ArticlePDF Available

Anaphoric arguments of discourse connectives: Semantic properties of antecedents versus non-antecedents

Authors:

Abstract and Figures

We have argued extensively in prior work that discourse connectives can be analyzed as en-coding predicate-argument relations whose ar-guments derived from the interpretation of dis-course units. All adverbial connectives we have analyzed to date have expressed binary relations. But they are special in taking one of their two arguments structurally, and the other, anaphori-cally. As such, interpreting adverbial discourse connectives can be understood as a problem of anaphora resolution. In this paper we study the S-modifying adverbial connective "instead" and what, in the context, does and does not serve as antecedent for its anaphoric argument. This work extends earlier work investigating syntactic pat-terns of anaphoric arguments across a range of adverbial discourse connectives and the reliabil-ity with which these arguments can be annotated. The current work establishes, for 100 successive corpus instances of "instead", lexico-syntactic features of the antecedents of their anaphoric ar-guments that can be automatically annotated and therefore used to distinguish actual antecedents from potential competitors in the context.
Content may be subject to copyright.
Anaphoric arguments of discourse connectives: Semantic properties of
antecedents versus non-antecedents
Eleni Miltsakaki, Cassandre Creswell,
Katherine Forbes,Aravind Joshi,
Institute of Research in Cognitive Science
University of Pennsylvania
elenimi@linc.cis.upenn.edu
creswell@babel.ling.upenn.edu
forbesk@linc.cis.upenn.edu
joshi@linc.cis.upenn.edu
Bonnie Webber
School of Informatics
University of Edinburgh
bonnie@inf.ed.ac.uk
Abstract
We have argued extensively in prior work that
discourse connectives can be analyzed as en-
coding predicate-argument relations whose ar-
guments derived from the interpretation of dis-
course units. All adverbial connectives we have
analyzed to date have expressed binary relations.
But they are special in taking one of their two
arguments structurally, and the other, anaphori-
cally. As such, interpreting adverbial discourse
connectives can be understood as a problem of
anaphora resolution. In this paper we study the
S-modifying adverbial connective “instead” and
what, in the context, does and does not serve as
antecedent for its anaphoric argument. This work
extends earlier work investigating syntactic pat-
terns of anaphoric arguments across a range of
adverbial discourse connectives and the reliabil-
ity with which these arguments can be annotated.
The current work establishes, for 100 successive
corpus instances of “instead”, lexico-syntactic
features of the antecedents of their anaphoric ar-
guments that can be automatically annotated and
therefore used to distinguish actual antecedents
from potential competitors in the context.
1 Introduction
Discourse relations can be lexicalized in at least
two ways – with subordinate/coordinate conjunc-
tions and with adverbial phrases,1as in:
(1) Subordinate conjunction. Although Mr.
Hastings had been acquitted by a jury,
lawmakers handling the prosecution in
Congress had argued that the purpose of
impeachment isn’t to punish an individual.
1Discourse relations can also be lexicalized with a null
connective as in: ’You should not lend Tom any books. He
never returns them’. While we have included null connectives
in previous studies, they are not discussed in this paper.
(2) Coordinate conjunction. The Berkeley
police don’t have any leads but doubt the
crime was driven by a passion for sweets.
(3) Adverbial connective. No price for the
new shares has been set. Instead, the com-
panies will leave it up to the marketplace
to decide.
Both types of connectives can be analyzed as
encoding predicate-argument relations whose ar-
guments derive from the interpretation of dis-
course units (Webber and Joshi, 1998). With
subordinate or coordinate conjunction, those dis-
course units are the ones structurally joined by
the conjunction, thus enabling the semantics
of the relation to be built compositionally via
well-understood mappings of syntax to semantics
(Webber et al., 1999). We call subordinate and co-
ordinate conjunctions structural connectives. For
example, the structural connective although in (4)
expresses a concessive relation between the two
eventualities, P = RARELY EAT (SALLY, MEAT)
and Q = ENJOYS (SALLY, CHEESEBURGER).
(4) Although Sally rarely eats meat,
she enjoys an occasional bacon cheese-
burger.
All the adverbial connectives we have analyzed
to date express binary predicate-argument rela-
tions. They differ from structural connectives in
only getting one of their two arguments struc-
turally – the one they get from their matrix clause.
With respect to their other argument, we have ar-
gued extensively (Webber and Joshi, 1998; Web-
ber et al., 1999; Webber et al., 2003) that adver-
bial connectives behave like common discourse
anaphors (pronouns and NPs), obtaining this ar-
gument from the discourse context. The prob-
lem of interpreting adverbial connectives with re-
spect to the discourse can thus be reformulated as
an anaphor resolution problem, and, for this rea-
son, we often call adverbial connectives anaphoric
connectives. For example, if (4) were followed by
(5) Otherwise, she would pine away for lack
of grease.
the adverbial connective otherwise conveys a con-
ditional relation between the complement of Q
= ENJOYS (SALLY, CHEESEBURGER) and R =
PINE AWAY (SALLY).
