ArticlePDF Available

Evolution of consciousness: Phylogeny, ontogeny, and emergence from general anesthesia

Authors:

Abstract and Figures

Are animals conscious? If so, when did consciousness evolve? We address these long-standing and essential questions using a modern neuroscientific approach that draws on diverse fields such as consciousness studies, evolutionary neurobiology, animal psychology, and anesthesiology. We propose that the stepwise emergence from general anesthesia can serve as a reproducible model to study the evolution of consciousness across various species and use current data from anesthesiology to shed light on the phylogeny of consciousness. Ultimately, we conclude that the neurobiological structure of the vertebrate central nervous system is evolutionarily ancient and highly conserved across species and that the basic neurophysiologic mechanisms supporting consciousness in humans are found at the earliest points of vertebrate brain evolution. Thus, in agreement with Darwin's insight and the recent "Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness in Non-Human Animals," a review of modern scientific data suggests that the differences between species in terms of the ability to experience the world is one of degree and not kind.
Content may be subject to copyright.
Evolution of consciousness: Phylogeny, ontogeny,
and emergence from general anesthesia
George A. Mashour
a
and Michael T. Alkire
b,1
a
Departments of Anesthesiology and Neurosurgery, Neuroscience Graduate Program, University of Michigan Medical School, Ann Arbor, MI 48109; and
b
Veterans Administration Long Beach Healthcare System, Department of Anesthesiology and Perioperative Care, Center for the Neurobiology of Learning
and Memory, University of California, Irvine, CA 92697
Edited by Francisco J. Ayala, University of California, Irvine, CA, and approved April 9, 2013 (received for review February 11, 2013)
Are animals conscious? If so, when did consciousness evolve? We
address these long-standing and essential questions using a modern
neuroscientic approach that draws on diverse elds such as con-
sciousness studies, evolutionary neurobiology, animal psychology,
and anesthesiology. We propose that the stepwise emergence from
general anesthesia can serve as a reproducible model to study the
evolution of consciousness across various species and use current data
from anesthesiology to shed light on the phylogeny of consciousness.
Ultimately, we conclude that the neurobiological structure of the
vertebrate central nervous system is evolutionarily ancient and highly
conserved across species and that the basic neurophysiologic mecha-
nisms supporting consciousness in humans are found at the earliest
points of vertebrate brain evolution. Thus, in agreement with Darwins
insight and the recent Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness in
Non-Human Animals,a review of modern scientic data suggests
that the differences between species in terms of the ability to experi-
ence the world is one of degree and not kind.
Evolutionary biology forms a cornerstone of the life sciences and
thus the neurosciences, yet the emergence of consciousness
during the timeline of evolution remains opaque. As the theory of
evolution began to eclipse both religious explanations and Enlight-
enment doctrines regarding the singularity of human consciousness,
it became clear that consciousness must have a point of emergence
duringevolution andthat point likelyoccurred before Homo sapiens.
How,Darwin questioned, does consciousness commence?His
post-Beagle research on this question evidently caused him violent
headaches. One such headache can be expressed as the 20th century
philosophical distinction of phenomenal consciousness and access
consciousness (1). Phenomenal consciousness relates solely to sub-
jective experience, whereas access consciousness includes (among
other processes) the ability to report such experiences verbally
(otherdistinctions related to consciousness can befound in Table 1).
Thus, thescientist looking for objectiveindices of subjective events is
primarily limited to humans manifesting access consciousness, an
obstacle in studying the evolution of consciousness antecedent to
our species. We could, however, take solace in the dictum that on-
togeny recapitulates phylogeny and search for clues in developing
humans. Unfortunately, Haeckels theory of recapitulation is not
scientically sound and, even if applicable in this case, we would still
be constrained by the high probability that babies develop phe-
nomenal consciousness before access consciousness. To overcome
the limitations in identifying the birth of consciousness, we need
a reproducible experimental model in which (i) consciousness
emerges from unconsciousness at a discrete and measurable point,
(ii) phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness are closely
juxtaposed or collapsed, and (iii) assessment of neural structure and
function is possible. In this article, we consider top-down and bot-
tom-up approaches to consciousness, nonhumanconsciousness, and
the emergence of consciousness from general anesthesia as a model
for the evolution of subjectivity.
Top-Down and Bottom-Up Approaches to Consciousness
To locate the birth of consciousness on the evolutionary time-
line, it will be benecial to consider the basic neural machinery
that is thought to be involved in human consciousness (28). The
distinction between phenomenal and access consciousness was
noted, but phenomenal consciousness itself reects the disso-
ciable neurobiological processes of awareness and arousal (913)
(Table 1). Awareness refers to the content of consciousness (red
apple vs. blue sky), whereas arousal refers to brain activation and
level-of-consciousness (alert vs. drowsy vs. asleep vs. anesthetized).
A number of current theories about consciousness propose that
the cortex is the primary site containing the neural correlates of
awareness (1419), whereas midline subcortical brain structures
provide ascending arousal inuences to the cortex (15, 17, 19).
Thus, we can explore both top-down and bottom-up approaches
to consciousness.
Top-Down Approach. Seth et al. (14) propose three main physio-
logical reasons supporting the importance of the neocortex to
the process of consciousness. First, the electroencephalogram
of virtually all mammals and birds in the awake state is charac-
terized by desynchronized, high-frequency, and low-amplitude
activity. This pattern changes to one of low-frequency, high-
amplitude activity during depressed levels of consciousness such
as nonrapid eye movement (NREM) sleep, minimally conscious
states, and anesthesia. Thus, a state-dependent change in the
electrical ring properties of the neurons across the neocortex
varies with the level of arousal and strongly supports the idea
that neuronal activity in the brain (and particularly in the neo-
cortex) is a necessary requirement for consciousness (20).
Second, consciousness appears to be linked more specically
with neural activity in the thalamocortical system. In this view,
the midline brain structures of brainstem and midbrain are thought
to be important for keeping the cortex in an aroused or awake
state, whereas the cortical regions are thought to serve as specic
cognitive modules contributing to the contents of conscious ex-
perience. The idea that certain brain regions are more important
than others for generating the contents of consciousness is fur-
ther supported by a number of basic neurological facts. For in-
stance, a person could suffer the loss of the cerebellum or large
bilateral portions of the medial temporal lobes, including
amygdala and hippocampus complex, and would not become
unconscious. However, focal damage to specic areas of cortical
tissue will change the contents of a persons consciousness in
a way that matches the loss of function associated with the
specic area damaged. Cortical lesions can thus result in such
specic impairments of consciousness that one may no longer be
able to speak, perceive color, or identify parts of themselves as
their own (21). Damage to lower midline brain structures, on the
This paper results from the Arthur M. Sackler Colloquium of the National Academy of
Sciences, In the Light of Evolution VII: The Human Mental Machinery,held January
1012, 2013, at the Arnold and Mabel Beckman Center of the National Academies of
Sciences and Engineering in Irvine, CA. The complete program and audio les of most
presentations are available on the NAS Web site at www.nasonline.org/evolution_vii.
Author contributions: G.A.M. and M.T.A. wrote the paper.
The authors declare no conict of interest.
This article is a PNAS Direct Submission.
1
To whom correspondence should be addressed. E-mail: malkire@uci.edu.
www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1301188110 PNAS
|
June 18, 2013
|
vol. 110
|
suppl. 2
|
1035710364
other hand, will likely alter the level of consciousness (i.e., arousal)
without necessarily changing its contents.
Thalamocortical oscillations have been posited to be of critical
importance to consciousness because they help integrate func-
tionally diverse and spatially distinct cognitive modules in the
cortex (22, 23). The interplay of segregation and integration is
a fundamental focus of the integrated information theory of con-
sciousness (8, 24). The capacity of the thalamocortical system to
achieve both integration and differentiation is reected in higher
levels of Phi, a proposed metric for consciousness (8). Phi reects
the amount of information generated by an integrated system
beyond the information contained within the components of the
system. In principle, this measure captures the emergent property
of the system (consciousness) that cannot be causally reduced to
individual subsystems (particular brain regions). Phi is predicted to
decrease during sleep and seizures; preliminary evidence suggests
it also decreases during anesthesia (25), possibly due to impaired
long-range coupling of neural spike activity (26). Although the
integrated information theory of consciousness has yet to be de-
nitively demonstrated, it is a guiding paradigm that can inform
the evolution of consciousness from the network perspective.
Creatures with brain network systems that are capable of gener-
ating high values of Phi are more likely to be conscious (27).
