Content uploaded by Thomas Nadelhoffer
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Thomas Nadelhoffer on Mar 28, 2014
Content may be subject to copyright.
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
Philosophical Psychology
Vol. 18, No. 5, October 2005, pp. 561–584
Surveying Freedom: Folk Intuitions
about Free Will and Moral
Responsibility
Eddy Nahmias, Stephen Morris, Thomas Nadelhoffer,
and Jason Turner
1
Philosophers working in the nascent field of ‘experimental philosophy’ have begun using
methods borrowed from psychology to collect data about folk intuitions concerning
debates ranging from action theory to ethics to epistemology. In this paper we present the
results of our attempts to apply this approach to the free will debate, in which
philosophers on opposing sides claim that their view best accounts for and accords with
folk intuitions. After discussing the motivation for such research, we describe our
methodology of surveying people’s prephilosophical judgments about the freedom and
responsibility of agents in deterministic scenarios. In two studies, we found that a
majority of participants judged that such agents act of their own free will and are morally
responsible for their actions. We then discuss the philosophical implications of our results
as well as various difficulties inherent in such research.
Keywords: Free Will; Moral Responsibility; Folk Psychology; Experimental Philosophy
1. Introduction: Motivating the Project of Testing Folk Intuitions
I am sometimes asked—in a tone that suggests the question is a major objection—
why, if conceptual analysis is concerned to elucidate what governs our classificatory
practice, don’t I advocate doing serious opinion polls on people’s responses to
various cases? My answer is that I do—when it is necessary. (Jackson, 1998, p. 37)
Philosophers disagree about the proper role that folk concepts, common sense, and
prephilosophical intuitions should play in shaping our philosophical ideas
Correspondence to: Eddy Nahmias, Department of Philosophy, Georgia State University, Atlanta, GA 30302-
4089, USA. Email: enahmias@gsu.edu
ISSN 0951-5089 (print)/ISSN 1465-394X (online)/05/050561-24 ß2005 Taylor & Francis
DOI: 10.1080/09515080500264180
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
and theories. Whereas some have dismissively viewed the beliefs and intuitions of
non-philosophers with either suspicion or scorn, others have attempted to refute
speculative philosophical theories—such as skepticism or idealism—by appealing
to what they take to be our commonsense intuitions.
2
Such intuitions play a
conspicuous role in the free will debate, where philosophers often motivate their
position by claiming that it is commonsensical, fits with ordinary intuitions, accounts
for our practices of attributing moral responsibility, and captures a conception of
freedom we value. However, few philosophers have tried to ascertain what these
commonsense intuitions actually are. More often than not, philosophers are content
to place their own intuitions into the mouths of the folk in a way that supports their
own position—neglecting to verify whether their intuitions agree with what the
majority of non-philosophers actually think.
This paper represents a preliminary attempt to correct for this oversight. In this
section we describe our project and the motivation for it. We then discuss two studies
we performed to test folk intuitions about free will, moral responsibility, and the
ability to do otherwise (section 2). We then consider some of the difficulties facing
this kind of empirical research and discuss how such research might impact the
philosophical debates about free will (section 3). We hope our research will spark
further interest in the examination of ordinary people’s intuitions about free will and
related concepts and in developing methods to study such intuitions.
We suggest that the best way to arrive at a sound—and empirically accurate, rather
than merely speculative—understanding of folk intuitions is to conduct surveys of
non-philosophers in an effort to generate the much needed data—to do what Jackson
suggests above: ‘‘serious opinion polls on people’s responses to various cases’’. Our
project can thus be viewed as part of a gathering storm of ‘experimental
philosophy’—recent attempts to empirically test the claims philosophers make
about folk intuitions in epistemology, ethics, and action theory.
3
In this paper, we
expand the scope of this novel, and we believe illuminating, approach to philosophy
by applying it to the free will debate. Jackson (1998) suggested that this sort of
research will not be necessary when philosophers’ claims about ordinary intuitions
are uncontroversial—when there is agreement about what people’s intuitions are and
philosophers ‘‘know that our own case is typical and so can generalize from it to
others’’ (p. 37).
4
In the free will debate these criteria are not met. There is substantial
disagreement among philosophers about what ordinary people’s intuitions are, as
we’ll illustrate shortly. This disagreement likely stems from the philosophers’ own
divergent intuitions. We suspect that this conflict indicates that philosophers’
intuitions have been corrupted by their theories, making it uncertain whether
their own case is ‘‘typical’’ and all the more necessary to survey the intuitions of
pre-theoretical folk.
While compatibilists believe we can have free will and be morally responsible even if
causal determinism is true, incompatibilists maintain that the existence of free will
entails the falsity of causal determinism. Libertarians are incompatibilists who think
we have free will; skeptics are incompatibilists who think we don’t. To say that these
parties find themselves in a stalemate would be an understatement. One indication of
562 E. Nahmias et al.
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
how intractable the debate has become—and how entrenched the respective parties
are—is the fact that so many philosophers claim that their own position has the most
intuitive appeal and best fits our ordinary conception of free will and our practices
of responsibility attribution.
We find, on the one hand, incompatibilists who suggest that their view is
commonsensical and that compatibilism is counter-intuitive. Robert Kane (1999), for
example, writes, ‘‘most ordinary people start out as natural incompatibilists ....
Ordinary persons have to be talked out of this natural incompatibilism by the clever
arguments of philosophers’’ (p. 218). Laura Ekstrom agrees that ‘‘we come to the
table, nearly all of us, as pretheoretic incompatibilists’’ (2002, p. 310) such that it is
the compatibilist who ‘‘needs a positive argument in favor of the compatibility
thesis’’ (2000, p. 57). Galen Strawson (1986) contends that the incompatibilist’s
libertarian conception of free will, though impossible to satisfy, is precisely ‘‘the kind
of freedom that most people ordinarily and unreflectively suppose themselves to
possess’’ (p. 30), adding that it is ‘‘in our nature to take determinism to pose a serious
problem for our notions of responsibility and freedom’’ (p. 89). And Thomas Pink
(2004) tells us that ‘‘most of us start off by making an important assumption about
freedom. Our freedom of action, we naturally tend to assume, must be incompatible
with our actions being determined’’ (p. 12).
5
By making these sorts of claims,
incompatibilists are presumably trying to situate the burden of proof on compat-
ibilists—demanding that they explain how compatibilist theories of free will could
satisfy our ordinary notions—while at the same time motivating the metaphysically
demanding libertarian theories that some incompatibilists defend (e.g., agent
causation) and that other incompatibilists (skeptics) attack as impossible or
implausible.
On the other hand, compatibilists also appeal to commonsense intuitions,
suggesting that the folk do not demand the libertarian conception of free will, which
requires an ability to do otherwise purportedly incompatible with determinism.
For instance, Daniel Dennett (1984b) claims that when ordinary people assign moral
responsibility, ‘‘it simply does not matter at all ...whether the agent in question
could have done otherwise in the circumstances’’ (p. 558). Frankfurt-style cases
(Frankfurt, 1969) are designed to bring to light the intuition that the freedom
necessary for moral responsibility does not require the ability to do otherwise and
hence is compatible with determinism.
6
Susan Wolf (1990) motivates her
compatibilist ‘‘Reason View’’ in part by claiming that it ‘‘seems to accord with and
account for the whole set of our intuitions about responsibility’’ (p. 89). And William
Lycan (2003) rejects the incompatibilists’ attempts to situate the burden of proof,
arguing instead that compatibilism is ‘‘the default position ...not only true, but the
only position rationally available to impartial observers’’ (p. 107).
7
Obviously, to the extent that incompatibilists and compatibilists claim that their
own respective positions best accord with and account for our prephilosophical
intuitions, they cannot both be right. Moreover, they can’t really claim to know if they
are right, since no one has systematically tested to see what people’s prephilosophical
intuitions are.
8
It is therefore important to determine the content of these intuitions.
Philosophical Psychology 563
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
However, finding an adequate method for testing such intuitions is no easy task.
