ArticlePublisher preview available

Extensional Versus Intuitive Reasoning: The Conjunction Fallacy in Probability Judgment

Psychological Review
Authors:
To read the full-text of this research, you can request a copy directly from the authors.

Abstract

Perhaps the simplest and the most basic qualitative law of probability is the conjunction rule: The probability of a conjunction, P(A&B), cannot exceed the probabilities of its constituents, P(A) and P(B), because the extension (or the possibility set) of the conjunction is included in the extension of its constituents. Judgments under uncertainty, however, are often mediated by intuitive heuristics that are not bound by the conjunction rule. A conjunction can be more representative that one of its constituents, and instances of a specific category can be easier to imagine or to retrieve than instances of a more inclusive category. The representativeness and availability heuristics therefore can make a conjunction appear more probable than one of its constituents. This phenomenon is demonstrated in a variety of contexts, including estimation of word frequency, personality judgment, medical prognosis, decision under risk, suspicion of criminal acts, and political forecasting. Systematic violations of the conjunction rule are observed in judgments of lay people and of experts in both between- and within-Ss comparisons. Alternative interpretations of the conjunction fallacy are discussed, and attempts to combat it are explored. (48 ref) (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2012 APA, all rights reserved)
Psychological Review
VOLUME
90
NUMBER
4
OCTOBER 1983
Extensional Versus Intuitive Reasoning:
The
Conjunction Fallacy
in
Probability Judgment
Amos Tversky Daniel
Kahneman
Stanford University University
of
British
Columbia,
Vancouver,
British
Columbia,
Canada
Perhaps
the
simplest
and the
most
basic
qualitative
law of
probability
is the
con-
junction
rule:
The
probability
of a
conjunction,
P(A&B),
cannot
exceed
the
prob-
abilities
of its
constituents,
P(A)
and
.P(B),
because
the
extension
(or the
possibility
set)
of the
conjunction
is
included
in the
extension
of its
constituents.
Judgments
under
uncertainty,
however,
are
often
mediated
by
intuitive
heuristics
that
are not
bound
by the
conjunction
rule.
A
conjunction
can be
more
representative
than
one
of its
constituents,
and
instances
of a
specific
category
can be
easier
to
imagine
or to
retrieve
than
instances
of a
more
inclusive
category.
The
representativeness
and
availability
heuristics
therefore
can
make
a
conjunction
appear
more
probable
than
one of its
constituents.
This
phenomenon
is
demonstrated
in a
variety
of
contexts
including
estimation
of
word frequency,
personality
judgment,
medical
prognosis,
decision
under risk,
suspicion
of
criminal
acts,
and
political forecasting.
Systematic
violations
of the
conjunction rule
are
observed
in
judgments
of lay
people
and of
experts
in
both
between-subjects
and
within-subjects
comparisons.
Alternative interpretations
of the
conjunction fallacy
are
discussed
and
attempts
to
combat
it are
explored.
Uncertainty
is an
unavoidable aspect
of the the
last decade (see, e.g., Einhorn
&
Hogarth,
human
condition. Many significant choices 1981; Kahneman, Slovic,
&
Tversky, 1982;
must
be
based
on
beliefs
about
the
likelihood Nisbett
&
Ross, 1980). Much
of
this research
of
such uncertain events
as the
guilt
of a de- has
compared intuitive inferences
and
prob-
fendant,
the
result
of an
election,
the
future
ability judgments
to the
rules
of
statistics
and
value
of the
dollar,
the
outcome
of a
medical
the
laws
of-probability.
The
student
of
judg-
operation,
or the
response
of a
friend.
Because ment uses
the
probability calculus
as a
stan-
we
normally
do not
have adequate
formal
dard
of
comparison much
as a
student
of
per-
models
for
computing
the
probabilities
of
such ception might compare
the
perceived sizes
of
events,
intuitive judgment
is
often
the
only objects
to
their physical sizes. Unlike
the
cor-
practical
method
for
assessing uncertainty. rect size
of
objects, however,
the
"correct"
The
question
of how lay
people
and
experts probability
of
events
is not
easily
defined.
Be-
evaluate
the
probabilities
of
uncertain events cause individuals
who
have
different
knowl-
has
attracted considerable research interest
in
edge
or who
hold
different
beliefs must
be
al-
lowed
to
assign
different
probabilities
to the
This
research
was
supported
by
Grant
NR197-058
from
same
event>
no
sing!e
value
can
be
correct
for
the
U.S.
Office
of
Naval
Research.
We
are
grateful
to
friends
all
people.
