ArticlePDF Available

Abstract

In this paper I argue that the concept of emotional intelligence (EI) is invalid both because it is not a form of intelligence and because it is defined so broadly and inclusively that it has no intelligible meaning. I distinguish the so-called concept of EI from actual intelligence and from rationality. I identify the actual relation between reason and emotion. I reveal the fundamental inadequacy of the concept of EI when applied to leadership. Finally, I suggest some alternatives to the EI concept. Copyright © 2005 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.
Why Emotional Intelligence Is an Invalid Concept
by Edwin A. Locke
University of Maryland
1
2
Abstract
In this paper I argue that the concept of emotional intelligence (EI) in invalid both
because it is not a form of intelligence and because it is defined so broadly and
inclusively that it has no intelligible meaning. I distinguish the so called concept of
emotional intelligence from actual intelligence and from rationality. I identify the actual
relation between reason and emotion. I reveal the fundamental inadequacy of the concept
of EI when applied to leadership. Finally, I suggest some alternatives to the EI concept.
3
Why Emotional Intelligence Is an Invalid Concept
The concept of intelligence refers to one’s ability to form and grasp concepts,
especially higher level or more abstract concepts. The observations on which the concept
of intelligence is formed are that some people are simply able to “get” things better than
others, that is, they are able to make connections, see implications, reason deductively
and inductively, grasp complexity, understand the meaning of ideas, etc. better than other
people. Motivation obviously plays a role in understanding concepts and can partly
compensate for low ability, but even highly motivated people differ in intellectual ability.
Those who are better able to grasp higher level concepts are better able to handle
complex tasks and jobs.
Intelligence must be clearly distinguished from rationality. Whereas intelligence
refers to one’s capacity to grasp abstractions, rationality refers to how one actually uses
one’s mind. A rational individual takes facts seriously and uses thinking and logic to
reach conclusions. A person can be very intelligent and yet very irrational (cf. many
modern philosophers; Ghate & Locke, 2003). For example, a person’s thinking may be
dominated by emotions, and they may not distinguish between what they feel and what
they can demonstrate to be true.
The concept of emotional intelligence (EI) was introduced by Salovey and Mayer
(1990), although related ideas such as “social intelligence” had been introduced by earlier
writers—originally by E.L. Thorndike. Salovey and Mayer (1990, p. 189) defined
emotional intelligence as, “the ability to monitor one’s own and others’ feelings and
emotions, to discriminate among them and to use this information to guide one’s thinking
4
and actions.” (Note: definitions of EI are constantly changing, an issue I will return to
later).There are several problems with this definition. First, the ability to monitor one’s
emotions does not require any special degree or type of intelligence. Monitoring one’s
emotions is basically a matter of where one chooses to focus one’s attention, outwards at
the external world or inward at the contents and processes of one’s own consciousness.
(This claim obviously implies that people have volitional control over focusing their
minds. For a detailed discussion and defense of claim that people possess volition or free
will, see Binswanger, 1991, and Peikoff, 1991.) Focusing inwards involves introspection.
Similarly, the ability to read the emotions of others is not necessarily an issue of
intelligence. It could simply be a matter of paying attention to others and being aware of
one’s own emotions so that one can empathize with others. For example, if one is
unaware, due to defensiveness, that one can feel fear, one will not be able to empathize
with fear in others.
Second, discriminating between emotions is a learned skill just as is detecting a
given emotion. A highly intelligent person may be better able to make very subtle
distinctions between similar emotions (e.g., jealousy and envy), but, for basic emotions
(e.g., love, anger, fear, desire), it just a matter of focusing inwards so as to develop one’s
introspective skill.
Third, whether one uses one’s knowledge in everyday action is not an issue of
intelligence per se. Many factors may come into play here. Among them are rationality
(vs. emotionalism), being in (vs. out of) focus, integrity (including courage in the face of
opposition), and the nature of one’s purpose. In sum, the definition of EI indicates that it
5
is really some combination of assorted habits, skills and/or choices rather than an issue of
intelligence.
It is simply arbitrary to attach the word intelligence to assorted habits or skills, as
Howard Gardner and EI advocates do, on the alleged grounds that there are multiple
types of intelligences. This extension of the term simply destroys the meaning of the
concept—which, in fact, is the hidden agenda of the advocates of multiple intelligences.