Third, widespread brain activity appears correlated with con-
scious activity. Sensory input spreads quickly from sensory cortex
to parietal, temporal, and prefrontal areas (28). This spread of
cortical activity is also associated with recurrent local feedback
occurring along the way, followed shortly thereafter by long-
range feedback from anterior to posterior structures (29). These
long-range connections are thought to be important for the ex-
periential aspects of consciousness (i.e., awareness) (30) and
appear to be preferentially suppressed during general anesthesia
(26, 31). In particular, there is strong evidence that networks
across the frontal and parietal cortices are associated with
awareness across multiple sensory modalities (3234). The lat-
eral frontoparietal network plays a role in mediating conscious-
ness of the environment, whereas the medial frontoparietal
network plays a role in mediating internal conscious states such
as dreaming and internally directed attention (35, 36). It is be-
coming increasingly clear that the directionality of corticocortical
network communication is relevant to conscious processing. In-
formation processing from the caudal to rostral direction (feed-
forward) is associated with sensory processing that can occur in
the absence of consciousness (e.g., general anesthesia, priming)
(37, 38). In contrast, information processing in the rostral-to-
caudal direction (feedback or cortical reafference) is thought to
be associated with experience itself and is preferentially inhibited
by general anesthetics (3840).
The neocortical view of consciousness originates, in part, from
early morphologic examination of brain differences across species
that suggested the capacities of consciousness increased as brains
evolved from more primitive reptilian organization, to mammalian
(or, with a limbic system, paleomammalian), and then neo-
mammalian organization, characterized by an intricately folded
neocortex. This conceptualization of brain evolution occurring in
stages during which more advancedbrainsalong with their ex-
panded behavioral repertoirewere built on the structure of earlier
forms was popularized by Maclean as the triune brain(41). Im-
portantly, this view of brain evolution is now largely considered er-
roneous (42, 43). It did offer an easy conceptualization for relating
brain structure with function and suggested evolutionary time points
for when various behaviors would have emerged. Newer ndings,
however, strongly refute the model of a triune brain, especially the
concept of a later developing neocortex (Fig. 1) (42). As it turns out,
a precursor of the neocortex was actually present in the earliest
evolving vertebrates, a claim based on some aspects of connectivity
and homology of early transcription factor expression (44). The basic
structural pattern of a brainstem, midbrain, and forebrain did not
need to be completely reinvented as each new species emerged.
Rather, as various ecological niches were exploited by various crea-
tures, those brain regions best suited for enhancing survival in the
local environment were emphasized for further development (42).
Bottom-Up Approach. Since the discovery of the ascending re-
ticular activating system by Moruzzi and Magoun in the late
1940s (45), the fundamental and permissive role for arousal in
generating conscious states has been well established. It is now
Table 1. Denitions relevant to consciousness
Terms Explanation
Easy vs. hard problem of consciousness This distinction was drawn by philosopher David Chalmers. Easy
problems of consciousness (which are easy in principle only) include
understanding the neural basis of feature detection, integration,
verbal report, etc. The hard problem is the problem of experience;
even if we understand everything about neural function, it is not
clear how that would explain subjectivity.
Awareness Cognitive neuroscientists and philosophers use the term awareness
to mean only subjective experience. In clinical anesthesiology, the
term awareness is (inaccurately) used to include both consciousness
and explicit episodic memory.
Wakefulness vs. awareness Wakefulness refers to brain arousal, which can be manifest by
sleepwake cycles and can occur even in pathologic conditions of
unconsciousness such as vegetative states. Thus, being awake is
dissociable from being aware.
Phenomenal vs. access consciousness Phenomenal consciousness is subjective experience itself, whereas access
consciousness is that which is available to other cognitive processes
(such as working memory or verbal report).
External vs. Internal consciousness External consciousness is the experience of environmental stimuli
(such as the sound of an orchestra), whereas internal consciousness is
an endogenous experience (such as a dream state).
Consciousness vs. responsiveness An individual may fully experience a stimulus (such as the command
Open your eyes!) but not be able to respond (as when a patient is
paralyzed but conscious during surgery).
Levels of consciousness vs. contents of consciousness Levels of consciousness include distinctions such as alert vs. drowsy vs.
anesthetized, whereas the contents of consciousness refer to particular
phenomenal aspects such as a red rose vs. a blue ball.
10358
|
www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1301188110 Mashour and Alkire
clear how a number of specic nuclei and specic cell types within
the brainstem, midbrain, basal forebrain, and diencephalon send
long-range axons throughout the cortex to enhance arousal and
generate a neurochemical environment in the cortex that is ca-
pable of supporting consciousness (11). The role of arousal in
regulating overall levels of consciousness is clearly established in
connection with depressed levels of consciousness as during sleep
or coma (46). How arousal machinery interacts with conscious-
ness during more subtle cognitive and behavioral manipulations is
the subject of much current research (4749). However, through
the study of arousal as it relates to emotion (50, 51), another link
is made that puts some of Darwins later investigations into
a more modern light.
Darwin spent the later years of his career investigating the
similarities and differences associated with emotional expression
in man and animals (52). He reasoned that if animals show
emotion through behavioral expression, and man is an animal,
then the behavioral expression of emotion in man must share
a similar neurobiologic evolution with the other animals capable
of expressing similar emotions. Put another way, years before
behaviorism dominated neuroscience, Darwin saw how com-
monalities in emotional expression across species likely reected
the occurrence of similar underlying states of mind that only
made sense within a theory of evolution. Modern study into the
emotional lives of animals now reveals how fundamentally sim-
ilar the brain structures are that support affective reactions in
animals and humans (53).
Consciousness may not have emerged from the need to make
an internal representation of the outside world, but rather as an
extension of very basic primitive or primordial emotional inu-
ences. Such emotional inuences would generate an arousal
response in an organism and prepare its brain for action. This
hypothesis is well elaborated by Denton in his book on primor-
dial emotions (6). It posits that the most basic instincts, such
as thirst, hunger for air, hunger for salt and food, and the
desire for sex are the dening starting points for evolving
a conscious brain (36). This idea holds within it the concept of
intention, desire, and action selection, where the basic intention
of a movement is in the service of fullling a desire. As noted by
Darwin (52), So strongly are our intentions and movements
associated together, that if we eagerly wish an object to move in
any direction, we can hardly avoid moving our bodies in the same
direction, although we may be perfectly aware that this can have
no inuence.
The basic behavior of an organism is driven by a fundamental
physiologic need to maintain homeostasis. Those cells and
systems used for monitoring and maintaining the internal milieu
are referred to as interoceptors (6). The basic behaviors driving
homeostasis are evident as far back as the rst multicellular
organisms that needed a vascular system to provide nutrients
to those cells no longer exposed directly to the environment.
Creatures that could meet their basic homeostatic needs are the
ones that survived; those that did not suffered extinction. The
brain structures needed for generating arousal and primitive
emotional responses are generally located in the brainstem,
midbrain, and limbic system and are as old as the vertebrate
radiation itself (54).
Recent work on the lamprey, a jawless sh whose common
ancestor forms the basis for all vertebrates more than 500 million
years ago, has revealed just how ancient the neuroanatomy and
neurochemistry needed for action selection is. Findings reveal
that the lampreys behavioral motor output system shows similar
complexity to higher-level vertebrates who are capable of regu-
lating behavior by both direct and indirect motor output pathways
from the basal ganglia (55). In other words, the lamprey is capable
of both selecting a motor output to perform and at the same time
inhibiting the performance of other possible outputs. Thus, they
are capable of making a choice depending on the situation with
which they are confronted. This reduction of uncertainty(a
classic denition of information) through action selection may be
the precursor to the highly informative states of consciousness
characteristic of humans. We address the relationship of motoric
behavior and consciousness in the next section.
More complex neocortical abilities offered a survival advan-
tage to more complex brains by giving organisms a larger grasp of
their surroundings, but these systems developed over time and
used sensory information from the environment or exteroreceptors
(6). Denton illustrates his point with the example of a dehydrated
frog placed next to a water source in the sun. The frog has only
a limited capacity in its visual system and when placed next to
a source of water it will usually die without moving, unless it
stumbles on the water by accident. If, by chance, the frog nds the
water, it will drink, which suggests functioning interoreceptors. In
contrast, the more highly evolved visual system of the lizard allows
that creature to see the water and immediately drink, suggesting
that its more evolved brain more successfully couples its extero-
receptor-mediated perceptions with its interoreceptor-mediated
needs. This coupling of an internally based need system with an
externally based situational awareness system is likely the foun-
dation for the emergence of consciousness, and it closely corre-
sponds to the mental machinery seen in humans for generating
awareness and arousal.
The brainstem arousal centers are, for the most part, juxta-
posed with the sensory motor inputs and outputs of the cranial
nerves that supply the head and neck with its ability to orient
a creature to its environment and provide a stable platform for
sensing its surroundings. The motor output of the cranial nerves
is fundamentally linked with the expression of emotion in es-
sentially all vertebrates, and this likely emanates from the oldest
of the predatorprey relationships. In essence, an open mouth
signies a meal for the predator, and if the hunt is successful, it
would likely be associated with internal sensations of goal/task
completion that would serve to fulll a basic need for food in the
predator. This goal completion/desire fulllment would likely
have positive reinforcing value for an organism and might easily
be hypothesized to lead to internal states comparable to a sense
of pleasure (53). For the prey, an open mouth heading toward it
would certainly be cause for alarm, prompting an immediate
escape response that, if successful, might be associated with an
internal state of heightened arousal and fear (53). Thus, the most
basic emotions and arousal states are associated with internal
feedback networks that serve to guide an organisms behavior
toward its best possible situational outcome. This emotional
arousal machinery underlies essentially all behavioral choices in
the vertebrate brain.