From both a theoretical perspective (Gundel et
al., 1993; Prince, 1981; Walker and Prince, 1996;
Prince, 1999) and an empirical perspective, it is
clear that different discourse anaphors (e.g., third
person pronouns, definite NPs, demonstrative pro-
nouns, demonstrative NPs, ”other” NPS, etc.) dis-
play different properties with respect to where and
what in the discourse context they can draw their
referents from. For particular anaphors or sets
of anaphors, empirical studies can help elucidate
what those properties are.
In this paper, we report on an empirical study
of the surprisingly interesting adverbial connective
“instead”. “Instead” occurs in two forms: (1) as a
bare adverbial, and (2) with an “of” PP modifier.
In the latter form, it can be found with every type
of phrase, including NPs (Example 6), AdjPs (Ex-
ample 7), and PPs (Example 8):
(6) John ate an apple instead of a pear.
(7) John chose a bright yellow instead of a
dull blue shirt.
(8) John spent the afternoon at the zoo instead
of at the museum.
In this form, both arguments of “instead” can be
derived structurally: the first, from the phrase it
modifiers (e.g., “an apple” in Example 6) and the
second, from the object of its “of” PP (e.g., “a
pear” in the same example). Semantically, the “in-
stead of” phrase conveys that its second argument
(here, the “of” PP) is a salient but unchosen al-
ternative to its first argument, with respect to the
given predication. The notion of salient but un-
chosen or unrealized alternatives is basic to the
interpretation of “instead” in both its modified and
bare forms.
As a bare adverbial, “instead” gets its second ar-
gument anaphorically, from the discourse context.
As before, this argument corresponds to a salient
but unchosen or unrealized alternative. But not ev-
ery discourse context provides salient alternatives
for the anaphoric argument of “instead” to resolve
with, and therefore its use is not always licensed –
e.g.
(9) John ate an apple. #Instead he wanted a
pear.
(10) John wanted to eat a pear. Instead he ate
an apple.
(11) John won’t eat fruit. Instead, he eats only
candy bars and potato chips.
To better understand “instead” as a discourse
connective, we carried out an empirical study of
its discourse context and the properties of what,
in that context, did and did not serve as an an-
tecedent for its anaphoric argument. The results
will help in the development of an anaphor resolu-
tion mechanism for “instead” and a methodology
for developing anaphor resolution mechanisms for
other anaphoric connectives.
2 Previous Work
Our first empirical work in this area (Creswell et
al., 2002) was aimed at verifying the distinction
between structural and anaphoric connectives that
we had argued for on theoretical grounds. We
described a preliminary corpus annotation effort
for nine discourse connectives. The results indi-
cate that classes of connectives display distinctive
resolution patterns, as do individual connectives.
The preliminary annotation included mainly sur-
face syntactic features such as the location and
size of the argument, its clausal characteristics and
the location of the connective. Consistent with ex-
pected attentional constraints, most of the stud-
ied connectives had a strong tendency for their
left argument to be identified locally (in the struc-
tural sense) – either in the immediately preceding
sentence or in immediately preceding sequence of
sentences, in most cases the preceding paragraph.
Most notably, it was observed that so always takes
a sentence or a sequence of sentences as its left
argument, indicating that it might be treated as a
structural connective. In addition,yet,moreover,
as a result and also, tend to take their left argument
locally but they demonstrate a larger syntactic va-
riety of potential arguments such as subordinate
clauses or phrasal constituents. Finally, so,never-
theless and moreover are more likely to take larger
discourse segments as arguments.
3 Corpus Annotation Study: “Instead”
Our annotation study of the anaphoric connective
instead has two parts: (1) annotation of the an-
tecedent of its anaphoric argument and of lexico-
syntactic features of that antecedent that could
correlate with semantic properties suggestive of
salient alternatives that could be (but haven’t
been) realized or chosen; and (2) annotation of
clauses in close proximity to this antecedent which
could potentially serve as distractors or competing
antecedents (cf. Section 3.2).
The purpose of the first part of the study was
to establish whether every true antecedent of in-
stead could be characterized in terms of lexico-
syntactic features that could be automatically an-
notated. The purpose of the second part was to es-
tablish whether competing alternatives displayed
such features. If they didn’t, then the absence of
any such features on previous clauses close to bare
instead could be used to reject true negatives, and
the presence of such features or feature sets could
be used to strongly suggest a true positive.
3.1 Annotation of competing antecedents
We examined 100 successive instances of sentence
initial instead, in each case (a) identifying the text
containing the antecedent of its anaphoric argu-
ment; (b) computing inter-annotator agreement;
and (c) annotating lexico-syntactic features of the
antecedent. We then quantified the frequency of
appearance of these features in the identified argu-
ments.
The features we chose to annotate were ones
present in instances of instead that we had pre-
viously collected serendipitously: clausal nega-
tion, presence of a monotone-decreasing quanti-
fiers (e.g., few,seldom), presence of a modal aux-
iliary, presence of conditionality, and verb type.