The ultimate motive is egalitarianism: redefining what it means to be intelligent so that
everyone will, in some from, be equal in intelligence to everyone else. The agenda here is
not scientific but political. However, arbitrary redefinitions do not change reality. Some
people actually are more intelligent, in terms of their ability to grasp concepts, than
others, but this ability is not necessarily reflected in every skill that people choose to
develop. If one wants to group a set of related phenomena into a single concept, there
must be a conceptually identified, common element among them. Otherwise, the concept
has no clear meaning.
As another case in point, consider how Salovey and Mayer, in the same article
cited above, (1990, p. 190) expand their conceptualization of emotional intelligence. It is
said to include: the appraisal and expression of emotions in the self, both verbal and non-
verbal; the appraisal and identification of emotions in others through non-verbal
identification and empathy; the regulation of emotions in oneself and in others; and the
utilization of emotions so as to engage in flexible planning, creative thinking, direction of
attention and motivation.
Observe that the concept of EI has now become so broad and the components so
variegated that no one concept could possible encompass or integrate all of them no
6
matter what the concept was called; it is no longer even an intelligible concept. What is
the common or integrating element in a concept that includes: introspection about
emotions, emotional expression, non-verbal communication with others, empathy, self-
regulation, planning, creative thinking and the direction of attention? There is none.
Following Salovey and Mayer, Daniel Goleman (1994) popularized the concept
of EI. According to Goleman, EI involves: self-motivation and persistence; skill at
introspection; delay of gratification; self-control of impulses, moods and emotions;
empathy; and social skills (the ability to make friends). These elements overlap
considerably with those of Salovey and Mayer and are equally un-integratible by means
of a single concept. Most of the actions involved actually require the use of reason.
To add to the confusion, in another article, Mayer (1999, p. 50) defines emotional
intelligence as, “the capacity to reason with emotion in four areas: to perceive emotion, to
integrate it in thought, to understand it and to manage it.” The fundamental problem here
is that one cannot “reason with emotion.” This is a contradiction in terms. Reason and
emotion are two very different cognitive processes, and they perform very different
psychological functions. To reason means to observe reality starting with the material
provided by the senses, to integrate, without contradiction, sensory material into concepts
and concepts into principles. Reason is the means of gaining and validating one’s
knowledge. It is a volitional process guided by the conscious mind.
In contrast, emotions entail an automatic process based on subconsciously held
knowledge and values. Emotions reflect one’s stored beliefs about objects, people or
situations and one’s subconscious appraisal of them based on one’s values. Emotions are
the form in which one experiences automatized value judgments (Peikoff, 1991). Every
7
emotion reflects a specific type of value judgment. For example, fear is the automatic
response to the judgment of a physical threat. Anger is the response to the judgment that
a wrong has been done to you or valued others. Joy is the result of having achieved some
important value. Desire results from appraising some object that one does not possess or
some person who one does not yet have a relationship with as a positive value.
Because emotions are automatic and based on subconsciously stored beliefs and
values, they cannot be assumed to be valid assessments of reality. One’s beliefs might be
wrong; one’s values might be irrational. Emotions—automatic productions of the
subconscious mind-- are not tools of knowledge. The psychological function of emotions
is not to know the world but to make automatic evaluations and motivate action.
Emotions contain, as part of the experience, felt action tendencies. Positive emotions
entail the felt tendency to approach, possess or retain the appraised object; negative
emotions entail the felt tendency to flee, harm or destroy the appraised object. This does
not mean, however, that emotions have to be acted on. Through the power of reason we
can decide whether action in a given case is appropriate or not, and if appropriate, what
action is most suitable given the total situation.
One cannot, therefore, “reason with emotion;” one can only reason about it. It is
through reason that one identifies what emotion one is experiencing, discovers the beliefs
and values that gave rise to it, and decides what action, if any, to take on the face of it. It
is also through reason, which, as noted earlier, is an active, volitional process, that one
determines whether the beliefs behind an emotion are valid and if the values that underlie
it are rational. Reason also enables one to re-program the subconscious so that the
automatized appraisals (beliefs, values) that give rise to specific emotions are changed.
8
Further, reason is used to identify defense mechanisms which may distort or prevent one
from experiencing emotions, and thus stultify their motivating power.
Reason is also the key to self-regulation, not only of one’s emotions in the sense
described above, but also of one’s life in general. Regulating one’s life requires being
purposeful, which means setting long range goals and identifying plans which will enable
one to achieve them.. This process is not divorced from emotions, since one has to
identify what one wants (e.g., in one’s career, in romance) before setting a goal to pursue
it, but reason must be used to identify one’s desires and insure that they are rational if one
is to achieve one’s long range goals. In short, reason, the volitional, active part of one’s
mind, has to be in charge or one is left at the mercy of the emotions of the moment.
