ArticlePDF Available

Participatory Sense-Making: an enactive approach to social cognition

Authors:

Abstract and Figures

As yet, there is no enactive account of social cognition. This paper extends the enactive concept of sense-making into the social domain. It takes as its departure point the process of interaction between individuals in a social encounter. It is a well-established finding that individuals can and generally do coordinate their movements and utterances in such situations. We argue that the interaction process can take on a form of autonomy. This allows us to reframe the problem of social cognition as that of how meaning is generated and transformed in the interplay between the unfolding interaction process and the individuals engaged in it. The notion of sense-making in this realm becomes participatory sense-making. The onus of social understanding thus moves away from strictly the individual only.
Content may be subject to copyright.
Participatory sense-making
An enactive approach to social cognition
Hanne De Jaegher &Ezequiel Di Paolo
Published online: 5 October 2007
#Springer Science + Business Media B.V. 2007
Abstract As yet, there is no enactive account of social cognition. This paper
extends the enactive concept of sense-making into the social domain. It takes as its
departure point the process of interaction between individuals in a social encounter.
It is a well-established finding that individuals can and generally do coordinate their
movements and utterances in such situations. We argue that the interaction process
can take on a form of autonomy. This allows us to reframe the problem of social
cognition as that of how meaning is generated and transformed in the interplay
between the unfolding interaction process and the individuals engaged in it. The
notion of sense-making in this realm becomes participatory sense-making. The onus
of social understanding thus moves away from strictly the individual only.
Keywords Social cognition .Enaction .Sense-making .Interaction process .
Coordination .Participatory sense-making .Autonomy
Introduction
Enaction is a promising and growing paradigm in cognitive science. However, there is
no well-rounded proposal for an enactive account of social cognition yet. This may
seem strange since enactivism, with its focused examination of the coupling between
agent and world and on experience as a full aspect of cognition and of cognition
research, seems to be a particularly promising arena for addressing unresolved
problems in the study of social cognition. Our aim in this paper is to sketch an
enactive account of social understanding that takes the properties of the interaction
process as its point of departure. In doing so, we hope to re-instill the notion of
interaction’–fashionable yet faded by casual usage with a workable meaning.
Phenom Cogn Sci (2007) 6:485507
DOI 10.1007/s11097-007-9076-9
H. De Jaegher (*):E. Di Paolo
Centre for Computational Neuroscience and Robotics, Centre for Research in Cognitive Science,
University of Sussex, Brighton, UK
e-mail: H.De.Jaegher@sussex.ac.uk
Traditional approaches such as Theory of Mind theory and simulation theory have
had to endure anti-cognitivist arguments like the problems of homuncularity, the
absence of the body, and the threatening infinite regress of perspectives that are rule-
based at the pragmatic level and therefore can never account for meaning-generating
processes. Apart from that, there is a recognition that explanation and prediction may
not be at the centre of our everyday social practice. Over-emphasis on the latter skills
has led most of contemporary social cognitive science to paint a picture of individuals
who have to work out each others minds much like they do with scientific problems.
In this view, what counts as socialdiffers from non-social problem-solving merely as
a matter of degree. These worries have led to a call for embodied alternatives, which
have been duly proposed. However, even though their proponents recognise the need
for a perspective change that does proper justice to the situatedness and embodiment
of the social subject, they often remain themselves methodologically individualistic.
That the importance of the interaction process is recognised in these circles is without
doubt (Gallagher 2001;2004;Hutto2004;2007;Ratcliffe2007;Thompson2001).
What we now need, however, is to move beyond recognition and work out what the
interaction process does for social cognition.
When we talk about social interaction in this paper, we refer to the face-to-face
encounters of everyday life. These encounters range from brief and superficial to
deep and extensive. At the affective level, they reach from leaving their participants
cold to changing their life forever. They take place in many different situations,
which can have more or less of an impact on what can and does get conveyed
between the interaction partners. We are concerned here with what, in social science,
is called the micro-level (not the macro-level of how societies form, live or change).
At this level, we focus on the common patterns found in the widest possible range of
social interactions, i.e. not restricted to linguistic or even human ones. Furthermore,
for reasons of simplification, we take as a model the dyadic interaction. We are
aware that interactions between more than two participants may present their own
characteristics, but we expect that many of the properties examined in this paper will
extend into those cases as well. With these caveats in mind we hope to lay a
foundation from which more specific future analyses can follow.
This intuitive scope has to be clarified by a proper definition of social interaction,
which we provide later in the paper. First, we introduce the enactive notion of sense-
making. Then we extend it into the social domain, passing through an analysis of the
interaction process in dynamical terms, and propose participatory sense-making as a
starting point for a richer account of social understanding. Finally, we outline some
implications emanating from this proposal.
Sense-making
There exist wider and narrower conceptions of enaction. Today we find a variety of
applications of this term, often sharing a family resemblance. In this paper, we
restrict its use to a well-defined set of ideas that together constitute a new approach
to cognitive science. These ideas have been articulated in the writings of Francisco
Varela and colleagues (Thompson 2007; Torrance 2005; Varela et al. 1991) and link
several themes centred around the role of life, self-organization, experience and the
486 H. De Jaegher, E. Di Paolo
animate body in shaping cognition as an ongoing and situated activity. When
referring to the enactive approach in this paper we will be referring specifically to
these central concepts.
Rather than being a set of all radically novel ideas, the enactive approach is better
construed as a synthesis of some new but also some old themes. Overall, the enactive
perspective is a kind of non-reductive naturalism. It sees the properties of living and
cognitive systems as part of a continuum and consequently advocates a scientific
program that explores several phases along this dimension. We identify five core ideas
that define the enactive paradigm. These are the mutually supporting concepts of
autonomy,sense-making,embodiment,emergence,andexperience (Di Paolo, Rohde
and De Jaegher 2007;Thompson2005,2007; Varela et al. 1991). We will not attempt
anything beyond the briefest of descriptions of these important concepts here.
The enactive approach takes as its point of departure the organizational properties
of living organisms that make them paradigmatic cases of cognisers. One such
crucial property is the constitutive and interactive autonomy that living systems
enjoy by virtue of their self-generated identity as distinct entities in constant material
flux. An autonomous system is defined as a system composed of several processes
that actively generate and sustain an identity under precarious conditions. To
generate an identity in this context is to possess the property of operational closure.
This is the property that among the enabling conditions for any constituent process
in the system one will always find one or more other processes in the system (i.e.,
there are no processes that are not conditioned by other processes in the network
which does not mean, of course, that conditions external to the system cannot be
necessary as well for such processes to exist). By precarious we mean the fact that in
the absence of the organization of the system as a network of processes, under
otherwise equal physical conditions, isolated component processes would tend to run
down or extinguish. Similar constitutive and interactive properties have been
proposed to emerge at different levels of identity-generation, including sensorimotor
and neuro-dynamical forms of autonomy (Di Paolo, Rohde and De Jaegher 2007;
Moreno and Etxeberria 2005; Thompson 2007; Varela 1979,1997).
Such a view of cognitive systems as autonomous rejects the traditional poles of
seeing cognisers as responding to environmental stimuli on the one hand, and as
satisfying internal demands on the other both of which fail to give the autonomous
agent its proper ontological status and subordinate it to a passive role of obedience.
A key principle of the enactive approach is that the organism is a centre of activity in
the world. The relation of emergence between novel forms of identity (e.g.,
integrated sensorimotor engagements as emerging from neural, bodily and
environmental dynamics) is one whereby the coupling between the emergent
process and its context leads to constraints and modulation of the operation of the
underlying levels (Di Paolo, Rohde and De Jaegher 2007; Thompson 2007;
Thompson and Varela 2001). Taking emergence seriously makes the enactive
approach very skeptical about the localisation of function at one level in specific
components at a lower level (homuncularity) and consequently it leads to the
rejection of boxologyas a valid method to address the how does it workquestion.
For the enactive approach, cognition is embodied action. In a concrete and
practical sense, a cognitive system is embodied to the extent to which its activity
depends non-trivially on the body. This is close to expressing a tautology: cognition
Participatory sense-making 487
cannot but be embodied. But pointing to this has been (and still is) necessary in the
computational/representational climate that gave rise to the embodied turn in cognitive
science. Far from being a controlled puppet, the animate body is the autonomous locus
and means for significant activity. But in order for this message not to dilute, it is
important to do much more than just say that cognition is embodied (Sheets-Johnstone
1999). The debate must be moved to the concrete realm of seeing exactly how the
animate body in its world is a mind. Abstract discussions of embodiment tend to be
rather impoverished and defenders of the role of the body in cognition have often
easily fallen back into disembodied patterns of thought (see discussion in Di Paolo,
Rohde and De Jaegher (2007)). The same indictment applies to taking experience
seriously (see also the discussion of corporeal impersonalismby Colombetti 2007).
For enaction, experience is central both methodologically and thematically. Far from
being an epiphenomenon or a puzzle as it is for cognitivism experience in the
enactive approach is intertwined with being alive and enacting a meaningful world. As
part of the enactive method, experience goes beyond being data to be explained. It
becomes a guiding force in a dialogue between phenomenology and science, resulting
in an ongoing pragmatic circulation and mutual illumination between the two
(Gallagher 1997; van Gelder 1999; Varela 1996,1999).
