ArticlePDF Available

Good computing: a pedagogically focused model of virtue in the practice of computing (part 2)

Authors:

Abstract and Figures

Purpose The purpose of this paper is to present a four component model of ethical behavior (PRIMES) that integrates literature in moral psychology, computing ethics, and virtue ethics as informed by research on moral exemplars in computing. This is part 1 of a two‐part contribution. Design/methodology/approach This psychologically based and philosophically informed model argues that moral action is: grounded in relatively stable PeRsonality characteristics (PR); guided by integration of morality into the self‐system; shaped by the context of the surrounding moral ecology; and facilitated by morally relevant skills and knowledge (S). Findings The model seeks to explain the daily successful (and unsuccessful) performance of moral action by computing professionals and to provide groundwork for a pedagogy that emphasizes ethically effective performance. Practical implications The model has significant implications for how ethical action might be taught to computer professionals and other design professionals. It also makes recommendations about what is needed to measure to construct a complete picture of sustained ethical action in a profession. Originality/value Most accepted models of ethical behavior are unidimensional, emphasizing either principled reasoning or a simplistic model of integrity/character. This model brings together a variety of disparate literatures in the light of its emphasis on sustained moral action in the profession. It thereby provides researchers and educators with a picture of what is needed to construct a complete understanding of moral action in the profession.
Content may be subject to copyright.
Good computing: a pedagogically
focused model of virtue in the
practice of computing (part 1)
Chuck Huff
St Olaf College, Northfield, Minnesota, USA
Laura Barnard
Duke University, Durham, North Carolina, USA, and
William Frey
College of Business Administration, University of Puerto Rico, Mayaguez,
Puerto Rico, USA
Abstract
Purpose – The purpose of this paper is to present a four component model of ethical behavior
(PRIMES) that integrates literature in moral psychology, computing ethics, and virtue ethics
as informed by research on moral exemplars in computing. This is part 1 of a two-part
contribution.
Design/methodology/approach This psychologically based and philosophically informed model
argues that moral action is: grounded in relatively stable PeRsonality characteristics (PR); guided by
integration of morality into the self-system; shaped by the context of the surrounding moral ecology;
and facilitated by morally relevant skills and knowledge (S).
Findings The model seeks to explain the daily successful (and unsuccessful) performance of moral
action by computing professionals and to provide groundwork for a pedagogy that emphasizes
ethically effective performance.
Practical implications – The model has significant implications for how ethical action might be
taught to computer professionals and other design professionals. It also makes recommendations
about what is needed to measure to construct a complete picture of sustained ethical action in a
profession.
Originality/value Most accepted models of ethical behavior are unidimensional, emphasizing
either principled reasoning or a simplistic model of integrity/character. This model brings together a
variety of disparate literatures in the light of its emphasis on sustained moral action in the profession.
It thereby provides researchers and educators with a picture of what is needed to construct a complete
understanding of moral action in the profession.
Keywords Computers, Ethics, Professional ethics, Individual psychology, Personality
Paper type Conceptual paper
The current issue and full text archive of this journal is available at
www.emeraldinsight.com/1477-996X.htm
The authors express their thanks to Jose Cruz-Cruz, Almut Furchert, Deborah Johnson,
Dan Lapsley, Darcia Narvaez, Michael Pritchard, and Simon Rogerson for their comments on
earlier versions of this theoretical approach. Thanks to Thomas Pearson, Charles Harris, and
Ken Fleischmann for detailed comments on an earlier version of this paper. This work was
partially supported by NSF grants DUE-9980786, DUE-9972280, and SES-0217298 to Chuck Huff
and NSF grant SES-0551779 to William Frey. The opinions expressed in this paper are the
opinions of the authors and not of the National Science Foundation.
JICES
6,3
246
Journal of Information,
Communication & Ethics in Society
Vol. 6 No. 3, 2008
pp. 246-278
qEmerald Group Publishing Limited
1477-996X
DOI 10.1108/14779960810916246
[...] we are inquiring not in order to know what virtue is, but in order to become good, since
otherwise our inquiry would have been of no use (Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, Book II,
Section 2).
In the summer of 1987, Nathaniel Borenstein received a call from Lt. Commander
David Blower asking him to consult with NATO on the design of embedded training
and help modules for battlefield weapons systems, including those that target and
launch theatre nuclear weapons. A lifelong pacifist, Nathaniel’s first reaction was to
politely decline; he had made it a habit, based on his principles, to avoid military work.
But after some conversation, Nathaniel decided to change his longstanding practice
and accept this particular invitation. The alternative, he felt, was too risky. Embedded
systems are training or help modules that run on actual battlefield weapons. Other
military consultants were recommending that NATO adopt this approach to training
and help systems. It had proven effective in many commercial and academic systems
(some of which Nathaniel had designed himself).
The problem, as Nathaniel saw it, was one of “Oops, I was sure that nuclear missile
launcher was in simulation mode... ” Even help systems that suggest how commands
might be completed (as in the popular TOPS-20 system of the time) can be dangerous.
There has always been resistance to taking the human completely out of the loop in
important military decisions such a missile launching. But under pressure, when the
embedded expert system for help says “Push the red button” we come closer to doing
just that, and the possibility of unintentional nuclear war. Nathaniel knew that
simulation and help systems are rarely written to the reliability standards of actual
battlefield systems, and that allowing them into the battlefield by this back door would
create a multitude of possible hazards (e.g. perhaps a malfunction fails to erase the
words “simulation mode” from the screen, leaving the operator to think a live weapon
is still in simulation). In a similar incident in 1979, jet fighters were “scrambled” to
protect against an illusory nuclear attack in the United States when a simulation tape
of an attack had been accidentally loaded into the monitoring systems.
Nathaniel decided to consult with NATO in order to convince them of the dangers of
such systems. He was pleasantly surprised by the intelligence, seriousness and ethical
concern of the military officials. And he was equally astonished by the lack of such
concern on the part of business contractors and some researchers whose livelihoods
depended on getting NATO money to design embedded systems. He thus found
himself a pacifist in the halls of a NATO working group in Berchtesgarten, helping to
design systems that kill people (Borenstein, 1989).
A pedagogical model of virtue in computing
How are we to understand Borenstein’s change of heart? It is clearly not a simple or an
isolated decision, and perhaps not even a change of heart. Nathaniel had a long history
of concern for ethical principles, and he continued this concern after his stint as a
NATO consultant. Nathaniel’s actions can best be understood in terms of his
development over time into a professional who had acquired the imagination,
creativity, commitment, and skills to respond flexibly to the demands of his profession.
Understanding this development, in all its complexity, is one central task for an
adequate ethics of computing (or of any profession). It is central because it is these
complex sequences of coordinated action over time that are at the heart of ethical
behavior. It is also central because understanding the development of the profesional’s
Good computing
247
ability to plan and guide these sequences is crucial to understanding how to foster that
development, that is, how to teach ethical computing (Cunningham, 2005; Davidson,
2005; Kupperman, 2005). Thus, we are proposing a model that helps us understand
how computer professionals sustain ethical action in their careers, with the aim that
this model will help us to think through the pedagogy of professional ethics. It will do
so by focussing our pedagogy and curriculum on those things that will most support
our students’ quest to be thoughtful, ethical professionals in their careers. We are not
interested in entering the foundationalist battles about whether consequentialist,
deontological, virtue, or some other form of ethical argument is the best decision model
for the computing professions. In fact, in terms of both values and method we are
unabashedly pluralist. There are multiple ways to be an ethical computer professional
and multiple methods that converge to support this goal. We are interested in
constructing a model that accurately reflects the reality of the moral careers of
computer professionals and that consequently can serve as a guide to pedagogy aimed
at preparing students for moral careers.
With these goals in mind, we propose a psychologically informed and
philosophically aware model of ethical computing. This model is based on the most
recent work in moral psychology (Haidt, 2008; Huff and Frey, 2005; Lapsley and
Narvaez, 2005; Narvaez and Lapsley, 2005) and on an analysis of extensive interviews
with moral exemplars in computing (Huff and Rogerson, 2005). The model is not
narrowly focused on how Nathaniel Borenstein might have made the right decision in
this particular story. Instead, it is focused on how he became the sort of person who
was able to recognize an opportunity for moral action, to make a good decision, and
then able to carry it out in the competitive discussion forum he encountered at NATO.
In psychological terms, we are interested in how individuals achieve sustained
excellence in ethical behavior in the field of computing. In philosophical terms, we are
interested in how individuals attain the virtues needed to achieve the virtuous practice
of computing. Our approach is intentionally pedagogical, partly because virtue theory
lends itself to this goal, but also because we are interested in more than simply
describing ethical behavior; we hope to provide a theoretical groundwork to support
the training of individuals to achieve ethical behavior.
Models of ethical behavior
The recent literatures in moral psychology and in philosophical ethics converge on a
model of ethical behavior that casts a wider net than older decision-based approaches
(Pincoffs, 1971, 1986) that view Borenstein’s behavior as a series of decisions joined by
commitment to principle. The philosophical turn to virtue theory has resulted in a
model that treats Borenstein’s behavior as stemming from his character. This approach
has helpfully broadened the field of view to characteristic ways of behaving (including
the necessary practical knowledge and skill to perceive moral opportunity, choose well,
and then enact those choices). But, it has usually left the notion of character or moral
commitment unanalyzed, and thus suffered at the hands of critics (Doris, 2002) who use
the social psychology literature to point out the seeming lack of coherence in principled
action that the character model presupposes. In turn, the moral psychology literature
has moved from a model of principled reasoning (Kohlberg and Kramer, 1969), to a
recognition of the importance of situational influence (Zimbardo, 2007), moral emotion
(Haidt, 2001), skills and knowledge (Narvaez and Lapsley, 2005), and the integration of
JICES
6,3
248
moral goals into the self concept (Blasi, 1980). But, this literature has remained
fragmented, and with a few exceptions (Doris, 2002; Appiah, 2008) not integrated into
the burgeoning virtue theory literature. Our intention here is to bring these literatures
together, in light of recent work on morally exemplary computing professionals (Huff
and Rogerson, 2005; Huff and Barnard, n.d.), and to use them to inform a model of
sustained moral action in computing that can guide our attempts to teach.