Some EI advocates might agree with all this and argue that EI, despite the
definitions usually given, really means being intelligent about emotions, that is,
recognizing their nature and proper function, their relationship to reason, and the need for
introspection. If this is what EI advocates mean by their concept, then what they are
actually referring to is not another form or type of intelligence but intelligence (the ability
to grasp abstractions) applied to a particular life domain: emotions. Intelligence, of
course, can be applied to any of thousands of life domains, but it does not follow that
there are thousands of types of intelligences. If we want to talk about how well a person
has mastered a certain domain, we already have a word for it: skill.
There is one more aspect to the EI story. In a later book, Primal Leadership,
Goleman, Boyatzis and McKee (2002) take EI theory a step further, into the realm of
leadership. Effective leadership traits which they claim to be based on EI include:
oObjective self-assessment
9
oSelf-confidence and self-esteem
oMoral character (e.g., honesty and integrity)
oAdaptability and flexibility
oAchievement motivation
oInitiative and self-efficacy
oOrganizational awareness (e.g., of organizational politics)
oCustomer service
oThe use of persuasion tactics
oDeveloping the ability of followers
oInitiating change
oConflict management
oTeam building
oThe use of humor
Goleman et al. (2002) also argue that EI includes the use any or all of the six
following leadership styles:
oVisionary
oCoaching
oAffiliative
oDemocratic
oPacesetting
oCommanding
The question one must ask here is, given that leadership based on EI allegedly
10
encompasses such a long list of characteristics that people have associated with effective
leadership, what does EI not include? One thing is missing from the list: actual
intelligence!
In addition to making the concept of EI-leadership preposterously all-
encompassing, Goleman et al. (2002, p. ix) seriously misconstrue what organizational
leadership involves. They claim that “The fundamental task of leaders is to create good
feelings in those they lead.” This is simply not true. The function of organizations is to
attain goals; in the case of private organizations the goal is long-term profitability.
Organizations, other than psychotherapy clinics, are not in the “feel good” business.
Employee morale is important, but as a means to an end not as an end in itself divorced
from effectiveness.
It ironic that Goleman et al’s EI approach to leadership, despite its long list of
elements, omits any discussion of the intellectual aspects of leadership—aspects which
are critical to organizational success, including business success. These aspects require
the leaders of profit-making organizations to focus not inwards but outwards, at the
business environment. For example, does the leader know or understand:
Where the company should be heading?
The role of the different corporate functions?
The big picture? (Is there an integrating vision?)
How to fit the different parts and processes of the organization
together?
The strategic and technological environments?
How to attain a competitive advantage?
11
How to achieve cash flow?
How to prioritize?
How to balance the short term with the long term?
How to judge talent when hiring and promoting?
How to build a culture?
How to formulate and enforce core values?
Note that performing these very complex tasks requires, among other qualities,
actual intelligence. Making oneself or other people feel good will not substitute for
intellectual deficiencies. Good leadership requires consistent rational thinking by a mind
that is able to grasp and integrate all the facts needed to make the business succeed.
Michael Dell (1999, p. 206) makes an important observation regarding the
relation of emotions and knowledge,
there are countless successful companies that are thriving now despite the fact that
they started with little more than passion and a good idea. There are also many
that failed, for the very same reason. The difference is that the thriving companies
gathered the knowledge that gave them a substantial edge over their competition,
which they used to improve their execution….those that didn’t simply didn’t
make it.
Leadership is not primarily about making people feel good; it’s about knowing
what you are doing and knowing what to do.
Conclusion
Despite the insuperable problems with the various definitions of emotional;
intelligence, there is no denying the importance of one element of EI in human life:
12
introspection. Introspection is a very important human skill; it involves identifying the
contents and processes of one’s own mind. It is only through introspection that one can
monitor such things one’s degree of focus, one’s defensive reactions and one’s emotional
responses and their causes. Such monitoring has important implications for self-esteem
and mental health.
Given their emphasis on introspection, it is ironic that advocates of EI show
virtually no understanding of the actual nature of emotions. For example, while granting
that emotions entail impulses to action, Goleman’ s (1995), discussion of their causes is
confined almost entirely to neurophysiology, especially brain structure. But psychology
cannot be reduced to neurophysiology (Bandura, 1997); ideas do not have the same
attributes as neurons. Especially unfortunate—and mistaken (see Peikoff, 1991)-- is his
claim that, like a Frankenstein monster, we have an innate mind-body dichotomy, two
clashing brains, one rational and one emotional. This is reminiscent of Freud’s arbitrary
division of the personality into opposing parts (id, ego and superego)—a notion which
originated with Plato.