Here we discuss our own attempts to collect data on folk intuitions about free will
and moral responsibility, some difficulties facing this sort of research, and
suggestions for further research. We also examine the question of what role such
data about folk intuitions should play in the philosophical debate.
9
In our attempts to get at folk intuitions, we employed thought-experiment
scenarios to see how ordinary people respond to different compatibilist and
incompatibilist hypotheses. This data is important because any adequate philoso-
phical analysis of free will should be, as Alfred Mele (2001) suggests, ‘‘anchored by
common-sense judgments’’ about particular cases—after all, if a philosophical
analysis of free will runs entirely afoul of what the majority of non-philosophers say,
this analysis ‘‘runs the risk of having nothing more than a philosophical fiction as its
subject matter’’ (p. 27). In this respect we also agree with Jackson (1998) that the
fundamental issue in the free will debate should be ‘‘whether free action according to
our ordinary conception, or something suitably close to our ordinary conception,
exists and is compatible with determinism’’ and that to identify our ordinary
conception we must ‘‘appeal to what seems to us most obvious and central about free
action ... as revealed by our intuitions about possible cases’’ (p. 31).
10
Consider, for instance, the aforementioned claims that the majority of non-
philosophers have incompatibilist intuitions. On the surface, this is a straightforward
empirical claim that entails certain predictions about how people would respond to
various thought experiments. So, for example, if it were true that most non-
philosophers do share the incompatibilists’ intuitions, then we should expect that if
they were given a thought experiment involving an (otherwise ordinary) agent in a
deterministic scenario, a majority of them would not attribute free will and moral
responsibility to the agent. Conversely, those compatibilists who claim that the folk
share their intuitions should predict that a majority of people would attribute free will
and moral responsibility to such an agent. Yet, until a concerted effort is made to
probe folk intuitions and judgments via systematic psychological experiments, the
truth of these sorts of empirical claims goes unchecked.
We are not, however, suggesting that discovering what folk intuitions really are
would resolve the free will problem. There are various responses either side could
make if it turned out their view did not fit with ordinary intuitions, some of which
we’ll discuss below. Nonetheless, if a philosophical theory does turn out to be
privileged by the endorsement of the folk, that would seem to position the burden of
proof on the shoulders of those who argue contrary to folk intuitions. If it turns out
that a significant majority of people make judgments that support either
compatibilist or incompatibilist views, that would at least give ‘‘squatters’ rights’’
to whichever position has such support. At least, this seems to be the idea expressed
by those incompatibilists and compatibilists quoted above who claim to have
commonsense intuition on their side.
Data about folk intuitions would also help situate other positions in the free will
debate. For instance, some philosophers argue that ordinary intuitions are mistaken
and folk concepts need to be revised or even eliminated.
11
Some offer an explanation
564 E. Nahmias et al.
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
for why people have the intuitions they do about free will but why those intuitions do
not in fact commit them to certain conceptual or theoretical views.
12
And some think
that we have a variety of conflicting paradigms of free and responsible action, which
has led philosophers to develop conflicting theories of free will (see Double, 1991,
1996). But these interesting positions still require that we first determine, rather than
merely speculate about, what the folk concepts and intuitions actually are—that is,
what it is that needs to be explained or revised, or whether we in fact have conflicting
views about free will. Hence, we must first make an earnest attempt to probe the
intuitions in question.
In our view, the best way to identify whether people have the intuition that
determinism conflicts with free will is to survey laypersons who have not studied—
and hence have not been influenced by—the relevant philosophical arguments about
free will. Such people should be presented with scenarios portraying determinism and
then asked whether they believe an agent acts in such a scenario of his or her own free
will and is morally responsible. Negative responses would indicate the intuition that
determinism conflicts with free will and responsibility; positive responses would
indicate that people do not have this incompatibilist intuition. By collecting such
data we hope to shed light on ordinary concepts and intuitions in a way that will be
useful to all of the parties in the free will debate. However, as we will discuss in
section 3, surveying intuitions about free will and determinism poses some
particularly difficult problems. And while we have attempted to address some of
these problems, we nevertheless view our studies as preliminary and exploratory and
hope they will generate interest in further research. We also hope to prompt
philosophers to be more explicit about the relationship between their conceptual
analyses of free will and folk concepts and intuitions—e.g., whether they mean to be
describing, explaining, revising, or eliminating the folk’s concept of free will.
2. Studies on Folk Intuitions
To find out what the freedom-relevant intuitions of the folk really are we performed a
number of empirical studies. These studies test the incompatibilist prediction that
most people will judge that agents in a deterministic scenario do not act of their own
free will and are not morally responsible for their actions.
13
2.1. Study 1: Jeremy Cases
In some initial surveys we found that people do not understand the concept
‘determinism’ in the technical way philosophers use it. Rather, they tend to define
‘determinism’ in contrast with free will. This result alone, we suggest, does not bolster
the incompatibilist position. It does not suggest that people consider ‘determinism’,
as defined in (one of ) the technical ways philosophers define it, to be incompatible with
free will or moral responsibility. Rather, it seems that many people think
‘determinism’ means the opposite of free will, as suggested by the phrase ‘the
problem of free will and determinism’.
14
Philosophical Psychology 565
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
So, in order to test whether folk judgments support incompatibilist intuitions, we
developed thought experiments describing deterministic scenarios, roughly in the
philosophical sense of the concept, without begging any questions by using the term
‘determinism’ or describing determinism as involving constraint, fatalism, or
reductionism. The first survey we ran uses a Laplacean notion of determinism.
15
Participants read the following scenario in Figure 1 (including the timeline) and
answered two questions about it (then, on the back of the questionnaire, they
responded to a manipulation check, were invited to explain their answer, and offered
some demographic information).
Scenario: Imagine that in the next century we discover all the laws of nature, and
we build a supercomputer which can deduce from these laws of nature and from
the current state of everything in the world exactly what will be happening in the
world at any future time. It can look at everything about the way the world is and
predict everything about how it will be with 100% accuracy. Suppose that such a
supercomputer existed, and it looks at the state of the universe at a certain time on
March 25, 2150 AD, 20 years before Jeremy Hall is born. The computer then
deduces from this information and the laws of nature that Jeremy will definitely
rob Fidelity Bank at 6:00 pm on January 26, 2195. As always, the supercomputer’s
prediction is correct; Jeremy robs Fidelity Bank at 6:00 pm on January 26, 2195.
For this study (and those discussed below), participants were undergraduates who
had not studied the free will problem.
16
In pilot studies we found that some
participants seemed to fail to reason conditionally (e.g., given their explanations on
the back of the survey, some seemed to assume that the scenario is impossible because
Jeremy has free will, rather than making judgments about Jeremy’s freedom on the
assumption that the scenario is actual). To correct for this problem, Question 1 asked
participants whether they think the scenario is possible (the majority responded
‘‘no’’, offering various reasons on the back of the survey).
17
Then they were then
asked to ‘‘suspend disbelief ’’ for the experimental question:
Regardless of how you answered question 1, imagine such a supercomputer actually
did exist and actually could predict the future, including Jeremy’s robbing the bank
(and assume Jeremy does not know about the prediction):
Do you think that, when Jeremy robs the bank, he acts of his own free will?
The results indicate that a significant majority of participants (76%) judged that
Jeremy robs the bank of his own free will.
18
2150 2170 2195
Computer
makes
p
rediction
Jeremy is
born
Jeremy
robs bank
Figure 1 Jeremy Case 1: Bank Robbing Scenario.
566 E. Nahmias et al.
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
We wondered whether some people were inclined to judge that Jeremy acts freely
because he performs a blameworthy action. Perhaps their emotional response primed
them to hold him responsible for robbing the bank, and this—combined with a tacit
belief that responsible actions must be performed of one’s own free will—led some
participants to answer in the way they did, masking the effect of the determinism in
this case (i.e., case 1, ‘negative action’). To test for this possibility, we ran two more
sets of surveys with identical wording except that in one case (case 2, ‘positive
action’) Jeremy performs the praiseworthy act of saving a child from a burning
building, and in another (case 3, ‘neutral action’) he goes jogging.