In addition, some of our serendipitously collected
examples showed the antecedent of instead em-
bedded in a higher clause, and thereby not part of
the assertions of the sentence, as in clause (12),
which neither entails, presupposes, nor implicates
clause (13). So we also annotated whether or
not an antecedent was embedded in some higher
clause.
(12) John wanted to eat a pear.
(13) John ate a pear.
Table 1 contains the complete set of features used
in annotating the antecedent of the anaphoric ar-
gument of instead.
Feature Abbreviation
Verbal negation (Verbal neg.)
Subject negation (Subj. neg.)
Object negation (Obj. neg.)
Monotone decreasing quantifier (MDQ)
Modal auxiliary (Modal)
Conditional sentence (Condit.)
Embedded antecedent (Embed.)
Table 1: Set of annotation features
Features YES (of 97) NO (of 97)
Verbal neg. 37 (38%) 60 (62%)
Subj. neg. 5 (5%) 92 (95%)
Obj. neg. 10 (10%) 82 (85%)
MDQ 1 (1%) 96 (99%)
Modal 12 (12%) 85 (88%)
Condit. 1 (1%) 96 (99%)
Embed. 57 (59%) 40 (41%)
Table 2: Results from antecedent annotation of the
anaphoric argument
3.1.1 Results from the antecedent annotation
Table 2 shows the results of this annotation for
97 out of the 100 tokens in the original set. In the
remaining three cases the annotators did not agree
on the argument of instead, and these cases were
excluded from further analysis.
Antecedents could display zero or more of the
features from the set given in Table 2 – for exam-
ple, both a negative subject and a modal auxiliary,
or no value for “object negation” if the verb in the
antecedent clause is transitive. Three things stand
out: (1) the presence of negation on the verb or
one of its arguments, (2) the presence of a modal
auxiliary, and (3) the presence of a higher verb.
(We discuss this last feature and its significance in
Section 3.2).
In the majority of tokens (65 of 97 cases), at
least one of the first six features in Table 2 (i.e. all
features but EMBED) was present in the antecedent
of the anaphoric argument of instead. In an addi-
tional 27% of tokens, the semantics of either the
verbal predicate in the antecedent itself or the ver-
bal predicate embedding the antecedent admits al-
ternative situations or events (e.g., expect, want,
deny etc.), such as demand in (14), which em-
beds the antecedent clause that he surrender. We
will see in the next section, that the frequency of
these features in antecedent clauses is significantly
greater than their frequency in clauses which do
not serve as antecedents of instead.2
(14) Arriving at daybreak , they found Julio in
his corral and demanded
that he surren-
der
.Instead, he whirled and ran to his
house for a gun, forcing them to kill him ,
Cook reported .
In sum, for a total of 94% of tokens, we were
able to characterize features of the arguments that
could be automatically extracted from existing an-
notations and used to help resolve these anaphoric
arguments. In the remaining cases, the annotated
features were absent, meaning that the set of con-
ditioning features is incomplete.
3.2 Annotation of competing antecedents
For the annotation of competing antecedents, we
defined competing antecedent as follows: any fi-
nite or non-finite clause contained in the sentence
2In the case of the feature EMBED, it is the semantics of
the embedding verb, not just its syntactic properties that make
it a conditioning feature for the presence of an antecedent
argument. However, as will be seen below, the frequency of
embedding in actual vs. potential antecedents indicates that
even disregarding the identity of the embedding verb, this is
a useful property for identifying actual antecedents.
which contains the antecedent of instead or that in-
tervenes between the antecedent and the sentence
containing instead.
We adopt the traditional definition of sentence,
which contains a single main verb and all its asso-
ciated finite or non-finite clauses including relative
and adverbial clauses. We have also classified as
‘sentence’ instances with two main verbs in cases
of VP coordination, i.e., when the subject of the
second verb is omitted. While other definitions of
“competing antecedents” are plausible, our defini-
tion takes advantage of earlier results which show
that in most cases the antecedent of the anaphoric
argument of instead is contained within the imme-
diately preceding sentence or shortly before it.
The same set of features used in annotating the
anaphoric argument was also used in annotating
competing antecedents. We made this choice as
a preliminary step in building an anaphora reso-
lution algorithm. Our primary goal in annotat-
ing competing antecedents with the same set of
features was to evaluate their strength in distin-
guishing arguments from non-arguments in a well-
defined syntactic locality.
3.2.1 Results
For the set of 97 tokens of instead extracted in
the first part of this study, we identified 169 to-
kens of ’competing antecedents’. Table 3 shows
the results of the annotation. Overall, comparing
Tables 2 and 3, two things stand out:
1. Negation of the verb or one of its argu-
ments is much more common in the an-
tecedent of instead than in potentially com-
peting antecedents – 52/97 times ( 53%)
versus 35/169 times ( 20%).
2. The antecedent of the anaphoric argument of
instead is much more frequently embedded in
a higher verb than is a potentially competing
antecedent – 57/97 times ( 59%) vs 14/169
times ( 8%).