Fig. 1. Theories of brain evolution. Ancient brain structure evolution theory
of Scala Naturae showing brain development proceeding from simple to
more complicated with the addition of new brain regions as evolution
progressed. This erroneous view is compared with a modern understanding
of brain structure evolution that reveals a basic common structure evolved in
the vertebrate brain and various regions expanded to accommodate each
specic animals needs. Modied from (42) with permission from Elsevier.
Mashour and Alkire PNAS
|
June 18, 2013
|
vol. 110
|
suppl. 2
|
10359
Consciousness in Nonhuman Species
If consciousness evolved in conjunction with cephalad develop-
ment of the central nervous system, then its emergence should, in
principle, be identiable at a discrete point on thetree of evolution.
Darwin reasoned that the cognitive differences between species
must be one of degree and not kind. This conclusion is consistent
with the recent Cambridge declaration that occurred on July 7,
2012, at the rst annual Francis Crick memorial conference on
consciousness.A group of prominent scientists formally declared in
a document entitled the Cambridge Declaration on Conscious-
ness in Non-Human Animalsthat the neurobiological structures
needed to support consciousness are not uniquely human (56). This
declaration essentially states that the capacity for consciousness
likely emerged very early in evolutionaryterms, and those processes
that support consciousness in humans are likely characteristic of
many living creatures. In fact, according to the declaration, based
on a number of considerations from comparative brain anatomy
and current knowledge about the neurobiology of consciousness, it
would seem almost certain that some form of consciousness is
present in all mammals and could have emerged on the evolu-
tionary timeline at the branch point of amniotes.
However, long before the Cambridge declaration, some thinkers
expressed serious concerns about attributing higher levels of con-
sciousness to all life. Indeed, Rene Descartes, often considered the
philosophical father of the mindbody relationship, questioned
whether a conscious self arose in the animal kingdom. He avoided
ascribing a conscious self to a particular animal because by doing so
he recognized that he mightbe compelled to ascribe a conscious self
to all animals. This all or none approach did not reect an evolu-
tionary theory perspective, which raised the possibility of a con-
scious continuum. This continuum, however, also introduces
difculty. As pointed out by Gallup, in discussing the emergence of
consciousness in animals (57), Where do we draw the line? On the
one hand, we could decide not to draw a line. This would presume
that all living things are sentient, conscious, and mindful. While the
data are admittedly incomplete, the issue should be taken seri-
ously. Life on this planet consists of several million different spe-
cies. Most are microorganisms, plants, and insects. I doubt that
there is a paramecium, a rosebush, or a termite alive today which is
aware of its own existence or has the capacity to become the object
of its own attention.With Gallups statement, we begin to see the
need for clarity in how or why we associate certain behaviors with
subjective experience and the need for some operational de-
nitions of the consciousnessbeing studied.
To identify the origin of sentience along an evolutionary time-
line, it is benecial to consider a common element that might link
consciousness across species, rather than focusing on the ostensibly
unique qualities of human experience such as self-reection.
Furthermore, this common element should likely relate to a goal-
directed behavior or response pattern that confers a survival
advantage in a given environment. In line with philosophers such
as Merleau-Ponty and neuroscientists such as Rudolfo Llinás and
György Buzsáki, we support motility (also referred to in this
context as motricity) as a strong candidate for the evolutionary
anlage of consciousness (58, 59). Consider, for example, the
unicellular paramecium, which is covered with several thousand
cilia. These cilia can serve both the function of sensing envi-
ronmental stimuli and initiating motility responses (e.g., attrac-
tion, avoidance) based on the nature of those stimuli. This
preneural example of a single structure (i.e., cilia and their co-
ordinated activity) mediating both sensation and response is in-
triguing but does not establish the primacy of motility as a kernel
of consciousness. Perhaps a more compelling case is that of the
sessile sea squirt, which possesses neural structures only tran-
siently during a larval stage (60). Neural ganglia and primordial
sensory processing allow the sea squirt to nd a suitable local
environment and underwater surface for attachment. However,
after this goal is achieved the neural tissue is digested, suggesting
a role related exclusively to movement. Although it is unlikely
that paramecia and sea squirts have phenomenal experience,
these early examples of sensation in the service of motility lead
us to start the search for the neurobiological origins of con-
sciousness in phylogenetically conserved structures.
What Is the Neural Coreof Consciousness?
To identify which aspects of the mental machinery should be the
focus of evolutionary consideration for consciousness, we need
to identify the neural correlates of the most primitive core of
human consciousness. The still emerging eld of consciousness
studies has been dominated in the last decade by a search for the
neural correlates of consciousness, which have been dened as
the specic and minimally adequate brain states that correspond
to states of consciousness (61). However, studies of the content
of consciousness (e.g., the awareness of a red rose placed in your
visual eld) already assume a conscious brain; thus, the neural
activity or structure identied in these paradigms correspond to a
specic content within a preexisting consciousness (62). Studying
the level of consciousness (e.g., arousal states) is also beset with
difculties. For example, the transition from a fully conscious to
unconscious state will inform us primarily of correlates required
for the full spectrum of waking human consciousness rather than
the minimal or core requirements. Furthermore, we must also
grapple with how to identify the true correlate (or substrate) of
consciousness vs. neural prerequisites or neural consequences of
consciousness (63, 64).
To address some of these difculties, a recent study explored
the neural correlates of the primitive form of consciousness that
arises during emergence from general anesthesia (65). With
anesthesia, the level of consciousness can be manipulated as an
experimental variable, and the resultant changes in brain activity
can then be determined with various neuroimaging and neuro-
physiologic techniques. Numerous studies have now examined
what happens to brain activity when consciousness is removed by
anesthesia (66, 67); however, fewer studies have investigated the
correlates of consciousness associated with its return following
a period of anesthesia (6871). In one recent study of healthy
male volunteers, positron emission tomography (PET) was used
to investigate the neural correlates of the recovery of con-
sciousness from the i.v. anesthetics propofol and dexmedeto-
midine (65). The order of the state transition is important
because the investigation of consciousness to unconsciousness
may yield a variety of nonspecic deactivations due to drug
effects that do not necessarily play a core role in consciousness.
The emergence of consciousness (as judged by the return of
a response to command) was correlated primarily with activity of
the brainstem (locus coeruleus), hypothalamus, thalamus, and
anterior cingulate (medial prefrontal area). Surprisingly, there
was limited neocortical involvement that correlated with this
primitive form of consciousness. Frontalparietal connectivity
appeared to be the key cortical response, which has been con-
rmed by studies of consciousness and anesthesia using electro-
encephalography (70). Similar ndings were seen in another
imaging study investigating the emergence of consciousness from
sleep (72). In the sleep study, midline arousal structures of the
thalamus and brainstem also recovered function well before
cortical connectivity resumed. Thus, the core of human con-
sciousness appears to be associated primarily with phylogeneti-
cally ancient structures mediating arousal and activated by
primitive emotions (36, 73), in conjunction with limited connec-
tivity patterns in frontalparietal networks (74, 75) (Fig. 2).
The emergence from general anesthesia may be of particular
interest to evolutionary biology, as it is observed clinically to prog-
ress from primitive homeostatic functions (such as breathing) to
evidence of arousal (such as responsiveness to pain or eye opening)
to consciousness of the environment (as evidenced by the ability to
follow a command) to higher cognitive function. Unlike the emer-
gence of consciousness over millions of years in phylogeny or
months during the gestational period in ontogeny, the emergence
10360
|
www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1301188110 Mashour and Alkire
of consciousness from the anesthetized state is a reproducible
model system that can be observed in real time over the course of
hours. Multimodal investigation using neuroimaging and neuro-
physiology, in conjunction with clinical observation and cognitive
evaluation, could uncover key shifts of neural activation or network
organization that support conscious processing. For example, high-
density electroencephalography could be used during recovery
from general anesthesia to measure Phi to help delineate in
humans the threshold for emerging consciousness. Such a thresh-
old could then be compared with other species in the waking state
to determine the relative value with reference to the neural core of
human consciousness. This approach could be applied to any
number of brain network properties, as assessed quantitatively
through graph theoretical methods (76).
Network approacheswhich have broad applicability in mathe-
matics, biology, computer science, and sociologymight be par-
ticularly attractive to test hypotheses across species, where func-
tionally similar cognitive systems may arise from neurobiologically
distinct structures. For example, the mammalian cortex and avian
pallium are histologically distinct (Table 2) (77), but may subserve
similar network functions that can be quantitatively assessed and
compared with human ndings. General anesthesia represents
a way of turning back the evolutionary clock of cognitive function
in humans anddepending on the depthand length of anes-
thetic exposureallows investigators to observe the return of
neural function in a way that could recapitulate phylogeny.
