ArticlePDF Available

Property Rights Theory and the Commons: The Case of Scientific Research

Authors:

Abstract

For some time now, commentators in and out of the scientific community have been expressing concern over the direction of scientific research. Cogent critics have labeled it excessively commercial, out of touch with its “pure,” public-spirited roots, and generally too much a creature of its entrepreneurial, self-interested times. In most if not all of this hand-wringing, the scientific community's growing reliance on intellectual property rights, especially patents, looms large. Indeed, for many the pursuit of patents is emblematic of just what is rotten in the republic of science today.
SCIENTIFIC INNOVATION,
PHILOSOPHY, AND PUBLIC POLICY
Edited by
Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller, Jr.,
and Jeffrey Paul
(1996)
CAMBRIDGE
UNIVERSITY PRESS
PROPERTY RIGHTS THEORY AND THE COMMONS:
THE CASE OF SCIENTIFIC RESEARCH
By ROBERT P. MERGES
I. INTRODUCTION
For some time now, commentators in and out of the scientific community have been
expressing concern over the direction of scientific research. Cogent critics have labeled it
excessively commercial, out of touch with its “pure,” public-spirited roots, and generally too
much a creature of its entrepreneurial, self-interested times. In most if not all of this and
wringing, the scientific community's growing reliance on intellectual property rights,
especially patents, looms large. Indeed, for many the pursuit of patents is emblematic of just
what is rotten in the republic of science today.
These concerns with property rights, and commercialization of science in general,
spring from a number of motivations. For some, the issue is strictly utilitarian. Under this
view of things, the traditional division of labor between the public and private spheres has
proven so effective-contributing as it has to the development of such modern indispensables
as semiconductors, penicillin, and jet transportation-that to change our approach now is
sheer madness.1 For these observers of the latest trends in science, the changes currently
afoot are a threat to kill (or at least cripple) the goose that has laid before us, like so many
golden eggs, many of the conveniences we take for granted.
Others are concerned for different reasons. They express a more fundamental objection:
that commercializing the heretofore noble, pure, and otherwise untainted field of science is
not just poor policy, but intrinsically bad.2 They are consumed with the notion that current
trends threaten to undermine not simply an effective set of institutions, but ultimately a
successful part of our shared public life-what they might characterize as
1. See Donald Kennedy, "Research in the Universities: How Much Utility?" in The Positive Sum Strategy:
Harnessing Technology for Economic Growth, ed. Ralph Landau and Nathan Rosenberg (Washington, DC: National
Academy Press, 1986); and Leonard G. Boonin, "The University, Scientific Research, and the Ownership of
Knowledge," in Owning Scientific and Technical Information: Value and Ethical Issues, ed. Vivian Weil and John W.
Snapper (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1989), p. 253.
2 See, e.g., Martin Kennedy, Biotechnology: The University-Industry Complex (New Haven: Yale University
Press, 1986); and Commercialization of Academic Biomedical Research (Hearings before the Subcommittee on
Investigations and Oversight and the Subcommittee on Science, Research, and Technology of the House Committee on
Science and Technology, Ninety-
@ 1996 Social Philosophy & Policy Foundation. Printed in the USA. 145
146 ROBERT P MERGES
an important cultural achievement of post-World War II democracy. To some extent, this
view finds expression in the recently renewed interest in eliminating patents for scientific
research directed toward isolating and characterizing human genes.3 Even those who would
shy away from this grand form of the argument contend that regardless of the greater
significance of scientific institutions and their historical achievements, those institutions
have a uniquely appropriate place in our social setup. And that place, all on this side agree,
is the public sphere.
As with so many issues, divergent vocabularies conceal similarities. Both the
high-principle defenders of traditional public science and their utilitarian/economist fellow
travelers share a sense that current trends pose a threat. For purposes of this essay, that is
enough to provide a starting-point. Although as I proceed I will try to keep in mind the two
very different motivations that lead to attacks on current trends in the direction of scientific
research and the institutions that conduct it, the essay must ultimately reflect my sense both
that the two sets of concerns motivate very similar policy arguments, and that at some level
they are in fact closely intertwined.
In any event, with this quick summary of the current discontents of science behind us,
we can turn to a statement of the burden I wish to carry in this essay. Simply put, the
burden has two parts: first, to show that the public sphere spoken of respectfully in
traditional science is less than it appears, being in fact more analogous in some ways to a
limited-membership, shared-access common area than a truly wide-open, unclaimed space;
and second, to argue that even under such a revised view of the public sphere, some current
practices-broadly cognizable under the heading of privatization or (less accurately)
commercialization-do indeed threaten to undermine certain cornerstones of our scientific
infrastructure. In short, although the shape of the worry is different from the one commonly
supposed, it is a real worry nevertheless. To some extent, I argue, the scientific community
has begun to address these concerns itself, primarily through a host of voluntary practices
that, in effect, water down patent rights. Yet enough of a threat remains that, toward the
end of the essay, I propose some policy directions that might alleviate the
————————
seventh Congress, First Session, 1981), pp. 62-63 (testimony of Dr. Jonathan King, Professor of Biology, Massachusetts
Institute of Technology):
The openness, the free exchange of ideas and information, the free exchange of strains, of protein, of
techniques, have been a critical component in the creativity and productivity of the biomedical research
community... This freedom of communication stemmed from the fact that all of the investigators shared the
same professional canon: the increase of knowledge of health and disease for the general benefit of the
citizenry...
3See Sally Lehrman, "Broad Coalition Adds Voice to Religious Protest on Gene Patents," Biotechnology
Newswatch, June 19, 1995, p. 1, in which Lehrman quotes Richard Levins, Professor of Population Science at the
Harvard School of Public Health, as stating that gene patenting is a means of "subordinating a common intellectual
heritage for private gain."
PROPERTY RIGHTS THEORY AND THE COMMONS 147
creeping propertization that characterizes science today. Perhaps not surprisingly, given my
understanding that even traditional “pure” science includes de facto (though skeletal)
property rights, I do not recommend the complete elimination of all property rights, formal
and informal, from basic scientific research. Instead, I argue for a more carefully crafted set
of property rights, including (1) a generally available exemption from patent infringement
liability in the case of pure research conducted with federal funds (a broad form of the so-
called “research exemption”), and (2) an occasional decision by senior science officials to
exclude particular research areas from patentability altogether, when the direct and indirect
costs of establishing, enforcing, and administering property rights is deemed excessive in
comparison to the benefits of access under the "normal" rules of basic science. The recent
decision by the director of the National Institutes of Health (NIH) to drop a series of patent
applications on aspects of the Human Genome Project serves as an example of reasoned
policy in this regard.
II. THE PUBLIC SPHERE, THE SCIENTIFIC COMMONS,
AND FORMAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
For most people, the description of science as an innately public enterprise comes quite
naturally. This is most likely a function of two attributes widely associated with scientific
research: government funding and open dissemination. These are closely related, of course;
but a moment's reflection ought to show that they are not coextensive. After all, there are
activities that are funded by the government that are not publicized (e.g., intelligence
work), and the private sector funds a fair amount of scientific research that is published in
peer-reviewed journals and otherwise bears the earmarks of public availability. In other
words, the implicit pairings "public/open" and "'private/closed" are misleading.
The large volume of privately funded basic research apparently does not undercut the
view of science as an inherently public undertaking. Because of this, it might even be
argued that the open dissemination of research results-which is, of course, common to most
basic science, who ever funds it-is thought by most to be the key indicator of basic or pure
science.
The point here is not to quibble with this, but to unpack it. That is, I am concerned in
this section with a brief description of how and under what circumstances basic research
results are shared with the world. As we shall see, it is a much more limited, and closely
regulated, form of disclosure than is usually imagined. The many limitations on truly public
dissemination lead, in fact, to the conclusion that science is not so much given freely to the
public as shared under a largely implicit code of conduct among a more or less
well-identified circle of similarly situated scientists. In other words, we will come to see
that science is more like a
148 ROBERT P. MERGES
Limited-access commons than a truly open public domain. Later we will see how this
revised understanding of the traditional degree of scientific openness contributes to our
understanding of what policies should be adopted to stem the tide of current abuses.