All these ideas (which we have hardly done justice to) will play a role in a fully-
fledged enactive theory of social cognition. But the central notion that best facilitates
our initial steps is that of sense-making.
Already implied in the notion of interactive autonomy is the realisation that
organisms cast a web of significance on their world. An organism that regulates its
coupling with the environment does so because there is a direction that this process
is aiming at: that of the continuity of the self-generated identity or identities that
initiate the regulation. This establishes a perspective on the world with its own
normativity, which is the counterpart of the agent being a centre of activity in the
world (Di Paolo, Rohde and De Jaegher 2007; Di Paolo 2005; Thompson 2007;
Varela 1997; Weber and Varela 2002). Exchanges with the world are inherently
significant for the cogniser and this is a definitional property of a cognitive system:
the creation and appreciation of meaning or sense-making in short. The distinction
between a strictly physical encounter and a cognitive one is to be found in the
dimension of significance for the cogniser itself that is characteristic only of the
latter class, even though cognitive interactions are themselves also physical
processes. Like few ideas in the past, the concept of sense-making strikes at the
heart of what is to be cognitive.
Reaffirming the implications of autonomy, sense-making is an inherently active
concept. Organisms do not passively receive information from their environments,
which they then translate into internal representations whose significant value is to
be added later. Natural cognitive systems are simply not in the business of accessing
their world in order to build accurate pictures of it. They actively participate in the
generation of meaning in what matters to them; they enact a world. Sense-making is
a relational and affect-laden process grounded in biological organization. The idea
that metabolism creates a perspective of value on the world has been defended by
Jonas (1966) and recently elaborated scientifically in terms of the theory of
autopoiesis (Di Paolo 2005; Thompson 2007; Varela 1991,1997; Weber and Varela
2002). Hence it does not promote a fissure between affect and cognition.
488 H. De Jaegher, E. Di Paolo
Traditional distinctions between action and perception arise only as the
specialisation of phases in an act of sense-making. Several examples that illustrate
this point have been discussed in the enaction literature, but perhaps the simplest and
clearest one is that of perceiving the softness of a sponge (Myin 2003). The softness
of a sponge is not to be found in itbut in how it responds to the active probing and
squeezing of our appropriate bodily movements (e.g., with the fingers or the palms
of the hand). It is the outcome of a particular kind of encounter between a
questioningagent with a particular body (sponges are solid ground for ants) and a
respondingsegment of the world. The confluence of lawful co-variations in this
dialogue stabilises the cognisers sense-making into an object. Movements are at the
centre of mental activity: a sense-making agents movements which include
utterances are the tools of her cognition.
Based on these core ideas, can we speculate on what might be the central
concerns of an enactive theory of social cognition? Such a theory would be
concerned with defining the social in terms of the embodiment of interaction, in
terms of shifting and emerging levels of autonomous identity, and in terms of joint
sense-making and its experience. This is in contrast to defining the problematic of
the social as the expansion of a very narrow perspective that focuses on a problem
that might be caricaturised as that of figuring out someone elses intentions out of
our individual observations of them; a sort of Rear Window approach to the social.
As we will see below, even embodied criticisms of cognitivist theories tend to
subscribe to some version of this approach as the framework for asking questions
about social cognition. This removed cognitive problem belongs indeed to a theory
of social understanding, but it has unfairly defined the flavour of most of the field at
the expense of downplaying the role of more engaged forms of interaction. One of
the main objectives of this paper is to shift the focus towards a view that is not
exclusively defined by individual cognitive mechanisms.
Participatory sense-making
Although several researchers have already started to regard problems in social
cognition from embodied perspectives (Gallagher 2001,2005,2007; Hutto 2004;
Klin et al. 2003; Thompson 2001), one motivation for our proposal is the
observation that they have not yet gone far enough in taking the interaction process
as central. For example, Gallaghersembodied practice of mind(whereby our
embodiment allows for a direct perception of the expressiveness of the others body,
Gallagher 2005) does not yet integrate a rich account of the interaction process and
its role in social understanding, even though it certainly recognises its importance
(Gallagher 2004). Once the point is made that the interaction is crucial, the next
thing we need to do is to clarify why and how this is so.
An account of our social capacities based solely on expressiveness can explain
why babies become distressed when their previously very engaging mother suddenly
sits very still and puts on an immobile, neutral face (Tronick et al. 1979). But it
cannot explain why, when mother and baby interact via a double TV monitor, it
seriously upsets the baby when the live footage of his mother is suddenly replaced
with a recording of her behaviour earlier in the same interaction (Murray and
Participatory sense-making 489
Trevarthen 1985). Here, we can be certain that it is not expressiveness that is
lacking, but the ongoing engagement that has been unhinged. If this (the lack of
contingency) disturbs the baby as much as the suddenly expressionless mother,
something crucial must also be going on in the interaction process itself.
Experientially this is not surprising interactions often have an affective dimension
in the sense that we can feel varying degrees of connectedness with the other.
Dynamics of coordination
In order to put the process of interaction at the centre of our investigation, we borrow
some concepts from dynamical systems theory. In particular, we spend some time
describing the phenomenon of coordination between coupled systems. This allows
us to view interactions as processes extended in time with a rich structure that is only
apparent at the relational level of collective dynamics. Once we understand how
coordination arises, is sustained, changes, and breaks down during social encounters,
we will be in a position to make a connection between these temporal aspects of
interaction and their consequences for joint and individual sense-making.
For our purposes, we take coordination to mean the non-accidental correlation
between the behaviours of two or more systems that are in sustained coupling, or
have been coupled in the past, or have been coupled to another, common, system. A
correlation is a coherence in the behaviour of two or more systems over and above
what is expected, given what those systems are capable of doing. For instance, when
we observe a crowd of people walking on a busy road, the fact that they walk is not
surprising, and we do not label this a case of coordination since walking is one of the
things people do on a road (as opposed to, say, flying). But if we find that they are
all walking in the same direction this could be a correlation, and if we suspect that
this is not by accident, we can hypothesise the presence of a coordinating factor (for
instance, an anti-war demonstration).
Coordination is a ubiquitous phenomenon in physical and biological systems.
Pendulum clocks, for instance, synchronise their oscillations when in each others
vicinity through the minute vibrations they provoke on the wall (Winfree 2001).
Several physical systems exhibit similar behaviour even when their coupling (the
amount of influence that a systems variables have on anothers parametrical
conditions) is weak. In biology, we also find many paradigmatic cases of
coordination. For instance, Buck and Buck (1976) describe a species of firefly that
lives in Southeast Asia, in which the individual flashing behaviour is synchronised at
the group level through the visual influence of the collective flashing pattern on the
individuals. These examples are merely indicators of the myriad of systems that
coordinate when coupled collectively that have been heavily studied in physics,
mathematical biology and dynamical approaches to cognition (e.g. Kelso 1995;
Kuramoto 1984; Port and van Gelder 1995; Winfree 2001).
One common finding in almost all these studies is that coordination is typically
easily achieved by simple mechanical means and, when cognitive systems are
involved, it does not generally require any cognitively sophisticated skill. On the
contrary, it is often hard to avoid. For instance, when asking pairs of subjects to
avoid synchronous oscillations while swinging a pendulum with their arms, Schmidt
and OBrien (1997) found that their oscillations were independent (uncoordinated)
490 H. De Jaegher, E. Di Paolo
when not looking at each other, but presented strong tendency to phase-lock when
they were allowed to look at each other. When coordination is observed we need not
postulate dedicated individual mechanisms that sustain it, but rather, in general, it is
a phenomenon to be expected under a variety of conditions if the systems possess
broadly similar properties. A commonly encountered characteristic is that coordina-
tion happens at multiple timescales (Winfree 2001). It is also important to note that
synchronization is not the only kind of coordination; many cases of appropriately
patterned behaviour, such as mirroring, anticipation, imitation, etcetera are general
forms of coordination according to our definition.
An important feature of coordination, particularly with regard to fluid social
interactions, is that it does not have to be absolute or permanent. There are degrees
of coordination and coupled systems may undergo changes in the level of
coordination over time. Kelso (1995) uses the notions of absolute versus relative
coordination to illustrate this point. He gives the following example. Imagine a child
and an adult taking a walk together. Due to their different body sizes, they would
naturally tend to walk at a different pace, but we often find that they remain together
overall. In order for this to happen, one or the other has to adjust either the frequency
of their step or the length of their stride. To keep up with each other, the adult may
now and then slow down a bit, and the child may skip a step or two. This kind of
coordination is far more variable, plastic and fluid... than pure phase locking
(Kelso 1995, p. 98). Pure phase locking is a form of absolute coordination, where the
synchrony is perfect: two series of events are perfectly entrained (e.g. pairs of
duetting tropical birds that sing in perfect antiphonal coordination, see for instance
Thorpe 1972). In absolute coordination, transitions in the coupling of the systems
take place from one stable, perfectly locking state to another, or to non-coordination.
Relative coordination, in contrast, has a much wider range of possibilities, as there
are no such transitions from one strictly coherent state to another. Systems in relative
coordination do not entrain perfectly. Instead they show phase attraction, which
means that they tend to go near perfect synchrony, and move into and out of the zone
that surrounds it. This is a common phenomenon in biology (Cook 1991; Haken and
Köpchen 1991). Coordination can be like a swaying into and out of states that are
close to stable, but not quite. Eventually, it may break down altogether.