Although not without difculties (including the contamination of
access consciousness, because language is involved in assessing
return of consciousness after anesthesia), advantages of emer-
gence from anesthesia as a model system for the evolution of
consciousness include convenience, reproducibility, real-time
observation, possibility of subjective report of experiences (with
experiments in humans), and amenability to neuroscientic in-
vestigation across multiple species.
When Does Consciousness of the World Arise?
The recent experiments with general anesthesia in humans sug-
gest that phylogenetically ancient structures in the brainstem and
diencephalonwith only limited neocortical involvementare
sufcient to support primitive consciousness. Where, then, does
consciousness arise on the evolutionary timeline? One might be
tempted to conclude that consciousness commenced as our
mammalian ancestors evolved just beyond reptiles and their pre-
dominantly subcortical brains. However, paleontological ndings
suggest that the synapsid line that gave rise to mammals and the
sauropsid line that gave rise to reptiles and birds both diverged
from the primitive anapsid line at a single point 315 million years
ago (78). Furthermore, there is signicant evidence that avian
species are capable of higher cognition and even consciousness
itself (79). For example, birds demonstrate evidence of explicit
episodic recall (i.e., conscious memory of an event) (80) and
theory of mind (i.e., attribution of subjective mental events to
another being) (81). Thus, it would be misguided to try to identify
a single point at which consciousness emerged because evidence
suggests that consciousness evolved along two independent line-
ages. As pointed out by Butler et al. (82), birds and mammals
share a number of homologous traits despite this evolutionary
divergence, including a dramatic increase in their brainbody ra-
tios (compared with reptiles), homeothermy, extended parental
care of offspring, habitual bipedalism, distinct sleep stages, and
complex social interactions. The neurobiology also reects ho-
mologous advances, particularly in the mammalian neocortex and
the avian pallium (Table 2). These advances include the emer-
gence of recurrent or feedback processing, which is not found in
reptiles. Thus, both birds and early mammals are equipped with
a neural substrate consistent with conscious processing: phyloge-
netically conserved brainstem, diencephalic structures such as
thalamus and hypothalamus, and association neocortex (or
equivalent) capable of recurrent processing. All of these struc-
tures appear to play a role as the neural core for primitive con-
sciousness in humans, as evidenced by experiments with
general anesthesia.
The critical role of subcortical structures in consciousness has
been further argued based on clinical observations of hydra-
nencephalic children, who are essentially devoid of neocortex and
yet who still demonstrate some behavioral signs of consciousness
(75). Others have attempted to link the arousal related compo-
nents of consciousness with the contents of consciousness by
placing emphasis on the dynamic recurrent activity that occurs in
the thalamus or through the thalamic reticular nucleus when
consciousness is present (83, 84). As such, the PET study showing
that the emergence of consciousness is correlated with increased
Fig. 2. Brain structures functionally related to primitive emotional arousal
and the return of consciousness following sleep or anesthesia. The primitive
emotional response of air hunger shows activations in brainstem and anterior
cingulate regions; thalamic changes are also seen (73). Subjective emotional
arousal activates similar regions in an event-related functional MRI study of
picture viewing. Reproduced with permission from (85). Midline thalamic and
anterior cingulate arousal is seen with PET neuroimaging when consciousness
rst reemerges following sleep or anesthesia. Reproduced with permission
from (72 and 65). A common brainstem, thalamic, cingulate neuroanatomy
associated with conscious brain activity is seen. Images used with permission.
Table 2. Comparison of neocortex and pallium with respect to requirements for cell assemblies
Requirements for Hebbian cell assembly Structure of mammalian neocortex Structure of avian pallium
Many neurons of the same kind About 85% pyramidal cells High number of multipolar cells
Connections with each other Most synapses are between pyramidal cells Many synapses between multipolar cells
Excitatory connections About 90% of synapses are type 1 (excitatory) Many synapses excitatory
Modiable connections About 75% of synapses are on spines Dendrites are densely spiny
Individual neurons connected to as
many other neurons as possible
About 8,000 synapses per neuron Many synapses per neuron
Distant connections across the network Large amount of white matter Axons more interspersed with neurons
Modied from (77) with permission from Elsevier.
Mashour and Alkire PNAS
|
June 18, 2013
|
vol. 110
|
suppl. 2
|
10361
activity in primitivebrain regions may reect an arousal-related
response to the test stimulus itself rather than a direct awareness
of the stimuli that is occurring in the thalamus. In either event,
the data clearly show that the neurocircuitry associated with
arousal is fundamental to consciousness. A further recent study
investigating long-term memory encoding also imaged the neural
correlates of subjective emotional arousal. As shown in Fig. 2, the
neural correlates for awareness of subjective arousal induced by
viewing of emotional stimuli involve the same midbrain arousal
structures seen with activation of primordial emotions (85).
Regarding ontogeny of H. sapiens, peripheral sensory receptors
are thought to be present from 20 wk of gestation in utero. The
developmental anlage of the thalamus is present from around day
22 or 23 postconception, and thalamocortical connections are
thought to be formed by 26 wk of gestation (74). Around the same
time of gestation (2529 wk), electrical activity from the cerebral
hemispheres shifts from an isolated to a more continuous pattern,
with sleepwake distinctions appreciable from 30 wk of gestation.
Thus, both the structural and functional prerequisites for con-
sciousness are in place by the third trimester, with implications for
the experience of pain during in utero or neonatal surgery. It is of
interest to note that the third trimester of human development is
thought to be the period in which the maximal proportion of time
spent in REM sleep occurs across the lifespan (86). This nding
supports the ontogenetic theory of REM sleep as a process of in-
ternally driven neuronal activation that prepares the developing
cortex for the coming inux of sensory stimuli at birth. The theory
of REM sleep as a form of protoconsciousness has recently un-
dergone further elaboration (87).
When Does Consciousness of the Self Arise?
One component of consciousness that seems linked to higher
cognitive abilities is awareness of the self rather than simply
awareness of the environment. One way to test for this possibility
is to use what is known as the mirror self-recognition (MSR) test
(88). In 1970, Gallup found that chimpanzees, but not monkeys,
were able to pass the MSR test (89). This test presupposes that the
experimental subject has sufcient cognitive ability to be aware of
itself as an entity that is distinct from another conspecic. This
ability then denes one form of consciousness (i.e., the ability to
have awareness of ones own awareness or self). In Gallups well-
controlled experiment, the animals were rst allowed ample time
with mirror exposure to allow social responses to their reected
images to diminish greatly. The number of social responses and
the number of self-directed responses were measured before the
animals had a mark covertly placed on their forehead or ear while
they were briey anesthetized. The animals were then allowed to
recover from anesthesia, and some hours later a mirror was
reintroduced. On seeing themselves in the mirror, the marked
chimpanzeesbut not the marked monkeysexhibited mark-
directed responses by spending time investigating the area of the
mark and examining their ngers after touching the mark. The
ndings led Gallup to conclude insofar as self-recognition of
ones mirror image implies a concept of self, these data would
seem to qualify as the rst experimental demonstration of a self-
concept in a subhuman form.Regarding the difference between
chimpanzee and monkey, he further concluded, Our data suggest
that we may have found a qualitative psychological difference
among primates, and that the capacity for self-recognition may
not extend below man and the great apes.The distinction among
primates suggests that the qualitative nature of the conscious
experience varies greatly across species and the introspective
nature of human consciousness may be evolutionarily quite rare.
The MSR test has now been used to examine the ability of
other species to show evidence of self-awareness. Primates that
have passed the MSR test include chimpanzees, orangutans, and
bonobos. The case for the gorilla is equivocal with mostly neg-
ative ndings; several studies have suggested that more socialized
gorillas might be able to pass the test. Humans begin to develop
a sense of self and pass the MSR test starting around 18 mo of
age, and by 2436 mo, almost all western children will show a
positive MSR response (90). The distinction between great apes
and monkeys would seem to provide a clear demarcation in the
capacity for consciousness between species. Numerous studies
have supported this demarcation, with multiple failed attempts
to detect self-awareness in monkeys, despite one recent report to
the contrary (91). However, a number of methodological con-
cerns limit enthusiasm for the one contrary study, and overall the
data continue to suggest that macaques do not evidence MSR
behavior (92). In evolutionary terms, if objective evidence of self-
awareness can be taken as evidence for consciousness, then con-
sciousness as it occurs in the primate with their more fully de-
veloped cortex may have evolved 5 million years ago, at around
the time when great apes split off from the lesser apes.
Mirror-self-recognition may not be limited to the relatively
big-brained great apes. More recent work with other big-brained
creatures suggest the possibility that dolphins, and at least one
African elephant, may also be capable of this response (9395).
As apes, elephants, and cetaceans have a very remote common
ancestor, these ndings would seem to suggest that the mental
machinery prerequisite for self-awareness must be at least as old
as the development of the placental divide in mammals (96).