A. The nature of scientific research
Science is a highly competitive enterprise regulated by a complex set of professional
norms. Indeed, because of the elegant elaboration of those norms-especially at the hands of
sociologists of science, particularly Robert Merton-they are sometimes confused with
science itself.
Merton4 described four norms that define the scientific culture: universalism,
communism, disinterestedness, and organized skepticism. Briefly, "universalism" means
that impersonal criteria, independent of the identity and characteristics of the individual
scientist(s) who does the research, are employed to judge the soundness of scientific work.
"Communism" means that scientific findings are made open to all, immediately, with no
sense that they are or should be proprietary in any way. “Disinterestedness” means that
scientists pursue truth rather than self-interest, that they are ideally indifferent to the
success of an experiment or the reception of a research finding. "Organized skepticism"
means that the scientific community should rigorously test research results before accepting
them as true, and that all research is in some sense "born in doubt," false until dispositively
proven true.
Of course, norms (in the sense in which Merton used the term) are aspirational; they
have-to notice the linguistic clue-a normative dimension. Consequently, it is not surprising
that sociologists of science have documented a set of practices that deviate in many respects
from the norms Merton identified. Of most interest to us here is a set of observations made
by the sociologist Warren 0. Hagstrom5 on what might be called proprietary practices in
science. Hagstrom states:
Scientists who are concerned about the possibility of being anticipated as a result
of the theft of their ideas tend to be secretive. An organic chemist [in an interview]
said that he only communicated with persons he was friendly with and could
trust....
To the extent that scientists can establish property rights over work in
progress, they need not fear anticipation. Such property rights may be more or less
explicit and formal.... When it becomes evident to two [scientists in the same field]
that their research will probably produce the same results, they may informally
agree on a division of labor... [Another way scientists treat their work as
proprietary is by
4 Robert K. Merton, The Sociology of Science (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1973).
5 Warren 0. Hagstrom, The Scientific Community (New York: Basic Books, 1965).
PROPERTY RIGHTS THEORY AND THE COMMONS 149
publishing a preliminary version of research in an abstract.] The latent function of
publishing abstracts is to permit individuals to “stake a claim,” establish property
rights on research in progress.6
Hagstrom concludes with the observation that "[s]cientific knowledge is community
property. Discoverers have limited rights, but among them are rights to be recognized for
their discoveries." Thus, we can summarize Hagstrom's findings by saying that he found
certain proprietary impulses at work beneath the surface of the otherwise Mertonian world
of shared, or public, science.
More recently, the practice of asserting informal property rights appears to have
become even more prominent .7 In cutting-edge biotechnology research, for example, pre-
and even post-publication practices with respect to biological materials useful to fellow
researchers (such as genetically engineered mice, or particularly useful cell lines) reflect
greater reluctance to share widely. While it is difficult to trace the contours of a practice
that few scientists admit to, and that few even seem willing to discuss openly, several
operational principles can be traced, if somewhat speculatively. First, the more expensive
and difficult it is to create a given biological material, the less likely it is that it will be
shared widely and quickly.8 Second, the creator of a biological material is more likely to
share quickly with those in fields unrelated to the creator's central interests; property rights
are asserted most forcefully, in other words, with direct competitors.9 Third, despite the
increased assertion of informal property rights, these rights still fall far short of absolute
exclusivity. A recent investigation of sharing practices in the field of recombinant DNA
research “reveals that while no makers of [mice] simply refuse to share them, some
researchers substitute their own policies for those of [the National Institutes of Health,
which mandates free access after publication]: not sharing mice until long after publication,
or sharing mice selectively.”10 In practice, then, this example suggests that scientists fall
short of the ideal of instantaneous, widespread disclosure.
Of course, the most obvious illustration of creeping propertization is the now
widespread practice of seeking formal property rights-in the
6 Ibid., pp. 87,91.
7 Jon Cohen, "Share and Share Alike Isn't Always the Rule in Science; Many Researchers Fail to Share
Materials," Science, vol. 268 (June 23, 1995), pp. 1715-18.
8 Ibid., p. 1715: "A National Research Council (NRC) report last year on problems with sharing genetically
engineered mice such as knockouts [i.e., mice genetically engineered to have immune systems lacking a defense against
a disease, used to test drugs aimed at treating that disease] concluded that 'increased cost and competition ... appear to be
challenging the tradition of sharing in some branches of biological research.”
9 See ibid., p. 1717, where Cohen recounts the story of the creator of a research mouse who directed his graduate
student to "initially [turn] down [a] request because [the requestor] was a direct competitor; that researcher was later
given the mouse for a specific experiment in an area unrelated to [the creator's work or that of his graduate student]."
10 Ibid., p. 1716.
150 ROBERT P. MERGES
form of patents-over research results. Nothing could be further from the aspirational norm
of openness. Indeed, the absolute exclusivity of a patent would seem entirely inconsistent
with the earlier observation that science is characterized by informal property rights. Yet
the truth is that in general, within the community of researchers, potentially patentable and
even patented research results are often shared, though on a more limited basis. Surely it
would be stretching quite a bit to argue that the presence of patents does not make a
difference in the conduct of science. Yet just as surely it would be wrong to say that patents
lead researchers to completely shut off the exchange of research results. Nor are patents
universally enforced to the hilt among researchers; far from it.
As the studies cited earlier reveal, patents have affected the way science is done. Even
so, in many cases scientist-patentees assert far less than the full exclusionary force bestowed
by the legal system via their patents. A limited set of rights is asserted against the
community, even though the patentee holds a greater set of rights. Indeed, it is not
stretching too far to argue that conduct in today's scientific community in many cases
approximates the effect achieved under the older practice of establishing "informal"
property rights. The difference is that, now, the "informal ness" of the rights is achieved by
relinquishing (or at least not asserting) some of the scientist's formal rights. It is as if the
old practice of establishing minimal property out of a background of zero formal rights has
been replaced by relinquishing some rights against a background of a strong, formal
entitlement.
Several recent uproars in the science world illustrate the community's continued
practice of costless sharing, even in the presence of patents. Arguments over conflict-of-
interest policies,12 the appropriateness of university patent-licensing policies,11 and the
licensing of patents for certain foundational research technologies reveal that the creeping
propertization identified earlier has not yet reached into every aspect of community
practice.
Like the internal tensions identified by sociologists of science in the pre-patent era,
contemporary arguments are almost always a matter of degree. Very rarely is it argued that
a member in good standing of the public research community is simply shutting the
community out entirely. The debate centers on the terms of access, and on whether the
restrictions some researcher seeks to impose are in keeping with the operational content of
the norm of shared knowledge as currently practiced, even in the presence of patents.
Again, the point is that few scientists see the debate in polar terms-as a simple choice
between the total
11 See, e.g., Student Note, "Ties That Bind: Conflicts of Interest in University-Industry Links," U.C. Davis Law
Review, vol. 17 (January 1984), p. 895.
12 See, e.g., Carl Dierassi, "The Gray Zone: Academic Researchers and Private Enterprise," Science, vol. 261
(August 20, 1993), p. 972.
PROPERTY RIGHTS THEORY AND THE COMMONS 151
absence of property rights (or their equivalent) and the wholesale adoption of strong, formal
property rights (in the form of patents). Most scientists seem to think that the optimal policy
entails maintaining some of the traditional practices that sociologists have identified with-
an informal set of property rights in research results, even in an era when formal property
rights have been widely adopted.
