ArticlePDF Available

The Groningen Protocol for newborn euthanasia; which way did the slippery slope tilt?

Authors:
  • University Medical Center Groningen, University of Groningen

Abstract

In The Netherlands, neonatal euthanasia has become a legal option and the Groningen Protocol contains an approach to identify situations in which neonatal euthanasia might be appropriate. In the 5 years following the publication of the protocol, neither the prediction that this would be the first step on a slippery slope, nor the prediction of complete transparency and legal control became true. Instead, we experienced a transformation of the healthcare system after antenatal screening policy became a part of antenatal care. This resulted in increased terminations of pregnancy and less euthanasia.
PAPER
The Groningen Protocol for newborn euthanasia;
which way did the slippery slope tilt?
A A Eduard Verhagen
Correspondence to
Dr A A Eduard Verhagen,
Department of Paediatrics,
University Medical Centre
Groningen, P.O. Box 30.001,
Groningen 9700 RB,
The Netherlands;
a.a.e.verhagen@umcg.nl
Accepted 4 February 2013
To cite: Verhagen AAE. J
Med Ethics 2013;39:
293295.
ABSTRACT
In The Netherlands, neonatal euthanasia has become a
legal option and the Groningen Protocol contains an
approach to identify situations in which neonatal
euthanasia might be appropriate. In the 5 years
following the publication of the protocol, neither the
prediction that this would be the rst step on a slippery
slope, nor the prediction of complete transparency and
legal control became true. Instead, we experienced a
transformation of the healthcare system after antenatal
screening policy became a part of antenatal care. This
resulted in increased terminations of pregnancy and less
euthanasia.
INTRODUCTION
It is widely known that The Netherlands was the
rst country in the world to legalise euthanasia in
adults. Justication is based on the patients volun-
tary request (autonomy) and on the doctors assess-
ment of the patients hopeless prognosis and
unbearable suffering. Less well known, even among
the Dutch, is the fact that in The Netherlands neo-
natal euthanasia for severely defective newborn
babies is also legal under very narrowly dened cir-
cumstances. Although formal legal change has not
yet taken place, the legal development has devel-
oped far enough to be reasonably condent about
what Dutch law is on the subject.
1
One of the
reasons that legal developments have come about
was the strong condence of the Dutch that legal
control could and should serve as a measure of
control of medical practice. Medical practice, in
turn, has been partly shaped by the consistent and
deeply rooted belief among Dutch doctors and the
public that in sick newborns and infants not all
options for treatment must always be used.
24
In
other words, some children might be allowed to
die, for example, if their prospects in life turn out
very grim. Even newborn euthanasia might be per-
missible in such situations.
In this paper, the gradual evolvement of that
concept over the last decade is described with an
emphasis on the developments regarding newborn
euthanasia. This description may be of particular rele-
vance, given the recent international discussions and
uproar in the media in response to a publication
about post-birth abortion.
5
The authors of that paper
argued that if abortion, at the parentsrequest, is
thought to be permissible under certain circum-
stances, then infanticide should also be permissible
under relevantly similar circumstances. As no other
society has legalised abortion and newborn euthanasia
under certain (strict) circumstances, the experiences
of the Dutch may be of value to others and contribute
to the discussion.
Basic words or descriptions such as withholding
or withdrawing life-sustaining treatment, terminal
care, life-ending measures, active ending of life, ter-
mination of life, neonaticide or infanticide, post-
birth abortion and neonatal euthanasia are often
used interchangeably, yet they convey very different
meanings to clinicians, patients, families and others.
Those different meanings can lead to unintentioned
confusion at the bedside, among healthcare provi-
ders, in the media and in the international debate,
and may result in potentially harmful consequences.
Clinicians rely on words, and so consistent use of
predened terminology in highly precarious matters
such as medical end-of-life decisions about severely
ill newborns is very important.
In this paper, end-of-life (EoL) decisions are
medical decisions with the effect or the probable
effect that death is caused or hastened. They include
the decision to withhold or withdraw life-sustaining
treatment, the decision to administer medication with
potentially life-shortening effect to alleviate pain and
suffering and the decision to deliberately end the life
of physiologically stable newborns with lethal drugs
that otherwise would not have died. The term neo-
natal euthanasiais used for the latter decision.
END-OF-LIFE DECISIONS IN NEWBORNS, THE
SITUATION BEFORE 2005
Neonatal EoL decision-making in The Netherlands
has been studied quite intensely over the last
1015 years. Two nationwide surveys in 1995 and
2001 showed that the majority (65%) of infants
younger than 12 months of age died because life-
sustaining treatment was withheld or withdrawn.