The turn to virtue
The resurgence of virtue ethics (Harmon, 1998/1999; Crisp and Slote, 1997; Solomon,
2003) provides a model that looks more long term at sequences of behavior and
characteristic ways of behaving. By viewing virtue as a character trait, it provides the
necessary unity of action over time that we see as a part of Borenstein’s life story. And
by identifying particular virtues that support action (e.g. patience, charity, and
empathy; Davis et al., 2004), and that support consistency (e.g. integrity; Blasi, 2005)
virtue theories attempt to link character to action.
This resurgence is conventionally dated to Anscombe’s (1958) call to set aside the
foundationalist debates of modern ethics (e.g. what is the best ethical system?) and
instead re-appropriate the notion of virtue. Even at this early date, Anscombe linked
the turn to virtue to the need for an adequate moral psychology (see Appiah, 2008, for a
helpful discussion of the role of moral psychology in the history of virtue ethics). In a
more thorough critique of moral theory since the enlightenment, MacIntyre (1981/2007)
attempted a review of the multiple lists of virtues that were emerging. He proposed that
differences in the lists were a function of differences in the moral communities that
called for and supported them. After MacIntyre (1981/2007), numerous systems of
virtue theory were developed (see Crisp and Slote, 1997 for a selection).
Still, much of the renaissance of virtue theory did not articulate the unanalyzed
conceptual unit of “character” more than to cast it as a disposition to act in a virtuous
way (Doris and Stich, 2005). The appeal to character provides the much-needed unity of
action over time that is essential to virtue approaches. Bradey (1876/1962) presents
responsibility in terms of the metaphor of answering a moral tribunal for our actions.
He outlines three presuppositions for attributing responsibility: self-sameness, moral
sense, and action-ownership ( ¼absence of ignorance or compulsion). Self-sameness
is the metaphysical condition that there be something sufficiently enduring to serve as
the target of responsibility attributions. In the context of this discussion, Bradley
proposes two criteria for an adequate account of character in the context of
responsibility attributions:
(1) character must be robust enough to satisfy the self sameness requirement; but
(2) it must not be so fixed as to render impossible character change (character
cannot be compulsion).
This balance of permanence and change has become the central bone of contention in
recent claims about the role of character in virtuous action.
The insistence on character as unity of action, in particular, tends to require
superhuman consistency of a virtuous person, since the “characteristic way” of acting
is supposed to be situationally invariant; rarely if ever bowing to pressure, always
manifesting itself, with any inconsistency thought of as failure of will or of virtue.
Thus, most of these simplistic virtue approaches fall prey to the radical situationalist
Good computing
249
critiques of philosophers like Harmon (1998/1999) and Doris (Doris and Stich, 2005;
Doris, 2002). Using classic work from social psychology (Milgram, 1974; Ross and
NIbsbett, 1991), they make it clear that simple cross-situational consistency is a
chimera. Still, the conclusion that there is no character, or that we must construct virtue
without it, is premature.
Solomon (2003, 2005) is one contemporary philosopher who provides us with a more
flexible and adaptive approach to virtue and character, perhaps because it is focused
on the real problems, situational fluidity, and pressures for compromise of the practical
field of business ethics. For Solomon, the virtuous businessperson develops over time,
responds flexibly to changing situations, makes judgments about when particular
virtues are relevant or appropriate, and thereby exhibits so much flexibility in behavior
that the simplistic expectation of consistency is bound to be disappointed. The virtuous
businessperson even constructs situations that constrain him or her to behave in a
virtuous manner. Thus, Solomon recognizes that virtue need not spring solely from
character. As he says, “circumstances and character cannot be pried apart and should
not be used competitively as alternative explanations of virtuous or vicious behavior”
(Solomon, 2003, p. 56). In a similar manner, Appiah (2008) draws from much of the
same social science literature as Doris (2002), but emerges with a picture of character in
the middle ground between adamant continuity and aimless situational drifting. For
both Solomon (2005) and Appiah (2008), character mediates between the goals and
desires of the individual and the situational demands of the moment.
In constructing our model, we take several core ideas from the emerging discussion
on virtue. First, we take its focus on long sequences of planned action considered in the
context of a continuous narrative of the moral career as the central issue in our
discussion of ethics. In Aristotle’s terms, this is because the discussion is about making
the enquiry of use to us so that we and our students can become good (and not merely
make a good decision). We also take the notion that virtue is something that is
developed over time, as the result of practice, and that it is thus in many ways like a
skill. And again, this is because the goal of the enquiry, for us and for our students, is to
become good, rather than simply to know what virtue is. And we adopt the insistence
of many virtue theorists (MacIntyre, 1981/2007; Doris, 2002) that virtue is embedded
within a community also leads us to take seriously the situationalist challenge and to
recognize the interactions among personal characteristics and enduring (and
ephemeral) characteristics of the social surround. Finally, while rejecting the notion
of character as a permanent, underlying, changeless substance, we preserve a dynamic
notion of character that lives between the extremes of changeless substrate and radical
dissolution. The psychological literature converges on the idea that character can best
be approached as emerging from the interaction of core personality traits, the self
system, skill and knowledge sets, and the moral ecology (ME) within which the
individual operates.
The renaissance of moral psychology
After initial enquiries into moral character in children (Hartshorne and May, 1930)
showed remarkably little consistency in character, work in moral psychology
languished until the cognitive revolution made possible Lawrence Kohlberg’s
(Kohlberg and Kramer, 1969) groundbreaking work in moral development.
Kohlberg’s work is rooted in models of cognitive development (Piaget, 1965) and
JICES
6,3
250
thus constructs the moral task as a phenomenalist (Kohlberg and Kramer, 1969;
Narvaez, 2005; Lapsley and Narvaez, 2005), assuming the centrality of conscious,
effortful cognition that generates decisions and intentions that then guide behavior.
Kohlberg (1971) was aware of the philosophical work of his time and attempted to
integrate philosophical concerns into his system. Thus, most of his empirical and
theoretical work focused on the moral reasoning associated with moral justification.
The advantage of this approach was that it made morality something one could
study with cognitive methods and something one could train. There is now a large
literature of Kohlberg-based research that supports the central role cognition plays in
moral life and makes clear the effect of training on moral reasoning (Rest, 1979, 1986;
Rest and Narvaez, 1994; Narvaez and Lapsley, 2005; Bebeau and Brabeck, 1994; Logan,
1985; Burson et al., 2006). But, there are also substantive critiques of this approach as
explaining only a small portion of ethical behavior, leading to a narrow and sterile
understanding that excludes the richness of ethical life as it is actually lived (Flanagan,
1991; Pritchard, 1991, 1996; Blasi, 2005; Marnburg, 2000; Gorman et al., 2000).
In recent work, Lapsley and Narvaez (2005) and Huff and Frey (2005) now explicitly
claim that moral psychology is “post-Kohlberg.” Both use the familiar “paradigm shift”
language (Kuhn, 1962) to emphasize the foundational importance of Kohlberg’s work
and to recognize that the most current work in the field is no longer occupied with the
phenomena, problems, and structure of moral psychology as conceived in Kohlberg’s
terms. Many are still doing the exciting work of character education that was pioneered
by Kohlberg (Lapsley and Narvaez, 2006), but the meaning of character, the language
used to describe it, and its relation to moral behavior are cast in quite different terms.
Rest (1979, 1986) was one of the first people to attempt to design a model that would
use Kohlberg’s approach to relate character, virtues, and moral action to one another in
meaningful ways. Rest proposed a four-component model and emphasized that each
component interacted with the others. Within Rest’s (1979, 1986) model were the
components moral judgment, moral sensitivity, moral motivation, and moral character.
The component of moral judgment involves recognizing the many courses of action
that are available and the competing demands upon oneself. In the midst of a situation
with many choices, the skill is in being able to recognize which option is the most just,
ethical, and responsible. This aspect of the model is where Kohlberg began and ended
his consideration of the skills and cognitions that lead to moral behavior (Narvaez,
2005; Bebeau and Thoma, 1999) and there is clear evidence that students can improve
in this area with training.
However, Rest’s (1979, 1986) model extends beyond moral judgment to incorporate
affective and behavioral components. Skill in moral sensitivity is the ability to interpret
situations as having potential for ethical responses. Second, moral motivation involves
marshalling the variety of available motivators, in the face of competing concerns, to
choose and maintain moral action. Moral character is the ability to plan and carry out
actions that support the moral choice. In his descriptions of these components, Rest
(1979, 1986) mentions a few concrete skills (e.g. moral character involves the skill of
avoiding distraction) but the only component with any real detail that might guide
pedagogy is the Kohlberg driven component of moral judgment. The model remains
abstract (though Narvaez et al. (2004) provide significant specificity in their list of
skills). Thus, while Rest (1979) was revolutionary in terms of bringing the cognitive,
behavioral, and affective components of morality together, what has been sorely
Good computing
251
needed since are adaptations of the model to make it specific so that it may inform
ethics education (Bebeau and Thoma, 1999; Narvaez et al., 2004). In addition, even the
neo-Kohlbergian approaches derived from Rest’s model (Narvaez, 2005) do not take
seriously the strong challenge from the situationalists (Doris, 2002) and do not
systematically incorporate the influences of the situation on moral action.