The autonomy of social interaction
While coordination is common to various kinds of coupled systems, it is of
particular interest when trying to understand social encounters. This concept allows
us to claim that social interaction constitutes a proper level of analysis in itself.
Several researchers in social science have recognised the importance of different
forms of coordination for understanding social interaction. There is indeed a
tradition within social science championed by figures such as Erving Goffman,
Harvey Sacks and others that starts from an understanding of interactive encounters
(see e.g. Goffman 1972,1983; Sacks 1992; Sacks et al. 1974). A whole field of
study is dedicated to uncovering behavioural coordination in interaction going under
different labels such as interaction studies, conversation analysis, gesture analysis
(see Schiffrin 1994). Within this field there is a debate about how to delineate
behaviour into the units to study, with sometimes rather arbitrary choices influencing
Participatory sense-making 491
the results (for instance, Jaffe and Feldstein 1970). It is also the case, in general, that
such studies do not amalgamate into a theoretical framework that has much concern
for the individual cogniser as such.
In order to bridge what we perceive as a gap between the social science and
cognitive science perspectives, we need to articulate how the individual and social
levels interrelate. The concept of coordination helps us to understand the social
interaction as an ongoing process. We must go beyond a view that defines interaction
as simply the spatio-temporal coincidence of two agents that influence each other. We
must move towards an understanding of how their history of coordination demarcates
the interaction as an identifiable pattern with its own internal structure, and its own
role to play in the process of understanding each other and the world.
Something that is not so common in cases of purely physical coupling, but that
we find in the social domain, is that patterns of coordination can directly influence
the continuing disposition of the individuals involved to sustain or modify their
encounter. In this way, what arises in the process of coordination (e.g. gestures,
utterances and changes in intonation that are sometimes labelled as back-channeling
or turn-repair, etc.) can have the consequence of steering the encounter or facilitating
(or not) its continuation. And the particular unravelling of these dynamics itself
influences what kinds of coordination are more likely to happen. This is due to the
fact that the interactors are highly plastic systems that are susceptible to being
affected by the history of coordination. When this double influence is in place (from
the coordination onto the unfolding of the encounter and from the dynamics of the
encounter onto the likelihood to coordinate) we say we are in the presence of a
social interaction. This emerging level is sustained and identifiable as long as the
processes described (or some external factor) do not terminate it.
In accordance with the core ideas of enaction, the above description is nothing
less than that of an emergent and autonomous process (Di Paolo, Rohde and De
Jaegher 2007; Thompson 2007; Thompson and Varela 2001; Varela 1979). It is,
however, typically a fleeting one. Even though normal social encounters, for
instance conversations, may only last a few minutes, our point is that during that
period they may organize themselves according to the two avenues of influence just
described: the agents sustain the encounter, and the encounter itself influences the
agents and invests them with the role of interactors. The interaction process emerges
as an entity when social encounters acquire this operationally closed organization. It
constitutes a level of analysis not reducible, in general, to individual behaviours.
This perspective bypasses the circularity that arises from pre-conceiving individuals
as ready-made interactors. Individuals co-emerge as interactors with the interaction.
This brings us to the further requirement for calling an interaction properly social.
Not only must the process itself enjoy a temporary form of autonomy, but the
autonomy of the individuals as interactors must also not be broken (even though the
interaction may enhance or diminish the scope of individual autonomy). If this were
not so, if the autonomy of one of the interactors were destroyed, the process would
reduce to the cognitive engagement of the remaining agent with his non-social
world. The otherwould simply become a tool, an object, or a problem for his
individual cognition (such a situation would epitomise what we have diagnosed
traditional perspectives on social cognition as suffering from: namely, the lack of a
properly social level).
492 H. De Jaegher, E. Di Paolo
We propose the following definition of social interaction:
Social interaction is the regulated coupling between at least two autonomous
agents, where the regulation is aimed at aspects of the coupling itself so that it
constitutes an emergent autonomous organization in the domain of relational
dynamics, without destroying in the process the autonomy of the agents
involved (though the latters scope can be augmented or reduced).
The transfer of body heat, for instance when waiting for the bus at a crowded
stop, is not a social interaction. In this case, there is coupling between the agents, but
the coupling is not actively regulated by the agents involved so as to affect this
coupling itself. Bumping into each other on a busy street is not a social interaction in
the first instance, but it can become one once one or both of the parties start to
regulate the ensuing coupling. A conversation about a sponge is a social interaction,
because the participants decide upon the topic together, regulate beginning, course
and ending of the dialogue, and their autonomy (neither as living beings, nor as
conversation partners) is not destroyed in the process.
Thus, social interaction has two characteristics: (1) there is a coupling, which is
regulated so as to generate and maintain an identity in the relational domain. Thus,
the resulting relational dynamics are autonomous in the strict sense of precarious
operational closure given in this paper and define events and processes as either
internal or external to the interaction. And (2) the individuals involved are and
remain autonomous as interactors. In order to illustrate the autonomy of the
interaction, it is easy to think of interactions in which the participants have an
interest in sustaining it (e.g., an interesting conversation, an enjoyable dance). But
these would not exemplify the point well enough. It is much better to think of a
situation where the individual interactors are attempting to stop interacting but where
the interaction self-sustains in spite of this.
Consider the situation in a narrow corridor when two people walking in opposite
directions have to get past each other. They have to decide whether to continue walking
as they are, or shift their movement to the right or to the left. Occasionally, such
encounters unfold like this. Instead of choosing complementary movements that would
allow them to carry on walking, the individuals move into mirroring positions at the same
time. This unintended coordinated change in individual position creates a symmetrical
mirroring relation. This symmetry, in combination with the spatial constraints of the
corridor, increases the likelihood that the next move will also be a mirroring one (there
are not many other moves available). Thus, the coordination maintains a property of the
relational dynamics that forces the individuals to keep facing each other and
consequently to remain in interaction (in spite of, or rather because of, their efforts to
break from this situation). In addition, the interaction promotes individual actions that
tend to maintain the symmetrical coordination. Coordinated sideways movements
conserve symmetry and symmetry promotes coordinated sideways movements.
We may describe this relation as the mutual influence between coordination
patterns and the interaction process (Fig. 1). Here, the coordinated lateral shifts in
position are functional for the continuation of the interaction (not for the interactors
intentions!) and so we call them functional coordination. And the relational
symmetry present in the interaction promotes certain patterns of coordination
(interactional coordination). Only when the symmetry is broken through some
Participatory sense-making 493
channel different from lateral position shifting (e.g., when one person invites the
other to move first) does the interaction finally break down. While it lasts, the
interaction shows the organization described above in terms of the mutual influence
between the individual actions and the relational dynamics. Here, we see that
interaction is not reducible to individual actions or intentions but installs a relational
domain with its own properties that constrains and modulates individual behaviour.
As we said above, there is a tendency in current approaches to social cognition to
acknowledge the importance of the interaction (see e.g. Gallagher 2001;Hutto2004;
Pickering and Garrod 2004), but as long as there is no explicit and focused attention to
this relational domain as illustrated in the example above, this emphasis on interaction
remains vacuous. In many of these approaches, the interaction seems merely an
addendum to a position that departs from what is really still an individualistic
perspective. In our opinion, any approach that mentions interaction, but fails to go into
the relational dynamics of the interaction process in detail, is simply not an interactive
account and probably not even a social one, despite the goodwill driving it. There are
other approaches that go further and not only recognise the importance of the
interaction but see in it a central and irreducible component of social cognition (e.g.
Auvray et al. 2006; Cowley 2007;Fogel1993;Gilletal.2000;Hobson2002;
Ratcliffe 2007; Shanker and King 2002; Trevarthen 1979; Tronick 2005). However,
what is still lacking is the articulation of a theoretical and methodological framework
that takes the interaction process as its point of departure. With the concept of
coordination and how it enables us to explicate the autonomy of the interaction
process, we have taken an alternative, inherently social route.
At the same time, it is vital to avoid the error of considering only the interaction
and ignoring the individual elements in it. Hence our emphasis on the autonomy of
the interactors throughout their engagement with each other in order for the
interaction to be considered properly social. For example, couple dancing involves
moving each other, making each other move, and being moved by each other. This
goes for both leader and follower. Following is part of an agreement and does not
equate with being shifted into position by the other. If the follower were to give up
her autonomy, the couple dancing would end there, and it would look more like a
doll being carried around the dance floor. The same goes for conversations: each
partner must engage from an autonomous standpoint. If conversational autonomy
were given up, neither partner would be able to influence the other. There are,
Fig. 1 Interaction influences coordination (interactional coordination), and coordination influences
interaction or has a function for the interaction (functional coordination)
494 H. De Jaegher, E. Di Paolo
however, interactions where one agent attempts to break (at least partly) the
autonomy of the other (e.g. coercion and torture). They do not always achieve this
goal, however, and when they do, in our view, they cease to be social at that point.