In our annotated example set, we do not
have enough instances of monotonically decreas-
ing quantifiers, modal auxiliaries or condition-
als to say whether their co-occurrence with the
antecedent of the anaphoric argument of instead
is significantly different from their co-occurrence
with potentially competing antecedents.
Features YES (of 169) No (of 169)
Verbal neg. 21 (12%) 148 (88%)
Subj. neg. 8 (5%) 161 (95%)
Obj. neg. 6 (4%) 139 (82%)
MDQ 0 (0%) 169 (100%)
Modal 17 (10%) 152 (90%)
Condit. 0 (0%) 169 (100%)
Emb. 14 (8%) 155 (91%)
Table 3: Results from feature annotation of com-
peting antecedents including higher verbs
What is not obvious from Table 2 is the nature
of the higher verbs that actual antecedents and po-
tentially competing antecedents occur with. The
difference between these sets is significant. In the
first case, the embedded clause may be desired
(“want”, “advise”, “insist”) or (un)expected (“ex-
pect”, “doubt”), described (“tell”, “say”), etc. but
is not asserted or presupposed to hold now or have
held before or to hold in the future. This makes
other alternatives that could hold both possible and
salient, one of which is the structural argument
of instead. Given the current set of seven fea-
tures here, a very simplistic resolution algorithm
based on implementing these features directly (i.e.
if
any
of the token’s features’ values is Y, then
the token should be marked as ANTECEDENT=Y)
would have very good recall, but poor precision.
Among other possible improvements, considera-
tion of the features of the structural argument of
instead, along with the features of the potential an-
tecedent candidate, could presumably decrease the
incidence of these false positives.
Table 4 shows that the set of features that ap-
pears to be successful for distinguishing between
actual and competing antecedents is not equally
useful for distinguishing between verbs that em-
bed the antecedent and competing antecedents. A
better characterization of the class of higher verbs
will be achieved by looking at differences of the
semantic properties of higher verbs that embed an-
tecedents from those that do not. In the case of
antecedents, higher verbs included insist, aban-
don, doubt, expect, tell, say, concede, want, be ap-
Features YES (out of 39) NO
Verbal neg. 4 (10%) 35 (90%)
Subj. neg. 1 (2%) 38 (98%)
Obj. neg. 2 (5%) 20 (51%)
MDQ 0 (0%) 39 (100%)
Modal 2 (5%) 37 (95%)
Condit. 1 (1%) 38 (99%)
Emb 2 (5%) 37 (95%)
Table 4: Results from feature annotation of higher
verbs
propriate), while higher verbs of potentially com-
peting antecedents included factive verbs such as
know. A clause with a factive verb can give rise
to salient alternatives, but not to alternatives to
the embedded clause because factive verbs presup-
pose its truth, as in (15). The continutation with
instead is possible in (16) but this is because of
the presence of negation in the higher clause.
(15) John regretted eating 12 bananas. *Instead
...
(16) John didn’t regret that eating 12 bananas.
Instead he was happy. (Instead possible
because of the negation)
Note that the antecedent of the anaphoric argu-
ment of instead is not the same as the abstract
object that serves as that argument (Webber et
al., 2003). Deriving arguments from antecedents
may require inference. However, as with resolv-
ing discourse deixis (Webber, 1991; Eckert and
Strube, 2001; Byron, 2002), properties of the ma-
trix clause containing the anaphor (here, instead)
can constrain the inference process. Thus in Ex-
ample 17, the fact that the anaphoric argument of
instead is an alternative to what Valhi and affiliates
will do with their Lockheed holdings, allows one
to infer from the (bolded) antecedent, that that ar-
gument is (roughly) Valhi and affiliates doing with
respect to Lockheed what the article said it would.
(17) Valhi Inc., another of Mr. Simmons’ com-
panies, responded to an article Monday in
The Wall Street Journal, which credited
a story in the Sunday Los Angeles Daily
News. Valhi said the articles didn’t ac-
curately reflect Valhi and its affiliates’
intentions toward Lockheed. Instead,
Valhi said, they may increase, decrease or
retain their Lockheed holdings , depend-
ing on a number of conditions.
4 Discussion
The set of annotated antecedents of the anaphoric
arguments of instead contained cases in which no
feature from our set was present. These cases are
particularly interesting as they highlight the com-
plex nature of the lexico-syntactic realization of
semantics that give rise to alternatives. In (18), for
example, annotators agreed that the antecedent of
instead was the phrase shown in boldface. How-
ever, this phrase has none of our annotated features
and the predicate ’recite’ is not one that appears to
give rise to alternatives.
(18) The tension was evident on Wednesday
evening during Mr. Nixon’s final banquet
toast, normally an opportunity for recit-
ing platitudes about eternal friendship
. Instead, Mr. Nixon reminded his host,
Chinese President Yang Shangkun, that
Americans haven’t forgiven China’s lead-
ers for the military assault of June 3-4 that
kil led hundreds, and perhaps thousands,
of demonstrators.