19
However, in both these cases participants’ responses closely tracked those from the
blameworthy case: 68% said Jeremy saves the child of his own free will, and 79% said
he goes jogging of his own free will.
20
Hence, the moral status of an action, and
any emotional responses it evokes, appeared to have no significant effect on
judgments of free will. The majority of participants judged that Jeremy acts of his
own free will in this deterministic scenario regardless of the type of action involved
(see Figure 2).
In order to test directly whether people judge that an agent is morally responsible
for his actions in a deterministic scenario, we asked participants (in case 4): ‘‘Do you
think that, when Jeremy robs the bank, he is morally blameworthy for it?’’ and
(in case 5): ‘‘Do you think that, when Jeremy saves the child, he is morally
Figure 2 Judgments of Free Will and Moral Responsibility. Percentage of participants
who judged Jeremy acted of his own free will when he robbed a bank (negative), saved a
child (positive), and went jogging (neutral), as compared with percentage of participants
who judged Jeremy morally responsible when he robbed a bank (negative) and saved a
child (positive).
Philosophical Psychology 567
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
praiseworthy for it?’’ Results from these participants closely tracked those offered by
participants who had responded to questions about free will (though a slightly higher
proportion of participants judged that Jeremy is morally responsible than had
those who judged that he acts of his own free will): 83% judged he was blameworthy
in the negative case and 88% judged he was praiseworthy in the positive case (see
Figure 2).
21
Since we surveyed one set of participants to make judgments about Jeremy’s free
will and another set to judge his moral responsibility, we can be confident that the
consistency in the response patterns is not being driven by individuals trying to
maintain consistency in their answers (e.g., first answering that he acted freely, then
inferring that he must be morally responsible, or vice versa). This consistency accords
well with philosophers’ claims that judgments about free will are closely related
to judgments about moral responsibility.
Finally, we examined whether people’s judgments of an agent’s ability to choose
otherwise in a deterministic scenario would track judgments about his free will and
moral responsibility, since philosophers disagree both about whether determinism
conflicts with people’s ordinary conception of the ability to do (or choose) otherwise
and also about whether free will and moral responsibility require the ability to do
otherwise. In these cases, participants were asked—again, imagining the scenario
were actual—whether or not Jeremy could have chosen not to rob the bank (case 6),
whether he could have chosen not to save the child (case 7), or whether he could have
chosen not to go jogging (case 8).
In the blameworthy variation, participants’ judgments of Jeremy’s ability to choose
otherwise (ACO) did in fact track the judgments of free will and responsibility we
collected, with 67% responding that Jeremy could have chosen not to rob the bank.
22
However, in the praiseworthy case, judgments of ACO were significantly different
from judgments of his free will and responsibility: Whereas a large majority of
participants had judged that Jeremy is free and responsible for saving the child, a
majority (62%) answered ‘‘no’’ to the question: ‘‘Do you think he could have chosen
not to save the child?’’
23
Finally, in the morally neutral case, judgments of ACO were
also significantly different from judgments of free will—again, whereas a large
majority had judged that Jeremy goes jogging of his own free will, a majority (57%)
answered ‘‘no’’ to the question: ‘‘Do you think he could have chosen not to go
jogging?’’
24
(See Figure 3.)
We offer two related interpretations of these interesting results. First, the results
may suggest that some folk have Frankfurtian intuitions (see note 6). That is, they
think, as suggested by Frankfurt (1969), that an agent’s action may be free and
responsible without the agent’s having the ability to do otherwise—though this trend
did not appear with the blameworthy actions.
25
So perhaps these intuitions are more
pronounced regarding agents who perform praiseworthy (or morally neutral)
actions. This would support Wolf ’s (1980) asymmetry thesis—roughly, that we tend
to judge an agent to be blameworthy only if we believe he could do otherwise, but we
are willing to judge an agent to be praiseworthy even if we believe he could not
568 E. Nahmias et al.
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
do otherwise.
26
In any case, it appears that judgments of free will and responsibility
can diverge from judgments about the ability to do otherwise.
The main finding in Study 1 is that most people do not judge determinism—at
least as described in this scenario—to be incompatible with an agent’s acting of his
own free will or with his being morally responsible for his actions.
27
Repeatedly, we
found that the number of participants making judgments inconsistent with
incompatibilist intuitions is two to three times greater than the number making
judgments indicative of incompatibilist intuitions.
28
2.2. Study 2: Fred and Barney Cases
One might object that in the Jeremy cases, by trying to avoid a question-begging
description of determinism, we did not make the deterministic nature of the scenario
salient enough to the participants.
29
Perhaps they were more focused on the fact that
Jeremy’s actions were predicted by the supercomputer than the fact that the
prediction was made based on deterministic laws. (If so, it would still be an
important result that most people do not judge such predictability to conflict with
free will and responsibility.
30
) To explore this possibility, we developed another
scenario that, we believe, presents determinism in a different and more salient way in
Figure 3 Comparison of Free Will and ACO Judgments. Comparison of percentage of
participants who judged that Jeremy acted of his own free will (FW) to those who judged
that he could have chosen otherwise (ACO) in robbing a bank (negative), saving a child
(positive), and going jogging (neutral).
Philosophical Psychology 569
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
that it points out that the agents’ behavior is sufficiently caused by factors beyond
their control (i.e., genes and upbringing):
Scenario. Imagine there is a world where the beliefs and values of every person are
caused completely by the combination of one’s genes and one’s environment. For
instance, one day in this world, two identical twins, named Fred and Barney, are
born to a mother who puts them up for adoption. Fred is adopted by the Jerksons
and Barney is adopted by the Kindersons. In Fred’s case, his genes and his
upbringing by the selfish Jerkson family have caused him to value money above all
else and to believe it is OK to acquire money however you can. In Barney’s case, his
(identical) genes and his upbringing by the kindly Kinderson family have caused
him to value honesty above all else and to believe one should always respect others’
property. Both Fred and Barney are intelligent individuals who are capable of
deliberating about what they do.
One day Fred and Barney each happen to find a wallet containing $1000 and the
identification of the owner (neither man knows the owner). Each man is sure there
is nobody else around. After deliberation, Fred Jerkson, because of his beliefs and
values, keeps the money. After deliberation, Barney Kinderson, because of his
beliefs and values, returns the wallet to its owner.
Given that, in this world, one’s genes and environment completely cause one’s
beliefs and values, it is true that if Fred had been adopted by the Kindersons, he
would have had the beliefs and values that would have caused him to return the
wallet; and if Barney had been adopted by the Jerksons, he would have had the
beliefs and values that would have caused him to keep the wallet.
Despite this seemingly potent description of complete causation by genes and
environment, a significant majority of participants (76%) judged both that Fred kept
the wallet of his own free will and Barney returned it of his own free will (case 9).
31
This response pattern was very similar to the pattern of participants’ judgments about
free will in the Jeremy cases, suggesting that this scenario probed similar intuitions
about the relationship between deterministic causation and free will.
32
We also tested whether participants judge that Fred is ‘‘morally blameworthy for
keeping the wallet’’ and that Barney is ‘‘morally praiseworthy for returning the
wallet’’ (case 10). For most participants (94%) these judgments were consistent, and
the response patterns were not significantly different from the judgments we collected
about free will: 60% judged that Fred is blameworthy and 64% judged that Barney is
praiseworthy.
33
Finally, we tested whether participants judge that Fred and Barney
could do otherwise than they did (case 11). Again, results closely tracked judgments
of freedom and responsibility, with 76% of participants responding that both Fred
and Barney could have done otherwise.
34
(See Figure 4.)