What is the error here? If EI advocates actually used introspection themselves,
they would observe that emotions, as noted earlier, are the product of subconscious ideas
—stored knowledge about the objects and automatic value appraisals based on that
knowledge. Thus there is no inherent clash between reason and emotion (Peikoff, 1991).
As noted, it is through reason that we are able to acquire the knowledge and the values
which cause our emotions. It is through reason that we can identify and, through
reprogramming, change our emotions. It is through reason that we have the power to
decide whether and how to act in the face of emotions. Emotions obviously have a
13
neurophysiological aspect, but brain structure does not determine the content of our
knowledge nor of our values. Nor does it determine whether and how we use our reason,
since reasoning is a volitional process (Binswanger, 1991).
EI’s extension into the field of leadership is even more unfortunate. By asserting
that leadership is an emotional process, Goleman denigrates the very critical role played
by rational thinking and actual intelligence in the leadership process. Given all the add-
ons to the concept proposed by Goleman et al (2002), any associations between
leadership effectives and an EI scale that included these add-ons would be meaningless.
What, then, are we to conclude about EI?
1. The definition of the concept is constantly changing;
2. Most definitions are so all-inclusive as to make the concept unintelligible.
3. One definition (e.g., reasoning with emotion) involves a contradiction.
4. There is no such thing as actual emotional intelligence, although intelligence can be
applied to emotions as well as to other life domains.
A more productive approach to the EI concept might be to replace it with the
concept of introspective skill. (This would be a prerequisite to emotional self-regulation).
Alternatively, it might be asked whether EI could be relabeled and redefined as a
personality trait. Possibly, providing it was (re)defined intelligibly and that it was
differentiated from skills and from traits that have already been identified (e.g., empathy).
However, it is not at all clear at this point what such a trait would be called.
Ayn Rand (1975, p. 77) stated that, “Definitions are the guardians of rationality,
the first line of defense against the chaos of mental disintegration.” With respect to the
14
concept of EI, not to mention many other concept in psychology and management
(Locke, 2003), we are more in need of rational guardians that ever.
15
References
Bandura, A. (1997) Self-efficacy: The exercise of control. New York: Freeman.
Binswanger (1991) Volition as cognitive self-regulation. Organizational Behavior &
Human Decision Processes, 50, 154-178.
Dell, M. (1999) Direct from Dell. New York: Harper Business.
Ghate, O. & Locke, E. (2003) Objectivism: The proper alternative to postmodernism.
In E. Locke (Ed.) Postmodernism and management: Pros, cons and the
alternative. Research in the Sociology of Organizations, Vol. 12, Amsterdam, JAI
(Elsevier Science Ltd.)
Goleman, D. (1995) Emotional intelligence. New York: Bantam.
Goleman, D., Boyatzis, R. & McKee, A. (2002) Primal leadership. Boston: Harvard
Business School Press.
Locke, E. (2003) Good definitions: The epistemological foundation of scientific
progress. In J. Greenberg (Ed.) Organizational behavior: The state of the science.
Mahwah, NJ: L. Erlbaum.
Mayer, J. (1999) Emotional intelligence: popular or scientific psychology? APA Monitor,
September, p. 50.
Peikoff, L. (1991) Objectivism: The philosophy of Ayn Rand. New York: Dutton.
Rand, A, (1975) The romantic manifesto. New York: Signet.
Salovey, P. & Mayer, J. (1990) Emotional intelligence. Imagination, Cognition and
Personality, 9, 185-211.
16
17
... The diversified development of measurement tools was rapidly developed at this stage (O'Connor et al., 2019). However, some critics pointed out that overly diverse definitions and characteristics might limit the development of EI, as an allinclusive approach to development could lead to confusion and misunderstandings among scholars (Locke, 2005;Mayer et al., 2008aMayer et al., , 2008b. The fourth stage is the Integration and Application phase (from the 2010s to 2020s), which saw the foundations of the EI concept become more solid after 20 years of knowledge accumulation (Kotsou et al., 2019). ...