For example, a number of brushfires have broken out in recent years regarding the
extent to which a researcher must make his or her results available to other members of the
community prior to, or even after, publication. Since major research results-finding a gene,
or identifying the active portion of a protein coded for by a gene of interest, for example-are
usually published very quickly, they are not usually at issue. Instead, the arguments are over
another issue: the dissemination of assays, reagents, and other research tools of the trade,
which have come to be known generically as biological materials. Very often these are
developed as an interim step on the way to the final goal of obtaining the gene or protein
subunit or whatever. Since most of the basic research funding that goes into the creation of
these tools is public money, the question arises: When must they be shared?
Often the discussion takes the form of back-channel gossip regarding a certain lab's
unwillingness to share a research tool.13 Interestingly, for our purposes, the point of this
gossip-induced social pressure is not that the tool must be described in a formal, printed
publication. It is simply that the tool be provided, on a reasonable basis, to other interested
labs so that they can use it in the course of their research. Indeed, other labs understand that
they will almost always be required to use the biological material under a duty not to
disclose it to others, and certainly not to disclose it to the public generally, until its
originator has published a full account of it.14
13 See, e.g., Cohen, "Share and Share Alike Isn't Always the Rule in Science," p. 1715:
[P]roblems in materials sharing ... crop up in cell-line repositories, crystallographic databases-indeed
wherever competitors would like to share research materials. And these problems stir passions in the
scientific community. "Typically, over coffee or beer at night, this is what our colleagues are talking about,"
says one researcher at the University of California, Berkeley, who insisted on anonymity.
Science's investigation, however, reveals that, e.g., "while no makers of [the genetically engineered mice known as
"knockouts"] simply refuse to share them, some researchers substitute their own policies for those of NIH: not sharing
mice until long after publication, or sharing mice selectively. Insiders in the field -none of whom would allow
themselves to be named -repeatedly mentioned Nobel prize-winning immunologist Susumu Tonegawa as someone
whose mice are not freely available immediately after publication."
14 See Dan L. Burk, "Misappropriation of Trade Secrets in Biotechnology Licensing," Albany Law Journal of
Science and Technology, vol. 4 (1994), pp. 141-42:
The professional norms of the scientific community have long required that scientists share data and
materials with one another, both to allow repetition and validation of reported results and to facilitate new
discoveries.... These exchange practices have to
152 ROBERT P. MERGES
Insider criticism of other contemporary practices is aimed at the same goal of limited
access. Thus, the controversy over inadequate disclosure of research tools employed in the
discovery of published research results subsided when certain benchmark publications such
as Science agreed to require researchers to simply make the tools available with a
reasonable set of restrictions.15
The same pattern holds when the patenting of research results is at issue. Normally, the
criticism of excessive patenting activity or inappropriate licensing practices does not start
from the assumption that complete public access should be the norm. For example, the
outcry over certain large-scale research funding arrangements between private industry and
prominent research institutions does not assume that the research output of the institutions
would be freely available to all in the absence of the funding agreement. Implicit is the
notion that the agreements exceed standard limits on the degree of privatization that is
acceptable in science. No one assumes that a modest degree of privatization is against the
working norms of the community.
This makes an interesting backdrop to our consideration of a historical moment when it
appeared that policymakers might adopt formal, statutory property rights for scientific
research.
B. History of explicit proposals for formal property rights in scientific discoveries
Traditionally, the findings of pure scientific research have been excluded from patent
protection.16 Some have proposed that it is a mistake to exclude such things, however. The
history of these attempts to extend formal rights to the products of scientific research bears
recounting for two reasons. First, it shows once again that despite the norm of openness (or
"communism," to use Merton's term), property rights-even of the formal variety-have not
been a complete stranger to the world of science. Second, certain objections to these earlier
proposals seem just as valid now as when they were first made. The upshot is that this older
debate holds some useful lessons for the current discussion.
The movement for formal property rights in scientific discoveries took shape in France
just after World War I, when scientists were suffering greatly from the national devastation
(and destitution) brought on by the
————————
some extent been constrained by an unwritten and often unspoken agreement among researchers that the
materials shared will not be used for commercial gain and will not be passed on without permission from the
original owner.
15 Ibid., p. 142.
16 See Robert P. Merges, Patent Law and Policy (Charlottesville, VA: Michie Co., 1992), ch. 2.
PROPERTY RIGHTS THEORY AND THE COMMONS 153
war.17 The movement received formal recognition in 1922, when a detailed legislative
proposal was introduced into the French Chamber of Deputies by J. Barthelemy, a French
law professor and Member of the Chamber. Professor Barthelemy's proposal would have
overturned a provision of the French Patent Law of 1844 which declared null and void all
patents concerning "principles, methods, systems, discoveries and theoretical or purely
scientific conceptions of which no industrial applications are indicated."18 Barthelemy's
proposal contained two essential provisions. First, it stipulated that a scientist who has
made a discovery may take no action so long as no one tries to apply the discovery. As soon
as a practical application of the theoretical discovery is made, however, the scientist may
present a claim for a part of the profits. Second, a scientist may obtain a "patent of
principle." This would not confer on the patentee an exclusive right to make or use the
discovery, but only the right to grant licenses for those utilizing the practical applications of
the discovery. Anyone would be free to utilize the invention or discovery, so long as he or
she paid royalties to the scientist who had discovered it. The duration of protection would
have been more akin to copyright: the life of the discoverer plus fifty years. As intellectual-
property scholar Stephen Ladas points out, the Barthelemy proposal was part of a larger
post-World War I movement in France in favor of a "Droit de Suite" or set of "moral rights"
for authors and creators.19
Also in 1922, the League of Nations' Committee on Intellectual Cooperation took up
the question of scientific property at the insistence of its chairman, Professor Bergson. The
committee eventually approved a plan drafted by Senator Ruffini of Italy.20 Ruffini's
proposal began by dismissing the theoretical objections to the patenting of scientific
discoveries. After reciting the various objections to protecting "discoveries" rather than
inventions, Ruffini concludes: "The whole question is dominated by crudest utilitarianism,
empiricism unhappily disguised in scientific nebulosity, and, finally, the most disconcerting
arbitrariness."21 Ruffini also pointed out that one objection to the proposal of Barthelemy in
France was that French industry would be handicapped by being forced to recognize an
intellectual property right not recognized throughout the world. Ruffini's solution was to
propose an international treaty which would
17 This and other details of the early movement for property rights in science are drawn from C. J. Hamson, Patent
Rights for Scientific Discoveries (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill Co., 1930).
18 Quoted in Stephen P. Ladas, Patents, Trademarks, and Related Rights: National and Inter national
Protection (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1975), vol. 3, p. 1856.
19 Ladas, Patents, Trademarks, and Related Rights, vol. 3, section 1012, p. 1856.
20 F. Ruffini, Report on Scientific Property (Committee on Intellectual Cooperation, League of Nations,
Document A. 38, 1923), XII, 10; quoted in Ladas, Patents, Trademarks, and Related Rights, section 1012, p. 1856.
21 Ibid.
154 ROBERT P. MERGES
create such a right in all signatory nations, thus eliminating the possibility that companies
in one country would carry the extra financial burden of paying royalties to scientists.
Ruffini's substantive proposals were straightforward. He proposed a term of protection
identical to that of Barthelemy's plan: life plus fifty years. He called for the exclusion of
discoveries which merely presented a scientific explanation of obvious facts or practices of
human life. (This point was made in response to a memorandum from Dean Henry
Wigmore of Northwestern Law School, who objected to the proposal on this basis.) In
addition, the plan provided for four possible means of establishing priority in an idea,
including publication, self-authentication, "patents of principle," and ordinary patents.