Still, recent psychological work on conscious and automatic processing has given
psychologists new language to describe the different ways that thought and emotion
influence action (and vice versa; Haidt, 2001). New work on values (Roccas et al., 2002;
Schwartz and Bilsky, 1990), on PeRsonality characteristics (John and Srivastava, 1999;
McCrae and Costa, 1999) and their expression in behavior (Shoda and Mischel, 1998;
Mischel et al., 2002), on expertise (Hogarth, 2001; Pritchard, 1998; Pritchard, 2006), on
how personal projects are expressed in action (Little, 1983) and on the structure of the
self (Blasi, 2005; Sheilds and Bredemeier, 2005) have all made possible a more
variegated understanding of how character might be formed and expressed in action.
Thus, we take inspiration from the explosion of psychological work relevant to
morality to create a model of virtue that incorporates recent understandings of both
internal and situational influences on sustained moral action.
The PRIMES model of successful moral action
This model arises from our study of moral exemplars in expertise (Huff and Rogerson,
2005; Huff and Barnard, n.d.). In this research, we did extensive interviews with
individuals in the UK and Scandinavia who had been nominated as moral exemplars in
the field of computing. Several striking findings from that work have shaped the
theoretical position we outline here. First, we found that there was not a unitary profile
of the way moral exemplars went about their work. There were, at least, two types:
reformers who tried to change social systems and craftspersons who designed systems
to help individuals. A significant number of the exemplars did not cleanly fit into either
category, leaving the likelihood that there are more types or forms of good computing.
This is empirical verification of the philosophical speculation by Flanagan (1991) who
uses the example of Christian saints to make the point that there are multiple (perhaps
infinite) ways of achieving “the good” and thus multiple “good lives” for which one
might strive. This insight suggests that we might be better served by teaching the
things these multiple paths have in common rather than teaching particular goods.
Second, we found that PeRsonality characteristics correlated strongly with the two
approaches to good computing. Reformers were much more likely to be extraverted
(socially dominant, outgoing) and craftspersons were much more likely to be open to
experience (welcoming new ideas, creative). This suggests that the developmental path
to multiple ways of doing good computing is influenced by more than historical
circumstance or individual choice. Third, we found that both social skills
(e.g. understanding other people) and technical skills (e.g. understanding database
structures) were associated with successful moral action in computing. Exemplars
consistently spoke of both skill sets as related to their success. This suggests that both
kinds of skill should be taught as a part of the curriculum for computer professionals.
Finally, we documented the importance of the social surround within which moral
action occurs. Together, these findings have suggested the model of good computing
we present here.
JICES
6,3
252
What emerges is a four-component model of sustained moral action in social context
(PRIMES). The model we present here grounds moral action in relatively stable
PeRsonality characteristics, guides moral action based on the integration of morality
(IM) into the self-system, shapes moral action by the context of the surrounding ME,
and facilitates moral action with morally relevant Skills and knowledge (thus the
PRIMES acronym). The model seeks to explain the daily performance of moral action
of computing professionals and to illuminate ways that computing professionals might
be trained to be more active, ethically committed, and ethically effective in their daily
performance, across the lifespan of their careers.
Personality. In the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle (1942) proposes a ship metaphor
for the influence of personal inclination. If a ship has a natural inclination to one side,
the wise pilot will steer a bit towards the other to correct. New work in personality
theory (Roberts et al., 2006) suggests that this kind of steering, particularly when
reinforced by social roles (that is, ME), can actually produce changes in PeRsonality
characteristics in early adulthood and later. Thus, though we treat personality as an
anchoring point for moral inclination, it can be influenced by appropriate life
experiences. Thus, personality grounds, but does not solely determine moral character
and action.
Integration of morality into the self. Much has been made of the centrality of moral
commitment. Psychologists (Blasi, 2005) and philosophers (Flanagan, 1991;
Kierkegaard, 1845/1958) treat moral commitment, or moral integrity (May, 1996;
Flanagan, 1991; Pritchard, 2006; Taylor, 1985), or moral will (Kant, 1965; Nietzsche,
1954), as the critical determinant of moral action. But, though moral commitment has
played this central role, few theorists have spoken carefully about the components of
moral commitment, how it is cultivated and achieved, and the ways that it influences
moral action. Again, recent work in psychology can help us build a multi-faceted view
of moral commitment as one component that guides moral action, but still is not solely
determinative of it.
Moral ecology. Moral action is embedded in a social surround that can either support
or thwart it. We call this social surround a ME (Donnelley, 1995; Alavi et al., 2006;
Harrington, 1996; Victor and Cullen, 1988; Berkowitz and Bier, 2005), or more
accurately, a system of interlinked moral ecologies. Countries, cultures, industries,
companies, divisions, workgroups, mentorship networks, and professional
organizations all have morally relevant expectations and pressures that constrain
and sometimes support moral action. Individuals can enter and leave moral ecologies,
can influence them, and can even act in defiance of them (Greene and Latting, 2004;
van Es and Smit, 2003; Marnburg, 2000; Trevin
˜o, 1986). Thus, knowing how to
navigate in the relevant moral ecologies is a crucial skill for computer professionals.
Moral ecologies thus constrain and support, but do not solely determine moral action.
Moral skills and knowledge. The literature on virtues has usually portrayed them as
dispositions that one can improve by practice (Muraven and Baumeister, 2000; Wood
et al., 2005; Webb and Sheeran, 2006). But just what is it that is strengthened by
practice? Is a virtue like a muscle that gets stronger with use (Wood, 2005; Neal et al.,
2006; Webb and Sheeran, 2006)? Or is it like a skill that gets better with appropriate
coaching and practice? Again, current literature in moral psychology can help untangle
this question. There are aspects of willpower that are like muscle (Muraven and
Baumeister, 2000; Neal et al., 2006; Wood et al., 2005; Webb and Sheeran, 2006),
Good computing
253
but much of what we call virtue is based in skills and knowledge of how to act in
particular worlds (Lapsley and Narvaez, 2005). Skills can be practiced to the level of
expertise and automaticity, and knowledge can be learned even to the level of implicit
use without conscious reflection. Together, these shape the form of, but do not solely
determine, moral action.
A significant advantage of this model is that it focuses on four identifiable domains
that influence the performance of good computing. As we will show in the rest of this
paper, these domains are not independent, but consistently interact with each other.
But, identifying each domain allows us to begin to investigate its independent and
mediated effects on the performance of moral action in computing. The model also
allows us to arrange the components along two dimensions (Figure 1). One is that of
malleability. Because of individual differences, skills and knowledge are not perfectly
malleable, but they are the most teachable, or coachable, component. ME and the IM
into the self are both somewhat malleable, while core personality is the least likely to
change. In the section on the self, we argue that the appropriation of morality is
ultimately a decision that the individual alone can make (though the decision can be
influenced by ME). Thus, the IM into the self system is most under the control of the
self. We have arranged the other components on this second dimension accordingly,
with the individual having the least control over ME. None of the components are
placed at an extreme end of a dimension: even core personality can change over time
(Roberts et al., 2006). The components are placed on the dimensions mostly to suggest
where instruction, coaching, and guidance will be most effective. Their actual places on
the dimensions are matters for empirical inquiries.
As we review each domain in this paper, we will also make suggestions about how
one might teach in the domain and measure characteristics or performance in the
domain. An adequate model of teaching good computing will require measurement in
at least three of the domains (personality can also be measured, but more to be aware of
its influence rather than to guide and assess instruction in it). Cunningham (2005)
writes that because we have no measures for moral development, we tend to teach it
less in school than we should. Thus, he states, “a better model of the self and human
development is crucial for character education.” We hope in this paper to provide an
Figure 1.
The four components
arranged on dimensions
of malleability and
personal control
Personality
Moral Ecologies
Moral Skill Sets
Mutability High
Control
Integration of
Morality into the
Self System
Low
External
Internal
JICES
6,3
254
outline of a model that can guide both research and pedagogy. The model uses extant
research and theory in the four domains to explain the nature and structure of the
influences on successful performance of moral action in computing. But, it can also
guide a pedagogy that attempts to cultivate development in each of the domains and
provide suggestions for the valid measurement of those domains.
Personality
Our exemplars often spoke of the personality traits that influenced their approach to
life projects (Aasen and Huff, 2007). By this, they meant something very like what
personality theorists call traits (e.g. extroversion, curiosity, and humility) that they saw
as fundamental aspects of their approach to life. In this paper, we will be using the term
personality to denote primarily the core traits that underlie the characteristic ways that
an individual approaches life tasks. Among the four components of the PRIMES model,
these are least likely to change over time (though as we show below, they are subject to
development). In the three-level system proposed by McAdams and Emmons (1995)
and LeVine (1973) these are core traits that are at least in part heritable ( John and
Srivastava, 1999 for heritability coefficients in personality). We treat the higher levels
of personality in this model (self-conception and life meanings) in the IM into the self
component that is discussed in another section. Thus, for now we are talking about
standard personality traits as they influence the successful expression of the virtues.