... This proportion is much lower than findings in other fields, as review articles generally tend to have a higher impact (Hallinger & Kovačević, 2019). The scarcity of review articles reflects the fragmentation and immaturity of research on educators' EI, which is consistent with the opinions of some commentary articles (Locke, 2005;Mayer et al., 2008a, b). They pointed out that there was a lack of consensus among scholars in the EI field, with multiple different models and definitions, and the use of inconsistent methods to assess EI. ...
... They pointed out that there was a lack of consensus among scholars in the EI field, with multiple different models and definitions, and the use of inconsistent methods to assess EI. Consequently, critics sharply questioned the scientific validity and innovation of this concept (Locke, 2005). As a result, proper reviews were necessary for making the research on educators' EI more cumulative and systematic, which exactly is the significance of this bibliometric review. ...
Article
Full-text available
This study conducted a bibliometric analysis of 525 journal articles on educators’ emotional intelligence research from 1998 to 2024, guided by both a four-dimensional framework and Job Demands-Resources theory. The study employed multiple bibliometric techniques including citation analysis, co-citation analysis, co-authorship analysis, co-occurrence analysis, and bibliographic coupling to map the intellectual landscape of this field. Through the four-dimensional lens, the analysis revealed temporal patterns of steady growth, spatial characteristics of broad geographical distribution yet limited collaboration, and compositional evolution from foundational concepts to contextualized applications. The Job Demands-Resources perspective further illuminated how educators’ emotional intelligence functions as a crucial personal resource in managing professional demands, particularly in emerging areas such as digital leadership, resilience, and creative performance. The synthesis through these complementary theoretical frameworks provides a systematic understanding of the field’s development, knowledge structure, and theoretical foundations. This integrated analysis also identifies critical directions for future research and practice in educational settings across different cultural contexts.
... Meta-analyses such as Van Rooy and Viswesvaran (2004) and later those by O' Boyle et al. (2011) have helped synthesize large bodies of inconsistent findings, offering more precise estimates of EI's predictive value. Locke (2005). Despite EI's popularity, critics argue that it lacks discriminant validity. ...
... Despite EI's popularity, critics argue that it lacks discriminant validity. Locke (2005) labeled EI an "invalid concept" unless clearly defined and separated from personality and intelligence constructs. Sy et al. (2006). ...
Article
Full-text available
This paper reviews the influential meta-analysis by Van Rooy and Viswesvaran (2004), which systematically examined the predictive validity and nomological net of emotional intelligence (EI). The study aimed to clarify the conceptual status of emotional intelligence (EI) in psychological literature by analyzing its relationship with cognitive intelligence, personality, and job performance. Using data from 69 studies involving over 7,000 participants, the authors found moderate correlations between emotional intelligence (EI) and both cognitive ability and personality traits. More importantly, EI showed incremental validity in predicting job performance beyond these traditional constructs. This review summarizes their methodology, key findings, and implications, and discusses the study’s relevance in the context of ongoing debates on EI's theoretical foundation and practical applications.
... • (Locke, 2005;Waterhouse, 2006). Kritici (Schultz & Roberts, 2002) spochybňovali taktiež vedeckú validitu niektorých modelov, pričom poukazovali na prekrývanie konceptu už s existujúcimi konštruktmi (napr. ...
... Hoci model schopností získal empirickú podporu a je považovaný za jeden z najvplyvnejších prístupov k emočnej inteligencii, čelí aj kritike. Niektorí autori spochybňujú, či je emočná inteligencia skutočne formou inteligencie a či spĺňa tradičné kritériá pre inteligenciu, ktorými sú predovšetkým obsahová a ekologická validita (Locke, 2005). Kritici argumentujú najmä tým, že úlohy obsiahnuté vo výkonovo orientovaných testoch emočnej inteligencie nemusia dostatočne zachytávať to, akými emočnými schopnosťami disponujú konkrétni jednotlivci v podmienkach reálneho života. ...
Book
Full-text available
V publikácii sa prelínajú témy sledujúce emočnú reguláciu v súvislostiach so psychopatológiou, zvládaním, emočnou inteligenciou, socializáciou emócií či psychickou pohodou, s témami, ktoré sa viac koncentrujú na tvorbu a overovanie existujúcich či nových nástrojov na meranie emočnej flexibility. Špecifické postavenie má posledná kapitola, v ktorej je predstavený novovytváraný autorský test riešiteľov projektu zameraný na meranie flexibility stratégií regulácie emócií nesúci názov Situačný test emočnej flexibility (STEF.02).