What appears to trigger alternatives are the
phrases “normally” and “an opportunity”, either
individually or together. The fact that (19) and
(20) are comparable to (21) and (22), suggests that
the range of lexical items triggering alternatives
is larger than negation and monotone decreasing
quantifiers, modality and certain classes of verbal
predicates, and moreover, does not correspond to
any previously defined set of linguistic elements.
(19) I had the opportunity to buy a cheap used
car. Instead, I bought a scooter.
(20) This event was an opportunity for John to
make amends. Instead, he caused more
trouble.
(21) I wanted to buy a car. Instead I bought a
scooter.
(22) John could have made amends. Instead he
caused more trouble.
5 Conclusion
In earlier work we argued that adverbial con-
nectives take one argument structurally and one
anaphorically. In this paper, we looked at the
lexico-syntactic realization of the antecedent of
the anaphoric argument of instead. For anaphora
resolution, the advantage of identifying lexico-
syntactic realizations of the relevant semantic fea-
tures is that such features can easily be extracted
automatically from available sources such as the
syntactic annotation of the Penn Treebank corpus
and the semantic annotation of the Penn PropBank
corpus. In future work, we plan to conduct a large
scale corpus annotation project on top of the Penn
Treebank and Penn PropBank in order to study (a)
the semantic properties of higher verbs embedding
the antecedent, (b) the relationship between the
structural and anaphoric argument of instead, and
(c) additional semantic properties of the arguments
of instead that will be useful in identifying the an-
tecedent of the anaphoric argument. The features
from the annotated corpus will then be used to de-
velop an anaphora resolution algorithm based on
a combination of a rule-based and machine learn-
ing procedure. The features from the annotated
corpus will then be used to develop an anaphora
resolution algorithm based on a combination of a
rule-based and machine learning procedure.
References
Donna Byron. 2002. Resolving pronominal reference
to abstract entities. In Proceedings of the 40 An-
nual Meeting, Association for Computational Lin-
guistics, pages 80–87, University of Pennsylvania.
Cassandre Creswell, Katherine Forbes, Eleni Milt-
sakaki, Rashmi Prasad, Bonnie Webber, and Ar-
avind Joshi. 2002. The discourse anaphoric prop-
erties of connectives. In Proceedings of the 4th Dis-
course Anaphora and Anaphor Resolution Collo-
quium (DAARC 2002), Lisbon, Portugal, pages 45–
50. Edic¸˜oes Colibri. (First four authors in alphabet-
ical order).
Miriam Eckert and Micahel Strube. 2001. Dialogue
acts, synchronising units and anaphora resolution.
Journal of Semantics.
Jeanette Gundel, Nancy Hedberg, and Ron Zacharski.
1993. Cognitive status and the form of referring ex-
pressions in discourse. Language, 69:274–307.
Ellen Prince, 1981. Radical Pragmatics, chapter To-
ward a Taxonomy of Given-New Information, pages
223–255. NY: Academic Press.
Ellen Prince, 1999. Focus: Linguistic, Cognitive, and
Computational Perspectives, chapter Subject Pro-
Drop in Yiddish, pages 82–101. Cambrige Univer-
sity Press.
Marilyn Walker and Ellen Prince. 1996. A bilateral ap-
proach to givenness: A hearer-status algorithm and a
Centering algorithm. In T. Fretheim and J. Gundel,
editors, Reference and Referent Accessibility, pages
291–306. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Bonnie Webber and Aravind Joshi. 1998. Anchor-
ing a lexicalized tree adjoining grammar for dis-
course. In ACL/COLING Workshop on Discourse
Relations and Discourse Markers, Montreal, pages
8–92. Montreal, Canada.
Bonnie Webber, Alistair Knott, Matthew Stone, and
Aravind Joshi. 1999. Discourse relations: A struc-
tural and presuppositional account using lexicalized
TAG. In Proceedings of the 37th Annual Meeting
of the Association for Computational Linguistics,
Maryland, pages 41–48. College Park MD.
Bonnie Webber, Aravind Joshi, Matthew Stone, and
Alistair Knott. 2003. Anaphora and discourse struc-
ture. Computational Linguistics.
Bonnie Webber. 1991. Structure and ostension in
the interpretation of discourse deixis. Natural Lan-
guage and Cognitive Processes, 6(2):107–135.
... However , in order to understand what licenses the use of a particular anaphoric discourse connective and hence resolve it, we also need to characterize the semantic properties of its arguments and their lexico-syntactic realization. This is the subject of (Miltsakaki et al., 2003), which focuses on the adverbial connective instead. Instead as a discourse connective conveys the fact that the interpretation of its matrix clause (its structural argument) is an alternative to something in the previous discourse that admits or invites alternatives (its anaphoric argument). ...