This short review will concentrate primarily on what are called the Big 5
personality traits (openness to experience, conscientiousness, extraversion,
agreeableness, and neuroticism; see Baumgarten, 1933; Allport and Odbert, 1936;
John and Srivastava, 1999). We do this in part because we have data on these traits in
the exemplar study (Huff and Rogerson, 2005; Huff and Barnard, n.d.), in part because
these traits, and their component facets, have been shown to do a remarkably good job
of covering the broadest span of applicable personality traits (John and Srivastava,
1999; Roccas et al., 2002), and because they have been shown to be related to values and
the performance of life tasks (Little, 1983; Christiansen et al., 1998; Schwartz and
Bilsky, 1990). There is of course, continuing conversation about their
comprehensiveness, their causal and ontological status, and their structure ( John
and Srivastava, 1999; Block, 1995). But, the Big 5 personality model is now widely
accepted as at least one important aspect of personality (McCrae and Costa, 1999; John
and Srivastava, 1999). The dimensions have been shown to replicate quite well in
Western cultures (McCrae and Costa, 1999) and reasonably well (with informative
exceptions) in non-western cultures (McCrae et al., 1998). The component facets of each
dimension might themselves be thought of as traits, and some represent areas
(e.g. assertiveness and achievement striving) that have a significant literature devoted
to them.
.Extraversion. Introversion-extraversion has been called variously confident
self-expression, surgency, assertiveness, social extraversion, and power. These
names tend to emphasize either a social vitality orientation or a tendency to exert
social dominance (two related aspects of the dimension). We found that those
moral exemplars who spoke most about, saw the need for, and took action
toward reform, were more likely to score high on extraversion (Huff and Barnard,
n.d.). According to Roccas et al. (2002), those high in extraversion tend to value
achievement and stimulation and to place less value on tradition.
Good computing
255
Thus, extraversion might help to support a particular kind of moral excellence
that involves leadership and facilitating change in society.
.Conscientiousness. Individuals who score high on this dimension tend to endorse
the values of achievement and conformity (John and Srivastava, 1999). High scores
on this dimension are reliably related to success in work environment and career,
to impulse control and delay of gratification, and to school and college grades
(John and Srivastava, 1999). In the professional context, this dimension and its
associated values would seem to underlie successful and careful work performance
(Hurtz and Donovan, 2000). Conscientiousness is the dimension that one might
think most reliably related to virtue, or at least virtue in an achievement-oriented
society. In our research however, it was the one dimension on which our exemplars
did not differ from the norm in their countries (Huff and Barnard, n.d.).
.Neuroticism. Emotional stability is a measure of negative emotional reactivity.
There is little correlation of this dimension with the endorsement of any values
(Roccas et al., 2002). In terms of life outcomes, it is correlated with less effective
coping and depression (John and Srivastava, 1999). High neuroticism can lead to
shutting down information search and to subsequent short-sighted responses
(John and Srivastava, 1999) and it seems reasonable that this might interfere with
many of the moral skills (moral imagination (MI) and creativity, reasonableness
(RE), perseverance (PE)) in the model. Our moral exemplars scored significantly
lower on this dimension than their country norms (Huff and Barnard, n.d.).
.Agreeableness. This has variously been called social adaptability, likeability,
friendly compliance, and love (John and Srivastava, 1999). It is another
dimension that seems readily adapted to supporting virtue, as it correlates
positively with endorsement of the values of benevolence and tradition and
negatively with endorsement of valuing power. Furthermore, high scorers on
this dimension tend to donate to charities more and to help others and tend to
work better in groups (John and Srivastava, 1999). On the other hand, one can
readily bring to mind famously grumpy saints (see Flanagan, 1991, for a
discussion of saints and virtue) or rights activists. Though not as extreme as
grumpy, Walker and Frimer (2007) found that the brave moral exemplars they
identified were less nurturant, generative, and optimistic than those exemplars of
the caring type (a somewhat similar distinction to our craft vs reform dimension).
As with the other dimensions, rather than determine one’s inclusion or exclusion
from the circle of virtuous, except at the extremes this dimension shapes the
characteristic way one expresses virtue.
.Openness. Openness to experience may initially not seem relevant to supporting
virtue, but we found (Huff and Rogerson, 2005; Huff and Barnard, n.d.) that
exemplars who are craftspersons (those who use their craft to help users and
clients) were more likely to score highly on openness to experience than were
reformers (who attempt to change the discipline or society). The causal structure
is unclear here: perhaps those with higher trait scores for openness (and the other
relevant commitments) are drawn to helping others in this way, but it may also
be that those who value and participate in computing design come to value and
reflect openness to experience. Given that all the personality traits are open to
environmental influence, we expect some of both kinds of influence to occur.
JICES
6,3
256
Other personality influences on virtue
There are certainly other ways of characterizing the influence of personality on virtue
(and vice versa). Optimism, for instance, has been linked to PE and also to flexibility in
response to challenges (Roccas et al., 2002). Tangney (2002) suggests that humility
(a characteristic often found in moral exemplars) is related to openness to experience,
and is independent of self-efficacy, since it involves accurate, rather than motivated,
self-assessment. Impulse and constraint (Carver, 2005) can also shape moral action by
encouraging impulsive action (either selfish or selfless). We are not trying here to
create a detailed theory of the influence of personality traits on virtue (or even to
catalogue all the possible influences). We are more simply making the point that any
attempt to understand how virtue is developed over the career of a computing
professional will need to take into account, in some way, the influence and interaction
of personality traits.
There is no single “moral personality”
It is crucial to underline the point that personality traits are unlikely to converge to
produce a single type of “moral personality.” Flanagan (1991) uses the example of
saints in the church to make this point. There is little in common among the
personalities of such diverse saints as Thomas Aquinas, Teresa of Avila, Ignatius
Loyola, Francis of Assisi, Joan of Arc, and Martin of Tours. All are exemplars for those
who revere the saints, but all are exemplary in very different manners. Work on
contingency theories of leadership (Vroom and Jago, 2007) makes a similar point. There
is not a single type of good leader, but leaders with different profiles match with
situations that make them effective or ineffective, for those followers and for that
situation. Recent work (Wood, 2005) views leadership as expressed within a particular
ME (in our model’s terms). In this view, leadership occurs in the interaction of
individuals (with particular characteristics) with situations, and leadership is less a
property of the leader than it is of the particular interaction.
Our interviews of moral exemplars in computing (Aasen and Huff, 2007; Huff and
Rogerson, 2005) provide stories of personality traits interacting with particular
organizational skills, moral ecologies, and differing moral commitments. Many of our
moral exemplars talked about the match (or mismatch) of their personalities and skills
to the particular requirements of the situations that confronted them.
Our discovery of two types of moral exemplars (Huff and Rogerson, 2005; Huff and
Barnard, n.d.) suggests that different personalities may fit one for different “moral
careers.” But we do not think that there are only two kinds of moral career in
computing (or any other professional career). There are a multiplicity of goods (Taylor,
1985) and thus likely a multiplicity of moral careers in pursuit of these goals. Cruz and
Frey (2003) and Frey and O’Neill-Carillo (2008) have data from case generation
exercises with engineers from the Caribbean context that suggest that in countries
where corruption is a regular price of business, moral exemplars may need to become
reformers in order to maintain their integrity. If so, they may also be better equipped
for this task if they have the PeRsonality characteristics typical of other reformers.
Pedagogy
Personality is not set in concrete in the way popular imagination constructs it. Roberts
et al. (2006) have documented the changes in each of the Big 5 personality dimensions
Good computing
257
across the life span. Not surprisingly, conscientiousness increases at the time when
many people are getting married and having children. Other life events (e.g. retirement,
ageing, and college attendance) also have effects on personality (e.g. college attendance
seems to increase openness to experience). It makes sense that, in addition to the
overall developmental trajectory, life events can change one’s personality. These can
include both traumatic events and self-initiated attempts to change (Roberts et al.,
2006). One can, to a limited extent, learn social skills, become more conscientious, learn
to love one’s neighbor, and become more accepting of change (Roberts et al., 2006).
Thus, though heritability sets an anchor, there is still significant latitude for movement
on every dimension. Within limits, our core personalities can change, develop, or
regress.
It is difficult to stage in the classroom the sort of life events that might help students
become, for example, more conscientious. Certainly one can begin to introduce students
to the pressures of the real workplace (with consulting projects, etc.) so that they can
get some coaching in how to deal with the demands of the workplace they will soon be
entering. But, we cannot expect this coaching to produce much change in core
personality.
Aristotle’s ship metaphor helps here. We might better use our time helping students
to become aware of their characteristic ways of approaching their work and their
profession so that they can prepare to take advantage of or to counter their proclivities.
But to do this, we will need good measurement of personality, and ways to track it over
time and relate it to other aspects of the model.
Measurement
There is an embarrassment of riches when it comes to measuring personality traits.
Large compendia of different personality measures are a regular feature on psychology
library shelves (Robinson et al., 1991; Pervin and John, 1999). Given the exploratory
nature of these relationships at the time, we think it best to begin with broad-based
personality inventories like the NEO-PRI (McCrae and Costa, 1999) or the BFI-44 (John
and Srivastava, 1999). Unless there are specific expectations about PeRsonality
characteristics (e.g. impulsiveness, optimism), these broad-based inventories offer the
best coverage of what are likely to be the relevant traits. We think more comprehensive
instruments like the NEO-PRI will be more useful than short versions (e.g. the BFI-44),
since these provide facet scores that allow one to see what parts of a dimension (e.g. the
social dominance aspect of extroversion) are the most important factors. We now know
enough to expect that personality traits are likely to shape the ways that individuals
are moral. This suggests assessment of ethical commitment, skill, or action should be
informed by knowledge of PeRsonality characteristics.