However, we may be able to take this idea on another path in
evolutionary time. As noted, the cognitive abilities of some birds
are now thought to be comparable to the abilities of some pri-
mates (80). Evidence suggests that the brain development of the
bird, which evolved on a different path from mammals, still has a
conceptually similar thalamocortical structure that can be de-
lineated (43). The cognitive abilities of various birds seem to
correlate with the relative size of the analogous avian prefrontal
cortex. Indeed, the crow-like Corvidae (crows, ravens, magpies,
rooks, jackdaws, and jays) appear to have the most advanced be-
havioral repertoire, as well as the largest prefrontal cortex (pal-
lium) (97). Importantly, a recent report shows Magpies (having
a relatively large prefrontal cortex) exhibit behavior consistent
with MSR (98). This nding, coupled with the current under-
standing of avian neuroanatomy and its well-developed thala-
mocortical structure, suggests that the foundations required for
both consciousness of the world and consciousness of the self may
have formed as early as the amniote radiation (78).
From a cognitive perspective, the meaning of self-awareness
behaviors in a mirror remains somewhat controversial (99). Some
argue that the mirror behavior could be more easily explained
by simple knowledge of ones body. The neurobiology of having
a body sense is something that is highly linked with a sense of
consciousness (100). Perhaps, as stated by Morin (99), all an
organism requires to self-recognize is a mental representation of
its own physical self; the organism matches the kinaesthetic
Fig. 3. Schematic showing relative size of frontal lobe across different
species and the potential capacity for anteriorposterior information ow.
The blue areas represent the prefrontal cortex, and the schematic shows
how the prefrontal cortex proportionally increases in size with increasing
brain size across species. Relative brain size is scaled to the human brain.
Modied from (102) with permission from Elsevier.
10362
|
www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1301188110 Mashour and Alkire
representation of the body with the image seen in the mirror and
infers that itsme.A number of other arguments against
overinterpreting MSR have been made, yet despite these relevant
concerns, from an evolutionary point of view the presence or
absence of a MSR response is at least a starting point for con-
sidering what having such a response might mean as a basis for the
evolution of consciousness. The MSR response allows one to
question what is functionally and structurally different about
brains that can self-recognize vs. those that cannot.
Why Is Human Consciousness Unique?
We have argued that the brainstem, diencephalon, and limited
association cortex capable of recurrent processing is consistent
with a core or primitive consciousness. However, what accounts
for the richness of human experience in contrast to those of early
mammals or birds? Drawing on the integrated information the-
ory of consciousness, the evolution of more complex brain net-
works capable of synthesizing the outputs of more functionally
diverse modules would result in a higher capacity for conscious-
ness. Indeed, integration of information appears to correlate
positively with tness in articial agents (animats) (27). It is un-
known in biology, however, whether it is the level or quality of
consciousness that differs across species. Although H. sapiens
may have more advanced cognition, it is difcult to imagine that
a sedentary human has a higher level of consciousness than
a highly alert beast in pursuit of prey; the richness of conscious
experience may be what differs. Alternatively, it is possible that
advanced symbolic processing in human cognition eclipses the
subjective characteristics of experience. In other words, cognition
may be potentially opposed to phenomenal consciousness. De-
spite these considerations, human consciousnessespecially the
capacity for self-consciousness and reection/projection in time
seems unique. Although evidence suggests that the core of con-
sciousness is rooted in phylogenetically older structures such
as the brainstem and diencephalon (75), the evolution of that
which is particular to human consciousness may be more closely
associated with the development of the frontal cortex. The rela-
tive size of the frontal lobes with respect to the total neocortex is
roughly the same in modern humans and great apes, but richer
interconnectivity might account for advanced cognition in H. sa-
piens (101). In particular, directed anterior-to-posterior connec-
tivity has been associated with conscious perception and is
dominant in humans (39) but not in rodents (38, 102) (Fig. 3). It
has been suggested that the afferent information from the
periphery converging at the hub of the posterior parietal cortex
becomes, with the expansion of the frontal cortex, dominated by
a strong anterior-to-posterior reafference (103). Indeed, a recent
neural mass model based on structural connectivity data from
diffusion tensor imaging in humans predicts an information ow
from the frontal to the posterior parietal cortex (104). In essence,
this information ow reversal suggests that human consciousness
is more dened by internal dynamics than external stimuli. This
level of information ow reversal may help explain, in part, those
animals capable of a MSR response. According to one theory,
human consciousness is a closed system or oneiric(dream-like)
state that is simply modulated by environmental input (105), a
theory consistent with REM sleep as a building block for human
consciousness. The relative independence from environmental
determination of conscious content would potentially permit
a greater diversity or richness of experience in comparison with
species without dominance of anterior-to-posterior ow. This
independence would also facilitate the projection and simulation
associated with future plans, of clear relevance to survival. It is
important to note, however, that the role of information ow
in consciousness is unclear at this time and requires further
neuroscientic investigation.
Conclusion
The emergence of consciousness on the evolutionary timeline
has been scientically considered at least since the time of
Darwin. The emergence of consciousness from the anesthetized
state may provide a practical and reproducible model for char-
acterizing the real-time evolution of the core neural correlates
required for consciousness of the world and of the self. Using
recent data from general anesthesia in humans, we suggest that
the arousal centers in the brainstem and diencephalonin con-
junction with even limited neocortical connectivity and recurrent
processingcan result in primitive phenomenal consciousness.
By reverse engineering,we postulate that early mammals and
birds possessing these structures (or their equivalents) are capa-
ble of phenomenal consciousness. However, the increased com-
plexity of networks and a functionally dominant prefrontal cortex
in the brain of H. sapiens likely accounts for the unique richness
of the human experience.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS. G.A.M. is supported by National Institutes of Health
Grant 1R01 GM098578 and the James S. McDonnell Foundation.
1. Block N (2007) Consciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology and
neuroscience. Behav Brain Sci 30(56):481499.
2. Baars BJ (2005) Subjective experience is probably not limited to humans: The evi-
dence from neurobiology and behavior. Conscious Cogn 14(1):721.
3. Blumenfeld H (2011) Epilepsy and the consciousness system: Transient vegetative
state? Neurol Clin 29(4):801823.
4. Crick F (1994) The Astonishing Hypothesis (Scribner, New York).
5. Damasio A (1999) The Feeling of What Happens (Harcourt Brace, New York).
6. Denton DA (2005) The Primordial Emotions: The Dawning of Consciousness (Oxford
Univ Press, Oxford, UK).
7. Edelman GM, Tononi G (2000) A Universe of Consciousness (Basic Books, New York).
8. Tononi G (2004) An information integration theory of consciousness. BMC Neurosci 5(1):42.
9. Jones BE (2003) Arousal systems. Front Biosci 8:s438s451.
10. Laureys S (2005) The neural correlate of (un)awareness: Lessons from the vegetative
state. Trends Cogn Sci 9(12):556559.
11. Lydic R, Baghdoyan HA (2005) Sleep, anesthesiology, and the neurobiology of
arousal state control. Anesthesiology 103(6):12681295.
12. Paus T (2000) Functional anatomy of arousal and attention systems in the human
brain. Prog Brain Res 126:6577.
13. Schiff ND, Plum F (2000) The role of arousal and gatingsystems in the neurology
of impaired consciousness. J Clin Neurophysiol 17(5):438452.
14. Seth AK, Baars BJ, Edelman DB (2005) Criteria for consciousness in humans and other
mammals. Conscious Cogn 14(1):119139.
15. Brown EN, Purdon PL, Van Dort CJ (2011) General anesthesia and altered states of
arousal: A systems neuroscience analysis. Annu Rev Neurosci 34:601628.
16. Crick F, Koch C (2003) A framework for consciousness. Nat Neurosci 6(2):119126.
17. Franks NP (2008) General anaesthesia: From molecular targets to neuronal pathways
of sleep and arousal. Nat Rev Neurosci 9(5):370386.
18. Tononi G, Edelman GM (1998) Consciousness and complexity. Science 282(5395):
18461851.
19. Van der Werf YD, Witter MP, Groenewegen HJ (2002) The intralaminar and midline
nuclei of the thalamus. Anatomical and functional evidence for participation in
processes of arousal and awareness. Brain Res Brain Res Rev 39(23):107140.
20. Revonsuo A (2006) Inner Presence: Consciousness as a Biological Phenomenon (MIT
Press, Cambridge, MA).
21. Aguirre GK, Zarahn E, DEsposito M (1998) Neural components of topographical
representation. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 95(3):839846.
22. Schmid MC, Singer W, Fries P (2012) Thalamic coordination of cortical communica-
tion. Neuron 75(4):551552.
23. Saalmann YB, Pinsk MA, Wang L, Li X, Kastner S (2012) The pulvinar regulates in-
formation transmission between cortical areas based on attention demands. Science
337(6095):753756.
24. Tononi G (2012) Integrated information theory of consciousness: An updated ac-
count. Arch Ital Biol 150(23):5690.
25. Lee U, Mashour GA, Kim S, Noh GJ, Choi BM (2009) Propofol induction reduces the
capacity for neural information integration: implications for the mechanism of
consciousness and general anesthesia. Conscious Cogn 18(1):5664.
26. Lewis LD, et al. (2012) Rapid fragmentation of neuronal networks at the onset of
propofol-induced unconsciousness. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 109(49):E3377E3386.