1
By escaping from the methodological individualism prevalent in todays cognitive
science (Boden 2006), our perspective offers an important implication for
fashionable theories of social cognition. There is a strong tendency in recent
embodied proposals to rely on neurological mechanisms such as so-called mirror
neurons when explaining social understanding. Unfortunately, such explanations do
not address the need to see the interaction as a structured and structuring process. A
subjects mirror neurons fire when he performs a goal-directed action and when he
perceives someone else doing it (Gallese et al. 1996). Even if these explanations had
no problems (but see de Vignemont and Singer 2006; Georgieff and Jeannerod
1998), in our view they remain within the problem-framework of a detached
individual trying to figure out the other; what we have earlier called the Rear
Window position. The problem of how such a figuring out participates in and is itself
shaped by coordination dynamics remains untouched. Appropriate correlations in
social activity are what we are trying to explain. Transferring their cause to a neural
correlation is simply to re-describe the problem. Explanations based on mirror
neurons provide no more than a snapshot view of how recognition of intentional
action could work. The problem is that the same recognition could equally be part of
a coordinated or un-coordinated period in an interaction, and the difference between
the two could not therefore be explained by this mechanism. It is this difference that,
we argue, plays a crucial role in how the interaction unfolds.
A similar problem results from attempts to explain social cognition by other forms
of pre-given coordination (i.e., coordinated tendencies of behaviour that pre-date the
encounter). These undoubtedly exist. How else would we be able to account for
situations where persons who have never met show the same table manners? In cases
like this, some level of structural congruence between these persons is already
present before the encounter thanks to previous interaction with culturally prevalent
behavioural norms what Bourdieu calls the habitus (Bourdieu 1990). Even though
certain pre-dispositions to coordinate can play a great role in everyday interactions, a
view based on pre-dispositions foregoes the need and capacity to account for all the
possible influences on an interaction; biological, bodily, emotional, situational, and
cultural. A pre-disposition for a particular coordination may break down as a result
of these influences in a given situational context. An account of social cognition
should be able to explain how we cope with this, and we propose that this coping
happens in interaction. Imagine two people from France where (for the sake of
1
We must acknowledge here that by autonomy of the interactors we should understand a possibly multi-
dimensional complex of identities that co-exist in what we call a subject, from his physical body, his
sensorimotor integration, his function in the interaction, to his broader contextual, relational and historical
roles. Complex interactions may result in the loss of the autonomy associated with a specific identity but
they are still social as long as other autonomous identities remain in interaction (e.g., a conversation where
an employee loses his job is a definitive blow to the sustained identity of the employee as such, but not to
the social agent that still enjoys his autonomy to express his reaction to the situation). We expect that even
though the proposed distinction holds in general (encounters are not social if an interactors autonomy is
lost), specific instances must be unpacked carefully in terms of what identities are at play in what we have
loosely termed an interactor.
Participatory sense-making 495
argument) people kiss each other on the cheek when saying goodbye who meet for
the first time in Britain where they both have been living for a number of years,
and where (again for the sake of the argument) strangers or even friends never kiss in
such situations. What will they do? We may expect a tension between the pre-
coordination given by their French habit and the present context. Faces may move in
probingly and cheeks may turn. Whether these two people kiss is determined by
their interactional coordination right there and then. On any other occasion the
outcome may be different. It is much like the two people attempting to pass each
other in the corridor. The solution depends on how the interaction and the individual
intentions eventually achieve (or not) a coordination.
In this section we have conceived of the interaction as an autonomous process.
One advantage of this view is that it allows us to understand the history of
coordination, breakdowns, and recoveries at different levels as elements that shape
the interaction throughout its history. Sustained interactions can be expected to have
undergone several instances of loss and regain of coordinating structures, each of
them leaving the interactors slightly better able to remain in such interaction or
reinitiate it experientially, we often perceive some interactions as improving over
time, and the recovery from a breakdown as a sort of learning in which our previous
moves acquire new contextual significance. Viewing interactions from this
perspective is akin to understanding the growth of an adaptive system. Such a view
allows us to connect interaction dynamics with sense-making. We now turn to how
meaning is generated and transformed in social interactions.
Sense-makers interacting
In the previous subsection we have described how coordination happens in physical,
biological and social systems. Now we ask the question: how does coordination
affect the picture of social understanding? How does the physical, interactional
coordination of behaviour, in particular movements, relate to our capacity to share
meanings and to understand each other?
Previous work has looked at the relation between patterns of coordination and
affect. This is already a way of connecting the interaction dynamics with the
dimension of significance for the interactors. An initial proposal is that periods of
high temporal coordination (manifested in the form of synchrony of movements and
speech) relate to periods of high rapport between the interactors (Condon and
Ogston 1971; Kendon 1990). This observation seems intuitively right as it is indeed
possible to generally associate well-coordinated engagements with typically positive
affective experiences. Further research, however, has proposed that it is actually a
moderate amount of coordination that correlates most strongly with positive affect
(Jaffe et al. 2001). Everyday experience, though, seems to indicate that correlations
between rapport and coordination are not unequivocal. A highly-charged verbal fight
can sometimes demonstrate a good degree of coordination without the corresponding
affect being positive. The relation between patterns of coordination and their
implications for meaning should perhaps not be approached in terms of general
mappings between the two domains but rather in terms of how the processes
involved in the grasping and generation of meaning are affected by coordination
during interaction.
496 H. De Jaegher, E. Di Paolo
In socially interactive situations, coordination affects individual sense-making.
Individuals are constantly engaged in sense-making activity and this is also true in
social encounters. As an activity, sense-making is intentional and expressive; it is
essentially embodied in action. Thus, it is directly affected by the coordination of
movements in interaction. Indeed, the activities of sense-making may themselves
become coordinated. If regulation of social coupling takes place through
coordination of movements, and if movements including utterances are the
tools of sense-making, then our proposal is: social agents can coordinate their sense-
making in social encounters. This means that the sense-making of interactors
acquires a coherence through their interaction and not just in their physical
manifestation, but also in their significance. This is what we call participatory
sense-making: the coordination of intentional activity in interaction, whereby
individual sense-making processes are affected and new domains of social sense-
making can be generated that were not available to each individual on her own.
The coherence of sense-making activities and the coordination patterns that
enable it do not relate as simple mappings but in a range of ways that can be
conceived as sitting on a spectrum of participation (see Fig. 2). On one end of the
scale, we find cases where sense-making remains largely an individual activity that
is at most modulated by the existence of coordination in interaction. At the other end
of the spectrum, where participation is highest, we find the sophisticated cases where
we fully and directly participate in a joint process of sense-making and the whole
sense-making activity becomes a shared one.
In what ways does coordination affect the process of sense-making? Firstly, we
can illustrate how the patterns of coordination (and breakdowns in coordination) can
directly influence the significance of a situation for the individual sense-makers.
Consider a dialogue over a low quality video conferencing line where there is a short
time delay. Pauses between turns are unavoidable in this channel. But even when the
interactors are aware of these technical constraints, they are often affected by the
potential significance of a pause as they may not be certain of its cause. This kind of
situation shows how properties of the interaction dynamics may alter the sense-
Fig. 2 Spectrum of degrees of participation in sense-making
Participatory sense-making 497
making of each individual without this change being intended by either. Consider the
following conversation (Ruhleder and Jordan 2001, p. 121):
A: That was a pretty good presentation.
(Pause)
A: If youre into that kind of work.
B: Well, I suppose someone has to do it.
Because B did not respond immediately, A anticipating a disagreement
rephrased what she said, slightly diminishing her praise, and thus altering its
meaning. B, who may have initially shared As enthusiasm has now adjusted to the
more moderate view. This example illustrates two things: (1) how the individual
sense-making activities become adjusted through the situation and how a shift in
meaning is in this case created by the interaction dynamics and not just the
individuals, and (2) that a crucial element in this adjustment is the (here temporal)
coordination in the interaction. It becomes clear that much of our sense-making in
interaction relies on continuously appropriate coordination, since breakdowns of
such coordination can alter the meaning and progression of the interaction.
This situation is not only manifested in the presence of external breakdowns of
coordination. It is often the case that breakdowns emerge from the dynamics of the
interaction even when the interactors are actively trying to avoid it. Misinter-
pretations about the intentions of others often provoke responses that are themselves
misinterpreted, leading the interaction into a spiralling dynamics likely to engender a
general breakdown. Examples of this abound in literature, we find a very clear one in
Ian McEwans recent novel On Chesil Beach (an account of a disastrously failed
sexual encounter by a couple on their honeymoon). Granic (2000) describes similar
run-away processes at a developmental timescale in her investigation of how
relationships between parents and child can turn sour even if this is not the intention
of either party.