... However, in order to understand what licenses the use of a particular anaphoric discourse connective and hence resolve it, we also need to characterize the semantic properties of its arguments and their lexico-syntactic realization. This is the subject of ( Miltsakaki et al., 2003), which focuses on the adverbial connective instead. Instead as a discourse connective conveys the fact that the interpretation of its matrix clause (its structural argument) is an alternative to something in the previous discourse that admits or invites alternatives (its anaphoric argument). ...
Article
Full-text available
Large scale annotated corpora have played a critical role in speech and natu-ral language research. However, while existing annotated corpora such as the Penn Treebank have been highly suc-cessful at the sentence-level, we also need large-scale annotated resources that reliably encode key aspects of dis-course. In this paper, we detail (1) our plans for building the Penn Dis-course Treebank (PDTB), (2) our pre-liminary annotation work, and (3) the re-sults to date of our efforts. Annotation in the PDTB will focus on coherence relations associated with discourse con-nectives, including their argument struc-ture and anaphoric links, thus exposing a clearly defined level of discourse struc-ture and supporting the extraction of a range of inferences associated with dis-course connectives.
... The annotator used here was one of the early developers of the D-LTAG environment that engendered the PDTB framework (Forbes-Riley et al., 2006;Miltsakaki et al., 2003;Forbes et al., 2002), and was thus viewed as an expert. To verify this presumption an inter-annotator agreement study was performed. ...
... Some work on Arg1 identification for English reports results around 80% accuracy based on surface and syntactic features (Elwell and Baldridge, 2008), but it seems not likely that this can be reached for the fairly complicated distinction between NPs, VPs, and sentences for the German connectives we are studying here. The most promising route might be to aim for identifying just the heads of the antecedents, as done for English, e.g., by Wellner and Pustejovsky (2007); also, it can help to consider semantic features, as proposed by Miltsakaki et al. (2003) for the anaphoric connective instead. ...
... Empirical data on the predicate-argument structure of discourse connectives are now available in Release 1.0 of the annotated Penn Discourse TreeBank 4 (Dinesh et al., 2005, Miltsakaki et al., 2004a,b, Prasad et al., 2004, Webber, 2005). An early effort to use data in the PDTB to develop a procedure for resolving the anaphoric argument of the discourse adverbial instead is described in Miltsakaki et al. (2003), and the effect of Information Structure on the preferred argument of the discourse adverbial otherwise is described in Kruijff-Korbayová and Webber (2001). One final note: although D-LTAG produces only trees, it is acknowledged in Webber et al. (2003) — as noted earlier by Bateman (1999) and Gardent (1997) — that a discourse unit must be allowed to participate in one constituent structure with left-adjacent material and another with right-adjacent material, as inFigure 5 . ...
Article
Full-text available
At the start of my career, I had the good fortune of working with Ron Kaplan on Bill Woods'Lunar system (Woods et al., 1972). One day, in talking with Ron, I marvelled to him over the range of syntac-tic constructions I was able to implement in Lunar's ATN grammar formalism. Ron replied was that you could implement anything in an ATN: the point was, rather, to identify the minimal machinery required for a task. This sensible advice I subsequently sought to follow, and in this paper for Ron's festschrift, I try to apply it to understanding and comparing accounts of discourse relations.
... In the trivial cases, one of the propositional arguments indexed by the marker (for instead, the state of affairs that does not hold; for otherwise, the state of affairs that would normally cause something to happen) happens to be in the same clause that the connective is in. Many other times the argument is deeply embedded in other clauses, or extends over several clauses (Miltsakaki et al., 2003). Suffice it to say that a full account of the meaning and use of discourse connectives requires an expansion of the task of reference resolution. ...
Article
The English discourse marker yeah is widely recognized to hold several functions, doing the work not only of agreement and acknowledgment, but also topic management and speaker shift. In contrast, little attention has been paid to no, intuitively its opposite in meaning. Through detailed study of turn-initial tokens of no extracted from corpora of recorded conversations, I propose three senses of no as a discourse marker, on the basis of their pragmatic, semantic, and turn-sequential characteristics. These senses do the work of (i) topic shift, (ii) misunderstanding management, and (iii) turn-taking conflict resolution. While they share key semantic and pragmatic features with other DM and non-DM senses of no, especially negation and indexicality, they are distinguished from each other and other senses by their position within the utterance and larger discourse. I point out the significance of the existence of these senses for examination of complex discourse markers, and for the representation of ongoing discourse.
... This brought the framework closer to a lexicalized TAG, and led Aravind Joshi and myself to begin to explore whether the insights of lexicalized grammars could also be applied to low-level discourse, that is, whether one could have an autonomous grammar for low-level discourse in which words (or in some cases, idiomatic phrases) were associated with discourse-level predicate–argument structures or modification structures that conveyed their syntactic-semantic meaning and scope (Webber & Joshi, 1998). This exploration has continued over the last 6 years, engaging the attention and efforts of several students and colleagues (Creswell et al., 2002;Forbes, 2003;Forbes et al., 2001;Forbes-Riley, Webber, & Joshi, submitted for publication;Miltsakaki, Creswell, Forbes, Joshi, & Webber, 2003;Miltsakaki, Prasad, Joshi, & Webber, 2004;Prasad, Miltsakaki, Joshi, & Webber, 2004;Webber, Joshi, & Knott, 2000;Webber, Knott, & Joshi, 2001;Webber, Knott, Stone, & Joshi, 1999a,b;Webber, Stone, Joshi, & Knott, 2003). Some of what we believe has been gained through this exploration is specific to a lexicalized approach to discourse, while other gains have been truly new and general insights into the way in which discourse structure and semantics project from lexico-syntactic elements. ...