27. Edlund JA, et al. (2011) Integrated information increases with tness in the evolu-
tion of animats. PLOS Comput Biol 7(10):e1002236.
28. Dehaene S, Sergent C, Changeux JP (2003) A neuronal network model linking sub-
jective reports and objective physiological data during conscious perception. Proc
Natl Acad Sci USA 100(14):85208525.
29. Lamme VA (2006) Towards a true neural stance on consciousness. Trends Cogn Sci
10(11):494501.
Mashour and Alkire PNAS
|
June 18, 2013
|
vol. 110
|
suppl. 2
|
10363
30. Singer W (1993) Synchronization of cortical activity and its putative role in in-
formation processing and learning. Annu Rev Physiol 55:349374.
31. Schröter MS, et al. (2012) Spatiotemporal reconguration of large-scale brain
functional networks during propofol-induced loss of consciousness. J Neurosci
32(37):1283212840.
32. Blumenfeld H (2012) Impaired consciousness in epilepsy. Lancet Neurol 11(9):814826.
33. Fahrenfort JJ, Scholte HS, Lamme VA (2008) The spatiotemporal prole of cortical
processing leading up to visual perception. JVis8(1):1112.
34. Gaillard R, et al. (2006) Nonconscious semantic processing of emotional words
modulates conscious access. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 103(19):75247529.
35. Boly M, et al. (2007) Baseline brain activity uctuations predict somatosensory per-
ception in humans. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 104(29):1218712192.
36. Denton DA, McKinley MJ, Farrell M, Egan GF (2009) The role of primordial emotions
in the evolutionary origin of consciousness. Conscious Cogn 18(2):500514.
37. Gaillard R, et al. (2007) Subliminal words durably affect neuronal activity. Neuro-
report 18(15):15271531.
38. Imas OA, Ropella KM, Ward BD, Wood JD, Hudetz AG (2005) Volatile anesthetics
disrupt frontal-posterior recurrent information transfer at gamma frequencies in
rat. Neurosci Lett 387(3):145150.
39. Ku SW, Lee U, Noh GJ, Jun IG, Mashour GA (2011) Preferential inhibition of frontal-
to-parietal feedback connectivity is a neurophysiologic correlate of general anes-
thesia in surgical patients. PLoS ONE 6(10):e25155.
40. Lee U, et al. (2009) The directionality and functional organization of frontoparietal
connectivity during consciousness and anesthesia in humans. Conscious Cogn 18(4):
10691078.
41. Maclean PD (1990) The Triune Brain in Evolution: Role in Paleocerebral Functions
(Springer, New York).
42. Emery NJ, Clayton NS (2005) Evolution of the avian brain and intelligence. Curr Biol
15(23):R946R950, www.sciencedirect.com/science/journal/09609822.
43. Jarvis ED, et al.; Avian Brain Nomenclature Consortium (2005) Avian brains and
a new understanding of vertebrate brain evolution. Nat Rev Neurosci 6(2):151159.
44. Striedter G (2005) Principles of Brain Evolution (Sinauer Associates, Sunderland, MA).
45. Moruzzi G, Magoun HW (1949) Brain stem reticular formation and activation of the
EEG. Electroencephalogr Clin Neurophysiol 1(4):455473.
46. Laureys S, Owen AM, Schiff ND (2004) Brain function in coma, vegetative state, and
related disorders. Lancet Neurol 3(9):537546.
47. Cahill L, Alkire MT (2003) Epinephrine enhancement of human memory consolida-
tion: Interaction with arousal at encoding. Neurobiol Learn Mem 79(2):194198.
48. Coull JT, Jones ME, Egan TD, Frith CD, Maze M (2004) Attentional effects of nor-
adrenaline vary with arousal level: Selective activation of thalamic pulvinar in hu-
mans. Neuroimage 22(1):315322.
49. Devilbiss DM, Page ME, Waterhouse BD (2006) Locus ceruleus regulates sensory
encoding by neurons and networks in waking animals. J Neurosci 26(39):98609872.
50. McGaugh JL (2005) Emotional arousal and enhanced amygdala activity: New evi-
dence for the old perseveration-consolidation hypothesis. Learn Mem 12(2):7779.
51. Paus T (2001) Primate anterior cingulate cortex: Where motor control, drive and
cognition interface. Nat Rev Neurosci 2(6):417424.
52. Darwin CR (1872) The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals (John Murray,
London, UK).
53. Panksepp J (2011) Cross-species affective neuroscience decoding of the primal af-
fective experiences of humans and related animals. PLoS ONE 6(9):e21236.
54. Jing J, Gillette R, Weiss KR (2009) Evolving concepts of arousal: Insights from simple
model systems. Rev Neurosci 20(56):405427.
55. Stephenson-Jones M, Ericsson J, Robertson B, Grillner S (2012) Evolution of the basal
ganglia: Dual-output pathways conserved throughout vertebrate phylogeny. J
Comp Neurol 520(13):29572973.
56. Low P (2012) Consciousness in human and non-human animals. The Francis Crick
Memorial Conference, eds Panksepp J, et al. (Cambridge, UK). Available at http://
fcmconference.org/img/CambridgeDeclarationOnConsciousness.pdf. Accessed April
26, 2013.
57. Gallup GG, Jr. (1985) Do minds exist in species other than our own? Neurosci Bio-
behav Rev 9(4):631641.
58. Cotterill RM (2001) Cooperation of the basal ganglia, cerebellum, sensory cerebrum
and hippocampus: Possible implications for cognition, consciousness, intelligence
and creativity. Prog Neurobiol 64(1):133.
59. Goodrich BG (2010) We do, therefore we think: Time, motility, and consciousness.
Rev Neurosci 21(5):331361.
60. Llinas R (2001) I of the Vortex: From Neurons to Self (MIT Press, Cambridge, MA).
61. Tononi G, Koch C (2008) The neural correlates of consciousness: An update. Ann N Y
Acad Sci 1124:239261.
62. Hohwy J (2009) The neural correlates of consciousness: New experimental ap-
proaches needed? Conscious Cogn 18(2):428438.
63. Aru J, Bachmann T, Singer W, Melloni L (2012) Distilling the neural correlates of
consciousness. Neurosci Biobehav Rev 36(2):737746.
64. de Graaf TA, Hsieh PJ, Sack AT (2012) The correlatesin neural correlates of con-
sciousness. Neurosci Biobehav Rev 36(1):191197.
65. Långsjö JW, et al. (2012) Returning from oblivion: Imaging the neural core of con-
sciousness. J Neurosci 32(14):49354943.
66. Alkire MT, Hudetz AG, Tononi G (2008) Consciousness and anesthesia. Science
322(5903):876880.
67. Brown EN, Lydic R, Schiff ND (2010) General anesthesia, sleep, and coma. N Engl J
Med 363(27):26382650.
68. Bonhomme VL, Boveroux P, Brichant JF, Laureys S, Boly M (2012) Neural correlates of
consciousness during general anesthesia using functional magnetic resonance im-
aging (fMRI). Arch Ital Biol 150(2-3):155163.
69. Friedman EB, et al. (2010) A conserved behavioral state barrier impedes transitions
between anesthetic-induced unconsciousness and wakefulness: Evidence for neural
inertia. PLoS ONE 5(7):e11903.
70. Lee U, Müller M, Noh GJ, Choi B, Mashour GA (2011) Dissociable network properties
of anesthetic state transitions. Anesthesiology 114(4):872881.
71. Xie G, et al. (2011) Critical involvement of the thalamus and precuneus during res-
toration of consciousness with physostigmine in humans during propofol anaes-
thesia: A positron emission tomography study. Br J Anaesth 106(4):548557.
72. Balkin TJ, et al. (2002) The process of awakening: A PET study of regional brain
activity patterns mediating the re-establishment of alertness and consciousness.
Brain 125(Pt 10):23082319.
73. Liotti M, et al. (2001) Brain responses associated with consciousness of breathlessness
(air hunger). Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 98(4):20352040.
74. Brusseau R (2008) Developmental perspectives: Is the fetus conscious? Int Anes-
thesiol Clin 46(3):1123.
75. Merker B (2007) Consciousness without a cerebral cortex: A challenge for neuro-
science and medicine. Behav Brain Sci 30(1):6381.
76. Stam CJ, van Straaten EC (2012) The organization of physiological brain networks.
Clin Neurophysiol 123(6):10671087.
77. Butler AB (2008) Evolution of brains, cognition, and consciousness. Brain Res Bull
75(2-4):442449, www.sciencedirect.com/science/journal/03619230.
78. Warren WC, et al. (2008) Genome analysis of the platypus reveals unique signatures
of evolution. Nature 453(7192):175183.
79. Butler AB, Cotterill RM (2006) Mammalian and avian neuroanatomy and the ques-
tion of consciousness in birds. Biol Bull 211(2):106127.
80. Emery NJ, Clayton NS (2004) The mentality of crows: Convergent evolution of in-
telligence in corvids and apes. Science 306(5703):19031907.