Conclusions
Continuing the marine metaphor, we might best think of core personality as an anchor
that shapes the resources each computer professional can bring to bear on the task of
constructing a moral career. On every dimension of personality, the individual can,
through effort or exposure to life events, change the anchor point some, to provide for
more resources in one area (e.g. to increase conscientiousness, or to become more
gregarious). The professional can also recognize these anchors as things that can shape
JICES
6,3
258
the sort of projects and aspirations he or she might take on. One can view the
constraints of personality as limiting choice, but also as supporting achievement.
IM into the self-system
Moral commitment is often spoken of as the central component that motivates the
moral life of the professional. Blasi (1980) recognized “integration of morality into the
self” as the critical component that was missing from Kohlberg’s (Kohlberg and
Kramer, 1969) moral development scheme. Work by Colby and Damon (1992) on moral
exemplars also places the moral self-concept at the center of exemplars’ motivations.
Instead of “the self,” current psychology speaks more of a “self-system,” recognizing
that how one thinks of oneself is contextually influenced (McKinnon, 2005; Blasi, 2005;
Higgins-D’Alessandro and Power, 2005; Sheilds and Bredemeier, 2005; Schwartz and
Bilsky, 1990; Horowitz et al., 2006; Locke, 2000). Thus, it is standard to talk about
domain-specific self-confidence (Burson et al., 2006; Christiansen et al., 1998), and to
recognize the multiple roles (Little, 1983; Christiansen et al., 1999) and contexts (Little,
1983) that produce multiple aspects of the self. In this section, we will primarily be
addressing the “professional-self-concept” (Bebeau et al., 1993), though we will draw
widely from the literature on the self, more broadly considered. “Professional
self-concept” is the individual practitioner’s understanding of who they are as a
computer scientist, software engineer, supervisor, or teacher. The computing moral
exemplars we interviewed (Huff and Rogerson, 2005) occasionally spoke of “the kind of
engineer I am,” and this picture is what we mean by the professional self-concept.
What does this integration consist of and how is it achieved? In a recent statement,
Blasi (2005) uses the word integration to mean “consistent moral commitment across
situations.” But cross-situational consistency is problematic even for the moral
exemplars that Colby and Damon (1992) studied. Many of their moral exemplars
neglected some aspects of their obligations precisely in order to concentrate on others.
Similarly, Oliner and Oliner (1988) found that the moral exemplars who rescued Jews
during the Holocaust were not primarily motivated by the sort of cross-situational,
principled commitments this conception of character invokes. They were more often
motivated by reference-group commitments, or the empathy they felt for particular,
individual sufferers. Nathaniel Borenstein’s story of consulting for NATO, in clear
violation of his anti-war principles, should serve as a caution to those who emphasize
principled consistency as the primary criterion.
Shoda and Mischel (1998) have comprehensively documented the inconsistencies in
behavior that challenge the simple expectation that personality will be reflected in rigid
cross-situational consistency. This manifest cross-situational inconsistency, shown
even by moral exemplars, has become the basis of a strong critique of
disposition-based virtue-theoretical approaches (Doris, 2002). If even moral
exemplars, those who express the virtues par excellence, do not show in a simple
way Doris’ required consistent moral commitment across situations, then how can this
be the basis for recommendations about how to be ethical?
Work by Shoda and Mischel (1998) and Mischel et al. (2002) provides one way out of
this quandary. Appropriate moral commitment does not produce a foolish consistency,
but is located instead in a discriminative facility the ability to make fine-grained
distinctions among situations and to respond to these situations with appropriate
kinds of appraisals, expectations and beliefs, emotions, goals, and behavioral scripts,
Good computing
259
given one’s larger moral commitments (Mischel, 2004). In this light, a more detailed and
careful understanding of Borenstein’s decision allows us to see the coherence behind
the surface inconsistency in his behavior.
Thus, we can expect moral commitment to be sensitive to subtle differences in
situations (Solomon, 2003). Correspondingly, the expected “integration of morality into
the self” (Blasi, 2005; Colby and Damon, 1992) will need to be of the sort that reflects
and produces this kind of subtlety. It will need to recognize the multiple markers,
dimensions, and processes by which commitments are incorporated into the self. Oliner
and Oliner (1988) recognize this multiplicity when they speak of three reasons that
people might become rescuers: obligation to a valued social reference group (the
primary motivation for 52 percent), empathic orientation triggered by a specific person
or incident (the motivation for 37 percent) and principled commitment (the smallest
group, 11 percent). These different motivations are not simply based on different
principles or values, but are of qualitatively different kinds: social reference groups,
emotional attachments, and commitment to particular values or principles. Thus, if we
are to understand the IM into the self-system, we need a model of the self that provides
for this kind of complexity in moral motivation.
McGregor and Little (1998) provide such a model of the self. They propose a model
of the self that is both temporally extended and contextually distributed. It is
temporally extended in two ways: it reaches into the past in stories, memories, and
established relationships and it reaches into the future in projections of possible selves,
life tasks, and the goals of personal projects. Thus, meaning (and moral commitment as
a kind of meaning) can be, indeed must be, part of an ongoing self that is anchored in
time. The self is also contextually extended. It is influenced by personal context,
friendships, and group memberships. There are cultural differences in the extent to
which the self is conceived as contextually influenced, but even the most individualistic
cultures acknowledge and celebrate the role of interpersonal connections (Hofstede,
2003).
This temporally extended and contextually distributed self, with multiple avenues
for the integration of meaning, can create the kind of complex personality that
responds subtly and creatively (and sometimes self-deceptively) to perceived
differences in situations. Figure 2 shows a schematic of seven of the avenues
through which moral commitment might be integrated into this complexity. Most of
the concepts presented here are not depth-psychological constructs, but instead what
McGregor and Little (1998) call “Personal Action Constructs” (PACs) that exist at the
middle level between behavior descriptions (at the most concrete) and deeper
personality trait approaches. The concepts are drawn from a multifarious and
expanding literature on motivation, values, meaning, and the planning and execution
of action. They often overlap each other (e.g. life tasks and personal projects are often
similar). The point here is not to offer a comprehensive and systematic listing of ways
of integrating meaning and morality into the self-system. It is, instead to give some
idea of the large diversity of ways that exist. It will be the task of later empirical work
to determine the extent and nature of the influences each avenue exercises in the moral
life of professionals. As suggested by the work of Murray (1938) and Oliner and Oliner
(1988), variability may indeed be the key to this: some persons may integrate
morality into the self-primarily in terms of relationships and roles (what would
my mentor think?), while others may do so via articulated principles and values
JICES
6,3
260
(X violates privacy rights). Both ways may be equally effective in supporting moral
action (or, perhaps, differentially effective, depending on the person and the ME).
For now, we will review the list of approaches in Figure 2 as a somewhat systematic
sampling of the way morality can become important to the self.
Affiliations and relationships. Psychologists have long recognized that relations to
others are primary constituents of the self. Bowlby (1969) and Ainsworth (1968) created
an influential depth model of attachment styles based on schemas structured by early
relationship experience. But our schemas and expectations based on past relationships
are not the only way, or even the primary way that our social connections influence our
sense of self, and thereby our IM into the self. Cross et al. (2000) have documented the
way that, even in the extremely individualistic US, people differ in the extent to which
they integrate current others into the sense of self. Those who do integrate others into
their self-system think and behave differently in terms of their obligations to those
others (Cross and Vick, 2001). Markus and Kitayama (1991) have concentrated on the
variation among cultures in what has been called individualism-collectivism. This
cultural variation is, in part, defined by the extent to which culturally defined relations
to others are integrated into the self.
Morality can be integrated into the social self to the extent that the relationships
entail obligations to close others and to the outsider. People in collectivist cultures often
view their obligations to close others differently than to outsiders (Li et al., 2006). Social
connection is not the only dimension, and obligations based on tribal status are often
mitigated and modified by principled claims from religion. In the work of Gregg (2005),
these are the contrasting claims of the honor-modesty system and the claims of Islam.
Only one of these systems (Islam) is an “ethic” in the classical sense, with principles
and rules of application (though Islam too, differs widely across cultures). The
obligations of the honor-modesty system are neither systematic nor rule-based, and are
comprised of the widely varying and subjective personal connections established in
different groups (Gregg, 2005).
Figure 2.
The IM in the self system
Personal
Projects
Past Behavior
& Experience
Beliefs, Attitudes,
& Values
Motives &
Strivings
Roles, Life Tasks,
Possible Selves
Affiliations &
Relationships
Stories & Defining
Memories
The self extends
over time and
across contexts
Source: McGregor and Little (1998)
Good computing
261
In terms of the social constituents of the professional self-concept, the computing
moral exemplars we interviewed often talked about the differences in the way they
viewed “the users” from the way many other computer scientists and engineers viewed
them. Thus, to them, users were less often an “other” to be handled but the primary
target of their moral concern (either in the design of computing systems or the attempt
to change social systems). This connection to their users influenced their design of
technology, even in some cases influenced the direction of their careers.
Stories and memories. Work begun by Murray (1938), and continued by McAdams
(1993; McAdams and Emmons, 1995) has documented the extent to which life meaning
is often embedded (and elicited) in autobiographical stories. In particular, stories about
“turning points” in individuals’ lives often serve as organizing units in the way a
personal life history is constructed and given meaning. Stories do not have to be
autobiographical. They can take the form of cautionary tales (Broderick, 1995)
remembered to make particular points.