67
The decision to do so was made for babies with an
incurable disease and inevitable death in 60% of
cases. In the remaining group of patients, the deci-
sion was made for quality of life reasons and con-
cerned patients who might otherwise have lived if
this treatment had not been withheld or with-
drawn. Those studies also showed that in 1% of
all cases, medication was administered with the
explicit intention to hasten death. Based on these
data, it was estimated that at least 1520 cases of
deliberate termination of life take place annually.
At that time, not many details about those babies
were available, except that they did not have any
life-sustaining treatment(s) (LST) that could be
withheld or withdrawn. Despite a legal obligation
for doctors to report those cases, and the acknow-
ledgment in two court cases that giving drugs to
hasten death was sometimes the most humane
Verhagen AAE. J Med Ethics 2013;39:293295. doi:10.1136/medethics-2013-101402 293
The argument
on May 29, 2021 at University of Groningen. Protected by copyright.http://jme.bmj.com/J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/medethics-2013-101402 on 1 May 2013. Downloaded from
thing to do, only three cases of neonatal euthanasia per year
were actually reported and reviewed between 19972005.
8
We analysed those cases retrospectively and found that they all
concerned babies with complex inoperable congenital malfor-
mations (mainly spina bida) combined with other complica-
tions and/or chromosomal abnormalities.
With only 15% to 20% of the estimated number of cases
being reported, the conclusion seems reasonable that the prac-
tice of neonatal euthanasia clearly existed before 2005 but it
was not at all transparent.
THE GRONINGEN PROTOCOL FOR NEONATAL EUTHANASIA
Our group developed an approach to identify situations in which
neonatal euthanasia might be appropriate and published the proto-
col for this in the New England Journal of Medicine in 2005.
9
This
protocol, known as the Groningen Protocol for neonatal euthan-
asia(GP), has ve major criteria that make euthanasia permissible:
(1) diagnosis and prognosis must be certain, (2) hopeless and
unbearable suffering must be present, (3) a conrming second
opinion by an independent doctor, (4) both parents give informed
consent and (5) the procedure must be performed carefully, in
accordance with medical standards.
The trigger for us to make the protocol, at the time, was a
huge dilemma about what the best intervention would be for a
baby girl with the severest type of a lethal skin disease named
epidermolysis bullosa.
10 11
The disease caused excruciating pain
and suffering. The parents requested euthanasia and the doctors
agreed that the suffering was intolerable and hence the request
understandable. The legal threat of potentially being prosecuted
for murder or homicide, however, made us refuse the parents
request. We transferred the patient back to the referring paedia-
trician. When we were notied how the baby had died
3 months later, we decided to make a protocol that would help
us to choose euthanasia if that might be appropriate in future
cases. In addition, we wanted the protocol to help regulate the
practice of neonatal euthanasia and make it more transparent.
Its publication immediately generated an international contro-
versy
1216
and forced doctors to analyse the differences between
the existing approaches in palliative care that are common in
many countries, such as withholding and withdrawing life-
sustaining treatment or the administration of high doses of nar-
cotics to relieve suffering, and the Dutch approach of actually
giving lethal medication to end life.
One of the main arguments raised against the GP was the slip-
pery slopeargument: the GP is a rst step down a slippery slope
and would lead to widely increased use of neonatal euthanasia
(erosion of norms). In addition, it was argued that ending the life
of a newborn is a violation of a doctors obligation to preserve
life and permitting doctors to do so will have a negative impact
on how the medical profession is perceived.
17 18
Those in favour
of the GP argued that the protocol allowed doctors to be openly
accountable for their decisions to all members of society. The
transparency of the process of reection and action required by
the GP serves as a mechanism to strengthen the patients trust in
their doctor.
12
Legalisation is an effective way to regulate
end-of-life practice and make it more transparent.
1
Most people would probably recognise that evidence for most
of the proand conarguments is very difcult to obtain. An
important question, however, and one that we thought might be
relatively easy to answer is: has either of the predictions come
true? Has euthanasia for neonates increased or decreased after
the implementation of the GP? Are cases reported? To answer
that question we analysed the data of the two studies that
reported how babies died in Dutch neonatal intensive care units
(NICUs) following publication of the GP, and reviewed all
reported euthanasia cases between 20012010.
THE SITUATION AFTER 2005: WHICH WAY DID THE
SLIPPERY SLOPE TILT?
Withholding and/or withdrawing life-sustaining treatment was
the mode of death in 95% of the patients dying in the
NICUs.
19 20
In 60% of cases, this concerned unstable babies
with an inevitable death while the remaining 40% was in stable
newborns for quality of life reasons. One newborn with type II
osteogenesis imperfecta was classied as neonatal euthanasia.
19
The attending doctor intentionally increased the morphine
medication until death occurred after it became evident that the
patients intolerable suffering could not be relieved otherwise.