Article
This paper surveys work on applying the insights of lexicalized grammars to low-level discourse, to show the value of positing an autonomous grammar for low-level discourse in which words (or idiomatic phrases) are associated with discourse-level predicate–argument structures or modification structures that convey their syntactic-semantic meaning and scope. It starts by describing a lexicalized Tree Adjoining Grammar for discourse (D-LTAG). It then reviews an initial experiment in parsing text automatically, using both a lexicalized TAG and D-LTAG, and then touches upon issues involved in how lexico-syntactic elements contribute to discourse semantics. The paper concludes with a brief description of the Penn Discourse TreeBank, a resource being developed for the study of discourse structure and semantics.
Article
Full-text available
Özet Söylemi konu alan berimsel kuramlar, bağdaşıklık ve doğal dil işlemleme konularını anlamamızı sağlar. Bu yazıda söylemi inceleyen çeşitli berimsel kuramlar ve ele aldıkları konular ele alınmaktadır. Örneğin, bağdaşıklık türlerini bağlaçların varlığıyla açıklayan, sözdizim-söylem arasında doğrudan bir bağ aramayı öneren ve sonlu sayıda olduklarını öne süren kuramlardan söz edilmekte, bu kuramların yapı ve anlama ne derecede bağlı kaldıkları konusuna ışık tutulmaktadır. Anahtar Sözcükler: söylem, bağdaşıklık, bağdaşıklık ilişkileri, berimsel dilbilim kuramları Discourse and Coherence Relations Abstract Computational theories of discourse have contributed to our understanding of discourse coherence and natural language processing. In this study, we address the issues raised in these theories, such as the connective-based approaches to discourse, the possibility of direct mapping from syntax to discourse, and whether the number of coherence relations is limited or left open based on empirical observations as suggested by the theories, their degree of reliance on the structure and meaning.
Article
Full-text available
Öz: Söylemi konu alan berimsel kuramlar, bağdaşıklık ve doğal dil işlemleme konularını anlamamızı sağlar. Bu yazıda söylemi inceleyen çeşitli berimsel kuramlar ve ele aldıkları konular ele alınmaktadır. Örneğin, bağdaşıklık türlerini bağlaçların varlığıyla açıklayan, sözdizim-söylem arasında doğrudan bir bağ aramayı öneren ve sonlu sayıda olduklarını öne süren kuramlardan söz edilmekte, bu kuramların yapı ve anlama ne derecede bağlı kaldıkları konusuna ışık tutulmaktadır. Anahtar sözcükler: söylem, bağdaşıklık, bağdaşıklık ilişkileri, berimsel dilbilim kuramları Abstract: Computational theories of discourse have contributed to our understanding of discourse coherence and natural language processing. In this study, we address the issues raised in these theories, such as the connective-based approaches to discourse, the possibility of direct mapping from syntax to discourse, and whether the number of coherence relations is limited or left open based on empirical observations as suggested by the theories, their degree of reliance on the structure and meaning.
Chapter
Languages enable their speakers to use word order to mark the information status of the various elements in a sentence. This chapter investigates the information status of syntactically subordinate clauses in Turkish by examining the cases where subordinate clauses have a discourse role. Using data from the current release of the Turkish Discourse Bank, the study finds that sentence-initial subordinate clauses do not have a discourse-level information status, but in cases where a series of subordinate clauses are chained to each other, non-sentence-initial subordinate clauses may have information value at the discourse level. The paper suggests that in Turkish, syntactic subordination is not always discourse-level subordination and that in non-sentence-initial positions, the subordinate clauses may be discourse-relevant.
Conference Paper
Full-text available
The Penn Discourse TreeBank (PDTB) is a new resource built on top of the Penn Wall Street Journal corpus, in which discourse connectives are annotated along with their arguments. Its use of standoff annotation allows integration with a stand-off version of the Penn TreeBank (syntactic structure) and PropBank (verbs and their arguments), which adds value for both linguistic discovery and discourse modeling. Here we describe the PDTB and some experiments in linguistic discovery based on the PDTB alone, as well as on the linked PTB and PDTB corpora.
Conference Paper
Full-text available
We show that discourse structure need not bear the full burden of conveying discourse relations by showing that many of them can be explained nonstructurally in terms of the grounding of anaphoric presuppositions (Van der Sandt, 1992). This simplifies discourse structure, while still allowing the realisation of a full range of discourse relations. This is achieved using the same semantic machinery used in deriving clause-level semantics.