Moving right on the qualitative scale of participation proposed in Fig. 2,we
encounter situations where, through coordination of sense-making, one of the
interactors is oriented towards a novel domain of significance that was part of the
sense-making activity of the other. Such cases of orientation are ubiquitous. Calling
attention to what is salient to one of the interactors and not yet the other is achieved
by the purposeful modulation of the sense-making of one interactor (who, for
instance, is visually scanning in search of a lost object) by the other (who grabs his
attention and points to it). We can see a similar phenomenon in the regulation of
affect between mother and infant, which is more explicit in the dimension of
extended temporal coordination. Stern describes an example. A mother repeats the
phrase Im gonna getchato her infant, each time stretching the temporal interval to
the next utterance and the phrase itself (Stern 2002/1977, p. 114). Stern says that this
increases the discrepancy from the expectedfor the infant and the infant becomes
more and more excited (ibid.). In his explanations, Stern seems to oscillate between
emphasising the interaction as a process and attempting to explain it in terms of
individual cognitive capabilities. He says there could be no such effectunless the
infant had some mechanism for timing the beat and forming a temporal estimate of
when the next beat should fall(ibid.). It is not necessary to go that far. In the view
presented here, the infant is oriented towards a change of affective state through his
498 H. De Jaegher, E. Di Paolo
participation in coordination with the mothers tempo. This could not have happened
if the mother were not herself attuned to the infants response or if the infant for
some reason was not able to sustain the interaction dynamics in this particular
engagement. The above example can be explained in terms of relative coordination
as described in the section Dynamics of coordinationwhereby, like the adult and the
child walking together, the tempos of mother and child exhibit the property of phase
attraction through their mutual coupling. This explanation would not require the
positing of any specialised individual cognitive capability. If pendulum clocks can do
it without mechanisms for timing the beatand forming a temporal estimate, why
cant babies? In our perspective, what infant and mother do in this example is
possible through the interaction alone. It may well be that they both have capabilities
for entering into a temporal interaction with an external event or object, but no more
than this is needed. What makes it a case of orientation is the mothers intended
regulation of the relative coordination and through it of the babys sense-making.
Intermediate between the cases of direct orientation and regulatory orientation, we
could place the following description by Currie that does justice to the fragility and
brittleness of this process. He describes a beautiful example of the subtlety of an
everyday social interaction. A man and a woman come to agree on a perspective on
their current, shared experience, and they do this with minimal gesturing or uttering.
Upon arriving at their holiday destination, Janet stands in front of the open window
and takes an appreciative breath of the air, in such a way as to make sure that John
perceives it. It is clearly a communicative act.
What does Janet mean by doing this? That the air is fresh? The freshness of the
air is already evident to John. Janet is arranging things so that she and John
attend to the freshness of the air, in a way that is mutually manifest to both of
them. But Janet is doing more: she is adjusting Johns cognitive and affective
take on the world: trying to get John to see the world in somewhat the way she
is currently seeing it. There is a small, highly salient portion of the world visible
to both of them, and Janet wants John to attend to that portion of it in the way
that she is attending to it: appreciatively, gratefully, with excitement at the
possibilities for the holiday that has just begun. She does not want to convey
any propositions to John: she wants him to notice certain things; to engage
imaginatively with certain possibilities which these things present; to see these
things and possibilities as valuable in certain ways. She wants John to frame the
visible world in a certain way. It would be vastly impractical perhaps
impossible for Janet to try to say all this, to make explicit the way she wants
John to frame the bit of world they are looking at. It would also be pointless:
the minimal gesture does the job very well (Currie 2007).
In these cases of orientation the orientee does not relate to the orienter as someone
who is trying to figure out her individual actions like a detached observer. Rather, it
is through a process of coordination and modulation of sense-making activities that
the orientee is directly affected by the orienters intentions and sense-making and
therefore he does not need to figure out what these intentions are in order to respond
accordingly. A coordinated response already embodies a practical understanding.
There is no need for John to attempt to decypher Janet as she directly calls his
attention to the intended meaning. But for this to happen the response must be
Participatory sense-making 499
attainable from the domain of possibilities of the orientee so that he can
autonomously turn towards it. In order to be oriented, the orientee cannot be totally
passive. He is a sense-maker himself. In her turn, the orienter must not only grasp
the others sense-making but must skilfully act so that the right modulation comes
about. The more participation is required, the more the orienter may find herself
changing her own sense-making in the process. The interactions between mother and
infant described above involve more participation than the first case where a simple
gesture to look over there keeps the orienters sense-making virtually unchanged.
The picture is at the same time more parsimonious and richer than the individualistic
portrait of interaction as the mutual figuring out of intentions.
An even more radical possibility towards the right-hand side of Fig. 2is when
interactors move beyond the coordination (e.g., orientation) of individual sense-
making activities and become engaged in a joint process of sense-making. Here
meaning is created and transformed through patterns of coordination and break-
downs. The phases of action and perception typically used to describe individual
sense-making now acquire collective aspects and sense is created through the
stabilization of patterns of joint activity. When such patterns lawfully stabilise some
invariant relation the perceptual result is jointly constructed, and novel meanings
may be established in interaction. In this kind of activity the interactors engage in the
highest degree of participation in sense-making.
High level of participation in sense-making, like orientation, is also ubiquitous. It
happens in all kinds of human social contacts to the extent that it is rather difficult to
see. Many obvious cases come to mind (e.g., collaborating in a joint research project,
reaching an agreement after group negotiation, making a shopping list or improvising
a dish together). But these examples are hard to unpack. To illustrate participatory
sense-making, we must drastically reduce the complexity of the situation.
2
Consider the game of charades. This is a game of pantomimes: players have to
act outa phrase without speaking, while the other members of the same team try to
guess what the phrase is. Imagine that the phrase is the title of a film with two
words. There are well-established gestures for indicating this (e.g., emulating an old
camera by rotating the right hand in small circles in front of the eye, and indicating
the number two by tapping the arm with two fingers). These gestures are readily
interpreted. The player starts miming the second word. With his fingers he draws a
large square in the air in front of him. Someone suggests box. He gestures no.
Another guesses picture, again no. He changes the gesture, drawing the big square
again and then moving his hands together to the centre of the square and pulling his
closed hands towards him while opening his arms outwards. Cupboard.
Wardrobe.He gestures nobut adds a waving almost theremovement of the
hand. Then he makes the same square, puts his hands in the middle, but now pushes
2
Participatory sense-making is not restricted to human social interactions. Many social animals build up
coherences of significance by engaging in coordinated displays, such as circle-walking in wolves where
potential contenders size each other up by making turns around each other (Moran et al. 1981), their intention
to fight or not being affected by the emergent coordination. Even in simple models in evolutionary robotics
the discrimination between different significant contexts can be performed through appropriate coordination
between individuals (Di Paolo, Rohde and De Jaegher 2007; Quinn 2001). Recent work modelling the
detection of social contingency in minimal agents shows in explicit terms how individual perception alters its
meaning as a result of social coordination (Di Paolo, Rohde and Iizuka 2007).
500 H. De Jaegher, E. Di Paolo
his hands forwards and outwards with an opening movement and then leans
forwards with his upper body and moves his head and gaze from left to right. The
right answer comes: Window!Then he points to his back with his thumb over his
shoulder. Rear Window!
This situation begins very much like the examples of orientation. The player
intends to orient his team-mates. In the beginning this is easy thanks to established
conventions. The first attempt at gesturing a window is misinterpreted. The player
now must improve the situation by adding to the initial gesture something more
specific, so he gestures the opening of a window. The team-mates do not yet guess
the right answer, but their guesses show that they have understood the opening
aspect. Now the player can improve on this partial re-affirmation of his intended
meaning and he gestures the act of opening the window again, but this time
outwards (avoiding previous misinterpretations); he stresses the gesture by looking
out. Now they guess correctly. As the interaction unfolds, what started off as
orientation becomes more symmetrical since all interactors have to adjust their
sense-making in a way that converges towards the rightgesture and the right
interpretation. The new meaning of the gesture is jointly constructed during
interaction and evolves through patterns of coordination and breakdowns. It is
now available to the interactors for futher use and possible transformation (imagine
when film titles like Room with a View or Through a Glass Darkly come up).
Of course, the game of charades is not the same as interactions in daily life. It is
guided by rules that prescribe certain kinds of interaction (i.e. non-verbal). The
example, however, illustrates the possibility of meanings being generated and
transformed during interaction. This also happens in everyday situations where
sustained interactions (e.g., in couples, between friends, family members, work-
mates) develop their own language and shared perspectives. A certain reference may
develop over time (cf. Levin and Kittys dialogue using the first letters of words,
written in chalk, in chapter 13, part 4 of TolstoysAnna Karenina). Such an
intimately shared referent comes about precisely through what we conjecture goes
on in the highest realms of participation in sense-making.
While it is clear that making sense together may happen in situations where the
interactors are collaborating towards this goal, it is even more convincing to think of
situations where sense-making is done purely in the interaction without the
individuals even being aware of how it is happening. Recent experimental studies
in dyadic interaction show exactly this (Auvray et al. 2006; Di Paolo, Rohde and
Iizuka 2007). In these experiments, two blindfolded participants interacting in a
shared minimal virtual environment are asked to recognise the presence of each
other. The only possibility to act is to move the cursor left and right along a virtual
tapethat wraps around. Subjects sense the presence of an object or the other player
only through a touch sensor whenever their own cursor stepson them. To make the
task non-trivial, there is also a static object of the same size as the other subject on
the tape (fixed lure), as well as a mobile object that shadows the motion of each
participant at a constant distance (attached lure). The problem to be solved is
therefore not only distinguishing moving from non-moving entities along the tape
using the touch feedback, but distinguishing between two entities that move exactly
the same, only one of which represents the sensingposition of the other subject.