While these proposals drew criticism, they also found defenders. One view had it that
the industries that used a scientific discovery in particular applications had a "quasi-
contractual obligation" to remunerate the discoverer of the principle.22 In fact, the plan
went so far as to be made the subject of a draft convention prepared by a committee of
experts at the League of Nations.23 However, the project lost momentum in 1930, and was
never revitalized, except in France. There the government adopted a decree creating a
Medal of Scientific Research with prizes, which took the place of the discovery patent. This
decree, and certain legislated principles in the socialist countries, are the only actual
legislative products of the scientific-discovery patent movement.24
A number of authors familiar with these proposals from the 1930s have raised or
reviewed objections to them.25 First, it is very often difficult to trace the scientific origins of
a particular industrial application. Second, there is a significant lag time between the
disclosure of a scientific discovery and the development of the first application; the
argument that fairness dictates compensation for the scientist who makes a discovery would
seem to be mitigated by the length of time between his or her discovery and its application.
Third, very often it can be assumed that a scientific disclosure will be missed by
industrialists; they will thus end up paying royalties for a scientific discovery which in fact
was not relied upon in creating their industrial application. And finally, the very significant
burdens on scientific communication that a system of property rights would create represent
perhaps the most severe problem. Since science was (and still is) thought to depend on free
and open communication, and since property rights are presumed to be at odds with such
free
22 See Laclas, Patents, Trademarks, and Related Rights, section 1017, p. 1862.
23 Ibid.
24 See ibid., sections 1021-26, pp. 1868-75. It should be noted that Article 2(viii) of the convention establishing
the World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO) includes, in the definition of "intellectual property," rights relating
to "scientific discoveries" and "all other rights resulting from intellectual activity in the ... scientific ... fields."
25 See Hamson, Patent Rights for Scientific Discoveries; and Ladas, Patents, Trademarks, and Related Rights.
PROPERTY RIGHTS THEORY AND THE COMMONS 155
communication, property rights and science were thought to be an ill-fated combination.
An additional objection to patents in scientific discoveries is that they are not necessary
to spur scientific research. As Judge Jerome Frank put it:
Epoch-making "discoveries" or "mere" general scientific "laws," without more, cannot
be patented.... So the great "discoveries" of Newton or Faraday could not have been
rewarded with such a grant of monopoly. Interestingly enough, apparently many
scientists like Faraday care little for monetary rewards; generally the motives of such
outstanding geniuses are not pecuniary... Perhaps (although no one really knows) the
same cannot be said of those lesser geniuses who put such discoveries to practical
uses.26
On this view, granting patents for discoveries that scientists would have made anyway
would be socially wasteful.
For many, this latter assumption would be far less defensible in today's environment of
tight federal budgets. Regardless of what motivates a scientist, the argument would surely
run, he or she cannot make any progress in the vast majority of scientific disciplines
without a great deal of money. Equipment, personnel, and the like-all essential to the
performance of modem science-are very expensive. Thus, since adequate funding is
essential to science, society will not receive the results of scientific research without either
extensive public support or some other revenue source. It follows that if property rights can
secure this alternative revenue source, they may well provide a necessary impetus for the
performance of research. Far from being redundant-an unnecessary reward, heaped on a
researcher who would have done the same work without it-they may well be essential. This
of course moots Judge Frank's objection to the granting of rights for pure scientific finding.
If it is true that property rights are increasingly essential to the research endeavor, it is
no less true that these rights will bring with them a host of problems. It is these problems-
which I would describe as an entire family of new transaction costs-which drive the
discussion in Section IV concerning policy solutions to the imposition of property rights in
science.
C. The rise of patents for the results of "pure" science
Proposals to explicitly allow patents for the results of basic scientific research
eventually faced a resounding defeat. Given that the only occasion on which the
appropriateness of these patents was discussed in detail yielded such negative results, it is
perhaps surprising that basic research is now considered an entirely proper source of
patentable subject matter. Although broad statements of scientific truth-such as E = MC2-
26 Katz v. Horni Signal Mfg. Corp., 145 F.2d 961, 63 U.S.P.Q. (BNA) 190 (2d Cir. 1944).
156 ROBERT P. MERGES
are still considered unpatentable,27 many of the fruits of contemporary basic science find
their way into patent claims of one variety or another these days. To some extent, this is a
result of growing sophistication by patent lawyers, who have learned to state a scientific
finding in terms of an at least nominally useful application.28 Apart from this, however,
what happened to produce this de facto change in policy?
For the most part, the answer lies with changes in the relationship between science and
technology since the 1930s .29 In the 1930s, the important science-based industries were
centered around the electrical and chemical fields. Because electrical engineering and
modem, analytic chemistry were still very young, the findings of basic science were very
basic indeed. The conceptual distance between basic research and applied technology, in
other words, was very large. As a consequence, huge investments were required to translate
the findings of the basic research laboratory into viable commercial products.
By the 1970s and 1980s, however, the relationship between science and technology had
grown a good deal closer in many fields. In important fields such as biotechnology and
certain branches of physics, the jump from lab result to commercial product was much
shorter than it had been in the past.30 Thus, for example, the basic Cohen-Boyer research on
gene-splicing led to a commercial product (genetically engineered insulin) in only a few
short years. The early work on lasers, to take another example, yielded commercial results
after a relatively short time as well.
In addition, a host of subsidiary factors contributed to the hastening rate of commercial
application. One important factor-often overlooked -is the change in the ease of capital
formation for science-intensive industries.31 In the 1930s, it was widely thought that only
large, integrated companies could afford the "luxury" of long-term-oriented basic scientific
research. By the 1970s, however, with the advent of the venture-capital industry and related
support institutions, start-up companies based on new scientific findings often found a
ready supply of capital from firms specializing in such speculative investments. Genentech,
founded in the mid-1970s, is of course the paradigm. It is also an example of a technology-
intensive start-up that was later highly touted by investment analysts when it made the jump
from "private" to public financing, via an initial public offering of stock.
27 See Merges, Patent Law and Policy, ch. 2.
28 This is the legal test used to determine patentability in close cases involving a putative "scientific principle." See
ibid., ch. 2.
29 See Robert Teitelman, Profits of Science: The American Marriage of Business and Technology (New York:
Basic Books, 1994).
30 See ibid., p. 8, where Teitelman contrasts the 1953 elucidation of the structure of the DNA molecule by James
Watson and Francis Crick, which had no commercial impact until decades later, with the 1973 Cohen-Boyer work on
recombinant DNA, which led to the founding of Genentech in 1976.
31 See ibid., ch. 1.
PROPERTY RIGHTS THEORY AND THE COMMONS 157
As the Genentech story illustrates, capital markets-together with the changing interplay
between science and technology-played a crucial role in the commercialization of basic
science. It is important to recognize that extensive university involvement in technology
licensing-another recent development often said to be at the heart of the commercialization
process-is in fact closely related to the growing sophistication of capital markets with
regard to basic science. For it is quite clear that without a prospective market, fueled by the
idea of significant returns on investments in the basic findings of science, the university
licensing offices founded with such frequency in the 1980s and 1990s would have no one to
sell to.
These licensing offices demonstrate the extent of the changes that have taken place
within many areas of basic science since the 1930s. Far from needing special legislation to
create a new branch of patent law, the laboratory findings of certain branches of modern
science fit comfortably within the contours of traditional patent law. Once the
science/technology interface grew closer, and capital was attracted, obstacles to
patentability largely dropped away.
D. Incentives to seek property rights despite community norms
Despite the fact that, for a variety of reasons, patents are now available for an
increasing proportion of the results of basic research, the community norm of open access
remains strong. Thus, it is perhaps not clear why, even though the operative legal standard
has changed vis-a-vis modem science, scientists and the institutions that employ them today
are seeking so many patents for their research. In other words, just because they can obtain
patents, it does not follow that all of them will. Why then is everyone, in fact, making more
and more use of the patent system?
The answer as I see it is fairly simple. The increasing value of patents makes adherence
to the traditional community norm of nonproprietary open access implicitly more
expensive. Thus, even if a particular scientist believes strongly in adherence to the norm, he
or she knows that others will be tempted to ignore it because of the higher payoff that stems
from seeking a patent. Since many scientists believe that although the norm is still the
“correct” mode of behavior, many of their colleagues will abandon it, even those scientists
who believe in the norm may well abandon it. Only a scientist who would revel in the
thought that he or she was the last one remaining who adheres to the norm would continue
to adhere to it.