Simply calling tales cautionary suggests how morality can be embedded in
important stories. The moral exemplar interviews we did were patterned after
McAdams’ (1993) Life Story interviews, and they proved particularly effective in
eliciting connections of morality to the professional self. The method of teaching ethical
decision making by case analysis takes advantage of this embedding of moral lessons
in stories, and the cases can then serve as cautionary tales for students.
Roles, life tasks, possible selves. The self can also be structured and given meaning
by conceptions about who I am or might become: the roles one plays, one’s larger life
goals, and the possible selves one might become. Possible selves are ideas about what
one might become in the future (Markus and Nurius, 1986). These can be negative or
positive, and, to the extent they are integrated into the self and deemed possible
(Oyserman et al., 2006), they can provide consistent motivation to achieve instrumental
goals that approach or avoid the possible self. Life tasks (Cantor and Harlow, 1994) are
larger scale commitments to achieve some goal.
Roles, life tasks, and possible selves all contain implicit or explicit expectations
about behavior. Many of these expectations take the form of moral judgments about
appropriate or inappropriate behavior. They are not necessarily freely chosen they
may be imposed by employment, family, or societal requirements. But, they can also
serve as important motivators of moral behavior like conscientiousness (Oyserman
et al., 2006). We asked our moral exemplars about negative and positive possible
selves, and received answers in terms of both environmental constraint (the economy
and health) and personal moral choice (decisions to change jobs, to pursue careers).
Motives and strivings. Motives and strivings are the most basic, or most broadly
based, constructs in this conception of the self. Motive language comes from Murray’s
(1938) work that is based on narrative as a window to the self (e.g. the thematic
apperception test in which people tell a story about a picture). Motives, for Murray,
were basic needs for intimacy, power, achievement, autonomy, cognition, etc. These
needs underlay a characteristic desire of the person across many situations, and could
be assessed by looking at the themes in the stories that people told. Diversity of needs
(both within and across people) is the rule (Murray, 1938). Personal strivings (Emmons,
1986; McAdams and Emmons, 1995) are recurring goals that a person is attempting to
accomplish across times and situations.
JICES
6,3
262
These needs and strivings are characteristics ways of approaching problems, and
may carry moral loading. But, the moral meaning of needs will be specific to the moral
status of the goals inherent in particular strivings (or projects, or life tasks).
Thus, someone low in “need for power” still may acquire power in order to reform
society (see the link between extroversion and reform in our moral exemplars).
Beliefs, attitudes, and values. There is an extensive literature on the relation of
beliefs, attitudes and values to moral behavior. Initial work emphasized the difficulty
of finding a connection between moral values and behavior (Feather, 1990). But, more
recent work like that of Mischel et al. (2002), has converged on an understanding of the
complex linkages between personal values, the interpretations of situations, and
resulting behavior in those situations.
There is an additional level of complexity that is documented in the works of
Schwartz (1994) Schwartz and Bilsky (1990) and Schwartz and Boehnke (2004) on
values. Figure 3 shows Schwartz’ circumplex of values an empirically validated
model of the relationships among what appear to be a cross-culturally valid listing of
values (Schwartz and Bilsky, 1990). The circumplex presents what Schwartz and
colleagues have shown to be relationships of opposition and similarity among the
values. Individuals who endorse a value on one side of the circumplex (e.g. stimulation)
are less likely to endorse the value on the opposite side of the circle (e.g. tradition). This
negative correlation in value endorsements sets up a tension among values that we
have seen foreshadowed in earlier statements about the complexity of moral
commitment. It makes a desire for a “unity of the virtues” problematic, and lays the
groundwork for understanding some of the “diversity of goods” that philosophers like
Taylor (1985) describe. In addition, this diversity of values suggests that there might
be advantage in “moral diversity” in a ME, in that different individuals may become
advocates for different values in a community.
Figure 3.
The theoretical circumplex
structure of values
Self-Direction
Stimulation
Hedonism
Achievement
Power
Security
Tradition
Comformity
Benevolence
Universalism
Source: Schwartz and Boehnke (2004)
Good computing
263
We asked our computing moral exemplars to list the three most important values for
systems design (Table I). Most of the values they articulated can be classified in one or
more of Schwartz and Bilsky’s (1990) circumplex (Figure 3). In addition, some of the
tension between values can be found in exemplar’s responses. For instance, values of
universal access (universalism) compete and must be balanced with values of system
security (safety).
When talking about values, we must take into account the cautions that Rohan
(2000) outlines in this complex area. Historically, we have used the word value to mean
many different things, from the personal goals of individuals to the overarching
ideologies that sustain societies. In this context, we are referring to those goals or
guiding principles that individuals adopt. In the section on ME we will consider the
ways in which values are embodied by organizations and societies.
Past behavior and experience. Dissonance research (Festinger, 1957) provides a
powerful argument for the importance of past behavior in establishing current
meaning. Most of this research has shown the effect of behavioral commitment on
directly expressed attitudes, opinions, or values (Festinger, 1957; Jonas et al., 2001), but
this is primarily because of the ease of measurement of changes on these dimensions.
The foot in the door effect (Cialdini, 1987) can be interpreted as prior behavioral
commitment affecting commitment to new personal projects. Behavior and experience
can shape memories and stories as well. In addition, work on habits (Wood et al., 2005;
Neal et al., 2006) suggests that there is a complex relationship between planned,
intentional action and the maintenance of good (and bad) habits. Thus, habits can
maintain goal-directed action even when it is not under intentional control. In this way,
habits contribute to “the kind of person I am.”
Pritchard (2006) has interviewed moral exemplars in engineering about the virtues
associated with good engineering. It is interesting to note that one of the virtues is “a
habit of documenting work.” In this way, repeated past behavior, based initially on
intentional action, becomes habitual, perhaps even automatic (Haidt, 2001), and
becomes a part of the professional self.
Personal projects. Personal projects are another mid-level construct that
psychologists have used to track the course of meaning in people’s lives (Little,
1983, 1999; McGregor and Little, 1998; Little et al., 1992). One’s personal projects are the
set of things one is doing at the time. These can be somewhat extended in time
(e.g. raising my children well) or relatively short-term (finishing a paper). The
important point is that a list of the projects one is engaged in allows one to see the
individual’s life as he or she parses it, with relevance to current action plans and
motivations. Research on personal projects has shown them to be relevant to how
meaningful people find life, how stressful their life is, and how fractured it feels. By
dividing projects into their stages of completion (inception, planning, action, and
termination) researchers have been able to show that different goals become salient at
different stages. For instance, deliberative goals (what is the best path) have more
salience earlier in a project, while implemental goals (finishing the project) supercede
during the action stages (Henderson et al., 2007). Deliberative goals are more likely to
take into account a broader array of contingencies (and more likely to be realistic) while
implemental goals often suffer from self-serving biases (Henderson et al., 2007).
McGregor and Little (1998) include two other items in their model that we
emphasize by moving them to other sections in this paper. We move “traits and
JICES
6,3
264
Exemplar Most important value Second important value Third important value
C1102 Take responsibility because there are no neutral
technologies... values are inherent in
technology
Create usable systems that make the world
transparent for the users and place them in
control
N/A
MI MI
C1103 Satisfy all the stakeholders
MI, RE, MC
It depends could be ease of use or safety
or simplicity
Ability to recognize for specific projects which
values are most important
RE MI
C5105 Taking account of the people (users) N/A N/A
MI, MC
C1101 To understand the problem right and to
understand the right problem and to
understand its consequences
MI, RE
To take different kinds of users into
consideration...You have to put (the design) in
context of their knowledge and what makes
sense to them when they are doing their work
N/A
MI
C2102 Honesty and responsibility... should realize
what the consequences are of what you are
doing
Transparency... everything should be open.
Opposes copyright
MI
N/A
RE
C4101 ...systematic and continuous interactions with
the people that are going to use the system
N/A N/A
MI, RE
C3102 Keep in mind that systems are for human
beings... they are for users... build them so
they are simple to use
You must work systematically, following a
project design
RE, PE
N/A
MI
C3101 That is actually giving power to the user...
empowerment
Do not jeopardize the health of people, and
make products user-friendly
Design software that increases the knowledge
and skill of its users
MI, MC MI MI, MC
C4104 To look for the needs that people and
organizations have... Those needs that we
should satisfy
Bring positive values to all users. help (users)
learn and develop
MI, MC
Respect the people that use the system
MI
MI
(continued)
Table I.
Computing exemplar’s
design values and the
skill sets they intersect
Good computing
265
Exemplar Most important value Second important value Third important value
C4102 Openness... Transparency
MI
You should also have that in mind when you
are... developing your product, you should
have an open mind to those who in the end will
use what you are doing
Equality. Keeping in mind that programmers,
designers, planners, and users are equal and
that systems should increase human resources
(skills)
MI MI, RE, MC
C4103 The system should have a purpose... needs to
take into account the complexity of its purpose
RE
Transparency. A system should be transparent
to the user so that they can predict what will
happen
Flexibility. Computer systems tend to stay
around for a long time... should be able to be
flexible to changing needs/times
MI RE, MC, PE
C5109 Quality: fitness for purpose... what the user
wants the system to do
RE, PE
To satisfy what the user really wants
MI
Risk assessment and security. Anticipating that
things will go wrong and having good disaster
plans
RE, PE
C5108 The most important thing has to be knowing
what your customer is going to do with it...if it
is useful
Knowing how the customer will use the system,
set it up, configure it, and administer it
MI
Asking self how the system fits within the
portfolio of my companies products?
RE
MI
C5112 Integrity... that the user is protected. The
person that is designing the system has to think
of the user
To give the user capabilities
MI, MC
Simplicity
RE, PE
N/A
MI
C5111 Structure and organization are key User-friendliness
RE, PE MI, MC
C5110 Understand why people think what they do.