2.3. Discussion
We suggest that—in the absence of further studies contradicting our results or
alternative explanations of them—these studies suggest that ordinary people’s
pre-theoretical intuitions about free will and responsibility do not support
incompatibilism. It appears to be false—or certainly too hasty—to claim that
570 E. Nahmias et al.
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
‘‘most ordinary persons ...believe there is some kind of conflict between freedom
and determinism’’ (Kane, 1999, p. 218), and that ‘‘We come to the table, nearly all of
us, as pretheoretic incompatibilists’’ (Ekstrom, 2002, p. 310). Rather, when
pretheoretic participants considered an agent (Jeremy) whose action is unerringly
predicted based on the state of the universe before his birth and the laws of nature, a
significant majority judged that the agent acts of his own free will and is morally
responsible for the action, and this tendency shows up when the action in question is
morally negative, positive, or neutral. Hence, most participants did not recognize an
incompatibility between determinism described in these terms and free will or moral
responsibility. Furthermore, when participants considered agents (Fred and Barney)
whose beliefs, values, and actions are completely caused by their genes and
upbringing, a significant majority judged that these agents act of their own free will
and are morally responsible for their actions. Hence, most participants did not
recognize an incompatibility between determinism described in these terms and free
will or moral responsibility. Judgments about the ability of agents in a deterministic
scenario to do or choose otherwise were more complex and, given their important
role in the philosophical debates, clearly demand more research.
35
Notice that, by claiming that most people do not express incompatibilist intuitions
in these cases, we are not endorsing the stronger claim that the folk do have
compatibilist intuitions. To be sure, compatibilists should take comfort from results
suggesting that their opponents do not have the support of pre-theoretical intuitions
on their side. Our results, however, were not unanimous—we consistently found
Figure 4 Judgments of Free Will, Moral Responsibility and ACO. Percentage of subjects
who judged that Fred and Barney acted of their own free will (FW), were morally
responsible for their actions (MR), and could have chosen otherwise (ACO).
Philosophical Psychology 571
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
a non-negligible minority of participants offering incompatibilist judgments. Such
results may support the idea that individuals have conflicting intuitions about free
will or moral responsibility.
36
Or they may indicate that intuitions vary significantly
between different individuals who themselves have consistent intuitions.
37
Nonetheless, we think that our results place the burden of proof on the shoulders
of incompatibilists. Incompatibilists are especially apt to cite folk intuitions in
support of their view, in part because their conception of free will is more
metaphysically demanding and therefore requires extra intuitive support to offset the
strength of their claims.
38
Put simply: if our ordinary intuitions do not demand
indeterminism, then why should our theories? If incompatibilists claim that
compatibilism is a ‘‘wretched subterfuge,’’ a radical revision of commonsense beliefs,
then we recommend that some empirical evidence should be offered to back up
this claim.
3. Objections, Replies, and Philosophical Implications
Our studies falsified the prediction that most lay persons will express incompatibilist
intuitions by judging that agents in a deterministic scenario lack free will and moral
responsibility. Again, however, we view these results as preliminary, not conclusive,
and hence as motivation for further research on folk intuitions about freedom and
responsibility and for further consideration of the role such intuitions should play in
the free will debate. One shortcoming of our studies is that they were limited to a
college student population. They should be replicated using participants with more
diverse educational backgrounds and socio-economic statuses. Ideally, they would
also be replicated with participants from other cultures to test whether there are
important differences among various cultures’ conceptions of free will and moral
responsibility.
39
Furthermore, the method of surveying judgments in response to
scenarios, though useful for our purposes, should be combined with other methods,
including coding participants’ responses in more open-ended interviews about the
relevant concepts (see Nahmias et al., 2004), and experimentally investigating
relevant behavioral responses to situations that involve people’s ascriptions of moral
responsibility (e.g., praising, blaming, excusing).
40
A potential problem more specific to our studies is that the presence of
determinism might not have been salient enough in the scenarios. We have already
explained why we think it would be problematic to use the word ‘determinism’ to test
whether ordinary people have incompatibilist intuitions. But if the description of
determinism is overly watered down, then people may simply fail to notice its
presence and therefore botch the (supposed) inference to the conclusion that agents
in the scenario are not free and responsible. We agree that the more salient
determinism is in the scenarios, the more significant the results would be (see Black &
Tweedale, 2002). Amping up determinism, however, is not as easy as it might seem.
First of all, using a technical definition of ‘determinism’ would likely be impractical.
For instance, using van Inwagen’s (1983, pp. 58–65) definition of determinism and
telling participants that, in Jeremy’s world, the past and the laws of nature entail any
572 E. Nahmias et al.
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
true proposition, would require providing participants with enough education to
ensure that they comprehend the technical notions of ‘proposition’ and ‘entail’, along
with understanding necessity and indicative conditionals. It is unlikely that
participants could be sufficiently educated on these issues without significant
training. (We discuss below problems with using participants trained in philosophy
for research like ours).
Attempts to make determinism more salient without teaching participants
technical notions run the risk of adding new factors that may themselves mask
whatever effects determinism has on people’s judgments with more obvious threats
to free will. For instance, determinism would be very salient if we changed the
Jeremy scenario so that his action was caused by a brilliant neuroscientist who
manipulated the initial conditions of Jeremy’s life in a way that she knew would
inevitably lead to his specific action. Here, the deterministic causation is clear—but
so is the presence of a ‘covert controller’. If participants then judged that Jeremy did
not act freely or was not morally responsible for his act, we would not be able to
determine whether it was because their intuitions about free will and moral
responsibility are responding to the determinism in the scenario or to the presence
of an active manipulator.
41
It would also beg the question to describe determinism
as entailing that the agent could not do otherwise, since some compatibilists
disagree with incompatibilists about whether the ordinary conception of ‘can’
relevant to freedom and responsibility is inconsistent with determinism. Indeed,
our diverse results from participants’ judgments about the ability to do or
choose otherwise suggest that further research will be required to understand this
concept.
42
With that being said, if one is able to find a way to increase the salience of
determinism without masking it with a different free-will threat, we welcome the
attempt. If turning up the volume on the ‘‘determinism knob’’ of the scenarios does
cause participants to withdraw their judgments of free will and moral responsibility
(and if this is clearly not a result of masking determinism), then we would withdraw
our current interpretation of the data. If a more clearly deterministic case does not
result in more judgments of unfree and unresponsible, though, our interpretation is
strengthened. In any case, the claim that people will withdraw judgments of freedom
when determinism is made more salient is an empirical claim. Philosophers are well
positioned to develop the relevant thought experiments to test this claim. But how
people will respond to such scenarios cannot be settled from our philosophical
La-Z-Boys. This response generalizes to any empirical or methodological objections
to our studies. We are not closing the door on the question of whether the folk have
incompatibilist intuitions; on the contrary, we are opening the door to further
research exploring such questions.
One significant problem facing any such test of folk intuitions about the
relationship between determinism and free will is that it requires participants to
reason conditionally. To determine whether or not people believe free will is
compatible with determinism, it is not enough to see whether (a) they believe we
have free will and (b) they believe our world (or at least its human population)
Philosophical Psychology 573
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
behaves in a deterministic way. If people believe both (a) and (b), that would strongly
suggest they have a compatibilist conception of free will. But if they believe (a) but
not (b), that would not show they have an incompatibilist theory—after all, they may
have reasons unrelated to free will for believing the world is not deterministic. Rather,
incompatibilism is the belief that free will is possible only if determinism does not
obtain. So, to test this belief directly, we must see what people believe about agents’
freedom and responsibility on the assumption that determinism does obtain.
In our attempts to make determinism salient to participants, we described
scenarios that many found implausible or impossible. Especially in the Jeremy study,
almost all participants responded that they believed the scenario is impossible, for a
variety of reasons (see note 17). Despite our efforts to induce participants to make
their judgments based on a conditional acceptance of the scenario, it is likely that
some did not do so, as evidenced by those who missed the manipulation check on the
back of the surveys, which tested whether they recognized the deterministic nature of
the scenario. Some of these participants may even have been expressing incompatibi-
list intuitions, e.g., by asserting that Jeremy acts of his own free will and then
(mis)responding that the scenario could therefore not have been describing a fully
deterministic situation. Hence, the challenge is to describe determinism in a way that
participants find salient, intelligible, and somewhat believable.