Those familiar with the logic of game theory will recognize the basic structure of this
situation. Although most players attribute the greatest value to continued shared access -to
"cooperation," in game theory lingo-even many of these, fearing the inevitable
abandonment of the shared norm in light of the higher individual payoffs from "defecting,"
will themselves defect from the prior cooperative arrangement. Others, anticipating
158 ROBERT P. MERGES
this, will also defect. In this way, even though everyone would be better off if the
cooperative behavior continued, the "equilibrium strategy" will be to defect. The problem,
to put it simply, is that there is no way to enforce the norm of shared access, and no way to
bind other members of the community to the cooperative arrangement. The players must
rely on each other to continue to do the right thing without formal sanctions for doing
otherwise. Once the payoffs from defecting increase, however, there is less assurance that
the other players will continue to do the right thing. One way of stating this is that the
implicit costs of the informal sanctions brought to bear on defectors-negative gossip, loss of
reputation, etc.-are outweighed by the benefits, in the form of greater payoffs due to the
enhanced returns provided by the formal property rights. As one highly astute observer of
these matters put it recently:
For years biomedical research has flourished while investigators have drawn heavily
upon discoveries that their predecessors left in the public domain. Even if exclusive
rights enhance private incentives to develop further research tools, they could do
considerable damage to the research enterprise by inhibiting the effective utilization of
existing ones.32
There is already evidence that this dynamic has begun to set in.33
Since scientists may well conclude that it is in each scientist's self-interest to patent his
or her research tools, each will expect the others to avail themselves of patents. This
expectation that others will defect leads even those who rue the demise of the norm of
cooperation to defect, since the very worst position of all is to continue to cooperate while
all those around you are defecting. In the case of patents on pure science, this would take
the form of a scientist refusing to patent her results despite the fact that all her colleagues
are patenting theirs. She would have to pay royalties to all the others to use their results,
while her own work went completely uncompensated. Indeed, if royalty income were a
substitute for research funding from the government or the like, she might even be
32 Rebecca Eisenberg, "A Technology Policy Perspective on the NIH Gene Patenting Controversy," University of
Pittsburgh Law Review, vol. 55 (Spring 1994), p. 646.
33 Jim Carlton, "Roche Brings Leading Institutions into Lawsuit over Patent Rights," Wall Street Journal, May
25, 1995, p. B4:
At a conference here this week, scientists reacted with dismay [to a suit brought by Roche against Promega,
another biotechnology company, in which Roche accused Promega of "contributory infringement" by supplying
scientists with a key component that allows them to use Roche's patented polymerase chain reaction (PCR)
technology], saying they could be prevented from using patented products-such as for computers and
biotechnology-in their scientific research. They say they have done research virtually unfettered by patent
constraints for some 200 years.
Note that many of these scientists -or at least the institutions where they work -are actively seeking patents on the results
of their research. In other words, they are dismayed that their own strategy of defecting from the cooperative
arrangement is becoming the norm!
PROPERTY RIGHTS THEORY AND THE COMMONS 159
driven out of science altogether. Thus, she might well adopt the approach of patenting her
research despite deep misgivings about abandoning the traditional norm of openness in
science.
Even if this account of the motivations of individual scientists is correct (and it is
admittedly highly stylized), some important questions remain. Just because patent law has
in effect dropped its objections to patenting what comes out of certain basic-research labs,
and just because scientists might have an incentive to patent, does that mean that the
science community, or society at large, should encourage widespread patenting of these
results? Are there policy concerns that extend beyond the domain of what patent law
considers appropriate subject matter? I take up these questions in Section IV.
A recent development illustrates how scientists and research labs are responding to the
incentives they face. In March 1995, a group called the Association of University
Technology Managers (AUTM) announced a new, standardized form for the transfer of
biological materials between nonprofit (i.e., government-funded) research labs.34 The
Uniform Biotechnology Materials Transfer Agreement, or UBMTA, embodies the research
community's current sense of the best practices with respect to the sorts of limitations that
can appropriately be placed on the transfer of research tools created with public funding.35
For our purposes, two features of the UBMTA scheme are of paramount importance. First,
there are two versions, one styled "nonprofit to nonprofit," and the other "nonprofit to for-
profit." (I explore this two-tier property rights regime in Section III.) Second, the UBMTA
recognizes a number of serious restrictions on use-incursions into the pure public domain, if
you will.
For example, in the "nonprofit to nonprofit" form, free use is given of the research tool
in its original form, but adaptations, modifications, and alterations are not covered. Indeed,
modifications intended for ultimate commercialization are to be the subject of negotiations
with the original provider of the material. And, perhaps most relevant here, the relatively
permissive treatment of transfers applies only if the transferee does not intend a subsequent
transfer to a private, for-profit firm. These private firms, being outside the common in some
sense, must negotiate formal, commercial licenses.
34 On lab transfer agreements, see Charles E. Lipsey et al., "Protecting Trade Secrets in Biotechnology," in
Protecting Trade Secrets (PLI Patent, Copyright, Trademarks, and Literary Property Course Handbook Series No.
224,1986), Exhibit K.
35 This uniform MTA suggests that standard contractual terms-a form of transaction-cost-reducing industry
coordination-are beginning to emerge. (My source here is a personal interview with Sandy Shotwell-an AUTM member
and a participant in the project to draft the Uniform Biotechnology Material Transfer Agreement (UBMTA) -conducted
in Washington, D.C., in February 1994.) On the evolution of transaction-cost-reducing institutions and practices in
intellectual property-intensive industries, see Robert P. Merges, "Of Coase, Property Rules, and Intellectual Property,"
Columbia Law Review, 1994, p. 2655; and Robert P. Merges, "Intellectual Property and the Costs of Commercial
Exchange: A Review Essay," Michigan Law Review, vol. 93 (1995), p. 1570.
160 ROBERT P. MERGES
E. Contemporary research on common-property regimes
This description of contemporary trends and understandings in science should give
some hint of why I have come to see science as a limited-access commons, rather than a
truly open public domain. In this subsection, I shall briefly review some contemporary
scholarship on common-access property rights regimes, both to get a deeper sense of how
the analogy works and to frame the discussion in Section IV concerning proper policy
toward scientific research.
Throughout the 1970s and into the 1980s, much of the research in political economy,
the economics of the public sector, and economics in general led to a great deal of
skepticism toward the workability not just of government, but of collective institutions in
general. At the formation stage, institutions were faced with formidable problems, most
notably the difficulty of overcoming self-interest; the problem of collective action, we were
told, was pervasive. And if by some miracle of cooperation or coercion collective
institutions took shape, they were immediately besieged by rent-seeking interest groups
concerned exclusively with turning the institution to private advantage. The forces at work
during the operative stage of an institution-which we might generally refer to as public-
choice concerns-were thus just as corrosive as the original conditions of collective action.
Partly in response to the deep skepticism engendered by the collective-action and
public-choice literatures, a number of social scientists set out to study real-world institutions
to see how they worked. Some started inductively, arriving at the threshold of the theory of
institutions only after having accumulated a mass of facts. Others began with a sense that
the received wisdom was somehow deficient; they seemed to have in mind the old adage
that sure, it worked in practice, but would it work in theory?
Whatever their starting point, however, these social scientists soon began to assemble
an intricate factual basis for some major revisions to the received view of institutions. In
sociology, economics, and even legal studies (with the work of scholars such as Robert
Ellickson at Yale Law School), detailed studies of institutions took shape.36 Collectively,
they form the basis for a much more nuanced theory of institutional formation,
administration, and change. As if to ratify the trend, the Nobel economics committee last
year awarded its prize to the granddaddy of institutional theorists, economic historian
Douglass North.