81. Emery NJ, Clayton NS (2001) Effects of experience and social context on prospective
caching strategies by scrub jays. Nature 414(6862):443446.
82. Butler AB, Manger PR, Lindahl BI, Arhem P (2005) Evolution of the neural basis of
consciousness: A bird-mammal comparison. Bioessays 27(9):923936.
83. Ward LM (2011) The thalamic dynamic core theory of conscious experience. Con-
scious Cogn 20(2):464486.
84. Min BK (2010) A thalamic reticular networking model of consciousness. Theor Biol
Med Model 7:10.
85. Hayama HR, et al. (2012) Event-related functional magnetic resonance imaging of
a low dose of dexmedetomidine that impairs long-term memory. Anesthesiology
117(5):981995.
86. Birnholz JC (1981) The development of human fetal eye movement patterns. Science
213(4508):679681.
87. Hobson JA (2009) REM sleep and dreaming: Towards a theory of protoconsciousness.
Nat Rev Neurosci 10(11):803813.
88. Keenan JP, Gallup GG, Falk D (2003) The Face in the Mirror: The Search for the
Origins of Consciousness (HarperCollins Publishers, New York).
89. Gallop GG, Jr. (1970) Chimpanzees: Self-recognition. Science 167(3914):8687.
90. Amsterdam B (1972) Mirror self-image reactions before age two. Dev Psychobiol
5(4):297305.
91. Rajala AZ, Reininger KR, Lancaster KM, Populin LC (2010) Rhesus monkeys (Macaca
mulatta) do recognize themselves in the mirror: Implications for the evolution of
self-recognition. PLoS ONE 5(9):e12865.
92. Anderson JR, Gallup GG, Jr. (2011) Do rhesus monkeys recognize themselves in
mirrors? Am J Primatol 73(7):603606.
93. Delfour F, Marten K (2001) Mirror image processing in three marine mammal spe-
cies: Killer whales (Orcinus orca), false killer whales (Pseudorca crassidens) and Cal-
ifornia sea lions (Zalophus californianus). Behav Processes 53(3):181190.
94. Plotnik JM, de Waal FB, Reiss D (2006) Self-recognition in an Asian elephant. Proc
Natl Acad Sci USA 103(45):1705317057.
95. Reiss D, Marino L (2001) Mirror self-recognition in the bottlenose dolphin: A case of
cognitive convergence. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 98(10):59375942.
96. Wildman DE, et al. (2007) Genomics, biogeography, and the diversication of pla-
cental mammals. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 104(36):1439514400.
97. Emery NJ (2006) Cognitive ornithology: The evolution of avian intelligence. Philos
Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 361(1465):2343.
98. Prior H, Schwarz A, Güntürkün O (2008) Mirror-induced behavior in the magpie (Pica
pica): Evidence of self-recognition. PLoS Biol 6(8):e202.
99. Morin A (2011) Self-recognition, theory-of-mind, and self-awareness: What side are
you on? Laterality 16(3):367383.
100. Damasio A (2003) Mental self: The person within. Nature 423(6937):227.
101. Semendeferi K, Lu A, Schenker N, Damasio H (2002) Humans and great apes share
a large frontal cortex. Nat Neurosci 5(3):272276.
102. Nieder A (2009) Prefrontal cortex and the evolution of symbolic reference. Curr Opin
Neurobiol 19(1):99108, www.sciencedirect.com/science/journal/09594388.
103. Noack RA (2012) Solving the human problem: The frontal feedback model. Con-
scious Cogn 21(2):10431067.
104. Stam CJ, van Straaten EC (2012) Go with the ow: Use of a directed phase lag index
(dPLI) to characterize patterns of phase relations in a large-scale model of brain
dynamics. Neuroimage 62(3):14151428.
105. Llinás R, Ribary U (1993) Coherent 40-Hz oscillation characterizes dream state in
humans. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 90(5):20782081.
10364
|
www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1301188110 Mashour and Alkire
... With death, a man can no longer move, think, laugh, cry, or ask questions. Humans begin to understand and describe their surroundings after becoming conscious of their existence (Mashour & Alkire, 2014;Shanta, 2015;Stewart, 2022). In a sense, a man spends his life by describing, evaluating, and concluding what he sees. ...
Article
Full-text available
There are various prejudices in society regarding the Islamic concepts of faith. These prejudices are easily eliminated when faced with true knowledge and basic religious sources. Allegations often represent uninformed judgment. The main goal of this article is to clarify a frequently asked question about Islamic beliefs regarding the afterlife. According to some, this question has recently caused young people to break away from faith. To what extent can we embrace a religion that predicts eternal torment? In this article, we draw attention to these prejudices and encourage readers to investigate the intellectual depth of Islam based on knowledge. Humans have great potential. However, a person can achieve happiness in both the world and the hereafter by revealing the potential given to him from birth through his/her choices and behaviors. A person can reveal his existing talent in the best and most accurate way by reflecting on the meanings of the names of his Lord, who created him, in his life and living in accordance with them. Prejudices regarding Islamic religion’s understanding of the afterlife have come to the fore on social media and books. In this article, we discuss the claim about Islam that "it scares us with eternal torment.” Does Islam really scare people with punishments? Are people attached to Islam out of fear, as claimed? Does the Holy Quran suppress questioning? Or does this encourage it? It is possible to find many pros and consensuses in the history of commentary and theology regarding whether punishment is eternal. While evaluating these views, we must be responsible for ensuring and filtering whether they conform to the spirit and basic goals of the Holy Quran and Hadiths. The fact that the names of forgiving, merciful, and merciful are among the beautiful Names of Allah (Al-Asma Al-Husna), but the names of the one who punishes, the one who is angry, and the one who torments are excluded, should be accepted as evidence that the punishment will not be eternal. Mercy is an ancient attribute that cannot be separated from the essence of Allah.
... experience, bridging the gap between neurophysiological changes, observable behavioural outcomes, and the difficult topic of animal consciousness. Previous studies have discussed the emergence of consciousness in the evolutionary timeline proposing the use of general anaesthesia to study the resulting emergence process of consciousness as a model to assess the development across species (Mashour & Alkire 2013). These approaches delve into the role of cortical and subcortical regions involved in the phenomenon of consciousness in non-human species, which tie in with our case by providing a broader context on how consciousness and sensory perception are interconnected across species. ...
Article
Full-text available
Anxiety affects 14–20% of dogs. Pharmacological treatments often fail. Psychedelics have shown to be useful for anxiety and depression in humans, but their veterinary use remains unexplored. We aimed to determine the effects of low-dose 1-cyclopropionyl-d-lysergic acid diethylamide (1cp-LSD) administered in a single dose to a dog, to observe the effect and establish the safety of the substance. The patient was a 13-year-old female dog, weighing 13 kg, mixed breed, and spayed. A total of 5 µg was administered orally, equivalent to 0.38 µg/kg. The animal has had a history of separation related behavioral problems throughout her life. To objectively assess the degree of anxiety in the dog, a validated scale was utilized. The trial was scheduled at the house where the animal lives. The owner was present throughout the experience. Informed consent was obtained prior to the assay. The trial began at 12:15 p.m. on January 10, 2024, lasting for 5 and a half hours. The response to anxiety-inducing stimuli was equally anxious during the first two hours. From that point onwards, a significant change in the animal’s behavior was observed, with no signs/mild signs of anxiety. The trial concluded without any adverse effects on the animal. The patient did not show signs of having a psychedelic experience. This is the first time that a study of this nature has been conducted and reported in the canine species. 1cp-LSD proved to be safe and exerted the desired effect on the animal’s behavior, significantly reducing the patient’s anxiety.
Chapter
This chapter discusses seven dimensions of spiritual intelligence that offer a comprehensive framework for understanding the multifaceted nature of spirituality. This conceptual framework delineates seven key dimensions of spiritual intelligence, each contributing to a holistic understanding of spirituality. These dimensions—Consciousness, Grace, Meaning, Transcendence, Truth, Peaceful Surrender to Self, and Inner directedness—encompass elements such as mindfulness, purpose, relational awareness, acceptance, and integrity. Together, they form a structured approach to exploring spiritual wellness.
Article
The evolutionary emergence of consciousness is a research topic that has been attracting increasing attention in recent years. In a brief span of time, the debate surrounding various models in this area is driving the development of an increasingly specific research agenda. In this article, we examine the main available models of emergence. All the models we discuss assume, with varying degrees of caution, that consciousness emerged through convergent evolution in three distinct phyla within the animal kingdom. Nevertheless, they provide a unified account that aims to comprehensively cover all independent tokens of emergence. After analyzing the suitability of this unifying strategy through the lens of contemporary evolutionary theory, we recommend adopting a token-by-token, phylum-by-phylum approach. At this point, we emphasize the advantage of accumulated comparative knowledge regarding vertebrate evolution, advocating for an interoceptive view of the emergence of consciousness in vertebrates.