Our second scenario (Fred and Barney cases) seems to have satisfied these
conditions better than our first, given that fewer participants responded that it was
impossible and fewer missed the manipulation check. Another scenario we have used
for pilot studies involves the ‘rollback’ thought experiment initially advanced to
probe intuitions about whether indeterminism can help secure free will (see Kane,
1999, p. 222). The scenario asks participants to imagine that the universe is re-created
at a certain point in time just before a particular event (e.g., an agent’s decision) with
all conditions and laws being identical. Then participants can be probed on whether
they believe our world is deterministic (would the same event occur every time?) and
whether they believe physical events are deterministic whereas agent’s decisions are
not (would the same decision occur every time?). Finally, determinism can be
stipulated (e.g., the same decision occurs every single time) to test whether
participants think such a decision (their own or another’s) is free and deserves praise
or blame. Such scenarios can also be varied to test whether indeterminism (e.g., one
decision occurs half the time and another occurs half the time) increases or decreases
participants’ judgments of free will and moral responsibility.
43
Even if we are able to get participants to recognize determinism and respond based
on the assumption of determinism, it may be argued that most of them are unable to
recognize the implications of determinism for free will and moral responsibility. This
problem can take a motivational form—participants don’t want to see the
implications of determinism—or a cognitive form—they cannot comprehend the
(alleged) connection between determinism and free will.
The motivational problem suggests that people may be so attached to being free
and responsible—and to holding other people morally responsible—that it is very
difficult to get them to judge that agents (at least agents resembling them) are not free
574 E. Nahmias et al.
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
and responsible.
44
This kind of ‘‘attachment’’ may, for example, hinder participants
from recognizing the deterministic elements of scenarios like the ones we used. The
idea here is that a person who harbors incompatibilist sympathies, and who views
the agent(s) in a scenario as being sufficiently like himself, may fail to acknowledge
the deterministic aspects of a scenario. However, if we can ensure that participants
are in fact recognizing the deterministic nature of a scenario, this motivational
problem should not be an issue. In this case the participants either (a) express an
incompatibilist intuition by judging that the agent is not like them because he is
determined (and hence respond that he, unlike them, is not free and responsible), or
(b) express a compatibilist intuition by responding that the determined agent is, like
themselves, free and responsible. After all, people do not need help recognizing that
certain types of causal processes, such as brainwashing or direct neural manipulation,
compromise free will and moral responsibility, presumably because they judge that
these processes are unlike those that govern their own behavior (see note 41).
Another possibility is that people want incompatibilist free will, but, if they find
themselves in a situation (actual or hypothetical) without it, they will settle for a less
satisfying kind of compatibilist free will instead. On this reading, folk come to the
table with the intuition that to be free in the fullest sense, determinism must be false,
but a less robust (but better-than-nothing) sort of freedom is available if determinism
turns out to be true.
45
If accurate, this would suggest people have a libertarian
conception of free will but, in lieu of that, they would accept a compatibilist
conception as a moderate revision rather than giving up entirely on the idea that we
are free and responsible agents. Whether or not the folk actually have this complex
psychology is an interesting question that would require studies that go beyond what
we have done here.
In any case, there is a lesson buried in this discussion. We commonly hear that
ordinary people have (or fail to have) something that might be called ‘‘the
incompatibilist intuition’’ (Pereboom, 2001, p. 89) or ‘‘natural incompatibilist
instincts’’ (Kane, 1999, p. 218). It is not clear what the content of this ‘intuition’, or
the nature of these ‘instincts’ is supposed to be. Is it a propensity to call determined
people unfree? Is it a desire to have a roughly incompatibilist rather than a
compatibilist kind of freedom, although either deserve the name ‘freedom’? Or is it
something else entirely? In addition to knowing what theoretical work philosophers’
appeals to folk intuitions are supposed to be doing, we also need to know what the
content of those intuitions is supposed to be.
One suggestion we expect to hear is that ‘‘the incompatibilist intuition’’ is the
propensity of participants to judge an agent in a deterministic scenario to be unfree
but only once they recognize the implications of determinism. Thus, in order to see if
people have the incompatibilist intuition, we need to help them see these
implications—help them overcome what we called above the cognitive form of the
problem. But getting people to ‘‘see the implications’’ of a case—especially a case like
this, where the referent of ‘the implications’ is so hotly contested—is tantamount to
giving the arguments in favor of one position or another. These arguments rely on
premises that are themselves controversial—and that are likely to be supported by
Philosophical Psychology 575
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
further appeal to intuitions. Furthermore, this does not seem a very plausible view of
what the incompatibilist intuition should be: if it takes a basic incompatibilist
argument to make incompatibilism the ‘‘intuitive view’’, then it seems that it is
the incompatibilists who are talking the folk into incompatibilism. At a minimum,
the compatibilists would not be talking the folk out of anything, in contrast to Kane’s
(1999) claim that ‘‘ordinary persons have to be talked out of [their] natural
incompatibilism by the clever arguments of philosophers’’ (p. 218).
We have no doubt that many ordinary people, after some exposure to
incompatibilist arguments, will make incompatibilist judgments. Similarly, people
exposed to compatibilist arguments are likely to make compatibilist judgments. But
as soon as philosophers provide such arguments, they are influencing people’s views
and shaping their intuitions. Even if a philosophy teacher is trying to maintain
neutrality, it is unlikely her views will not influence the way she presents the material
to her students.
46
And even if her own views don’t influence her students, the
material itself consists of conflicting claims meant to persuade people; getting a
balanced view of the debate would require exposure to the philosophical literature
seldom found outside of graduate school. Such an education would, however,
compromise one’s status as one of the ‘‘folk’’ whose intuitions we are trying to
understand. Of course, it may be possible to test whether people’s judgments change
after they have studied the free will debate and whether they change in different ways
depending on how they study it. Perhaps a compatibilist teacher, despite any efforts
to present both sides of the debate fairly, would influence his students to respond
with more compatibilist judgments, whereas an incompatibilist teacher would
produce students who respond with more incompatibilist judgments.
47
If so, it would
be difficult to get pre-theoretical intuitions from people who have been exposed to
the relevant philosophical arguments.
Perhaps we should instead be interested in the reflective intuitions of well-trained
philosophers rather than folk uninformed about the complex philosophical issues
surrounding free will.
48
Van Inwagen (1992, p. 58) has suggested that arguments
about free will should be pitched at an audience whose members have been exposed
to the best arguments on both sides of the debate but have not reached a firm
conclusion about the compatibility question (see also Lycan, 2003; Mele, 1995). If our
project motivates philosophers to adopt this view, that would at least be a significant
result: no longer could any side claim that they have common sense on their side,
since the well-trained philosopher’s sense is not exactly common sense.
The worry here is that a conceptual analysis that fits the reflective intuitions of
well-trained philosophers may have ‘‘nothing more than a philosophical fiction as its
subject matter’’ (Mele, 2001, p. 27). We face a dilemma. If ‘free will’ is beholden only
to the post-theoretic intuitions of philosophers, then it is a technical concept, not
unlike ‘determinism’, ‘validity’, or ‘skepticism’ in philosophy (or ‘quark’ or
‘momentum’ in physics). If it is a technical concept, then philosophers should not
be particularly interested in folk intuitions about it. But this route seems problematic
since the concept of free will most philosophers are interested in is the one that
is necessary for moral responsibility and attributions of praise and blame. And it
576 E. Nahmias et al.
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
would be strange indeed if people’s actual notions of moral responsibility and their
actual practices of attributing praise and blame had no important relationship to
philosophers’ theories about them. Even if ‘free will’ is a technical concept, it will
have to be at least constrained by the non-technical concepts and practices of
responsibility attribution if it is to do the work the philosophical community has set
for it. On the other hand, if ‘free will’ is not meant to be a technical philosophical
concept—or if it is, but it is constrained by folk intuitions about moral
responsibility—then philosophers should be interested in prephilosophical judg-
ments relevant to the concept. In that case, philosophers should be interested in the
facts about such judgments and the concepts they reveal. To understand what those
facts are, we must consider surveying the folk; thus, folk intuitions are once again
relevant.