Many of the trends that culminated with the award of the Nobel to North are on display
in Eleanor Ostrom's pioneering book, Governing the
36 See Robert Ellickson, Order without Law (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989); and Thrairm
Eggertsson, Economic Behavior and Institutions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990).
PROPERTY RIGHTS THEORY AND THE COMMONS 161
Commons.37 The thrust of Ostrom's work is a description of how voluntary institutions arise
to allocate scarce, commonly shared resources such as water, without formal property rights
or significant government oversight. Her cases reveal a rich pattern of adaptive, consensual
responses to the "tragedy of the commons." Each case describes who organized the
institution and why. Then Ostrom details the complex rules governing who can join, how
informal "rights" to resources are determined, how compliance is monitored, how rules are
enforced (e.g., how violators are sanctioned), and whether (and to what extent) "external"'
governmental authorities are called on to structure, ratify, oversee, or enforce any aspects of
the institution.
Because they mirror the operation of scientific research institutions in some ways, I
will consider the example of water basin authorities in Southern California, a set of
institutions Ostrom studies in detail. These institutions emerged out of a classic tragedy of
the commons: an open access resource combined with minimal (almost nonexistent)
property rights. Municipalities that shared these water basins-which are large, permanent
subsurface water sources-formed water authorities in response to repeated litigation over
how much water each city could appropriate under state law. This law was based on the
notion of capture; it provided that a municipality had the right to use as much water as it
could make beneficial use of, subject to the caveat that the total usage could not exceed the
sustainable yield of the water basin. In the shadow of this minimal set of first-comer
entitlements, and under the threat of continuous, litigation under the just-mentioned caveat,
the municipalities formed voluntary organizations such as the Raymond Basin water district
and the West Basin Water Association. After initially implementing proportional water-
pumping cutbacks, to comply with the sustainable-yield requirement, these institutions
assumed their current operational role. They now provide for fixed water allocations,
neutral monitors (so-called watermasters, whose salaries are paid mostly by member cities
but partly by the state of California), and even systematic investments in groundwater
enhancement technologies, paid for by proportional contributions of the member cities.
Although the influence of government can be seen in the formation and operation of these
institutions, Ostrom stresses the essentially private nature of the collective action behind
these institutions: "The solutions to the pumping race ... were not imposed on the
participants by external authorities. Rather, the participants used public arenas to impose
constraints on themselves." Ostrom's study of water authorities and the other common-pool
organizations culminates in eight design principles, which Ostrom lays out as a checklist
for institutional designers. These are her answers to the deficiencies of the received theory
of institutions, especially collective-action theory and public choice. For our
37 Eleanor Ostrom, Governing the Commons (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990).
162 ROBERT P. MERGES
purposes, what is important is that she demonstrates the operation of voluntary common-
property resource allocation institutions based on shared rules and norms. (A host of other
studies in the same vein reach quite similar conclusions.)38
F. Scientific research as a common-property resource
One could agree that the baseline in science is not complete openness, and still resist
the analogy between common-property regimes and con temporary norms of science. After
all, unlike water or common pasture land, scientific research is not a product of nature,
waiting to be exploited. It has to be created. Thus, the thought might be that the institutions
that operate in the realm of science cannot be legitimately compared to those that allocate
access to preexisting natural resources such as water.
This is no doubt true; the analogy is incomplete in many respects, perhaps fatally so.
There is, however, one similarity so important as to make it worth pursuing (in my mind, at
any rate): the notion that both in the common-resource institutions studied by social
scientists such as Ostrom and in the case of scientific research, the members of the
community act as if some intermediate form of social organization -neither purely private
nor completely nonprivate, i.e., public-is in force.
This shared assumption stems, at least in part, from the fact that although science itself
is not a freely given asset, such as water or pasture land, it is based on a resource that the
members of the relevant community treat as a given: public money. Thus, public funding
produces science, which therefore carries with it some of the attributes of a public (or, I
would argue, common) resource. True, unlike with a physical resource, where the only issue
is allocation, science must first be produced by participants. And true, once it is produced, it
must be disclosed in order for other members of the community to use it. Nevertheless, in
many ways the practice of science makes these distinctions less important than they might
at first appear. First, the production of science is a highly cooperative venture. Those who
produce it understand that the community always has extensive claims on it, because
without shared knowledge, research techniques, and even biological materials, there would
often be no results, no progress, and hence nothing to argue about. Second, and most
importantly, in the absence of shared norms, science, like water, would be subject to highly
deleterious forms of self-serving behavior. A lab that always "takes" research results, but
that never "gives" in return, for example, is like a municipality that pumps water as fast as
it can, at the expense both of its neighbors and ultimately of rational
38 See, e.g., Glenn Stevenson, Common Property Economics: A General Theory and Land Use Applications
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), which presents empirical studies of grazing rights in common
pastures. (The Ostrom quote earlier in this paragraph is from Governing the Commons, p. 110.)
PROPERTY RIGHTS THEORY AND THE COMMONS 163
water use. Thus, in science, as with open-access water resources, cooperation produces very
large gains.
III. THE NEW NORMS OF SCIENCE: TWO-TIERED PROPERTY RIGHTS
In science, as we have seen, emerging pro-commercialization practices coexist
(sometimes uneasily) with traditional "Mertonian" norms. The resulting set of practices,
although still in the formative stage, suggests a basic structure that is quite compatible with
Ostrom's institutional analysis. It is worthwhile to take a moment to reconsider these
practices, then, with an eye to understanding them as an example of collective-action
institutions in formation.
In essence, the new practices can be explained-roughly and preliminarily-in the
following terms. They seek to preserve the old norms while recognizing a fundamentally
changed landscape.39 They do this by dividing potential transactions into two classes: those
with other pure scientists, in which efforts are made to preserve the old rules of scientific
discourse; and those with commercial entities, in which more-explicit insistence on
property rights, and the attendant element of immediate compensation, are both expected.
Consistent with the earlier explanation, it is important to notice that the former set of
transactions are not in any sense devoid of property rights. Instead, they rely on informal
property rights. The latter transactions, by contrast, depend on formal property rights, and
are conducted "in the shadow of" these rights. This explains, for example, why transfers of
as-yet-unpatented materials to commercial labs come with greater restrictions. The
possibility that a patent might be sought leads to greater safeguards, such as an insistence
that any commercialization, publication, or property right claims growing out of the
commercial recipient's use of the materials come only after the sender has received notice
and has time to respond. (This can preserve the sender's right to file his or her own patent,
for instance, a right that might be endangered if the recipient makes the sender's invention
public before the sender acts, e.g., by filing a patent application.)
Although I believe the two-tiered property right concept properly captures an important
feature of contemporary science, I would add some warnings about its continued relevance.
In general, science is in such a rapid state of flux that the differential treatment of pure and
commercial science may only be a way station on the road toward a totally new set of
39 In this respect, they bring to mind some intriguing observations of my colleague Bob Cooter regarding the
formation of formal markets for property rights in Papua New Guinea, a country currently undergoing a transition from
a traditional, clan-based system of real-property ownership to a more modem system. See Robert Cooter, "Inventing
Market Property: The Land Courts of Papua New Guinea," Law and Society Review, vol. 25 (1991), p. 760, where
Cooter argues that the best approach to modernizing is for courts to encourage novel forms of market property that are
more congenial to tradition."
164 ROBERT P. MERGES
practices. Perhaps the destination will be the complete specification and enforcement of
property rights, against all comers, pure and commercial. Perhaps it will be a return to the
old patterns of interaction, fueled by a declining interest in funding from commercial
entities. The point here is that the two-tiered system I observe currently is only one possible
configuration in the long term. Before extensive policy formation is undertaken in response
to it, we should make sure it has some degree of permanence.
IV. SOME TENTATIVE POLICY IDEAS
What policy recommendations flow from the fact of "creeping propertization" of
science, and the emergence of a two-tiered system? And what do we gain, in formulating
policies, by seeing scientific research both as a common asset shared under strict rules by a
close-knit community, and as a marketable product? I present the answers to these
questions in two parts: first, a pair of formal policy proposals, and second, an admonition
on implementation.