Have to satisfy mathematicians... engineers...
government... and customers will be changing
their minds
Compromise...get totally conflicting views and
work out which bits of each one you can take
away
MI, MC
Build tasteful systems that can be maintained
in the future because they are clean, logical, and
done in ways that allows for the future
RE, PE
MI
C5107 Systems should do what the user wants them to
do in a way that is easy for the user
Take into account the variability of users Reliability and avoiding unnecessary
functionality
MI, MC MI RE, PE
Notes:
a
The initials indicate the four moral skill sets of MI, RE, moral creativity (MC), and PE. These indicate which of the skills aid the expression of
these professed important values in system design
Table I.
JICES
6,3
266
competencies” to the personality component and the skills and knowledge component,
respectively. And we move “personal contexts” to the ME component. We do not deny
that these items are also integrated into the self-system, but we want to explore these
particular items in more depth (see the discussions in those sections). The heuristic
value of separating items to concentrate on their differences should not lead us to
assume that all four components of the model are unconnected to each other and
operate independently. Indeed, Johnson (1999) has argued that it is logically incoherent
to speak of the influence of the situation (in our terms, the ME) independent of its effect
on a person with particular personality dispositions.
In most of the discussion here, we have spoken in terms of how morality is integrated
into the self through these various avenues. As Colby and Damon (1992) and Blasi (2005)
suggest, morality is deeply integrated in the self-system for some individuals. But for
other people, different kinds of meaning are integrated. There are other
meaning-structures that can be integrated into this complex self (McGregor and
Little, 1998). These include fun/hedonism, communion/social connectedness,
achievement, and agency/power accumulation. McGregor and Little (1998) call these
identity themes and base their list on a factor analytic approach to people’s ratings of
their personal projects. One can easily list other likely identity themes (e.g. moral
commitment, religious commitment, etc.) that would be less likely to show up in factor
analytic approaches simply because of their relative rarity or the nature of the ratings
provided. Certainly, some of these identity themes have elements that are related to
moral principles, moral stories, possible moral selves, and morality-based projects, etc.
But one might expect exemplars to show a more thorough IM into these various aspects
of the self and, indeed to have morality in some form as a central identity theme.
Two final cautions before we move to issues of pedagogy and measurement. First,
the values our computing exemplars list (Table I) have an unmistakable “characteristic
of the ultimate” (Taylor, 1985) that moral claims appear to share. We emphasize this
point to discourage the easy conclusion that this model requires an ethical relativism
that any values (e.g. hedonism, or bare power assertion) can be integrated into the
“moral self.” The model is certainly consistent with a reasonably thoughtful ethical
relativism, but it does not require it. It only requires a recognition of what Taylor has
called the “diversity of goods” that we claim as moral values. The internal logic of what
Taylor calls the “contrastive language” of values like RE, tradition, and happiness still
allows for, and even requires, praise and blame for those who excel or fail on the
relevant dimensions. Additionally, this contrastive language may be most evident in
the declarative structure of values and attitudes, but we expect that it can also be found
in stories, personal projects, possible selves, and most of the other avenues we list
above for integrating morality into the self-system.
Secondly, the influence of the morally committed self on behavior is not simply a
one-way determinism. People actively construct the self (Little, 1983, 1999; McGregor
and Little, 1998; Little et al., 1992; Christiansen et al., 1998; Wood et al., 2005). We
choose moral ecologies that are congenial to our self-goals (Little, 1983; Little et al.,
1992) and these ecologies in turn shape our sense of who we are.
Pedagogy
There is little real objection to teaching skills and knowledge, or to helping students
become more aware of the influences of personality and ME on their professional
Good computing
267
actions. The issue becomes more difficult when we talk about influencing the self. Here,
we tread perilously close to accusations of “indoctrination” and “coercion.” So, ought
ethics be taught using the targeted approach we suggest here of influencing the
professional self-concept?
One answer comes from looking at other professions. Nurses and social workers
(Council on Social Work Education Inc., 2004) are explicit in their desire to train new
members of their professions so that they have integrated ethical commitments into
their professional self-concepts. There is explicit work in nursing showing that
changes in the ME that result in patients being treated more as commodities have
produced a feeling of a “loss of identity” among nurses (Weiss et al., 2002). This
evidence of identity loss shows that these nurses, at least, had integrated into their
professional self-concept a commitment to treating patients as humans. We find
parallel comments among moral exemplars in computing about the negative influences
of the moral ecologies in which they work (Huff and Rogerson, 2005).
If we do want to educate professional character, Lapsley and Narvaez (2005) claim
that we cannot do so by simply teaching knowledge and skills. We must instead give
students the opportunity, and encourage them, to integrate moral commitments into
their identity (in our focus here, into their professional self-concept). Other work on
exemplars (Colby and Damon, 1992; Oliner and Oliner, 1988) makes the point that this
IM into the self-concept helps to explain the immediate sense of “the right thing to do”
that exemplars often feel. When “the right thing to do” becomes difficult or impossible
(as in the case of the nurses in the Weiss et al. (2002) study), then a loss of meaning is felt.
Pritchard (1998, 2006) asserts that this moral commitment can and must be taught.
In fact, the engineering professions (including software engineering) see moral action
as inseparable to good professional performance (Huff and Rogerson, 2005). These
internal goods of the profession (Taylor, 1985) are what enable the “craftsperson”
moral exemplars in our research to make claims on and influence others to better
practice (Weaver et al., 2005). As the “reformer” moral exemplars show, there are also
goods that are external to the profession that some professionals will campaign for as
important goods that the profession should adopt. This constant negotiation of what
counts as a good for the profession is in fact part of what we mean by the dynamic
nature of the ME of a profession. This dynamic negotiation means that people of
goodwill will disagree about some of the goods that ought to be taught in the classroom
and about some of the moral commitments that students should be encouraged to
adopt as part of their professional self-concept. Indeed, one should doubt whether an
identifiable profession exists to the extent that there is no agreement about internal
goods (Ladd, 1991).
The process for teaching these goods, for encouraging the adoption of moral
commitments into the professional self-concept, was outlined long ago by Aristotle
(1942). One learns a virtue, according to Aristotle, by enacting it, by practicing it.
Lapsley and Narvaez (2005) use the literature on expertise to help us understand the
process that moves the student from novice in ethical action to expertise, by way of
guided practice. It involves extensive practice of appropriate actions, under conditions
of explicit and clear feedback, with the concomitant provision of explicit theory about
the structure, nature, and planning of the performance. These conditions can be met
from extensive work with cases (Huff and Frey, 2005) or with project-based education
(Huff, 1996). Extensive practice provides students with the knowledge and skills they
JICES
6,3
268
need to actually perform the virtue. But, it can also provide students with the
opportunity to enjoy the fruits of ethical action, encourage them to recognize the
centrality of the internal goods to their work, and to adopt the goods into their
professional self-concept.
It is important to note one danger here: that of technique-driven morality. The
techniques we suggest here for encouraging the construction of a professional
self-concept do not guarantee that a student, given the opportunity, will become the
moral clone of the instructor. The appropriate metaphor here, and one used by
Aristotle, is that of coaching. The coach can guide and influence, and often has
significant influence that can be misused. But in the end, it is the athlete who must
practice and who must internalize the instruction.
There is, then, a gap that technique cannot bridge, and that the student must cross
with a personal act of appropriation. And because of the diversity of goods (Taylor,
1985), and the likely opposition of some values with others (Schwartz and Bilsky, 1990;
Taylor, 1985; Mannix and Neale, 2005; Bartels and Medin, 2007) any meaningful
appropriation of some values also entails loss, or at least tension, with others. Adopting
the techniques (e.g. skills and knowledge) without this personal act of appropriation
will result in something short of virtuous action in the profession (and possibly even
vicious action in the profession). Finally, this act of appropriation is not a one-time
commitment, but a process that continues as the student becomes a professional and
the professional becomes more mature across the lifespan (see Colby and Damon, 1992
for a description of this process in moral exemplars in social service).
Measurement
One of the significant advantages of the model of IM into the professional self that we
propose is that it makes this integration amenable to measurement. Little and Gee
(2007) have done extensive work on measuring the properties of PACs and provide
useful methodological guidance.
The measurement method consists of eliciting a set of PACs (personal projects, life
tasks, possible selves, etc.) that are of personal relevance to the individual. On average,
people list about 15 personal projects at any given time, some of which are long-term
strivings (e.g. maintain my expertise in database structures) and some that are
short-term goals that will be replaced upon completion with new short-term goals
(e.g. prepare the team report for Friday). The PACs the person lists then become the
basis for a series of ratings of each PAC. Interesting research has been done rating
PACs on a number of dimensions including:
.Meaning. How enjoyable, important, value congruent, and expressive of identity
each PAC is.
.Structure. Whether the individual initiated the PAC, their perceived control over
its success, whether the person has enough time to devote to the PAC, and the
PAC’s congruence with other PACs the individual has.
.Community. Whether the PAC is supported or valued (or thwarted) by
significant others or the organizational climate. This assessment can be done at
different levels of the ME the immediate group or micro-climate, the larger
organization, the profession, etc.
.Efficacy. Whether the PAC is likely to be successful.
Good computing
269
.Stress. Whether the PAC produces stress in the person’s life, because of
incongruity with the self, with others, or with other projects.