The momentary sensory patterns therefore do not suffice to distinguish the three
Participatory sense-making 501
entities that may be encountered. The only clue to tell whether a sensation is caused
by the other subject or not is the change of sensation over time in response to the
subjects own motion. It is conceivable that, from an individual point of view, the
problem could be solved by detecting this relational contingency. This is not what
happens. Even when the movement of the attached lure and the other partner are
indistinguishable, recognition still occurs, because both participants are looking for
each other. The findings show that recognition relies on sensorimotor coordination,
rather than on an individuals capacity to express a confident judgement on whether
a stimulus is actually caused by the partner or not. When subjects encounter a
stimulus they tend to oscillate around it and these scanning movements only remain
stable in the case that both subjects are in contact with each other. A subject could be
fooled by the partners attached lure, but only to the point that the partner remains
more or less on the spot (one-way coupling). This situation is unstable as the partner
(unaware that his shadow is being scanned) will eventually move away to continue
the search. Only when the two-way interaction is established (i.e. when both subjects
are in direct contact) does the situation become globally stable. Hence the solution to
the cognitive task is established because both partners are searching for each other,
but it does not rely on individuals performing any kind of perceptual recognition
between responsive and non-responsive objects. They find each other almost
inadvertently. The sense-making that solves the task only happens at the level of the
collective dynamics.
The spectrum of participation in sense-making sketched here covers a very wide
range of possibilities in social encounters, from third person observations of others
behaviours, to development of properly jointly created meanings. By taking the core
enactive ideas seriously and focusing on the dynamics of the interaction process we
have seen how an approach to social understanding can be based on unpacking the
relation between coordination and sense-making along its many possibilities.
Discussion
In this paper we have established a set of ideas that together lay the foundations for a
radical reorientation in approaches to social cognition. Many of these ideas
undoubtedly deserve further elaboration and improvement. In this final section we
limit ourselves to briefly mentioning some implications and directions for
development; they remain speculative at this stage.
A central question arising from this proposal is that of clarifying further the
relations between autonomy, agency, interaction, and intersubjectivity. Since new
domains of sense-making can be opened up through participation, these can affect
the individual and social identity of the interactors. Our dynamical view can provide
a novel theoretical link between the social and individual domains for advancing on
this issue. One possible route for this is developmental. The dynamics of interaction
can span multiple timescales: from coordination patterns in interaction, over single
and recurring interactions, to histories of interaction (relationships). Ontogenetically,
we need to explain how the early embodied, highly affective interactions between
mothers and infants eventually lead all the way up to the capacity for full-blown
adult conversations and the use of symbolic inscriptions with all their intricacies and
502 H. De Jaegher, E. Di Paolo
subtleties (Cowley 2007). Until now, there is no unified account that can encompass
the whole range of social capacities from primary intersubjectivity to the highest
reaches of human language and social cognition. We think there is potential for the
enactive approach presented here to advance on this problem. What this approach
does ensure, in contrast to non-interactive proposals, is an explicit two-way link
between individual and social processes, leaving open the possibility for individual
cognitive skills to have dual or even purely social developmental origins. This is a
strictly closed avenue for approaches that are not properly interactive, be they
embodied or not.
Social skills, under the enactive view, are by definition relational. Although
agents can have different individual potentials for entering into an interaction, this
potential is not fixed and can be modulated by actual interactions. This is an
implication of having established the autonomy of the interactional domain.
Sometimes otherwise socially stilted persons are able to interact very well with
particular others or in certain situations. As we have seen, it is easy but often
misleading to infer individual level cognitive capabilities in order to explain
interactional phenomena. This same lesson applies to social skills. It is easy to make
individuals fully responsible for aspects of a social interaction; to infer competence
from performance. But this misses the part of responsibility that corresponds to the
interaction itself. This simple systemic insight can have implications for approaching
disorders with a social aspect such as autism where individual predispositions
undoubtedly have an effect on social encounters, but less attention has been paid to
the dynamics of the latter for better understanding, diagnosing and treating the
disorder (see De Jaegher 2006).
Relatedly, we implicitly hold the view (but have not argued for it) that other social
aspects of cognition, including those that are third-personal or observational, can be
understood through the interaction either in a direct or derivative sense. Proponents
of embodied alternatives have recognised the importance of this latter point. In
accordance with Gallaghers suggestion in his (2001) paper, and those of other
researchers, we hold that third-person observational social capacities develop on the
back of interpersonal social capacities. Our proposal should help to elaborate on the
implications of this realisation. By now it should be clear that we have turned
the traditional approaches on their head and instead of going from third-personal
situations into the interaction, we take the opposite route. Even outside direct social
interaction, sense-making can be expressive and this is at play in third-personal
social aspects of cognition. To complement this, an observer of a social
phenomenon, even though he can indeed be a passive bystander as it were, is qua
sense-maker always in some way, even if minimally, engaged with the other whose
behaviour he is observing.
The enactive perspective, therefore, questions the traditional axiom that others are
non-transparent to us. We have demonstrated how the sense-making that underlies
social understanding can itself be coordinated and extended in interaction. But how
is the other experienced according to this view? We have seen the example of the
squeezing of a sponge as a now almost paradigmatic instance of enactive perception.
Unlike a sponge, the other-in-interaction is not fully and lawfully constituted by my
sense-making activity. The sponge becomes an object in itself when confronted by
my sense-making. It is experienced as complete as far as my practical interests are
Participatory sense-making 503
concerned. By contrast, from a purely individual perspective, the other-in-interaction
is available to me in this way only partially. Her autonomy demands frequent re-
adjustments of my individual sense-making. When interaction and individual
intentions coordinate, we feel mutually skilful to navigate the interaction: we
experience a kind of transparency of the other-in-interaction. But when, for a variety
of reasons, a breakdown occurs, and until a new coordination is attained, we
experience the other as opaque. Keeping the interactorsautonomy as an essential
requirement of the social achieves in this way a correspondence with the
phenomenological insight of the alterity of the other (e.g. Zahavi 2005). We dont
experience the other-in-interaction as totally obscure and inaccessible, nor as fully
transparent (like an object fully constituted by my sense-making activity), but as
something else: a protean pattern with knowable and unknowable surfaces and
angles of familiarity that shapeshift as the interaction unfolds. Those patterns of
change are influenced by my own participation in the emergence and breakdown of
joint relational sense-making, hence they are not totally alien. My actions contribute
to define the other-in-interaction not so much as my squeezing contributes to the
experience of softness of the sponge but rather in ways that do not necessarily settle
into a lawful relationship. I must alter my actions contextually in order to re-
encounter the other and in the process, sometimes, be encountered myself when her
sense-making unexpectedly modulates my own. This recursive effect on my actions
describes the co-modulation of self-in-interaction and other-in-interaction. Others
have pointed to the co-determination of self and other (Thompson 2001; Thompson
and Varela 2001). We concord, but choose to call this mutual modulation instead so
as not to imply a self-sufficiency of the social domain that obscures the interplay
between the autonomy of the interaction process and that of the interactors.
Our approach also has practical implications. It reinforces certain styles of
studying social cognition from the interaction (e.g. conversation analysis), but
looking at coordination dynamics in its many guises (not just linguistic). For this,
experimental approaches that minimalise and control sensorimotor coupling (such as
the perceptual crossing studies of Auvray et al. 2006) are likely to yield the most
interesting results in support of the ideas presented here. Combined dynamical
systems and robotics modelling and novel measures of interaction (Di Paolo, Rohde
and Iizuka 2007) have already shown their value at complementing such empirical
studies. The measurement of coordination is an enormously important issue, where
inspiration could be taken from movement analysis and neuroscience. Measuring
coordination however, needs to be complemented by a disciplined approach to the
experience of interaction, including experiences such as connectedness. Our enactive
proposal favours an approach that combines empirical research in psychology and
social science with dynamical and synthetic modelling and phenomenology.
Conclusions
The task of elaborating a strong and coherent enactive theory of social cognition can
only be sketched in this paper. We believe that the enactive approach can say very
specific things about social cognition. It can do so by two non-traditional starting
moves: first, by providing the tools that allow us to recognise the interaction process
504 H. De Jaegher, E. Di Paolo
as establishing an autonomous domain, and second, by defining cognitive
engagement as the activity of sense-making. The interplay between these initial
moves is what we have attempted to develop here. It is, however, only an initial
analysis and much further work will be needed.
By positing the process of interaction as an emergent autonomous domain, our
enactive proposal, paradoxically, devolves an autonomy to social agents that was
never thematised by previous approaches to social cognition: that of participation.
Acknowledgements We would like to thank Stephen Cowley, Marek McGann and Steve Torrance for
their very helpful comments on this paper.
References
Auvray, M., Lenay, C., & Stewart, J. (2006). The attribution of intentionality in a simulated environment:
The case of minimalist devices. In Tenth Meeting of the Association for the Scientific Study of
Consciousness. Oxford, UK.
Boden, M. (2006). Of islands and interactions. Journal of Consciousness Studies,13,5363.
Bourdieu, P. (1990). The logic of practice. Cambridge: Polity.
Buck, J., & Buck, E. (1976). Synchronous fireflies. Scientific American, 234,7485 (May).
Colombetti, G. (2007). Enactive appraisal. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, (This issue).
Condon, W. S., & Ogston, W. D. (1971). Speech and body motion synchrony of the speakerhearer. In D.
L. Horton, & J. J. Jenkins (Eds.) The perception of language. Columbus, Ohio: Charles E. Merril
Publishing Co.
Cook, J. E. (1991). Correlated activity in the CNS: A role on every timescale? Trends in Neurosciences,
14, 397401.
Cowley, S. (2007). How human infants deal with symbol grounding. Interaction Studies,8,81104.