Furthermore,
a
correct
probability
and
colleagues,
too
numerous
to
list
by
name,
for
their
cannot always
be
determined even
for a
single
useful
comments
and
suggestions
on an
earlier
draft
of
person
Outside
the
domain
of
random
sam-
'Xuets
for
reprints
should
be
sent
to
Amos
Tversky,
PlinS>
Probability theory does
not
determine
Department
of
Psychology,
Jordan Hall, Building
420,
the
probabilities
of
uncertain
events—it
merely
Stanford
University, Stanford, California 94305.
imposes constraints
on the
relations among
Copyright 1983
by the
American Psychological Association, Inc.
293
... loss-framed appeals on individuals' engagement in health interventions. In addition, we identified a fourth factor, which emerged only in the second period of analysis, consisting of the seminal articles by Tversky and Kahneman, [5,[17][18][19][20] suggesting a resurgence of interest in the origins of framing effects and prospect theory in current times. ...
... [5] The authors further state that "the structure adopted by a decision maker is controlled in part by the formulation of the problem and in part by the norms, habits, and personal characteristics of the decision maker" (p.453). [5] In their 1983 work, [17] the authors criticize one of the laws of probability, the rule of conjunction (see more in Dempster and Suppes), [119,120] which became known as the "fallacy of the conjunction". The authors claim that the representativeness and availability of heuristics can make a conjunction of events seem more likely to happen than one of its constituent events, demonstrated in various contexts, including word frequency estimation, personality judgment, medical prognosis, decision under risk, suspicion of criminal acts, and political foresight. ...
... Liu and Azzopardi (2024) explored user interactions with search interfaces, focusing on biases and heuristics that influence the search process. Their tutorial discussed cognitive biases and heuristics, as proposed by Tversky and Kahneman (1983), and their implications for search decisions in contexts such as health and finance. The authors aim to enhance the design and evaluation of information retrieval systems by accounting for these cognitive factors. ...
Article
This paper examines the evolution and future directions of Information Foraging Theory (IFT) research over the past 32 years (1992–2023). The findings reveal a sustained interest in IFT, with an average of 14 publications per year, culminating in a total of 449 papers authored by 933 researchers. Key contributors such as Peter Pirolli and Margaret Burnett have significantly shaped the field. Initially rooted in cognitive psychology and human-computer interaction (HCI), IFT has since expanded its influence to domains including information science, organizational behaviour, and machine learning. Core concepts of IFT, such as information scent and information patches, have been empirically validated, reinforcing their importance in understanding user behaviour. Publication trends highlight a peak in research activity around 2012, followed by fluctuations and a recent resurgence. The prominence of conference papers reflects the dynamic and rapidly evolving nature of the field. Keyword analysis identifies research clusters focusing on human decision-making, user interfaces, information retrieval, visualization, social networking, and behavioural studies, demonstrating the interdisciplinary application of IFT. Emerging themes such as cognitive load, uncertainty, virtual reality, and big data point to promising new research directions. This overview underscores IFT's significant contributions and ongoing relevance in understanding of human information-seeking behaviour and optimizing systems to meet user needs.
... Mercier and Sperber argue that the experiments used to justify rationality-pessimistic positions are not ones in which participants are in a "typical dialogical context" (Mercier and Sperber 2017, 227). In contrast, experiments that place participants in dialogical contexts demonstrate that 17 For example, Tversky and Kahneman (1983) conducted research showing that human reasoners predictably fall prey to the conjunction fallacy (i.e., fallaciously believing that there is a greater probability of "A and B" than there is of just "A" or "B"). Moreover, research suggests that human reasoners fail at alarming rates to abide by logical rules governing conditionals (Mercier and Sperber 2017, 28;Byrne 1989;Evans 1989). ...
Article
Full-text available
This paper argues that we are not just social epistemic creatures because we operate in social contexts. We are social epistemic creatures because of the nature of our epistemic cognitive capacities. In The Enigma of Reason , Hugo Mercier and Dan Sperber develop and defend the view that reasoning is a social competence that yields epistemic benefits for individuals through social interaction with others. I argue an epistemological consequence of their position is that, when beliefs are formed and sustained by dialogical deliberation, the relevant justification-conferring process doesn’t occur solely within the cognition of the subject whose belief is under evaluation. Rather, it extends to include her interactive engagement with other deliberative participants. I argue this demonstrates that not all justification-conferring is evidential. As such, the analysis not only supports reconceiving the process reliabilist’s notion of justification-conferring processes; it also serves as an argument against evidentialism. A goal of this paper is to demonstrate that social epistemology isn’t merely a siloed offshoot of traditional epistemology. Even when approaching social epistemology using a conservative methodology, our investigation has serious implications for fundamental questions concerning epistemic normativity.