Article
Full-text available
This paper examines demonstrative pronouns used as deictics to refer to the interpretation of one or more clauses. Although this usage is frowned upon in style manuals such as (Strnnk and White, 1959), who say "This. The pronoun this, referring to the complete sense of a preceding sentence or clause, cannot always carry the load and so may produce an imprecise statement." it is nevertheless very common in written text. Handling this usage poses a problem for Natural Language Understanding systems. The solution I propose is based on distinguishing between what can be pointed to and what can be referred to by virtue of pointing. I argue that a restricted set of discourse segments yield what such demonstrative pronouns can point to in the discourse model and a restricted set of what Nunberg (1979) has called referring functions yield what they can refer to by virtue of that pointing.
Article
Full-text available
Discourse connectives can be analyzed as encoding predicate-argument relations whose arguments derive from the interpretation of discourse units. These arguments can be anaphoric or structural. Although structural arguments can be encoded in a parse tree, anaphoric arguments must be resolved by other means. A study of nine connectives, annotating the location, size, and syntactic type of their arguments, shows connective-specific patterns for each of these features. A preliminary study of inter-annotator consistency shows that it too varies by connective. Results of the corpus study will be used in the development of resolution algorithms for anaphoric connectives.
Article
Full-text available
This paper has shown how using a bilateral approach to givenness which treats Hearer-status independently of Discourse-status can account for the distinction between different types of Evoked or Activated discourse entities. We have proposed a simple Hearer-status algorithm and have used the Centering framework to model Discourse-status. The distinctions in Centering between the Cb and the Cp and among the Transitions Continue, Retain, Smooth-shift, and Rough-Shift define a preference ranking of interpretations.
Article
Full-text available
We here explore a "fully" lexicalizod Tree-Adjoining Grammar for discourse that takes the basic ele- ments of a (monologic) discourse to be not simply clauses, but larger structures that are anchored on variously realized discourse cues This link with intra-sentential grammar suggests an account for different patterns of discourse cues. while the different structures and operations suggest three sepa- rate sources for elements of discourse meaning: (1) a compositional semantics tied to the basic trees and operations; (2) a presuppositional semantics carried by cue phrases that freely adjoin to trees; and (3) general inference, that draws additional, defensible conclusions that flesh out what is conveyed compositionally.
Conference Paper
This paper describes PHORA, a technique for resolving pronominal reference to either individual or abstract entities. It defines processes for evoking abstract referents from discourse and for resolving both demonstrative and personal pronouns. It successfully interprets 72% of test pronouns, compared to 37% for a leading technique without these features.
Article
In this paper we propose six implicationally related cognitive statuses relevant for explicating the use of referring expressions in natural language discourse. These statuses are the conventional meanings signalled by determiners and pronouns, and interaction of the statuses with Grice's Maxim of Quantity accounts for the actual distribution and interpretation of forms when necessary conditions for the use of more than one form are met. This proposal is supported by an empirical study of the distribution of referring expressions in naturally occurring discourse in five languages-English, Japanese, Mandarin Chinese, Russian, and Spanish.
Article
Thesis proposal; final thesis appeared as TR 815. Existing algorithms for pronoun resolution typically cast the problem into a coreference task, which means they simply identify an antecedent noun phrase for each pronoun. Selection of the antecedent is usually based on a calculation of salience or focus. This simplified approach is unable to account for pronouns without noun-phrase antecedents. Examples are abstract referents such as events, propositions, and speech acts that might appear in the linguistic surface form as sentential complements, verbal constructions or entire sentences, as well as consequences or outcomes that don't appear in the surface form at all. This paper contains a survey of current methods of pronoun resolution for natural language understanding. It then proposes a strategy for resolving pronominal reference to abstract entities that incorporates semantic information in addition to salience calculations. Preliminary experiments are described that show the strategy to perform well above baseline on a collection of spoken task-oriented dialogs.
Article
In this paper, we present the results of a corpus analysis, and a model of anaphora resolution in spontaneous spoken dialogues. The main finding of our corpus analysis is that less than half the pronouns and demonstratives have NP antecedents in the preceding text; 22% have sentential antecedents and the remainder have no identifiable linguistic antecedents. As part of' the corpus analysis we present the results of inter-annotator agreement tests. These were carried out for the annotation of anaphor types and their antecedents, and for the segmentation of the dialogues into dialogue acts. The results of the inter-annotator agreement tests indicate that our classification method is reliable and that the annotated dialogues can be used as a standard against which to measure the performance of the anaphor resolution algorithm. The algorithm, based on Strube (1998), is capable of classifying pronouns and demonstratives, and co-indexing anaphors with NP and sentential antecedents. The domain from which potential antecedents for both individual and discourse-deictic anaphors can be elicited is defined in terms of dialogue acts. The dialogue segmentation method uses dialogue acts to form Synchronizing Units , which reflect the achievement of common ground (Stalnaker 1974, 1979). We show that predicate information, NP form, and dialogue structure can be successfully used in the resolution process.