... Empirically, they show a small association-meta-analytic ρ = 0.12 (Joseph & Newman, 2010), likely because self-efficacy beliefs are based partly on actual capacities. As such, researchers have argued that using the term 'emotional intelligence' for both constructs represents a jingle fallacy (assuming that two things are the same because they share the same label; Bucich & MacCann, 2019;Landy, 2005;Locke, 2005). In fact, empirical evidence robustly demonstrates that self-rated and ability EI differ. ...
Article
Full-text available
Emotionally intelligent people tend to have higher wellbeing. It is possible that their high emotional intelligence (EI) also affects the wellbeing of the people they interact with. This is particularly true in romantic relationships, where a person’s EI may play an important role in their partner’s emotional experiences. The current study (N = 407 romantic dyads) uses actor-partner interdependence models to examine the associations between EI (ability and self-rated) and wellbeing (psychological wellbeing, life satisfaction, affect). Self-rated EI showed consistent actor effects on all wellbeing variables with relatively large effects. Actor effects for ability EI were much smaller and inconsistent for men versus women. Partner effects were largely significant for self-rated, but not ability EI. The results suggest that romantic partners’ self-rated EI impacts some aspects of wellbeing. Findings are discussed in terms of the distinction between emotional abilities (ability EI) and self-beliefs (self-rated EI), including implications for couples counselling.
... Emotional intelligence (EI) concerns how well people reason about emotions and emotional information Mayer and Salovey, 1997). From this perspective, emotions do not disrupt intellect as many believed (Young, 1936;Shaffer et al., 1940;Locke, 2005), but rather serve as signal systems that convey important information: for example, fear signals threat, happiness signals wishes fulfilled. Each emotion conveys a meaning (Plutchik, 2001). ...
Article
Full-text available
Introduction The model of emotional intelligence as an ability has evolved since its introduction 35 years ago. The revised model includes that emotional intelligence (EI) is a broad intelligence within the Cattell-Horn-Carroll (CHC) model of intelligence, and that more areas of problem solving are involved than originally detailed. An argument is made here that veridical scoring of EI test responses is a sound procedure relative to scoring keys based on expert consensus or a single emotion theory. To the degree that EI fits present-day theories of intelligence (i.e., the CHC model), any subsidiary factors of EI reasoning should correlate highly with one another. These and other considerations led to a revision of the original Mayer-Salovey-Caruso Emotional Intelligence Test (MSCEIT) to the MSCEIT 2. Methods The MSCEIT 2 was developed and tested across 5 studies: Two preliminary studies concerned, first, the viability of new item sets (Study 1, N = 43) and, in Study 2 (N = 8), the development of a veridical scoring key for each test item with the assistance of Ph.D. area experts. Next, a pilot study (Study 3, N = 523) and a normative study (Study 4, N = 3,000) each focused on the test’s item performance and factor structure, including whether a four-domain model continued to fit the data in a manner consistent with a cohesive broad intelligence. Study 5 (N = 221) examined the relation between the original and revised tests. Results The studies provide evidence for factor-supported subscale scores, and good reliability at the overall test level, with acceptable reliabilities for 3 of the 4 subscale scores, and adequate measurement precision across the range of most test-takers’ abilities. Discussion Overall, the MSCEIT 2 used updated theory to guide its construction and development. Its test scores fit the CHC model, and correlate with the original MSCEIT. The revised test is 33% shorter than the original.
... Critics argue EQ and SQ lack construct validity compared to the established psychometric rigor surrounding IQ testing (Locke, 2005). However, growing evidence supports EQ and SQ as distinct intelligences that uniquely predict occupational outcomes beyond IQ (Khalili, 2012). ...
Article
Full-text available
Purpose – This paper investigates how intellectual quotient (IQ), emotional quotient (EQ), and spiritual quotient (SQ) influence workplace behaviors and outcomes. Historically research concentrated on IQ, but now recognizes intelligence as multidimensional. Beyond IQ, EQ involves emotional skills, while SQ relates to finding meaning.Methodology/approach – The systematic review follows PRISMA guidelines. Multiple databases were searched for relevant studies published between 2021-2022. Studies were screened based on predefined eligibility criteria. Data was extracted using a standardized form and analyzed through a narrative synthesis approach focused on patterns regarding the comparative and combined effects of IQ, EQ and SQ on work factors.Findings – IQ strongly predicted technical proficiency but had limits in interpersonal contexts. EQ uniquely improved leadership, teamwork, stress management, and customer service. SQ enhanced motivation, ethics, resilience, and well-being. Combined, IQ, EQ, and SQ synergistically optimized achievement, conduct, adaptation, and satisfaction across diverse occupational roles.Novelty/value – This review provides a comprehensive, up-to-date synthesis of empirical evidence demonstrating the multidimensional impacts of IQ, EQ, and SQ on workplace effectiveness. The insights can guide employee selection, training, and management practices focused on cultivating intellectual, emotional, and spiritual competencies in balance
... EI, as described by Mayer and Salovey [19], encompasses inter-individual differences in the recognition, understanding, expression, regulation, and utilization of one's own emotions and the emotions of others. The concept of EI has historically been subject to criticism and debate, particularly regarding two contrasting perspectives: the ability-based approach and the personality-based approach [19][20][21][22][23]. The ability model, derived from the original framework by Salovey and Mayer, conceptualizes EI as a cognitive ability closely linked to Competitive sport is a context known for its high emotional intensity, where emotions serve as signals of the significance of the situation [1][2][3][4]. ...