Article
A resurgence of panpsychism and dualism is a matter of ongoing debate in modern neuroscience. Although metaphysically hostile, panpsychism and dualism both persist in the science of consciousness because the former is proposed as a straightforward answer to the problem of integrating consciousness into the fabric of physical reality, whereas the latter proposes a simple solution to the problem of free will by endowing consciousness with causal power as a prerequisite for moral responsibility. I take the Integrated Information Theory (IIT) as a paradigmatic exemplar of a theory of consciousness (ToC) that makes its commitments to panpsychism and dualism within a uniȂed framework. These features are not, however, unique for IIT. Many ToCs are implicitly prone to some degree of panpsychism whenever they strive to propose a universal deȂnition of consciousness, associated with one or another known phenomenon. Yet, those ToCs that can be characterized as strongly emergent are at risk of being dualist. A remedy against both covert dualism and uncomfortable corollaries of panpsychism can be found in the evolutionary theory of life, called here “bioprotopsychism” and generalized in terms of autopoiesis and the free energy principle. Bioprotopsychism provides a biologically inspired basis for a minimalist approach to consciousness via the triad "chemotaxis-efference copy mechanism-counterfactual active inference" by associating the stream of weakly emergent conscious states with an amount of information (best guesses) of the brain, engaged in unconscious predictive processing.
Preprint
Full-text available
Are there at least some ‘tin-foil hat guys’ who aren’t crazy? In simple terms this paper seeks to analyse the credibility of the primary argument: If multiple defense and intelligence officials claim, often to their discredit, that: i) they have been neurologically assaulted by microwaves; ii) Neuroweapons have been researched and developed for over 60 years iii) non-human intelligence currently interact with humans and utilise advanced regarding several former premises; then in applying the principle of charity, why should we not consider the possibility that at least some civilians may actually be affected by such technology on earth; iv) there is a significant government-led disinformation campaign Electromagnetic phenomena? The primary aim of this paper was to epistemologically examine the possibility Theory. for claims of neurowarfare or electronic harassment to be veridical within a proportion of individuals self-describing as a Targeted Individual (TI) or as having Havana Syndrome (HS). The secondary aim was to address gaps in the literature and ongoing medicolegal discourse which have, thus far, not been contended with within analytical philosophy. It was found that HS and TI claims did not meet the full criteria for an Unwarranted Conspiracy Theory (UCT) and can be regarded as a progressive Research Program (RP). While, prima facie, appearing as an epistemological black hole, some claims were found inductively to have a legitimate basis for concern. Therefore, stigmatising preconceptions may act as an epistemic harm to well- meaning but misinformed practitioners in the process of diagnosis. The primary issue that was then dealt with is how clinicians may demarcate the presence of a disorder given that substantiated justification remains empirically undefined. In conclusion, the paper found clinicians ought to adopt consideration to a wider array of individual and socio-political contextual factors in the process of evaluating the coherency of self-reporting TI belief systems. Furthermore, in defining the complex etiology encountered, correlation with Electromagnetic Hypersensitivity (EHS), Anomalous Health Incidents (AHI), Radio Frequency (RF) exposure, Non-Human Intelligence (NHI) interactions and Exceptional Experiences (EE) should all be considered in the formation of explanatory hypotheses.
Chapter
So far, I have dealt with numerous animal thought processes that are good candidates for attribution of consciousness. These are thought processes that are usually not possible in humans without consciousness; they include logical reasoning, creative tool use and production, causal understanding and insightful problem-solving, volitional action, time travel (episodic memory, planning), metacognition, and perspective taking. (This list is not exhaustive; one could add imitation, teaching, mirror self-recognition, quantity estimation, abstraction, categorisation, and concept formation to the list.) But before I try to answer the question of whether animals act consciously in the aforementioned thought processes, I should first clarify what I mean by the term “consciousness”. This term has many meanings and, above all, very strong connotations for human science and everyday language.
Book
How do we know who we are? When and how did we become aware of our presence and thoughts? Why do some species develop self-awareness, while others do not? This question of self-awareness and consciousness has puzzled philosophers and scientists alike, from Aristotle and Darwin to Descartes and William James. In his famous "mirror test" thirty years ago, leading researcher Gordon G. Gallup Jr. showed that self-awareness begins with the recognition of one’s reflection in the mirror, an ability that only higher order primates possess. In The Face in the Mirror, Julian Paul Keenan, Gordon G. Gallup Jr., and Dean Falk further explore mirror recognition as the key to understanding the origins of consciousness and its role in our evolution, everyday behavior, and ongoing survival. For the past decade, Julian Paul Keenan and his colleagues have been closing in on the source of self-awareness in the brain. With the advent of MRI technology and other techniques, they have examined the hypothesis that there is a brain network specifically involved in self-recognition. This book shows how the right hemisphere of the brain (where mirror recognition takes place), often relegated to "supporting role" status, may be a more crucial determinant of higher order consciousness. Keenan also shows how recognizing our reflection -- an ability we take for granted -- is linked to such common self-related functions as memory and to emotions like empathy, narcissism, and deception, which play a crucial role in evolution. Insightful, witty, and accessible, The Face in the Mirror plunges the reader into the forefront of thedebate on consciousness in humans and primates. From animals who share our ability for self-recognition, to the development of self-awareness in children, to case studies of patients who no longer recognize who they are, Keenan examines some of the latest evidence in the fields of neurology, psychology, and anthropology and suggests remarkable and surprising results about the function of self-awareness in humans and other primates.
Article
To understand what is happening in the brain in the moment you decide, at will, to summon to consciousness a passage of Mozart's music, or decide to take a deep breath, is like trying to 'catch a phantom by the tail'. Consciousness remains that most elusive of all human phenomena - one so mysterious that even our highly developed knowledge of brain function can only partly explain it. This book traces the origins of consciousness. It takes the investigation back many years in an attempt to uncover just how consciousness might have first emerged. Consciousness did not develop suddenly in humans - it evolved gradually. The book investigates the evolution of consciousness. Central to the book is the idea that the primal emotions - elements of instinctive behaviour - were the first dawning of consciousness. Throughout the book examines instinctive behaviours, such as hunger for air, hunger for minerals, thirst, and pain, arguing that the emotions elicited from these behaviours and desire for gratification culminated in the first conscious states. To develop the theory the book looks at behaviour at different levels of the evolutionary tree, for example of octopuses, fish, snakes, birds, and elephants. Coupled with findings from neuroimaging studies, and the viewpoints on consciousness from figures in philosophy and neuroscience, the book presents a new look at the problem of consciousness.
Article
Placing a patient in a state of general anesthesia is crucial for safely and humanely performing most surgical and many nonsurgical procedures. How anesthetic drugs create the state of general anesthesia is considered a major mystery of modern medicine. Unconsciousness, induced by altered arousal and/or cognition, is perhaps the most fascinating behavioral state of general anesthesia. We perform a systems neuroscience analysis of the altered arousal states induced by five classes of intravenous anesthetics by relating their behavioral and physiological features to the molecular targets and neural circuits at which these drugs are purported to act. The altered states of arousal are sedation-unconsciousness, sedation-analgesia, dissociative anesthesia, pharmacologic non-REM sleep, and neuroleptic anesthesia. Each altered arousal state results from the anesthetic drugs acting at multiple targets in the central nervous system. Our analysis shows that general anesthesia is less mysterious than currently believed.
Article
Summary Awakening from sleep entails rapid re-establishment of consciousness followed by the relatively slow (20‐30 min later) re-establishment of alertness—a temporal dissociation that facilitates specification of the physiological underpinnings of each of these facets of the awakening process. H2 15 O PET was used to assess changes in regional cerebral blood flow (rCBF) upon awakening from stage 2 sleep. Cerebral blood flow (CBF) was most rapidly re-established in centrencephalic regions (e.g. brainstem and thalamus), suggesting that the reactivation of these regions underlies the reestablishment of conscious awareness. Across the ensuing 15 min of wakefulness, further increases in CBF were evident primarily in anterior cortical regions, suggesting that the dissipation of sleep inertia effects (postawakening performance and alertness deficits) is effected by reactivation of these regions. Concomitant shifts in correlation patterns of regional brain activity across the post-awakening period [in particular, a waning negative correlation between prefrontal cortex and mesencephalic reticular formation (RF) activity, and a waxing positive correlation between prefrontal cortex and ventromedial caudate nucleus (CAUD) activity] suggest that the post-awakening reversal of sleep inertia effects may be mediated by more than mere reactivation—it may also involve the functional reorganization of brain activity. Conversely, stable post-awakening correlations—such as those found between the anterior cingulate cortex (ACC) and most other brain regions— may denote the pattern of functional connectivity that underlies consciousness itself.
Article
[opening paragraph] -- Clark: The ‘astonishing hypothesis’ which you put forward in your book, and which you obviously feel is very controversial, is that ‘You, your joys and sorrows, your memories and ambitions, your sense of personal identity and free will are, in fact, no more than the behaviour of a vast assembly of nerve cells. As Lewis Carroll's Alice might have phrased it: ‘You're nothing but a pack of neurons’.’ But it seems to me that this is not so astonishing a statement for a scientist to make. Isn't this what reductionist science has always believed?