We conclude with one more reason why it is unlikely philosophers will, or should,
give up talking about folk concepts and intuitions regarding free will and moral
responsibility. A significant recent trend in the free will debate involves philosophers
on all sides of the debate analyzing the concept of free will in the light of what we
value—they aim, in Dennett’s (1984a) language, for a concept of free will ‘‘worth
wanting.’’ Though this often means looking for a concept that supports our
practices of ascribing moral responsibility, it also involves the values we place on
human dignity, uniqueness, creativity, hope, and love (see, e.g., Kane, 1996, ch. 6).
And philosophers have also noted that moral responsibility itself involves a range of
issues, from reactive attitudes to practices of punishment and reward to moral
rehabilitation (see, e.g., Pereboom, 2001). Considering the issue in this way has led to
the recognition that various conceptions of free will may secure various things we
value, perhaps to different degrees, and that various putative threats to free will, such
as determinism, may threaten different things we value, perhaps to different degrees.
For instance, as Randolph Clarke (2003) suggests, it may be that an event-causal
libertarian theory (like Kane’s) can secure some aspects of dignity we value even if it
does not undergird moral responsibility any better than compatibilist accounts.
Similarly, as Fischer and Ravizza (1998) argue, it may be that determinism precludes
the freedom to act otherwise but that such freedom is not required for moral
responsibility. Fischer (forthcoming) has written, ‘‘The discovery that causal
determinism is true would significantly alter our picture of ourselves. ... But I do
not believe we would need entirely to jettison ...deliberation, moral responsibility,
and judgments of deontic morality [which] are compatible with causal determinism
and the lack of free will (in the sense involving alternative possibilities)’’ (p. 23).
These moves suggest that certain theories of free will and moral responsibility may
require us to revise some, but not all, of our current concepts, beliefs, and practices
about freedom and responsibility (see Vargas, forthcoming). But in order to know
whether a particular theory demands revision (or even elimination) of our concepts,
beliefs, or practices, we have to know what these are. And though armchair
speculation may help here, it is unlikely to be sufficient—especially given the
vigorous debates among philosophers about what is intuitive when it comes to
freedom and responsibility. Rather, we should make some attempt to get systematic,
Philosophical Psychology 577
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
empirical data about the relevant concepts, beliefs, and practices. Though this may
ultimately be work best left to psychologists and sociologists, philosophers will have
to help lay out exactly which issues should be tested and how to set up scenarios to
test the relevant intuitions.
Because any attempt at conceptual revision, especially in light of various values we
attach to freedom concepts, will depend on our understanding of how people actually
use these concepts and what values they actually attach to them, we submit that our
general methodological proposal may be particularly important to the current free
will debate. Beyond the particular studies we carried out here in an attempt to get at
folk judgments about incompatibilism, we need to achieve a better understanding of
a wide range of folk judgments, practices, and intuitions concerning freedom and
responsibility. As Vargas (forthcoming) has written, ‘‘Our ability to determine
whether a theory [of free will and responsibility] is revisionist turns on the extent to
which we have correctly characterized responsibility practices, attitudes, and beliefs.’’
Furthermore, we hope this paper will motivate philosophers in the free will debate
to do two things. First, we think philosophers should be more explicit about how they
think their theories of free will and moral responsibility align with—and diverge
from—people’s actual intuitions and practices. And second, to the extent that they
claim their theories do align closely with these intuitions and practices, they should be
more explicit and careful about their reasons for believing such alignment exists. We
are not suggesting that philosophers should make a practice of surveying the folk
about every question of interest. They can at least, however, perform the following
thought experiment: ‘‘How would I determine whether the folk would agree with this
particular claim about free will and moral responsibility? If it turned out they did
agree, what evidential value would that have for the claim? If, on the other hand, it
turned out they did not agree, what problems would that raise for the claim, and how
might I respond to them? And if it simply does not matter whether or not
prephilosophical people would agree with the claim, why is that?’’ Considering
questions like these will help ensure that, as we continue to argue about free will, our
arguments will be about more than just a philosophical fiction.
Acknowledgements
For their helpful suggestions, we would like to thank Joshua Knobe, John Doris,
Tamler Sommers, Mike McKenna, Brandon Schmeichel, George Graham, two
anonymous referees, and, especially, Shaun Nichols, Manuel Vargas, and Al Mele.
Notes
[1] Authorship is equal.
[2] For discussions see, for example, Jackson (1998) and essays in DePaul and Ramsey (1998).
[3] See, for example, Adams and Steadman (2004), Doris and Stich (forthcoming), Knobe (2003a,
2003b, 2004), Mele (2003), Nadelhoffer (2004, 2005), Nahmias, Morris, Nadelhoffer, and
Turner (forthcoming), Nichols (2004), Nichols, Weinburg, and Stich (2003), Weinburg,
Nichols, and Stich (2001), Woolfolk, Doris, and Darley (forthcoming), and Turner and
Nahmias (in preparation).
578 E. Nahmias et al.
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
[4] However, Jackson’s example of an uncontroversial case, Gettier examples in epistemology,
has in fact been challenged by empirical results suggesting that people from different
cultures or of different socio-economic statuses have different intuitions about such
examples (see Nichols et al., 2003; Weinburg et al., 2001). See also Stich and Weinberg
(2001).
[5] See also Smilansky (2003, p. 259), Pereboom (2001, p. xvi), O’Connor (2000, p. 4), and
Campbell (1951, p. 451).
[6] Frankfurt cases aim to pump the intuition that an agent can be responsible for an action even
if he could not do otherwise: for instance, if there were a neuroscientist ready to manipulate
the agent to do Aif he were not going to do it on his own, then the agent could not do
otherwise than A, but if the agent did Aon his own without the neuroscientist intervening, it
seems the agent is nonetheless responsible for A-ing.
[7] Lycan (2003) argues that it is the incompatibilist who must provide a positive argument for
her position, in part because ‘‘numerous commonsense claims of free action will always
be more plausible than are the purely philosophical premises’’ of incompatibilist arguments
(p. 120).
[8] Compatibilists and libertarians offer a parallel set of conflicting, but empirically untested,
claims about the phenomenology of free will—for instance, our experiences of the ability to
do otherwise and of the self as source of actions (see Nahmias, Morris, Nadelhoffer, &
Turner, 2004).
[9] See also Nahmias et al. (forthcoming), Nichols (2004), and Nichols and Knobe
(in preparation).
[10] Compare Fischer and Ravizza’s (1998) conception of how to understand moral
responsibility: ‘‘we shall be trying to articulate the inchoate, shared views about moral
responsibility in (roughly speaking) modern, Western democratic society .... Here we shall
be identifying and evaluating ‘considered judgments’ about particular cases—actual and
hypothetical—in which an agent’s moral responsibility is at issue’’ (pp. 10–11).
[11] For a helpful discussion of ‘revisionism’ in the free will debate see Vargas (forthcoming).
[12] For instance, Graham and Horgan (1994) offer a contextualist sort of explanation for why
people might express incompatibilist intuitions in certain philosophical contexts, and
Velleman (2000) developed an error theory for why our epistemic freedom leads us to believe
we have metaphysical (libertarian) freedom.
[13] We should note that two of the four authors are compatibilists and two are incompatibilists.
Every effort was made not to prejudice the data through misleading experimental design, and
the diversity of opinions within the team was beneficial to this end (though frustrating at
times!). We also sent our surveys to a dozen or so philosophers with various views in the free
will debate and received no responses suggesting that the surveys were in any significant
sense misleading or problematic.
[14] Examples of participants’ definitions of ‘determinism’ include: ‘‘Being unable to choose’’,
‘‘That people have a set fate’’, and ‘‘The lack of free will’’. Many others thought it meant
‘determined’, as in ‘resolute’. Fischer (1994, p. 152) predicted that the phrase ‘causal
determinism’ may seem threatening to people but that this alone would not indicate they
have incompatibilist intuitions.