A. Specific policy proposals
First, we ought to consider adjusting some of the rules of the formal intellectual
property system to better reflect the fact that science originates as a product of the
commons. As is well recognized, the bold individual is the darling of our system, and of
patent law especially. Yet the origin of scientific research is with the group, and its use and
dissemination, in the first instance at least, ought to be a group affair. Thus, the common-
property approach would lead us to consider very seriously proposals to formalize a line of
legal decisions hinting at a pure research exemption to patent infringement.40 While none
of these proposals to date would explicitly allow fellow scientists to use research results
notwithstanding
40 See Rebecca Eisenberg, "Patents and the Progress of Science: Exclusive Rights and Experimental Use,"
University of Chicago Law Review, vol. 56 (1989), p. 1017, where Eisenberg describes the interaction between the
scientific research ethos and intellectual property rules.
The pure research exemption to patent infringement, known as the experimental-use doctrine, had its origins in
justice Joseph Story's opinion in Whittemore v. Cutter, 29 E Cas. 1120 (C.C.D.Mass. 1813) (No. 17,600). In this case,
the defendant appealed a jury instruction which stated, in effect, that the "making of a machine ... with a design to use it
for profit" constituted infringement. Justice Story upheld the trial judge's instruction, and stated that "it could never have
been the intention of the legislature to punish a man, who constructed such a machine merely for philosophical
experiments, or for the purpose of ascertaining the sufficiency of the machine to produce its described effects" (29 F.
Cas. at 555). Other cases followed, generally limiting the exception to these quite narrow grounds. See Note,
"Experimental Use as Patent Infringement: The Impropriety of a Broad Exception," Yale Law journal, vol. 100 (1991),
p. 2169, which states that the experimental-use exception "should be applied as it has been in the past: in a very
restrictive manner, consistent with the purpose and function of the patent system."
In Roche Products, Inc. v. Bolar Pharmaceutical Co., 733 F.2d 858, 221 U.S.P.Q. (BNA) 937 (Fed. Cir.), cert.
denied, 469 U.S. 856 (1984), the Federal Circuit Court of Appeals considered
PROPERTY RIGHTS THEORY AND THE COMMONS 165
the presence of formal patent rights,41 the "experimental-use doctrine" seems precisely the
right sort of accommodation between the needs of the scientific community and the
requirements of a formal property rights system. Whereas under current norms scientists in
effect scale back their property rights when dealing with each other, the experimental use
doctrine as typically described42 scales back the rights that any patentee-commercial entity
or pure scientist-can assert against a pure researcher. The doctrine could thus be described
as having two primary effects: codifying current practices within the scientific community,
and extending those practices to dealings between commercial entities and pure scientists.
The second proposal worth considering is to explicitly reevaluate the patent system's
rule regarding how early in a research project a researcher can file a viable patent
application. This rule, called the "utility requirement" by patent lawyers, plays a crucial role
in mediating the boundary between academic (or pure) science and applied, commercially
valuable science. Although there are some decided cases that show an appreciation that the
requirement serves this role, there is as yet no thoroughgoing conceptualization along these
lines. What is needed is an appreciation of the fact that pure researchers, long before it is
clear whether they are actually infringing any patent, change their behavior upon the mere
filing of a patent application by some other researcher or lab. They may shy away from the
area covered by the patent application, in fear of eventual patent litigation; they may file a
competing application, "defensively" as it were, to counter the incipient threat with a
property right of their own; or they may be seduced wholeheartedly into the speculative
game, and thus file a patent with potential commercial gain in mind-that is, an "offensive"
patent.
The utility requirement does not prevent these results, it merely delays them. By
requiring that an invention must reach a significant degree of practical promise before a
patent application is filed, it at least prevents the kind of "race to the patent office" that is
both theoretically predictable and actually observed in some cases.43
————————
the experimental-use defense for the first time. Here, the defendant, Bolar Pharmaceuticals, engaged in infringing acts
prior to the expiration of the plaintiff's patent in order to facilitate Food and Drug Administration testing, so as to be
ready to market the drug as soon as the patent expired. The Federal Circuit Court overruled the district court's finding of
noninfringement, holding that the experimental-use exception did not include "the limited use of a patented drug for
testing and investigation strictly related to FDA drug approval requirements . . ." (733 F.2d at 861).
41 In fact, in "Patents and the Progress of Science," Eisenberg explicitly recommends that "[r]esearch use of a
patented invention with a primary or significant market among research users should not be exempt from infringement
liability when the research user is an ordinary consumer of the patented invention."
42 See Eisenberg, "Patents and the Progress of Science."
43 The most notorious recent case involves patents on short snippets of genetic material, which, it is hoped, will one
day be identified as portions of larger, whole genes having commercial applications. See Rebecca Eisenberg, "Genes,
Patents, and Product Develop-
166 ROBERT P. MERGES
B. "Open-access absolutism": A policy to avoid
In pursuing the policy goals outlined above (as well as others intended to address the
same problem), I propose that we keep one important thought in mind: we must show
respect for the internal rules of the scientific community. This will take the form, primarily,
of refusing to adopt flat requirements that all federal scientific research, or even some
portion of it, be made instantaneously available to the general public, or even to all other
scientists. In other words, we must show an understanding that even if formal property
rights are prohibited, a set of norms in the scientific community will continue to regulate
access and related issues in ways that might be described as the imposition of certain
informal property rights. Where this is so, we must respect it. Instead of conceiving of
science as innately public, and therefore viewing any and all restrictions on public
availability as inherently wrong, we should ask why the community does things the way it
does. Some restrictions on dissemination-such as the prohibition on commercial use of
shared biological materials-may well be designed to add to the amount and quality of
science that is ultimately available to the public. Some practices, such as less-than-total
disclosure of research tools upon publication, might have important roots in the incentive
structure of individual scientists working in the context of the scientific community. (That
is, in order to develop a new tool in the first place, scientists might need an extra advantage
of exclusive use of a new research tool for some period beyond the first publication
generated by use of that tool.) In any case, we ought to see how the practice under scrutiny
evolved in the community, and how it affects the overall functioning of the community,
instead of bluntly requiring that science adhere to the naive baseline of total and immediate
public dissemination.
V. CONCLUSION
I have attempted to describe the emergence of a new set of practices, or norms, in the
scientific community. This community, which is undergoing a process of "creeping
propertization," has responded by adapting the informal norms that served it in the past to a
new regime, one characterized by the presence of strong, formal property rights. I have
argued that while science was never completely "open," and while "informal" property
rights were asserted and recognized even in the older, precommercial era, the advent of
formal rights has resulted in an uneasy, shifting configuration
————————
ment," Science, vol. 257, p. 903; Reid Adler, "Genome Research: Fulfilling the Public's Expectations for Knowledge
and Commercialization," Science, vol. 257 (1992), p. 908; Thomas Kiley, "Patents on Random Complementary DNA
Fragments?" Science, vol. 257 (1992), p. 915; and Bernadine Healy, "Special Report on Gene Patenting, New England
Journal of Medicine, vol. 327 (1992), p. 664.
PROPERTY RIGHTS THEORY AND THE COMMONS 167
best described as a two-tiered system of rights. In the realm of "pure" research, the older
practices involving "informal" property rights are still ascendant, though certain
accommodations have been made, based on the shared understanding that what is pure
today may have commercial potential tomorrow. In the main, in other words, there are
signs that the scientific commons has been defended from the onslaught of propertization,
at least for the time being. Dealings between pure researchers and those in the realm of
commercial research are conducted on a different basis, however. They are based more on
formal rights, and financial compensation (present or future) is an expected component of
the relationship. In this case, when members of the commons deal with outsiders,44 informal
rights give way to formal rights. It is an interesting feature of the scientific community that
its members can simultaneously maintain informal internal institutions for conducting
exchange, and also conduct market transactions with those who are not members of the
community.