Currie, G. (2007). Narrative frameworks. In D. D. Hutto (Ed.) Narrative and understanding persons:
Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 60 (pp. 1742). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
De Jaegher, H. (2006). Social interaction rhythm and participatory sense-making: An embodied,
interactional approach to social understanding, with implications for autism, D.Phil. Thesis. In
University of Sussex, Brighton, UK.
de Vignemont, F., & Singer, T. (2006). The empathic brain: How, when and why? Trends in Cognitive
Sciences,10, 435441.
Di Paolo, E. A. (2005). Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive
Sciences,4,97125.
Di Paolo, E. A., Rohde, M., & De Jaegher, H. (2007). Horizons for the enactive mind: Values, social
interaction, and play. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. Di Paolo, (Eds.), Enaction: towards a new
paradigm for cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Di Paolo, E. A., Rohde, M., & Iizuka, H. (2007). Sensitivity to social contingency or stability of
interaction? Modelling the dynamics of perceptual crossing. New Ideas in Psychology.
Fogel, A. (1993). Developing through relationships: Origins of communication, self and culture. London:
Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Gallagher, S. (1997). Mutual enlightenment: Recent phenomenology and cognitive science. Journal of
Consciousness Studies,4, 195214.
Gallagher, S. (2001). The practice of mind: Theory, simulation or primary interaction? Journal of
Consciousness Studies,8,83108.
Gallagher, S. (2004). Understanding interpersonal problems in autism: Interaction Theory as an alternative
to Theory of Mind. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology,11, 199217.
Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gallagher, S. (2007). Logical and phenomenological arguments against simulation theory. In D. D. Hutto
& M. Ratcliffe (Eds.), Minding our practice: Folk psychology re-assessed. Springer.
Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., et al. (1996). Action recognition in the premotor cortex. Brain,119 ,
593609.
Participatory sense-making 505
Georgieff, N., & Jeannerod, M. (1998). Beyond consciousness of external events: A whosystem for
consciousness of action and self-consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition,7, 465477.
Gill, S. P., Kawamori, M., Katagiri, Y., et al. (2000). Role of Body Moves in dialogue. International
Journal of Language and Communication,12, 89114.
Goffman, E. (1972). Interaction ritual: Essays on face-to-face behavior. London: Allen Lane.
Goffman, E. (1983). The interaction order. American Sociological Review,48,117.
Granic, I. (2000). The self-organization of parent-child relations: Beyond bidirectional models. In M. D.
Lewis, & I. Granic (Eds.) Emotion, development, and self-organization. Dynamic systems approaches
to emotional development (pp. 267297). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Haken, H., & Köpchen, H. P. (1991). Rhythms in physiological systems. Berlin: Springer.
Hobson, R. P. (2002). The cradle of thought. London: Macmillan.
Hutto, D. D. (2004). The limits of spectatorial folk psychology. Mind and Language,19, 548573.
Hutto, D. D. (2007). The narrative practice hypothesis: Origins and applications of Folk Psychology. In D.
D. Hutto (Ed.), Narrative and understanding persons. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement:
Cambridge University Press.
Jaffe, J., Beebe, B., & Feldstein, S., et al. (2001). Rhythms of dialogue in infancy: Coordinated timing in
development. Oxford: Blackwell.
Jaffe, J., & Feldstein, S. (1970). Rhythms of dialogue. London: Academic.
Jonas, H. (1966). The phenomenon of life. Toward a philosophical biology. Evanston, IL: Northwestern
University Press.
Kelso, J. A. S. (1995). Dynamic patterns: The self-organization of brain and behaviour. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Kendon, A. (1990). Conducting interaction: patterns of behavior in focused encounters. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Klin, A., Jones, W., Schultz, R., et al. (2003). The enactive mind, or from actions to cognition: Lessons
from autism. Philosophical Transactions of The Royal Society London B,358, 345360.
Kuramoto, Y. (1984). Chemical oscillations, waves and turbulence. Berlin: Springer.
Moran, G., Fentress, J. C., & Golani, I. (1981). A description of relational patterns of movement during
ritualized fightingin wolves. Animal Behavior,29, 11461165.
Moreno, A., & Etxeberria, A. (2005). Agency in natural and artificial systems. Artificial Life,11, 161176.
Murray, L., & Trevarthen, C. (1985). Emotional regulation of interactions between 2-month-olds and their
mothers. In T. M. Field, & N. A. Fox (Eds.) Social perception in infants (pp. 177197). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Myin, E. (2003). An account of color without a subject? Behavioral and Brain Sciences,26,4243.
Pickering, M. J., & Garrod, S. (2004). Toward a mechanistic psychology of dialogue. Behavioral and
Brain Sciences,27,169190.
Port, R. F., & van Gelder, T. (Eds.) (1995). Mind as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cognition.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Quinn, M. (2001). Evolving communication without dedicated communication channels. In Advances in
artificial life: Sixth European Conference on Artificial Life (ECAL 2001). Prague: Springer pp. 357366.
Ratcliffe, M. (2007). Rethinking commonsense psychology: A critique of folk psychology, theory of mind
and simulation. Hampshire/New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Ruhleder, K., & Jordan, B. (2001). Co-constructing non-mutual realities: Delay-generated trouble in
distributed interaction. Journal of Computer Supported Cooperative Work,10,113138.
Sacks, H. (1992). Lectures on conversation volumes I and II. Oxford: Blackwell.
Sacks, H., Schegloff, E. A., & Jefferson, G. (1974). A simplest systematics for the organization of turn-
taking for conversation. Language,50, 696735.
Schiffrin, D. (1994). Approaches to discourse. Oxford: Blackwell.
Schmidt, R. C., & O'Brien, B. (1997). Evaluating the dynamics of unintended interpersonal coordination.
Ecological Psychology,9, 189206.
Shanker, S., & King, B. J. (2002). The emergence of a new paradigm in ape language research. Behavioral
and Brain Sciences,25, 605656.
Sheets-Johnstone, M. (1999). Emotion and movement: A beginning empirical-phenomenological analysis
of their relationship. Journal of Consciousness Studies,6, 259277.
Stern, D. (2002/1977). The first relationship: Infant and mother. London: Harvard University Press.
Thompson, E. (2001). Empathy and consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies,8,132.
Thompson, E. (2005). Sensorimotor subjectivity and the enactive approach to experience. Phenomenology
and the Cognitive Sciences,4, 407427.
Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Harvard University
Press.
506 H. De Jaegher, E. Di Paolo
Thompson, E., & Varela, F. J. (2001). Radical embodiment: Neural dynamics and consciousness. Trends in
Cognitive Sciences,5, 418425.
Thorpe, W. H. (1972). Duetting and antiphonal song in birds: Its extent and significance. Leiden: E. J. Brill.
Torrance, S. (2005). In search of the enactive: Introduction to special issue on enactive experience.
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences,4, 357368.
Trevarthen, C. (1979). Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description of primary
intersubjectivity. In M. Bullowa (Ed.) Before speech (pp. 321347). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Tronick, E. (2005). Why is connection with others so critical? The formation of dyadic states of
consciousness and the expansion of individualsstates of consciousness: Coherence governed
selection and the co-creation of meaning out of messy meaning making. In J. Nadel, & D. Muir (Eds.)
Emotional development (pp. 293316). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tronick, E. Z., Als, H., & Adamson, L. (1979). Structure of early face-to-face communicative interactions.
In M. Bullowa (Ed.) Before speech (pp. 349370). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
van Gelder, T. (1999). Wooden iron? Husserlian phenomenology meets cognitive science. In J. Petitot, F.
J. Varela, B. Pachoud, & J.-M. Roy (Eds.) Naturalizing phenomenology (pp. 245265). Stanford, CA:
Stanford University Press.
Varela, F. J. (1979). Principles of biological autonomy. New York: Elsevier (North Holland).
Varela, F. J. (1991). Organism: A meshwork of selfless selves. In A. Tauber (Ed.) Organism and the origin
of self pp. 79107. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Varela, F. J. (1996). Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy for the hard problem. Journal of
Consciousness Studies,3, 330349.
Varela, F. J. (1997). Patterns of life: Intertwining identity and cognition. Brain and Cognition,34,7287.
Varela, F. J. (1999). The specious present: A neurophenomenology of time consciousness. In J. Petitot, F.
J. Varela, B. Pachoud, & J.-M. Roy (Eds.) Naturalizing phenomenology (pp. 266314). Stanford, CA:
Stanford University Press.
Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human
experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Weber, A., & Varela, F. J. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of
biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences,1,97125.
Winfree, A. T. (2001). The geometry of biological time. London: Springer.
Zahavi, D. (2005). Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Participatory sense-making 507
... For example, objects such as hula hoops and ropes (see 4.5) have been observed to facilitate physical connections, encouraging participants to move together and engage in dynamic interactions. This aligns with the concept of social affordances [18,49], where physical prompts support interaction and collaboration [14], and reflects prior studies such as Yao et al.'s [97] exploration of motion-sensing ropes for collaborative play. Exploring how tactile artefacts, combined with features such as force feedback, can support dynamic and expressive movement practices is an interesting direction for future work. ...