They issued a certicate declaring the childs natural death. The
medical team reviewed the case several weeks after the infants
death and concluded that in retrospect, their practice could best
be described as deliberate ending of life. The case was not
reported to the legal authorities.
Review of the reported euthanasia cases revealed that, follow-
ing the GP, euthanasia had decreased from 15 to 2 cases over
5 years.
2123
The two cases were babies with lethal epidermoly-
sis bullosa. In spina bida, euthanasia decreased from 15 to 0
cases. We tried to nd out why this was. Starting in 2007, struc-
tural ultrasound examination at 20 weeks was offered to all
pregnant women at no extra cost. Before that time, access to
ultrasound screening was only available for women above
35 years of age and/or on strict medical indication. The reports
published by the registry of congenital malformation and by the
national registry for termination of pregnancy (TOP) showed a
signicant increase of TOP before the 24th week of foetuses
with spina bida after 2007 in comparison to the preceding
5 years.
24
These ndings yield the conclusion that a transform-
ation of the healthcare system (antenatal screening policy
became a part of antenatal care) resulted in increased abortions
and fewer incidences of euthanasia. In addition, it seems fair to
conclude that the effects of the GP were totally different from
those predicted by either supporters or critics.
ARE ALL CASES REPORTED?
The apparently very low reporting rate may be totally explainable
by the developments in prenatal screening as stated above.
However, one cannot exclude the possibility that doctors might
still be hesitant to report their case after their patient died from
euthanasia. Certainly, the reporting has become easier because
the requirements for due practice and the legal position of the
doctor have been made much clearer by the GP. In addition, the
government has helped to lower the doctorsbarrier to reporting
by adjusting the reporting procedure in that the initial reporting
would be made to a multidisciplinary committee of experts (con-
sisting of ethicists, doctors and legal people) instead of the pros-
ecuting ofce. This committee has been in place since 2007.
One of the possible reasons for the low reporting rate could
be that different healthcare providers still dene newborn
euthanasia differently. The use of paralysing medication at the
end of a newborns life in the NICU, as described in two recent
studies,
25 26
may serve as an example. Some Dutch doctors
administer this medication, which is similar to the medication
used for euthanasia, on parental request to stop the gasping
efforts of the dying baby. They do not consider their action as
euthanasia but as symptom management and part of palliative
care. Those cases are never brought to the committee.
Consensus among the medical profession has not yet been
reached on this delicate issue, but it probably will be after the
294 Verhagen AAE. J Med Ethics 2013;39:293295. doi:10.1136/medethics-2013-101402
The argument
on May 29, 2021 at University of Groningen. Protected by copyright.http://jme.bmj.com/J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/medethics-2013-101402 on 1 May 2013. Downloaded from
publication of a report by the Dutch Medical Association on
this subject in 2013. The report is expected to contribute to
even more transparency of medical practice and more efcient
legal control.
CAN EUTHANASIA EVER BE PREFERRED OVER OTHER
LIFE-ENDING INTERVENTIONS?
The nding of increased abortions and less euthanasia following
the introduction of prenatal screening raises the interesting
question about the moral difference between euthanasia and
abortion. It can be argued that for some patients, neonatal
euthanasia might be preferable to second trimester termination.
The level of certainty available to establish the diagnosis and
prognosis, for example in babies with congenital malformations,
is often much lower at 20 weeks in comparison to the situation
after birth. After birth, the medical team and the parents will
have much more time to plan the diagnostic procedures needed
to increase the quality of the diagnosis and prognosis. More
time (and more expertise) might be available to discuss with the
parents about all the treatment options including the option of
palliative care. If all stakeholders conclude that the prognosis is
very grim, the babies condition is judged as one with sustained
and intolerable suffering, and the parents request for euthanasia,
why should that not be permissible as an alternative to second
trimester termination? In addition, the question can be raised
what the moral difference is between euthanasia and withhold-
ing feeding and hydration? This question has gained importance
after the publication by Diekema et al
27
and the American
Academy of Pediatrics (AAP) Committee on Bioethics.
27
After
reviewing the medical, ethical and legal issues relevant to the
withholding or withdrawing of medically provided uids and
nutrition in children, they conclude that withdrawal thereof is
ethically acceptable in limited situations. The practice of with-
holding feeding and hydration is another example of an
approach in palliative care that might need rethinking. Id like
to argue that for some patients and/or parents, neonatal euthan-
asia might be preferable to withholding feeding and hydration.
Especially in the situation, although rare, that every hour every
day of life imposes an intolerable burden on the baby and the
parents. The outcome in such a situation is clear: the baby will
die soon; If the parents wish to shorten that course, and organ-
ise their childs death more in the way they have envisioned it,
shouldnt euthanasia be available for them?