Article
Full-text available
The effect of simultaneously performing two tasks (dual-task effects, DTEs) has been extensively studied, mainly focusing on the combination of cognitive and motor tasks. Given their potentially detrimental impact on real-life activities, the impact of DTEs has been investigated in both healthy individuals and patients. In this Registered Report, we aimed to replicate previous DTEs when a task requiring executive-inhibitory skills is involved while also expanding the evidence on basic facets of decision-making. We recruited 50 healthy young participants who performed a stop-signal task and two gambling tasks (loss-aversion and risk-aversion) while sitting and while walking at three treadmill speeds (normal, slow and fast). We report a significant difference in performance during single-task and dual-task, although with high individual variability. The data show no effect of the walking speed on all the cognitive tasks. Analyses on postural alignments, assessed in the cadence, gait cycle length and stance phase, confirm previous results on cognitive prioritization strategies of healthy individuals. Based on our results, we highlight the need to further investigate prioritization strategies when tasks involving higher cognitive functions are performed along a motor task in healthy individuals and patients with the aim of offering targeted training and rehabilitation protocols. The stage 1 protocol for this Registered Report was accepted in principle on 28/06/22. The protocol, as accepted by the journal, can be found at: https://doi.org/10.17605/OSF.IO/5MWH7.
Chapter
Eine lange Tradition der Experimentalforschung in Ökonomie und Psychologie vertritt die einflussreiche Auffassung, dass menschliches Denken nicht mit den Regeln rationalen Denkens vereinbar wäre (Tversky und Kahneman, Science 185:1124–1131, 1974). Diese Forschungsarbeiten zu Heuristiken und Biases stellen das menschliche Urteilen und Entscheiden als systematisch fehleranfällig dar; geprägt durch mentale Abkürzungen („Heuristiken“) und einem in vielerlei Hinsicht verzerrten Verständnis fundamentaler Regeln der Wahrscheinlichkeitstheorie und Statistik.
Article
How should we identify interesting topics in cognitive science? This paper suggests that one useful research strategy is to hunt for, and attempt to resolve, paradoxes: that is, apparent or real contradictions in our understanding of the mind and of thought. The rationale for this strategy is the assumption that our current thinking, and our various partial theories, of any topic are typically ill‐defined, inconsistent or both. Thus, contradictions and confusions abound. Isolating paradoxes helps us expose vagueness and contradictions and demands that we formulate our ideas more precisely. From this point of view, finding a robust and puzzling contradiction in our current thinking should be celebrated as an achievement in itself. Ideally, of course, we then make further progress by clarifying how the paradox may be resolved, by clarifying our theories or finding new data that may decide between inconsistent assumptions. This approach is illustrated through examples from the author's research over several decades, which seems in retrospect to involve a repeated, if largely unwitting, application of this strategy.
Article
Full-text available
Further N-Frame networking dynamics of conscious observer-self agents via a functional contextual interface: predictive coding, double-slit quantum mechanical experiment, and decision-making fallacy modeling as applied to the measurement problem in humans and AI. Artificial intelligence (AI) has made some remarkable advances in recent years, particularly within the area of large language models (LLMs) that produce human-like conversational abilities via utilizing transformer-based architecture. These advancements have sparked growing calls to develop tests not only for intelligence but also for consciousness. However, existing benchmarks assess reasoning abilities across various domains but fail to directly address consciousness. To bridge this gap, this paper introduces the functional contextual N-Frame model, a novel framework integrating predictive coding, quantum Bayesian (QBism), and evolutionary dynamics. This comprehensive model explicates how conscious observers, whether human or artificial, should update beliefs and interact within a quantum cognitive system. It provides a dynamic account of belief evolution through the interplay of internal observer states and external stimuli. By modeling decision-making fallacies such as the conjunction fallacy and conscious intent collapse experiments within this quantum probabilistic framework, the N-Frame model establishes structural and functional equivalence between cognitive processes identified within these experiments and traditional quantum mechanics (QM). It is hypothesized that consciousness serves as an active participant in wavefunction collapse (or actualization of the physical definite states we see), bridging quantum potentiality and classical outcomes via internal observer states and contextual interactions via a self-referential loop. This framework formalizes decision-making processes within a Hilbert space, mapping cognitive states to quantum operators and contextual dependencies, and demonstrates structural and functional equivalence between Frontiers in Computational Neuroscience 01 frontiersin.org Edwards 10.3389/fncom.2025.1551960 cognitive and quantum systems in order to address the measurement problem. Furthermore, the model extends to testable predictions about AI consciousness by specifying informational boundaries, contextual parameters, and a conscious-time dimension derived from Anti-de Sitter/Conformal Field Theory correspondence (AdS/CFT). This paper theorizes that human cognitive biases reflect adaptive, evolutionarily stable strategies that optimize predictive accuracy (i.e., evolved quantum heuristic strategies rather than errors relative to classical rationality) under uncertainty within a quantum framework, challenging the classical interpretation of irrationality. The N-Frame model offers a unified account of consciousness, decision-making, behavior, and quantum mechanics, incorporating the idea of finding truth without proof (thus overcoming Gödelian uncertainty), insights from quantum probability theory (such as the Linda cognitive bias findings), and the possibility that consciousness can cause waveform collapse (or perturbation) accounting for the measurement problem. It proposes a process for conscious time and branching worldlines to explain subjective experiences of time flow and conscious free will. These theoretical advancements provide a foundation for interdisciplinary exploration into consciousness, cognition, and quantum systems, offering a path toward developing tests for AI consciousness and addressing the limitations of classical computation in representing conscious agency.