Article
Full-text available
Emotional intelligence (EI) is a determinant of athletic performance. Since each sport has its own psychological requirements, individual EI dimensions could have different relevance for athletic performance. This study investigated EI variations among athletes participating in 48 different sports, considering the specific emotional challenges faced by athletes in competitive sports using the appraisal theory of emotions. A total of 605 athletes (44.3% female) actively engaged in competitive sports completed the Trait Emotional Intelligence Questionnaire via an online survey. Analyses of variance, controlling for age and gender, revealed no overall link between EI and different sports. However, the dimension of self-control within EI demonstrated significant relevance among athletes in contact sports, sports with a higher degree of control over environmental conditions, and sports with direct referee intervention. On the other hand, the dimension of well-being within EI exhibited significant relevance for athletes in individual sports. Thus, this study suggests that investigating appraisal processes in athletes’ emotional experiences, particularly focusing on the self-control dimension of EI, useful for future research in the field of EI.
... Por ejemplo, Waterhouse (2006a) ha criticado la inteligencia emocional por las pocas evidencias empíricas y los deficientes estudios basados en las ciencias neurocognitivas, generando aún mayores cuestionamientos sobre por qué esta teoría es trascendental en los establecimientos educativos si no ha sido comprobada de manera científica (Manrique, 2015;Waterhouse, 2006b). Frente a su construcción teórica, Locke (2005) afirma que tener habilidades emocionales es hacer uso de una cantidad de recursos que no necesariamente están relacionados con la inteligencia; además, este concepto se podría interpretar como una superposición intelectualista de lo afectivo, es decir, que muestran mayor relevancia al conocimiento que se adquiere de la razón y las experiencias, y no tanto de las emociones. ...
Article
Full-text available
Las teorías pioneras sobre la inteligencia emocional, las habilidades socioemocionales y el aprendizaje socioemocional han presentado problemas conceptuales, tales como: la falta de consenso entre los autores sobre la definición de habilidades, competencias y lo socioemocional; el uso impreciso de términos como capacidades, habilidades y competencias; las críticas a la inteligencia emocional como base teórica de las habilidades socioemocionales; y, finalmente, la escasez de estudios empíricos que les otorguen soporte. Por lo tanto, se propone un modelo de capacidades socioemocionales que busca superar estas limitaciones al estar fundamentado en teorías que abordan lo social, lo emocional, lo socioemocional, las capacidades, habilidades y competencias. El texto concluye con una propuesta clara sobre qué se debe entender por capacidades socioemocionales.
... Regarding the first issue, EI does not yet have a unanimous definition, and the debate over the use of the term "intelligence" is still open [5,6]. Therefore, it would be more important to focus on the point of agreement within the scientific debate, namely, the importance for the individual to acquire socioemotional competencies [7,8]. ...
Article
Full-text available
Given the importance of social–emotional skills in fostering highly prosocial behaviors and the increasing frequency by which relationships are established and maintained in cyberspace, several studies have been conducted focusing on the role of social-emotional skills developed in the online environment. However, the instruments developed to date have mainly considered “face-to-face” interactions, without considering the unique features of the virtual environment. The purpose of the present study was to validate the Italian translation of the Socio-Emotional e-Competencies Questionnaire. This instrument has been constructed to assess the knowledge, skills, and attitudes necessary to understand and manage emotions in the online environment for fostering positive relationships (e-competencies (e-COM)). The final sample consisted of 1096 adults (53.0% men) aged between 18 and 73 years. Factor analyses confirmed the original five-factor structure, which showed excellent fit indices (i.e., root mean square error of approximation (RMSEA), Tucker–Lewis index (TLI), and comparative fit index (CFI)). Correlation analyses with other instruments related to social–emotional competence (i.e., E-motions Questionnaire, Brief Emotional Intelligence Scale, and Difficulties in Emotion Regulation Scales) confirmed the convergent validity of the scale. Gender differences were also explored, in which women scored higher than men in all dimensions of e-COM except for emotional e-independence. Overall, this study demonstrated that the Italian version of e-COM is a reliable and valid tool for measuring social-emotional competence in a virtual context.