CONCLUSIONS
In The Netherlands, neonatal euthanasia has become a legal
option and the Groningen Protocol contains an approach to
identify situations in which neonatal euthanasia might be appro-
priate. In the 5 years following the publication of the protocol,
neither the prediction that this would be the rst step on a slip-
pery slope, nor the prediction of complete transparency and
legal control became true. Instead, we experienced a transform-
ation of the healthcare system after antenatal screening policy
became a part of antenatal care. This resulted in increased ter-
minations of pregnancy and fewer instances of euthanasia.
Competing interests None.
Provenance and peer review Not commissioned; externally peer reviewed.
REFERENCES
1 Grifths J, Weyers H, Adams M. Termination of life in neonatology. Euthanasia and
Law in Europe. Oxford and Portland, Oregon: Hart Publishing, 2008:21755.
2 Nederlandse Vereniging voor Kindergeneeskunde. Doen of laten. Grenzen van het
medisch handelen in de neonatologie (To treat or not to treat? Limits for
life-sustaining treatment in neonatology). Utrecht: Den Daas, 1992.
3 KNMG Commissie Aanvaardbaarheid Levensbeeindigend handelen. Medisch
handelen rond het levenseinde bij wilsonbekwame patiënten. Houten: Bohn Staeu
Van Loghem, 1997.
4 Overleggroep toetsing zorgvuldig medisch handelen rond het levenseinde bij
pasgeborenen. Toetsing als spiegel van de medische praktijk (Assesment as mirror
of medical practice). Rijswijk: Ministerie van Volksgezondheid Welzijn en Sport,
1997.
5 Giubilini A, Minerva F. After-birth abortion: why should the baby live? J Med Ethics
2013;39:2613.
6 van der Heide A, van der Maas PJ, van der Wal G, et al. Medical end-of-life
decisions made for neonates and infants in the Netherlands. Lancet 1997;350
(9073):2515.
7 Vrakking AM, van der Heide A, Onwuteaka-Philipsen BD, et al. Medical end-of-life
decisions made for neonates and infants in the Netherlands, 19952001. Lancet
2005;365(9467):132931.
8 Verhagen AA, Sol JJ, Brouwer OF, et al. Actieve levensbeeindiging bij pasgeborenen
in Nederland; analyse van alle 22 meldingen uit 1997/04. (Deliberate termination
of life in newborns in The Netherlands; review of all 22 reported cases between
1997 and 2004). Ned Tijdschr Geneeskd 2005;149(4):1838.
9 Verhagen E, Sauer PJ. The Groningen protocoleuthanasia in severely ill
newborns. N Engl J Med 2005;352(10):95962.
10 Crouch G. A crusade born of a suffering infants cry. New York Times 19 March
2005; Sect A:4.
11 Yuen WY, Duipmans JC, Molenbuur B, et al. Long-term follow-up of patients with
Herlitz-type junctional epidermolysis bullosa. Br J Dermatol 2012;167(2):37482.
12 Lindemann H, Verkerk M. Ending the life of a newborn: the Groningen Protocol.
The Hastings Center Report 2008;38(1):4251.
13 Chervenak FA, McCullough LB, Arabin B. Why the Groningen Protocol should be
rejected. The Hastings Center report 2006;36(5):303.
14 Kon AA. Neonatal euthanasia is unsupportable: the groningen protocol should be
abandoned. Theor Med Bioeth 2007;28(5):45363.
15 Jotkowitz A, Glick S, Gesundheit B. A case against justied non-voluntary active
euthanasia (the Groningen Protocol). Am J Bioeth 2008;8(11):236.
16 de Vries MC, Verhagen AA. A case against something that is not the case: the
Groningen Protocol and the moral principle of non-malecence. Am J Bioeth
2008;8(11):2931.
17 Nufeld Council on Bioethics. Decision making: ethical issues. Critical care decisions
in fetal and neonatal medicine. London: Nufeld Council on Bioethics, 2006.
18 Costeloe K. Euthanasia in neonates. BMJ 2007;334(7600):91213.
19 Verhagen AA, Dorscheidt JH, Engels B, et al. End-of-life decisions in Dutch neonatal
intensive care units. Arch Pediatr Adolesc Med 2009;163(10):895901.
20 Verhagen AA, Janvier A, Leuthner SR, et al. Categorizing neonatal deaths: a
cross-cultural study in the United States, Canada, and the Netherlands. J Pediatr
2010;156(1):337.
21 Commitee Late Termination of Pregnancy and Termination of Life in Newborns
(Commissie Late Zwangerschapsafbreking en levensbeeindiging bij pasgeborenen).
Annual report 200910 ( Jaarverslag 200910), 2010. http://www.lzalp.nl/
documentatie/ (accessed 21 Jan 2013).
22 Commitee Late Termination of Pregnancy and Termination of Life in Newborns
(Commissie Late Zwangerschapsafbreking en levensbeeindiging bij pasgeborenen).