Article
Purpose This study aims to examine the micro-foundations of dynamic capabilities in the Irish retail banking sector, focusing on strategic alignment, leadership and organisational structure. It investigates how banks navigate regulatory constraints while sustaining competitiveness in a rapidly evolving financial landscape. Using Institution Omicron as a case study, the research identifies structural rigidities, risk-averse leadership and resource gaps that hinder dynamic capability development. To address these challenges, the study introduces two novel frameworks: the Capability Development Framework, which aligns strategic goals with regulatory compliance, and the Capability Implementation Framework, which ensures structured execution and continuous adaptation. Design/methodology/approach This qualitative case study integrates 14 semi-structured interviews with senior banking executives and financial data analysis to explore the operation of dynamic capabilities within a regulated financial institution. Thematic analysis identifies key constraints, including strategic misalignment, conservative decision-making and digital skills shortages. Findings The study reveals that regulatory constraints reinforce organisational inertia, limiting banks’ ability to reconfigure resources and enhance adaptability. While dynamic capabilities are often linked to agility, this research demonstrates that in compliance-driven sectors, they require structured adaptation rather than unrestricted flexibility. Practical implications The proposed frameworks offer actionable insights for financial institutions and other regulated industries, such as healthcare and telecommunications, to enhance strategic adaptability while ensuring compliance. Key recommendations include fostering leadership agility, embedding cross-functional collaboration and developing internal expertise in digital innovation. Originality/value This study extends dynamic capability theory by demonstrating that in heavily regulated environments, competitive advantage depends not solely on agility but on structured adaptation within institutional constraints. The introduced frameworks provide a novel approach to balancing compliance with innovation, offering transferable insights for strategy execution in regulated industries.
Article
Full-text available
Geometric representations of psychological dimensions were analyzed and compared to an alternative set-theoretical approach. Judgments of similarity between forms and figures by 244 high school and undergraduate students revealed the following effects: (a) Qualitative attributes were curved relative to quantitative attributes, contrary to intradimensional subtractivity; (b) quantitative attributes augmented differences in qualitative attributes, contrary to interdimensional additivity; and (c) adding a new dimension with a fixed value increased similarity, contrary to translation invariance. The implications of these results for multidimensional representations of proximity data are discussed. (24 ref)
Article
The book that launched the Dempster–Shafer theory of belief functions appeared 40 years ago. This intellectual autobiography looks back on how I came to write the book and how its ideas played out in my later work.
Article
Many decisions are based on beliefs concerning the likelihood of uncertain events such as the outcome of an election, the guilt of a defendant, or the future value of the dollar. Occasionally, beliefs concerning uncertain events are expressed in numerical form as odds or subjective probabilities. In general, the heuristics are quite useful, but sometimes they lead to severe and systematic errors. The subjective assessment of probability resembles the subjective assessment of physical quantities such as distance or size. These judgments are all based on data of limited validity, which are processed according to heuristic rules. However, the reliance on this rule leads to systematic errors in the estimation of distance. This chapter describes three heuristics that are employed in making judgments under uncertainty. The first is representativeness, which is usually employed when people are asked to judge the probability that an object or event belongs to a class or event. The second is the availability of instances or scenarios, which is often employed when people are asked to assess the frequency of a class or the plausibility of a particular development, and the third is adjustment from an anchor, which is usually employed in numerical prediction when a relevant value is available.