. Spicer, A. J. Thorpe, and M. R.
Allen. 2005. Uncertainty in predictions of the climate response to ris-
ing levels of greenhouse gases. Nature 433: 403–06.
Van den Hove, Sybille, Marc Le Menestrel, and Henri-Claude de Bet-
tignies. 2003. The oil industry and climate change: Strategies and eth-
ical dilemmas. Climate Policy 2: 3–18.
Watkin, Daniel J. 2004. Roman Catholic priests’ group calls for
allowing married clergy members. New York Times, April 28, B5.
98 Naomi Oreskes
Watson, Robert T., ed. 2001. Climate change 2001: Synthesis report.
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Watson, R. T., Marufu C. Zinyowera, and Richard H. Moss, eds.
1996. Climate change 1995: Impacts, adaptations and mitigation of
climate change—Scientific-technical analyses. Intergovernmental Panel
on Climate Change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Weart, Spencer R. 2003. The discovery of global warming. Cam-
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Wilson, Edward O. 1998. Consilience: The unity of knowledge. New
York: Alfred A. Knopf.
The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change 99