Annual report 2008 ( Jaarverslag 2008). 2010. 2008. http://www.lzalp.nl/
documentatie/ (accessed 21 Jan 2013).
23 Commitee Late Termination of Pregnancy and Termination of Life in Newborns
(Commissie Late Zwangerschapsafbreking en levensbeeindiging bij pasgeborenen).
Annual report 2007 ( Jaarverslag 2007). 2007. http://www.lzalp.nl/documentatie/
(accessed 21 Jan 2013).
24 Jaarrapportage 2007 van de Wet afbreking zwangerschap (2007 Annual Report
on the Termination of Pregnancy Act). Den Haag: Inspectie Volksgezondheid
(The Netherlands Health Care Inspectorate), 2008 November.
25 Verhagen AA, Dorscheidt JH, Engels B, et al. Analgesics, sedatives and
neuromuscular blockers as part of end-of-life decisions in Dutch NICUs. Arch Dis
Child 2009;94:F4348.
26 Janvier A, Meadow W, Leuthner SR, et al. Whom are we comforting? An analysis of
comfort medications delivered to dying neonates. J Pediatr 2011;159(2):20610.
27 Diekema DS, Botkin JR. Clinical reportforgoing medically provided nutrition and
hydration in children. Pediatrics 2009;124(2):81322.
Verhagen AAE. J Med Ethics 2013;39:293295. doi:10.1136/medethics-2013-101402 295
The argument
on May 29, 2021 at University of Groningen. Protected by copyright.http://jme.bmj.com/J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/medethics-2013-101402 on 1 May 2013. Downloaded from
... Yendo al derecho de rechazo o de renuncia [87] de los tratamientos médicos, [88][89][90][91][92][93][94][95][96][97][98][99][100][101][102][103][104][105][106][107] transitando por el suicidio médicamente asistido, [108][109][110][111][112][113][114] hasta llegar al derecho a la eutanasia, [115][116][117][118][119][120][121][122][123][124][125][126][127][128][129][130][131][132][133] incluso la infantil, [134][135][136][137][138][139][140][141][142] el derecho a la salud se quiebra y se fragmenta en la ya mencionada poliedricidad de métodos médico-legales tendientes a la concreción de un único objetivo común; es decir, la intervención de IVS. ...
Article
Full-text available
Right to health between eugenetic selection and dignity of a person. The article examines the issue about the right to health between the eugenetic selection and human dignity. The right to health is claimed in assisted reproductive technologies, in abortion, in euthanasia. In these three situations, the right to health is understood as public and as an individual. In this perspective, the right to health is to be found in the middle between the desire to select eugenically people and the duty to respect their dignity. However, what is the right to health? Moreover, what is dignity? These questions are answered in the following work.
... The Groningen Protocol arose from a conflict over the best care for a baby girl with a lethal type of epidermolysis bullosa [23][24][25][26]. The disease caused excruciating pain and suffering, her parents requested euthanasia, and a large multidisciplinary group of health care providers agreed that her suffering was intolerable and, hence, the request understandable. ...
Article
Neonatal deaths can be categorized in 5 modes along the dimension of intervention and physiology. This classification can be helpful to analyze the choices that can be made in end-of-life care in the NICU. In the Netherlands, neonatal euthanasia became an optional 6th mode of death since publication and legalization of the Groningen Protocol. This paper summarizes the history, legal status and ethical justification of the Groningen Protocol, and describes end-of-life practice in the subsequent years. Since the implementation of the Groningen Protocol, the practice of neonatal euthanasia has almost disappeared. Simultaneously, there has been spectacular growth in neonatal palliative care programs in the Netherlands. Is there still a need for this last-resort option?
Article
Full-text available
Background and Aims Euthanasia is a controversial issue related to the right to die. Although euthanasia is mostly requested by terminally sick individuals, even in societies where it is legal, it is unclear what medical conditions lead to euthanasia requests. In this scoping review, we aimed to compile medical conditions for which euthanasia has been requested or performed around the world. Methods The review was preferred reporting items for systematic reviews and meta‐analysis for scoping reviews (PRISMA‐ScR) checklist. Retrieved search results were screened and unrelated documents were excluded. Data on reasons for conducting or requesting euthanasia along with the study type, setting, and publication year were extracted from documents. Human development index and euthanasia legality were also extracted. Major medical fields were used to categorize reported reasons. Group discussions were conducted if needed for this categorization. An electronic search was undertaken in MEDLINE through PubMed for published documents covering the years January 2000 to September 2022. Results Out of 3323 records, a total of 197 papers were included. The most common medical conditions in euthanasia requests are cancer in a terminal phase (45.4%), Alzheimer's disease and dementia (19.8%), constant unbearable physical or mental suffering (19.8%), treatment‐resistant mood disorders (12.2%), and advanced cardiovascular disorders (12.2%). Conclusion Reasons for euthanasia are mostly linked to chronic or terminal physical conditions. Psychiatric disorders also lead to a substantial proportion of euthanasia requests. This review can help to identify the features shared by conditions that lead to performing or requesting euthanasia
Article
Highlights •Consider all relevant prognostic factors (not just gestational age) in decision-making about resuscitation at birth for extremely preterm infants (EPI) •Where palliative care is planned in the delivery room, the presence of experienced neonatal staff may support parallel planning and symptom management •Non-pharmacological measures should always be provided for EPI receiving palliative care (in the delivery room or NICU). Buccal or nasal opioids may be of value where infants do not have vascular access. •Where intensive care has been initiated, and infants fail to respond or develop complications, consider the option of withdrawal of treatment in situations where withholding of treatment (if not started) would be ethical.