I have also argued that the current accommodation may prove to be unstable, and that
in any event it would be wise to consider certain policies that reflect the dual nature of
contemporary science. In particular, I suggest giving some thought to proposals to
formalize an "experimental use" defense against charges of patent infringement, for pure
research scientists, and I suggest reconceiving the utility requirement in patent law to hold
the line on early patenting, and thus preserve the two-tiered structure scientists seem to be
converging on. These and other policy ideas are well worth considering when one takes into
account the enormous contributions made by science to social welfare in the past several
hundred years. It is also worth considering that the institutional and legal foundation on
which science rests plays an important part in bringing about these welfare gains, and that
any policy or practice that affects this foundation deserves as much attention as the content
of the scientific research itself.
Law, University of California, Berkeley
This essay was also published, without introduction and index, in the semiannual
journal Social Philosophy & Policy, Volume 13, Number 2, (1996).
44 The "outsiders" may also be members of the commons, only acting in a commercial capacity. It is typical in university
research circles for academic researchers to have commercial affiliations. I assume here that community members "role
differentiate" in their dealings with each other, that is, behave differently in a transaction with the same partner when
that partner is acting in a different role (e.g., commercial entity rather than academic colleague).
... Nor is it necessarily a trend that should be reversed. It is unrealistic to suggest that there should be no level of secrecy within university research, (Merges 1996) that no applied research is appropriate and that all commercialization in universities should cease. If one reads the numerous reviews conducted in this area, it is difficult to reject the proposition that some degree of commercialization offers positive benefits for universities, researchers and society. ...
... Or is it a genuine free-for-all, with open access common to all comers? Berkeley professor Robert Merges points out that many scientific advances occur among groups of scientists, who share information and methods among themselves while very much resisting the encroachment of outsiders-particularly outsiders who wish to monetize the scientists' work through exclusive intellectual property (Merges 1996). Others have argued that a kind of limited commons of group collaboration is at the heart of intellectual achievements more generally. ...
Article
Full-text available
This article explores current developments in theoretical thinking about the commons. It keys off contemporary reconsiderations of Garret Hardin’s “Tragedy of the Commons” and Elinor Ostrom’s response to Hardin in Governing the Commons and later work. Hardin’s idea of a “tragedy” has received much criticism, especially from Ostrom herself; but Ostrom’s own work has also raised some questions in more recent commons literature. The key issue that emerges from this reconsideration revolves around the understanding of commons on the one hand as limited common regimes, central to Ostrom’s work, or on the other hand as open access, as espoused by more recent advocates of widespread access to information and communications networks.
Chapter
The third chapter deals with a question that is usually considered philosophical; however, it is crucial for everyday life and the social determinations involving economics and politics. Among most schools of thought, the study of the being—ontology—has been widely regarded as a branch of metaphysics. Both the critique of political economy and the study of the social being have revealed that existence must not be considered from a metaphysical standpoint—thus rigid, abstract, eternal—but as a movement, a process, a constant transformation. Following this method, knowledge production must be understood as a product of two interchangeable movements. The first unveils the historical emergence of knowledge; the second exposes the existing contemporary conditions for its production and reproduction.
Chapter
This final chapter establishes a point of contact with the book’s findings connecting multiple dimensions, thus creating a single thread. The developed notion of totality does not have the pretension to exhaust the topic but simply to forego any claim imposing one-dimensionality into intellectual property as a sufficient condition for its understanding. While intellectual property theory has operated on the realm of metaphysics; in reality, knowledge is not something abstract, independent and metaphysical but a crucial dimension of material life and simultaneously a vital condition for its transformation. While metaphysical fetishism acritically endows validity to private appropriation of knowledge, the high stakes of knowledge production impose the need for an understanding beyond this simplistic worldview.
Chapter
Intellectual property law faces the challenge of balancing the interests of right holders and users in the face of technological change and inequalities in information access. Concepts of Property in Intellectual Property Law offers a collection of essays which reflect on the interaction between intellectual property and broader, more traditional, notions of property. It explores the way in which differing interpretations of the concept of property can affect the scope of protection in the law of copyright, patent, trade marks and confidential information. With contributions from leading and emerging scholars from a variety of jurisdictions, the book demonstrates how concepts of property can assist in shaping a conceptually coherent and balanced response to the challenges faced by intellectual property law.
Thesis
Dissertation zum patentrechtlichen Erfinderbegriff und KI
Article
The antecedents of the artists’ resale right (ARR) can be traced back to late 19th century France, the droit de suite, as it then was, was as much a welfare right as it was a response to the failures of the French droit d'Auteur system to adequately reward visual artist for their creative endeavours. Today, the success of the ARR may be attested to by its prominence in international law, however, this internationalisation has not brought with it uniformity. The European experience speaks to this; under the harmonisation framework of the Artists’ Resale Right Directive 2001/84, Member States are granted significant scope in its implementation and accordingly ARR models have come to pass which encompass a social security function reflective of the original French formulation. This article, by drawing on the social history of visual artists, and by considering the nature of the ARR and its predecessor the droit de suite, argues that socially orientated ARR models, which exist in Germany and Norway, represents a modern formulation of the droit de suite which more fully responds to the needs of visual artists today. KEYWORDS artists' resale right, copyright, droit de suite, social citizenship, social inclusion, visual artists, welfare
Article
Patents have been theorised as serving a multitude of different aims and functions since their inception. The role of patents is chameleon-like. At the same time, studies show that males are significantly more likely than females to be the inventors of patented inventions. A nascent but emphatic body of literature highlights that this is, in part, due to patent law itself being gendered. This article examines how gendered patenting and patent law have implications for the role of patents. It shows that the role of patents is not only a chameleon but a gendered chameleon.
Article
This article reports field research on Papua New Guinea's land courts, which decide property disputes in customary law. Customary law did not contemplate exchange of real property outside the kin group. Changing conditions have created an irresistible pressure for markets in land, which require extending law to encompass exchange with outsiders. The freehold solution is to give absolute, unitary ownership over land to individuals and end the kin group's role in resource allocation. Alternatively, the kin group can be reconstituted as a cooperative with ownership rights. If imposed by legislative fiat, either of these solutions will disrupt the customary economy by displacing its incentive system. A better solution allows custom to evolve and modernize itself through the common law process.
Article
An important research programme has developed in economics that extends neo-classical economic theory in order to examine the effects of institutions on economic behaviour. The body of work emerging from this line of inquiry includes contributions from various branches of economic theory, such as the economics of property rights, the theory of the firm, cliometrics and law and economics. This book is a comprehensive survey of this research programme which the author terms 'neoinstitutional economics'. The author proposes a unified approach to this research, integrating the work of various contributors and emphasising the common principles of inquiry that tie the work together. The theoretical discussion is accompanied by empirical studies dealing with a range of institutions and economic systems. This book will serve as the primary resource for economists and students who want to learn about this important branch of economic theory.
Book
Common property economics defines and clarifies the theoretical distinction between open access and common property and empirically tests the adequacy of resource allocation under common property and empirically tests the property in comparison with private property. Group use of natural resources has often received the blame for overexploitation and mismanagement, whether of fisheries, grazing land, oil and gas pools, groundwater, or wildlife. In this book two types of group use are identified: open access and utilization without any controls on extraction rates, a situation in which resource overexploitation often occurs. In contrast, common property refers to the situation where the group controls the access to and extraction rates of the resource. The common property solutions differ from those associated with open access. The nonoptimality of open access is demonstrated with graphic, game theoretic, and mathematical models. The necessary and sufficient conditions for common property to overcome the difficulties of open access are examined. Stevenson discusses historical examples, the basis in legal concepts, the contrast with public goods, the formation, and the stability of common property. In a detailed, empirical study of alpine grazing in Switzerland, the author compares the performance of common property with that of private property. He also notes the similarity in structure between the Swiss grazing commons and the English open field system.