... Despite some researchers critiquing the theory of EI (Daus and Ashkanasy, 2003;Locke, 2005;Matthews et al., 2006;O'Connor et al., 2019), there are numerous reasons explaining the widespread adoption of EI in the business realm. Many scholars back and confirm the significance of EI in achieving individual and workplace success (Joseph and Newman, 2010;Urquijo, Extremera, and Azanza, 2019). ...
Article
Full-text available
This article presents a framework for emotional intelligence, a set of skills hypothesized to contribute to the accurate appraisal and expression of emotion in oneself and in others, the effective regulation of emotion in self and others, and the use of feelings to motivate, plan, and achieve in one's life. We start by reviewing the debate about the adaptive versus maladaptive qualities of emotion. We then explore the literature on intelligence, and especially social intelligence, to examine the place of emotion in traditional intelligence conceptions. A framework for integrating the research on emotion-related skills is then described. Next, we review the components of emotional intelligence. To conclude the review, the role of emotional intelligence in mental health is discussed and avenues for further investigation are suggested.
Article
Full-text available
Self-control theories have focused on various aspects of the processes involved in exerting self-control. In the present paper, we intend to add to this literature by demonstrating that exerting self-control leads one to narrow one's attention and cognition, inducing a narrow mindset. We demonstrate this in three studies. Participants who exerted self-control applied a narrower view (Study 1), applied a narrower categorization (Study 2), and used more concrete language (Study 3) than participants who did not exert self-control. Results are discussed in light of the possibility that a narrow mindset enhances performance on the self-control task at hand at the cost of poorer performance on other tasks.
Article
Emotional intelligence is a type of social intelligence that involves the ability to monitor one's own and others' emotions, to discriminate among them, and to use the information to guide one's thinking and actions (Salovey & Mayer, 1990). We discuss (a) whether intelligence is an appropriate metaphor for the construct, and (b) the abilities and mechanisms that may underlie emotional intelligence. © 1993.
Article
You must attach clear, specific meanings to words, i.e. be able to identify their referents in reality…. All philosophical con games count on your using words as vague approximations. You must not take a catch phrase – or any abstract statement – as if it were approximate. Take it literally. Don’t translate it, don’t glamorize it, don’t make the mistake of thinking, as many people do: “Oh, nobody could possibly mean this!” and then proceed to endow it with some whitewashed meaning of your own. Take it straight, for what it does say and mean. Instead of dismissing the catch phrase, accept it – for a few brief moments. Tell yourself, in effect: “If I were to accept it as true, what would follow?” This is the best way of unmasking any philosophical fraud…. To take ideas seriously means that you intend to live by, to practice, any idea you accept as true. Philosophy provides man with a comprehensive view of life. In order to evaluate it properly, ask yourself what a given theory, if accepted, would do to a human life, starting with your own (Rand, 1982, p. 16).We begin this chapter by taking Ayn Rand’s advice. We project – by means of a fictional story – what it would be like for a businessman to accept and live by the philosophy of postmodernism.
Article
Living organisms exhibit various levels of self-regulation, the highest of which is man's ability to regulate the operation of his conceptual faculty. Ayn Rand's theory of free will, the basis of this article, identifies this level of self-regulation with volition. The locus of direct volitional choice is placed in the choice “to think or not to think,” where thinking is understood as rational, purposefully directed cognition. The nature of this choice is analyzed in detail, with special emphasis on Rand's concept of mental “focus.” The epistemological status of the theory is discussed, including the role of introspective evidence in its behalf. It is argued that one's volitional control over one's own thinking has the status of an axiom, and that any attempted denial of this control is self-refuting.
Emotional intelligence: popular or scientific psychology? APA Monitor Objectivism: The philosophy of Ayn Rand
  • J Mayer
  • L Peikoff
Mayer, J. (1999). Emotional intelligence: popular or scientific psychology? APA Monitor, 30, 50. Peikoff, L. (1991). Objectivism: The philosophy of Ayn Rand. New York: Dutton.