Article
Objective: To investigate long-term outcomes of infants who survive despite life-and-death discussions with families and a decision to withdraw or withhold life-sustaining interventions (WWLST) in one neonatal intensive care unit (NICU). Study design: Medical records for NICU admissions from 2012-2017 were reviewed for presence of WWLST discussions or decisions, as well as the 2-year outcome of all children who survived. WWLST discussions were prospectively recorded in a specific book; follow-up up to age two was determined by retrospective chart review. Results: WWLST discussions occurred for 266 of 5251 infants (5%): 151 (57%) were born at term and 115 (43%) were born preterm. Among these discussions, 164 led to an WWLST decision (62%) and 130 were followed by the infant's death (79%). Of the 34 children (21%) surviving to discharge after WWLST decisions, 10 (29%) died before 2 years of age and 11 (32%) required frequent medical follow-up. Major functional limitations were common among survivors, but eight were classified as functionally normal or with mild to moderate functional limitations. Conclusions: When a WWLST decision was made in our cohort, 21% of the infants survived to discharge. By 2 years of age, the majority of these infants had died or had major functional limitations. This highlights the uncertainty of WWLST decisions during neonatal intensive care, and the importance of ensuring that parents are informed of all possibilities. Additional studies including longer-term follow-up and ascertaining the family's views will be important.
Chapter
There are 4 main arguments for euthanasia: (1) arguments appealing to consistency (e.g., from passive to active euthanasia); (2) the argument from respect for autonomy; (3) appeals to justice; and (4) the argument from interests (mercy or relief of suffering). I will argue that only the last is directly relevant to active euthanasia as a medical intervention, though arguments together from autonomy and justice can in practice (through the backdoor) provide a ground for voluntary active medical euthanasia (AME).
Chapter
Ethics are an inherent part of our day-to-day life, when dealing with self or others related issues, especially in situations demanding decision making. They become more important in medical practice where the treating physician is required to decide on the treatment modalities best suited to the patient for the most favorable outcome. Anesthesiologists are always faced with the ethical dilemmas when deciding on the technique and drugs to use, what monitoring to do, and mainly whether it is safe to subject the patient to anesthesia at all or not. In most cases, anesthesiologists choose the option of optimizing the patient to the best of available facilities and take a calculated risk. In preverbal and nonverbal babies, premature and term newborns, and neonates, this issue assumes significant importance, because of the unknown issues in this age group, and risk of high morbidity and mortality. One must remember that anesthesia is administered for the sole purpose of easing the pain and stress of surgery, and in this aspect, the anesthetist is bound to do the best for the patient, despite the added risk of anesthetic technique and drugs. This chapter will take one through all the aspects of ethics in the practice of anesthesia in the neonates, the dilemmas faced, the historical facts relating to development of ethics, role of communication, consent taking, and legal issues, and during research in neonates.
Article
Full-text available
Increasing numbers of research teams are investigating the feasibility of developing artificial amnion and placenta technology (AAPT), commonly referred to as "artificial womb technology". This technology, aimed at supporting ex vivo gestation, has not yet been tested in humans, but it has been stated that we are closer to clinical application than ever before as breakthroughs in animal studies demonstrate good proof of principle. With these proof-of-concept models, further dissemination of AAPT as a research modality is expected. In this review article, we consider the ethical implications of the most imminent anticipated applications for AAPT. We focus specifically on the specific ethical complications regarding the improvements this technology may offer to conventional neonatal intensive care, its potential utility in facilitating prenatal interventions, and some of the broader socio-legal implications such as the debates about abortion access and reproductive and gestational choices. We discuss translational and societal questions when it comes to designing and developing this technology, like commitments to value-sensitive design, along with an examination of the legal and moral status of the entity gestating ex utero, which will be relevant for how it ought to be treated in the context of these various applications. From these perspectives, this review identifies the ethical questions that we believe to be most pressing in the development and potential introduction of AAPT, with due attention to their manifestation as translational and legal issues.