[15] Laplace defines ‘determinism’ in terms of an intelligent being such that if it had complete
knowledge of the laws of nature and the current state of the universe, it could know all past
events and predict all future events. Van Inwagen’s (1983) technical definition
of ‘determinism’ is related: a proposition describing the complete state of the universe
at one time and the laws of nature logically entails a proposition describing the complete
state of the universe at any other time. Laplacean determinism entails van Inwagen
determinism, but the converse is not true.
[16] Participants were drawn from an Honors student colloquium and several introductory
philosophy classes at Florida State University (before studying the free will problem).
Philosophical Psychology 579
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
Any participants who indicated that they had taken a previous college philosophy course
were excluded from the results. We also excluded those participants who missed the
manipulation check and the few who answered ‘‘I don’t know’’ in response to the
experimental question.
[17] The reasons participants offered for believing the scenario to be impossible were wide-
ranging, including, for instance, that the computer could never acquire that much data, that
people could undermine the predictions by learning about them, and that chaos theory or
quantum theory makes such predictions impossible. See section 3 for a discussion of the
problem of surveys that require conditional reasoning.
[18] This result (16:5) is statistically significant using a
2
goodness-of-fit test:
2
(1,
N¼21) ¼5.76, p¼0.016.
[19] For all of these cases we used different sets of participants to avoid any order or interference
effects due to participants’ attempting to keep their judgments consistent across different
cases—i.e., any given participant read just one survey and answered just one experimental
question.
[20] Case 2 results (15:7) approach statistical significance:
2
(1, N¼22) ¼2.9, p¼0.088). Case 3
results (15:4) are statistically significant:
2
(1, N¼19) ¼6.37, p¼0.012. Binomial
proportion comparison tests show no significant differences between the response patterns
of participants in case 1 and case 2 (p¼0.56), or between those in case 1 and case 3
(p¼0.84).
[21] Case 4 results (15:3) are significant:
2
(1, N¼18) ¼8, p¼0.005. Case 5 results (16:2) are
significant:
2
(1, N¼18) ¼10.9, p¼0.001. Binomial proportion comparison tests show no
significant differences between the response patterns of participants in case 1 and case 4
(p¼0.58), between those in case 1 and case 5 ( p¼0.30), or between those in case 2 and case
5(p¼0.12).
[22] Binomial proportion comparison tests between the response patterns of participants in case
1 and those in case 6 (14:7) show no significant difference ( p¼0.50).
[23] Binomial proportion comparison tests between the response patterns of participants in case
2 and those in case 7 (8:13) show that there was a statistically significant difference
(p¼0.05).
[24] Binomial proportion comparison tests between response patterns of participants in case 3
and those in case 8 (6:8) show a statistically significant difference (p¼0.03).
[25] To test this interpretation, it would be better to have the same participants making
judgments about both the ability to do otherwise and free will (or moral responsibility). See
Woolfolk et al. (forthcoming) for empirical results suggesting that ordinary people have
Frankfurtian intuitions.
[26] We suspect that it is particularly difficult to probe intuitions about modal concepts such as
the ability to do otherwise (see note 35). See Turner and Nahmias (in preparation).
[27] Participants’ explanations of their answers suggest that some of them even had fledgling
compatibilist theories in mind. For instance, some suggested that Jeremy acts freely because
no outside forces compel him, because he controls his actions or consciously decides to do
them, or because the prediction is based on what he decides to do. (Similarly, some of the
minority who judged that Jeremy is unfree offered fledgling incompatibilist arguments.)
[28] We should add that in numerous pilot studies as we fine-tuned descriptions of the scenarios,
experimental questions, and manipulation checks, we were surprised by the consistency
of the results: in almost every set of surveys, 70–85% of participants judged that Jeremy acts
of his own free will or that he is morally responsible for his action.
[29] We should note that we tried several variations of the wording of the Jeremy case, including
one that said, ‘‘The computer then deduces from this information and the laws of nature that
it is physically impossible for Jeremy to do anything other than to rob Fidelity Bank [save the
child, etc.]’’ and results showed the same trends (as reported in note 28). For further
discussion of this concern about the salience of determinism, see section 3.
580 E. Nahmias et al.
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
[30] We wonder whether some participants, having reconciled themselves to the problem of
God’s foreknowledge and free will, were less inclined to see the supercomputer’s
foreknowledge as a threat to free will. We obtained information about participants’
self-reported religiosity, but we have not yet correlated this information with the results.
[31] Methods for study 2 were the same as study 1 except that participants answered two
experimental questions (one about Fred and one about Barney). Fewer participants judged
that the scenario was impossible and fewer missed the manipulation check (three
participants who answered differently for Fred and Barney were not included in the analysis
of results). Results for case 9 (26:8 judging that both agents acted of their own free will) were
statistically significant using a
2
goodness-of-fit test:
2
(1, N¼34) ¼9.53, p¼0.002.
[32] A binomial proportion comparison test shows no significant difference between the response
patterns of participants in case 1 and those in case 9 ( p¼0.98).
[33] Comparison tests show no significant differences between the response pattern of
participants in case 9 and the pattern of blameworthy judgments in case 10 (21:14,
p¼1.06), or in the response patterns of participants in case 9 and the pattern of praiseworthy
judgments in case 10 (23:13, p¼0.25). Interestingly, a smaller majority of participants in
these cases judged that the agents were morally responsible than those judging Jeremy to be
morally responsible (in cases 4 and 5).
[34] Comparisons between the response patterns of participants in case 8 and those in case 11
(20:11) were not significantly different ( p¼0.29). Because we asked the same participants
about both Fred’s and Barney’s ability to do otherwise, and all participants made consistent
judgments, we were unable to confirm the interesting results from study 1 suggesting that
such judgments vary depending on whether the action is blameworthy or praiseworthy/
neutral.
[35] As we suggested above, in some cases the pattern of responses suggests to us that people may
have Frankfurtian intuitions whereby they are willing to assign blame despite believing the
agent could not do otherwise. In other cases, the responses suggest people may be employing
a conditional conception of the ability to do otherwise, such that the agents could do
otherwise despite their actions being determined.
[36] Compare Double (1991, 1996). We take very seriously the possibility that free will and moral
responsibility are best analyzed as context-relative concepts (see Graham & Horgan, 1994).
If so, empirical research aimed at mapping the contours of the relevant contexts would be
important.
[37] This would suggest an interesting explanation (perhaps found in the work of William James
and Ludwig Wittgenstein) for the long-standing free will stalemate. After decades of
argument, compatibilists and incompatibilists tend to retain conflicting intuitions about
crucial disputes in the debate; perhaps they end up where they do in part because they start
off where they do—as ordinary folk with different intuitions about the concept of free will
and its relationship to determinism.
[38] Libertarian theories require, at a minimum, indeterministic causation—in just the right
place (Kane, 1996)—and often also an ontologically distinct type of causation, agent
causation, that demands either substance dualism or emergent causation (O’Connor, 2000).
Furthermore, in general, claims about the incompatibility of any two concepts require more
evidence to establish than claims about their compatibility, in part because concepts that are
not obviously incompatible should be assumed to be compatible barring an argument to the
contrary. (See Lycan, 2003; Nahmias et al., forthcoming.)
[39] See Weinburg et al. (2001) and Nichols et al. (2003) for experimental work on
epistemological intuitions suggesting that these intuitions vary among people with different
educational backgrounds and between people from American and Asian cultures.
[40] Much of the work on people’s ‘‘folk theories’’ of biology, physics, and psychology (e.g.,
theory of mind) involves such experiments. Some find differences between participants’
Philosophical Psychology 581
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
reported intuitions about the relevant situations and their actual behavior in such situations
(see, for example, Keysar, Lina, & Barr, 2003).
[41] We ran pilot studies suggesting this. Scenarios describing an agent who was neurally
manipulated to deliberate and act in a certain way elicited almost unanimous judgments that
he was neither free nor responsible. When combined with the results from studies 1 and 2,
this suggests to us that people do not have the intuition, sometimes advanced by
incompatibilists, that determinism is no different than such covert manipulation (see
Pereboom, 2001), though further tests of this question would be useful.