Preprint
Full-text available
Dance teachers rely primarily on verbal instructions and visual demonstrations to convey key dance concepts and movement. These techniques, however, have limitations in supporting students who are blind or have low vision (BLV). This work explores the role technology can play in supporting instruction for BLV students, as well as improvisation with their instructor. Through a series of design workshops with dance instructors and BLV students, ideas were generated by physically engaging with probes featuring diverse modalities including tactile objects, a body tracked sound and musical probe, and a body tracked controller with vibrational feedback. Implications for the design of supporting technologies were discovered for four contemporary dance learning goals: learning a phrase; improvising; collaborating through movement; and awareness of body and movement qualities. We discuss the potential of numerous multi-sensory methods and artefacts, and present design considerations for technologies to support meaningful dance instruction and participation.
... Several strategies were employed to ensure the trustworthiness of this research. To aid 'sense-making' [31] of emergent findings, FY (lead analyst) sought continual feedback from GP researchers in the team and regular in-person visits to the university's GP academic unit. This included presentation of preliminary findings (FY, MM) for feedback across four workshops / seminars with non-project attendees. ...
Article
Full-text available
Background Ensuring sufficient supply of general practitioners (GPs) is critical for servicing increasing healthcare demands. Heightened by pandemic conditions, chronic shortages of GPs persist globally. Whilst many factors reinforcing general practice specialty choices are known, system-level understanding of GP career decision-making influences across medical training requires investigation. Aim To explore specialty choice rationales through career selection narratives of recently registered Australian GPs, using a system-level perspective. Design & setting Semi-structured interviews were selected for in-depth explorations of GP specialty choice rationale. Within Australia, medical specialty training choices are typically made after both university medical education and mandatory one-to-two year prevocational (hospital-based) training is completed. Method Interviews were conducted online with GPs who had completed all training in the last 10 years. De-identified and verified transcripts underwent participant checking. Deductive framework analysis using career counselling constructs, and inductive thematic analysis were performed. Results There were 25 participants. Career counselling constructs provided system-level understanding of GP specialty decision-making processes. Large gaps in GP career information were highlighted throughout medical training for many participants. Overcoming negative medical narratives about general practice was necessary for most in choosing a GP career. However, positive experiences with GP communities or work created insights into the broad flexibility of GP person-specialty fit. Conclusion GP work experiences and personal GP connections could counteract prominent negative narratives about GP careers. However, lack of systemic and regular exposure to GPs throughout medical training is a critical barrier that should be addressed through sustained policy and professional interventions.
Article
Full-text available
In this proposal, we present the folkloric performance of the Egetmann Pageant in Tramin as what we call a dynamic imaginative niche.We outline a notion of monstrous figures as “forms of trust” (cf. Ingold 2013). We suggest that the participatory enactment of such figures scaffolds material and interpersonal affective niches (Colombetti and Krueger 2015) for coping with future threats. We will develop a methodology of drawings and analysis in which we situated the monstrous figure, the Schnappviecher, in the context of both contemporary agro-pastoral communities in northern Italy and the 1940s under the influence of Himmler’s National Socialist cultural program. As we will illustrate, the enactment of “monstrous figures” in different historical situations can come to scaffold radically different feelings of belonging and shape who is included or excluded from a community. We will argue how interpersonal dynamics, of at first sight similar “socio-material niches” can either become an affirmation of rigid “bad moral habits” (Dewey 1916) or can scaffold communal exploration of new ways of relating to future threats, by affording moments of surprise in the participatory enactment of the monster.
Article
In the sense of the Sustainable Development Goals (SDGs), global efforts to create a sustainable society will not be sufficiently successful under the current geopolitical and socio‐economic trends. For this reason, recent sustainability research has increasingly focused on systemic coherence, the subject of cognition, and psychological and epistemological aspects. With regard to the sustainability discourse, this article proposes a perspective based on systems theory's findings in its enactivist interpretation. It understands this as a joint process of sense‐making that must be actively maintained on an ongoing basis. Scientific knowledge and human experience are not described as mutually exclusive and informing spheres but as part of the world of experience actively spanned by the organism in its self‐execution, which inherently involves ambiguities and complexity reductions that leave the subject and object undetermined. Such an understanding of systemic thinking should help to prevent the process of sustainable development itself from being called into question when some goals are inevitably missed.
Article
Full-text available
This article aims to broaden the theoretical perspective of historical criminology in a twofold way: 1) it introduces Martin Heidegger's notions of temporality and historicity to further clarify how the unity of future, past, and present structures our everyday lives; 2) and relatedly, drawing on phenomenological approaches to embodiment, it outlines how culture and tradition are passed down over generations by means of collective body memories. To demonstrate how this plays out in practice, the article uses examples of the colonial past influencing contemporary social policy. It explains how violence stemming from the colonial period, in general, may live on and continue to shape encounters between police and marginalised communities, and how that maintains the boundaries between in-and out-groups.
Article
Full-text available
In the decade and a half since the appearance of Varela, Thompson and Rosch's workThe Embodied Mind,enactivism has helped to put experience and consciousness, conceived of in a distinctive way, at the forefront of cognitive science. There are at least two major strands within the enactive perspective: a broad view of what it is to be an agent with a mind; and a more focused account of the nature of perception and perceptual experience. The relation between these two strands is discussed, with an overview of the papers presented in this volume.
Chapter
The human world is replete with narratives - narratives of our making that are uniquely appreciated by us. Some thinkers have afforded special importance to our capacity to generate such narratives, seeing it as variously enabling us to: exercise our imaginations in unique ways; engender an understanding of actions performed for reasons; and provide a basis for the kind of reflection and evaluation that matters vitally to moral and self development. Perhaps most radically, some hold that narratives are essential for the constitution of human selves. This volume brings together nine original contributions in which the individual authors advance, develop and challenge proposals of these kinds. They critically examine the place and importance of narratives in human lives and consider the underlying capacities that permit us to produce and utilise these special artifacts. All of the papers are written in a non-technical and accessible style.
Chapter
The human world is replete with narratives - narratives of our making that are uniquely appreciated by us. Some thinkers have afforded special importance to our capacity to generate such narratives, seeing it as variously enabling us to: exercise our imaginations in unique ways; engender an understanding of actions performed for reasons; and provide a basis for the kind of reflection and evaluation that matters vitally to moral and self development. Perhaps most radically, some hold that narratives are essential for the constitution of human selves. This volume brings together nine original contributions in which the individual authors advance, develop and challenge proposals of these kinds. They critically examine the place and importance of narratives in human lives and consider the underlying capacities that permit us to produce and utilise these special artifacts. All of the papers are written in a non-technical and accessible style.
Article
Psychologically normal adult humans make sense of intentional actions by trying to decide for which reason they were performed. This is a datum that requires our understanding. Although there have been interesting recent debates about how we should understand ‘reasons’, I will follow a long tradition and assume that, at a bare minimum, to act for a reason involves having appropriately interrelated beliefs and desires.
Book
What is a self? Does it exist in reality or is it a mere social construct—or is it perhaps a neurologically induced illusion? The legitimacy of the concept of the self has been questioned by both neuroscientists and philosophers in recent years. Countering this, in Subjectivity and Selfhood, Dan Zahavi argues that the notion of self is crucial for a proper understanding of consciousness. He investigates the interrelationships of experience, self-awareness, and selfhood, proposing that none of these three notions can be understood in isolation. Any investigation of the self, Zahavi argues, must take the first-person perspective seriously and focus on the experiential givenness of the self. Subjectivity and Selfhood explores a number of phenomenological analyses pertaining to the nature of consciousness, self, and self-experience in light of contemporary discussions in consciousness research. Philosophical phenomenology—as developed by Husserl, Heidegger, Sartre, Merleau-Ponty, and others—not only addresses crucial issues often absent from current debates over consciousness but also provides a conceptual framework for understanding subjectivity. Zahavi fills the need—given the recent upsurge in theoretical and empirical interest in subjectivity—for an account of the subjective or phenomenal dimension of consciousness that is accessible to researchers and students from a variety of disciplines. His aim is to use phenomenological analyses to clarify issues of central importance to philosophy of mind, cognitive science, developmental psychology, and psychiatry. By engaging in a dialogue with other philosophical and empirical positions, says Zahavi, phenomenology can demonstrate its vitality and contemporary relevance. Bradford Books imprint
Book
1980 Preface * 1999 Preface * 1999 Acknowledgements * Introduction * 1 Circular Logic * 2 Phase Singularities (Screwy Results of Circular Logic) * 3 The Rules of the Ring * 4 Ring Populations * 5 Getting Off the Ring * 6 Attracting Cycles and Isochrons * 7 Measuring the Trajectories of a Circadian Clock * 8 Populations of Attractor Cycle Oscillators * 9 Excitable Kinetics and Excitable Media * 10 The Varieties of Phaseless Experience: In Which the Geometrical Orderliness of Rhythmic Organization Breaks Down in Diverse Ways * 11 The Firefly Machine 12 Energy Metabolism in Cells * 13 The Malonic Acid Reagent ('Sodium Geometrate') * 14 Electrical Rhythmicity and Excitability in Cell Membranes * 15 The Aggregation of Slime Mold Amoebae * 16 Numerical Organizing Centers * 17 Electrical Singular Filaments in the Heart Wall * 18 Pattern Formation in the Fungi * 19 Circadian Rhythms in General * 20 The Circadian Clocks of Insect Eclosion * 21 The Flower of Kalanchoe * 22 The Cell Mitotic Cycle * 23 The Female Cycle * References * Index of Names * Index of Subjects