Article
Full-text available
Palliative care is a topic that is gaining more and more relevance. This therapy benefits the patient throughout their illness, for that reason, the scientific community is becoming aware of the importance of including such treatments in basic health services. Unfortunately, only some of the developed countries manage to have decent assistance in this type of care, and that is why governments and world organizations are taking more ambitious objectives in order to improve health quality even more. The evidence presented in this article shows the future possibilities of PC, focusing its attention on pediatric patients and their families, as well as the guidelines to be followed by the professional team to guarantee a complete and satisfactory approach.
Article
Full-text available
Objective. To gain insight into the reporting and assessment of active termination of life in newborns in the Netherlands . Design. Retrospective . Method. Data on all cases of deliberate termination of life in newborns up to the age of 6 months, reported to the public prosecutor as from 1997 onward, were collected and compared. Results. In January 1997-June 2004, 22 cases of deliberate termination of life in newborns were reported. All cases concerned newborns with spina bifida and hydrocephalus. Deliberate termination of life was acceptable to the physicians because of the presence of hopeless suffering, with no means of alleviating the suffering. In all cases, at least 2 doctors were consulted outside the medical team. In 17 of 22 cases, a multidisciplinary spina bifida team was consulted. All parents consented to the termination of life ; in 4 cases they explicitly requested it. In 14 cases a combination of analgesics, sedatives and paralyzing drugs were used, in 8 cases only analgesics and sedatives were administered. For the public prosecutor the termination of life was acceptable if 4 requirements were properly fulfilled : the presence of hopeless and unbearable suffering, consent of the parents to termination of life, consultation having taken place and a careful execution of the termination. The mean time between reporting of the case and the decision concerning prosecution was 5.3 months. None of the cases led to prosecution . Conclusion. Three cases of deliberate termination of life in newborns were reported in the Netherlands annually. The public prosecutor used fixed criteria to assess the case and all cases of active termination of life reported were found to be in accordance with good practice .
Article
Full-text available
To clarify the practice of end-of-life decision making in severely ill newborns. Retrospective descriptive study with face-to-face interviews. The 10 neonatal intensive care units in the Netherlands from October 2005 to September 2006. All 367 newborn infants who died in the first 2 months of life in Dutch neonatal intensive care units. Adequate documentation was available in 359 deaths. Presence of end-of-life decisions, classification of deaths in 3 groups, and physicians' considerations leading to end-of-life decisions. An end-of-life decision preceded death in 95% of cases, and in 5% treatment was continued until death. Of all of the deaths, 58% were classified as having no chance of survival and 42% were stabilized newborns with poor prognoses. Withdrawal of life-sustaining therapy was the main mode of death in both groups. One case of deliberate ending of life was found. In 92% of newborns with poor prognoses, end-of-life decisions were based on patients' future quality of life and mainly concerned future suffering. Considerations regarding the infant's present state were made in 44% of infants. Virtually all deaths in Dutch neonatal intensive care units are preceded by the decision to withdraw life-sustaining treatment and many decisions are based on future quality of life. The decision to deliberately end the life of a newborn may occur less frequently than was previously assumed.
Article
Junctional epidermolysis bullosa, type Herlitz (JEB-H) is a rare, autosomal recessive disease caused by absence of the epidermal basement membrane adhesion protein laminin-332. It is characterized by extensive and devastating blistering of the skin and mucous membranes, leading to death in early childhood. To present the results of the long-term follow-up of a cohort of patients with JEB-H, and to provide guidelines for prognosis, treatment and care. All patients with JEB-H included in the Dutch Epidermolysis Bullosa (EB) Registry between 1988 and 2011 were followed longitudinally by our EB team. Diagnosis was established using immunofluorescence antigen mapping, electron microscopy and DNA analysis. In total, we included 22 patients with JEB-H over a 23-year period. Their average age at death was 5.8 months (range 0.5-32.6 months). The causes of death were, in order of frequency: failure to thrive, respiratory failure, pneumonia, dehydration, anaemia, sepsis and euthanasia. The pattern of initial weight gain was a predictor of lifespan in these patients. Invasive treatments to extend life did not promote survival in our patients. It is important to diagnose JEB-H as soon as possible after birth so that the management can be shifted from life-saving to comfort care. The palliative end-of-life care can take place in hospital, but is also safe in the home setting. Suffering in patients with JEB-H can become so unbearable that in some patients who do not respond to adequate analgesic and sedative treatment, newborn euthanasia, performed according to the Groningen protocol, is legally permitted in the Netherlands.