[42] Similar worries would apply to any description of determinism that suggests that the laws of
nature control or constrain us, that our actions are fated by the past, that our conscious
decisions are causally inefficacious, etc. Such question-begging descriptions of determinism
would not show that the folk are incompatibilists about free will and determinism but only
that they are incompatibilists about free will and constraint, fate, epiphenomenalism, etc.
Notice that introductions to the problem of free will often use such misleading images
to portray the threat of determinism.
[43] Nichols (2004) used a roughly similar set-up and found that adults and children are more
likely to judge that a person could behave otherwise than that a physical object could. Nichols
suggested that these results indicate that people have a theory of agent causation, but for a
variety of reasons we think such a conclusion is too hasty. (See Turner & Nahmias, in
preparation.)
[44] Compare Peter Strawson’s (1962) claim that the reactive attitudes are ‘‘natural, original ...in
no way something we could choose or could give up’’ (note 7).
[45] This view is similar to van Inwagen’s (1983) view, dubbed ‘‘metaphysical flip-flopping’’ by
Fischer & Ravizza (1998), that if he were convinced determinism were true, he would
become a compatibilist rather than a skeptic about free will.
[46] Kane (1999) suggests that students ‘‘subjected to [a compatibilist] argument may have the
uneasy feeling they are being had’’ (p. 218). O’Connor (2000) writes, ‘‘Does freedom of
choice have this implication [that causal determinism is false]? It seems so to the typical
undergraduate on first encountering the question’’ (p. 4). We wonder whether these
philosophers’ students have these reactions in part due to the incompatibilist sympathies of
their professors.
[47] In fact, we ran one such test. One of the authors (E.N.), who happens to be a compatibilist,
ran the Fred and Barney survey on his Intro students soon after a two-week section on the
free will debate. The results, it turned out, were not significantly different from the results
garnered from ‘untrained’ participants: 83% of the ‘trained’ participants judged that Fred
and Barney acted of their own free will, where 76% of untrained participants had made such
judgments). Participants were asked whether studying the free will debate had influenced
their judgments, and roughly half said it had.
[48] Though we need to be wary of selling the folk short. My (E.N.) furniture delivery men, on
discovering I was a philosopher, told me they had solved the old riddle of whether the cup
was half full or half empty: ‘‘It’s half full,’’ they explained, ‘‘if it’s been filled halfway up and
it’s half empty if it’s been emptied halfway.’’ An excellent example of contextualist semantics!
References
Adams, F., & Steadman, A. (2004). Intentional action in ordinary language: Core concept or
pragmatic understanding? Analysis,64, 173–181.
Black, S., & Tweedale, J. (2002). Responsibility and alternative possibilities: The use and abuse of
examples. The Journal of Ethics,6, 281–303.
Campbell, C. A. (1951). Is ‘‘free will’’ a pseudo-problem? Journal of Philosophy,60, 441–465.
Clarke, R. (2003). Libertarian accounts of free will. New York: Oxford University Press.
582 E. Nahmias et al.
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
Dennett, D. (1984a). Elbow room: The varieties of free will worth wanting. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Dennett, D. (1984b). I could not have done otherwise: So what? Journal of Philosophy,81, 553–565.
Doris, J., & Stich, S. (forthcoming). As a matter of fact: Empirical perspectives on ethics. In F.
Jackson & M. Smith (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of contemporary analytic philosophy. Oxford,
England: Oxford University Press.
Double, R. (1991). The non-reality of free will. New York: Oxford University Press.
Double, R. (1996). Metaphilosophy and free will. New York: Oxford University Press.
Ekstrom, L. W. (2000). Free will. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Ekstrom, L. W. (2002). Libertarianism and Frankfurt-style cases. In R. Kane (Ed.), The Oxford
handbook of free will (pp. 309–322). New York: Oxford University Press.
Fischer, J. M. (1994). The metaphysics of free will. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.
Fischer, J. M. (forthcoming). Responsibility and alternative possibilities.
Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Frankfurt, H. (1969). Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility. Journal of Philosophy,66,
5–20.
Graham, G., & Horgan, T. (1994). Southern fundamentalism and the end of philosophy. In M. R.
Depaul & W. Ramsey (Eds.), Rethinking intuition (pp. 271–292). Lanham, MD: Rowman &
Littlefield.
Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics: A defense of conceptual analysis. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Kane, R. (1999). Responsibility, luck, and chance: Reflections on free will and indeterminism.
Journal of Philosophy,96, 217–240.
Keysar, B., Lina, S., & Barr, D. J. (2003). Limits on theory of mind use in adults. Cognition,89,
25–41.
Knobe, J. (2003a). Intentional action and side-effects in ordinary language. Analysis,63, 190–193.
Knobe, J. (2003b). Intentional action in folk psychology: An experimental investigation.
Philosophical Psychology,16, 309–324.
Knobe, J. (2004). Intention, intentional action and moral considerations. Analysis,64, 181–187.
Lycan, W. (2003). Free will and the burden of proof. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Minds and persons: Royal
Institute of Philosophy supplement (pp. 107–122). Cambridge, England: Cambridge University
Press.
Mele, A. (1995). Autonomous agents. New York: Oxford University Press.
Mele, A. (2001). Acting intentionally: Probing folk notions. In B. Malle, L. Moses & D. Baldwin
(Eds.), Intentions and intentionality: Foundations of social cognition (pp. 27–43). Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Mele, A. (2003). Intentional actions: Controversies, data, and core hypotheses. Philosophical
Psychology,16, 325–340.
Nadelhoffer, T. (2004). The butler problem revisited. Analysis,64, 277–284.
Nadelhoffer, T. (2005). Skill, luck, and folk ascriptions of intentional action. Philosophical
Psychology,18, 343–354.
Nahmias, E., Morris, S., Nadelhoffer, T., & Turner, J. (2004). The phenomenology of free will.
Journal of Consciousness Studies,11, 162–179.
Nahmias, E., Morris, S., Nadelhoffer, T., & Turner, J. (forthcoming). Is incompatibilism intuitive?
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.
Nichols, S. (2004). The folk psychology of free will: Fits and starts. Mind and Language,19,
473–502.
Nichols, S., & Knobe, J. (in preparation). Moral responsibility and determinism: Empirical
investigations of folk intuitions.
Nichols, S., Stich, S., & Weinburg, J. (2003). Metaskepticism: Meditations in ethno-epistemology.
In S. Luper (Ed.), The skeptics (pp. 227–247). Burlington, VT: Ashgate.
Philosophical Psychology 583
Downloaded By: [Swets Content Distribution] At: 12:08 8 February 2008
O’Connor, T. (2000). Persons and causes: The metaphysics of free will. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Pereboom, D. (2001). Living without free will. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Pink, T. (2004). Free will: A very short introduction. New York: Oxford University Press.
Smilansky, S. (2003). Compatibilism: The argument from shallowness. Philosophical Studies,115,
257–282.
Stich, S., & Weinberg, J. (2001). Jackson’s empirical assumptions. Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research,62, 637–643.
Strawson, G. (1986). Freedom and belief. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
Strawson, P. (1962). Freedom and resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy,48, 1–25.
Turner, J., & Nahmias, E. (in preparation). Are the folk agent-causationists? A response to Shaun
Nichols’ ‘‘The folk psychology of free will.’’
van Inwagen, P. (1992). Reply to Christopher Hill. Analysis,52, 56–61.
van Inwagen, P. (1983). An essay on free will. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
Vargas, M. (forthcoming). The revisionist’s guide to moral responsibility. Philosophical Studies.
Velleman, D. (2000). Epistemic freedom. In D. Velleman (Ed.), The possibility of practical reason.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Weinburg, J., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2001). Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical
Topics,29, 429–460.
Wolf, S. (1980). Asymmetrical freedom. Journal of Philosophy,77, 157–166.
Wolf, S. (1990). Freedom within reason. New York: Oxford University Press.
Woolfolk, R., Doris, J., & Darley, J. (forthcoming). The intuitive scientist as moral cognizer:
Constraint, identification, and responsibility.
584 E. Nahmias et al.