Article
Abortion is largely accepted even for reasons that do not have anything to do with the fetus' health. By showing that (1) both fetuses and newborns do not have the same moral status as actual persons, (2) the fact that both are potential persons is morally irrelevant and (3) adoption is not always in the best interest of actual people, the authors argue that what we call 'after-birth abortion' (killing a newborn) should be permissible in all the cases where abortion is, including cases where the newborn is not disabled.
Article
To clarify the process of end-of-life decision-making in culturally different neonatal intensive care units (NICUs). Review of medical files of newborns >22 weeks gestation who died in the delivery room (DR) or the NICU during 12 months in 4 NICUs (Chicago, Milwaukee, Montreal, and Groningen). We categorized deaths using a 2-by-2 matrix and determined whether mechanical ventilation was withdrawn/withheld and whether the child was dying despite ventilation or physiologically stable but extubated for neurological prognosis. Most unstable patients in all units died in their parents' arms after mechanical ventilation was withdrawn. In Milwaukee, Montreal, and Groningen, 4% to 12% of patients died while receiving cardiopulmonary resuscitation. This proportion was higher in Chicago (31%). Elective extubation for quality-of-life reasons never occurred in Chicago and occurred in 19% to 35% of deaths in the other units. The proportion of DR deaths in Milwaukee, Montreal, and Groningen was 16% to 22%. No DR deaths occurred in Chicago. Death in the NICU occurred differently within and between countries. Distinctive end-of-life decisions can be categorized separately by using a model with uniform definitions of withholding/withdrawing mechanical ventilation correlated with the patient's physiological condition. Cross-cultural comparison of end-of-life practice is feasible and important when comparing NICU outcomes.
Article
This Clinical Report was reaffirmed January 2014 and June 2024 There is broad consensus that withholding or withdrawing medical interventions is morally permissible when requested by competent patients or, in the case of patients without decision-making capacity, when the interventions no longer confer a benefit to the patient or when the burdens associated with the interventions outweigh the benefits received. The withdrawal or withholding of measures such as attempted resuscitation, ventilators, and critical care medications is common in the terminal care of adults and children. In the case of adults, a consensus has emerged in law and ethics that the medical administration of fluid and nutrition is not fundamentally different from other medical interventions such as use of ventilators; therefore, it can be forgone or withdrawn when a competent adult or legally authorized surrogate requests withdrawal or when the intervention no longer provides a net benefit to the patient. In pediatrics, forgoing or withdrawing medically administered fluids and nutrition has been more controversial because of the inability of children to make autonomous decisions and the emotional power of feeding as a basic element of the care of children. This statement reviews the medical, ethical, and legal issues relevant to the withholding or withdrawing of medically provided fluids and nutrition in children. The American Academy of Pediatrics concludes that the withdrawal of medically administered fluids and nutrition for pediatric patients is ethically acceptable in limited circumstances. Ethics consultation is strongly recommended when particularly difficult or controversial decisions are being considered.
Article
Clinicians frequently administer analgesics and sedatives at the time of withholding or withdrawal of life-sustaining treatment in newborns. This practice might be regarded as intentionally hastening of death. To describe type, doses and reasons for administering medications as part of end-of-life decisions in the Dutch neonatal intensive care units. We reviewed the medical files of 340 newborn deaths with a preceding end-of-life decision over a 12-month period to describe the use of analgesics, sedatives and/or neuromuscular blockers. The neonatologists of 147 of the 150 newborns with a preceding end-of-life decision based on the infant's poor prognosis were interviewed to obtain additional details about the use of medication. Analgesics and sedatives were administered to 224 of 340 newborns before the end-of-life decision and to 292 newborns after the decision. The medication was increased in 94 of 289 newborns whose death was imminent and in 110 of 150 newborns with a poor prognosis. Reasons for the increase were treatment of pain and suffering, and in 4% of cases hastening of death. Reasons were undocumented in 55% of deaths. Neuromuscular blockers were administered in 16% of patients because they already received these agents or to stop or prevent gasping. Analgesics and sedatives are generally increased after the end-of-life decision to treat pain and suffering and rarely to hasten death. Neuromuscular blockers were administered in 16% of deaths. Medical files provide insufficient documentation of considerations leading to the increase of medication, which hinders (external) review.
Article
The Groningen Protocol allows active euthanasia of severely ill newborns with unbearable suffering. Defenders of the protocol insist that the protocol refers to terminally ill infants and that quality of life should not be a factor in the decision to euthanize an infant. They also argue that there should be no ethical difference between active and passive euthanasia of these infants. However, nowhere in the protocol does it refer to terminally ill infants; on the contrary, the developers of the protocol take into account the future quality of life of the infant. We also note how the Nazi Euthanasie Programm started with the premise that there is some life not worthy of living. Therefore, in our opinion, the protocol violates the traditional ethical codes of physicians and the moral values of the overwhelming majority of the citizens of the world.