This is a wealth of information. Surely one cannot ask all of it in a single sitting, but the
method provides a way to ask structured, statistically tractable questions about the
extent to which moral commitments are integrated into those projects that are most
important to the self. Research teams (Christiansen et al., 1998, 1999; McGregor and Little,
1998; Little, 1983, 1999) have shown that these data can be analyzed across projects,
within a single person, to get indexes of meaning, structure, etc. that predict important
outcome variables such as depression, job satisfaction, meaning in life, and happiness.
PAC measurement is likely to be able to track, in pre- and post-measurement designs,
changes in moral commitments that are the result of education or other interventions.
We have also mentioned another useful measurement instrument here, the
circumplex scale of interpersonal values (Schwartz and Bilsky, 1990). This scale has
been extensively validated across cultures (Schwartz and Bilsky, 1990; Schwartz, 1994;
Schwartz and Boehnke, 2004) and though there is ongoing discussion of the nature of
the circumplex relationships among the values (Perrinjaquet et al., 2007) (as there is
about the Big 5 trait scales), the scale would be very useful to track changes in
endorsement of values across time.
This general measurement of value structure will be useful in itself, but perhaps more
useful as a baseline or model for constructing similar value scales that are based on the
internal goods (and goods under debate) within the profession. Initial work by
philosophers such as Pritchard (1998, 2006) can provide a basis for constructing these
profession-specific scales. And the methods used by Schwartz and Bilsky (1990) can
provide models.
Finally, Bebeau et al. (1993) have developed a measurement instrument
(the professional role orientation inventory) tailored to the specific values of the
profession of dentistry. This involves rating a series of items about the role obligations of
dentists. They have shown that an ethics curriculum can produce improvements on this
inventory (Bebeau, 1994). It is important to note that this scale is not unidimensional – one
does not simply adopt more “professional role orientation” as a result of training. Thereare
two dimensions underlying this instrument, adoption of responsibility (how much is the
professional responsible for others?) and authority (How much shoulddecisions rest with
the profession alone?). This produces four combinations, low on both responsibility and
authority (a sort of hired gun model), high on both (a professional guild model), high
authority and low responsibility (a commercial model), and low authority and high
responsibility (a kind of service model). Training moves professional away fromthe hired
gun model. Bebeau (1994) supplement this instrument with an essay that is scored for the
presence of six obligations that supposedly distinguish occupations from professions.
These suggestions for measurement of this component provide sufficient evidence
that we are likely to be able to measure increases in IM into the professional self. It may
well be that inventories and methods will need to be established for every profession of
interest.
Conclusions
The IM into the professional self-concept is the one influence on sustained moral action
in the profession that is most under the control of the individual computer scientist.
JICES
6,3
270
Teachers, mentors, and coaches can invite and instruct, but the individual must, in the
end, adopt a professional self-image of his or her own. Since it is constructed by the
individual, out of stories, histories, roles, goals, values, and commitments, each
self-concept can be quite different from others across the profession. This pluralism in
the most individual part of the model need not be a bad thing, as it leaves room for
individuals to specialize in different visions of the good for the profession, its clients,
and society. If we can begin to measure this component, we can then begin to
understand the range of visions of the good that make up the profession of computing.
Concluding comments for part 1
We have presented here the first two components of the PRIMES model of ethical
behavior in the field of computing, discussing the ways in which personality (PR) and
the IM into the professional self-shape moral action. In the second part of the paper, we
will present the final two components of the model, the ME within which a moral career
is constructed and the skills and knowledge (S) required to sustain moral action in the
profession successfully.
This model can help us rethink our pedagogy of computing ethics (and perhaps of
other engineering disciplines too) and help us to track that pedagogy by suggesting the
variety of measurement techniques that will be needed to encompass a full picture of
moral action in the profession of computing.
References
Aasen, K. and Huff, C. (2007), Personality Characteristics in the Life Stories of Moral Exemplars in
Computing, St Olaf College, Northfield, MN (unpublished manuscript).
Ainsworth, M.D.S. (1968), “Object relations, dependency, and attachment: a theoretical review of
the infant mother relationship”, Child Development, Vol. 40, pp. 969-1025.
Alavi, M., Kayworth, T. and Leidner, D.E. (2006), “An empirical examination of the influence of
organizational culture on knowledge management practices”, Journal of Management
Information Systems, Vol. 22, pp. 191-224.
Allport, G.W. and Odbert, H.S. (1936), “Traitnames: a psycho-lexical study”, Psychological
Monographs, Vol. 47, p. 171.
Anscombe, G.E.M. (1958), “Modern moral philosophy”, Philosophy, Vol. 33, pp. 1-19.
Appiah, K.A. (2008), Experiments in Ethics, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Aristotle (1942), The Nicomachean Ethics, translated by Ross, W.D., Random House,
New York, NY.
Bartels, D.M. and Medin, D.L. (2007), “Are morally motivated decision makers insensitive to the
consequences of their choices?”, Psychological Science, Vol. 18, pp. 24-8.
Baumgarten, F. (1933), “Character traits”, Beitraege zur Charakter – und Personlick –
Keitsforschung, Vol. 1, p. 81.
Bebeau, M.J. (1994), “Influencing the moral dimensions of dental practice”, in Rest, J. and
Narvaez, D. (Eds), Moral Development in the Professions: Psychology and Applied Ethics,
Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ, pp. 121-46.
Bebeau, M.J. and Brabeck, M. (1994), “Ethical sensitivity and moral reasoning among men and
women in the professions”, in Puka, B. (Ed.), Caring Voices and Women’s Moral Frames,
Garland Publishing, New York, NY, pp. 240-59.
Good computing
271
Bebeau, M.J. and Thoma, S.J. (1999), “‘Intermediate’ concepts and the connection to moral
education”, Educational Psychology Review, Vol. 11, pp. 343-60.
Bebeau, M.J., Born, D.O. and Ozar, D.T. (1993), “Development of a professional role orientation
inventory”, The Journal of the American College of Dentists, Vol. 60, pp. 27-33.
Berkowitz, M.W. and Bier, M. (2005), “The interpersonal roots of character education”,
in Lapsley, D.K. and Power, F.C. (Eds), Character Psychology and Character Education,
University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, IN, pp. 1-17.
Blasi, A. (1980), “Bridging moral cognition and moral action: a critical review of the literature”,
Psychological Bulletin, Vol. 88, pp. 1-45.
Blasi, A. (2005), “Moral character: a psychological approach”, in Lapsley, D.K. and Power, F.C.
(Eds), Character Psychology and Character Education, University of Notre Dame, Notre
Dame, IN, pp. 67-100.
Block, J. (1995), “A contrarian view of the five-factor approach to personality description”,
Psychological Bulletin, Vol. 117, pp. 187-215.
Borenstein, N. (1989), “My life as a NATO collaborator”, Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, April,
pp. 14-20.
Bowlby, J. (1969), Attachment and Loss, Vol. 1: Attachment, Basic Books, New York, NY.
Bradey, F.H. (1876/1962), Ethical Studies, 2nd ed., Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Broderick, C.B. (1995), “‘That reminds me of a story...’: the therapeutic use of cautionary tales”,
Contemporary Family Therapy: An International Journal, Vol. 17 No. 1, pp. 17-26.
Burson, K.A., Larrick, R.P. and Klayman, J. (2006), “Skilled or unskilled, but still unaware of it:
how perceptions of difficulty drive miscalibration in relative comparisons”, Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, Vol. 90, pp. 60-77.
Cantor, N. and Harlow, R.E. (1994), “Personality, strategic behavior, and daily-life problem
solving”, Current Directions in Psychological Science, Vol. 3, pp. 169-72.
Carver, C.S. (2005), “Impulse and constraint: perspectives from personality psychology,
convergence with theory in other areas, and potential for integration”, Personality and
Social Psychology Review, Vol. 9 No. 4, pp. 312-33.
Christiansen, C.H., Little, B.R. and Backman, C. (1998), “Personal projects: a useful approach to
the study of occupation”, The American Journal of Occupational Therapy, Vol. 52,
pp. 439-46.
Christiansen, C.H., Backman, C., Little, B.R. and Nguyen, A. (1999), “Occupations and well-being:
a study of personal projects”, The American Journal of Occupational Therapy, Vol. 53,
pp. 91-100.
Cialdini, R.B. (1987), “Compliance principles of compliance professionals: psychologists of
necessity”, in Anna, M., Olson, J.M. and Herman, C.P. (Eds), Social Influence: The Ontario
Symposium, Vol. 5, Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ.
Colby, A. and Damon, W. (1992), Some do Care: Contemporary Lives of Moral Commitment, Free
Press, New York, NY.
Council on Social Work Education Inc. (2004), Educational Policy Standards, available at: http://
socialwork.iu.edu/media/EPAS.htm (accessed August 8, 2007).
Crisp, R. and Slote, M. (Eds) (1997), Virtue Ethics: Oxford Readings in Philosophy, Oxford
University Press, Oxford.
Cross, S.E. and Vick, N. (2001), “The interdependent self-construal and social support: the case of
persistence in engineering”, Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, Vol. 27, pp. 820-32.
JICES
6,3
272
Cross, S.E., Bacon, P. and Morris, M. (2000), “The relational interdependent self-construal and
relationships”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Vol. 78, pp. 791-808.
Cruz, J.A. and Frey, W.J. (2003), “An effective strategy for integrating ethics across the
curriculum in engineering: an ABET 2000 challenge”, Science and Engineering Ethics,
Vol. 9 No. 4, pp. 543-68.
Cunningham, C.A. (2005), “A certain reasoned art: the rise and fall of character education in
America”, in Lapsley, D.K. and Power, F.C. (Eds), Character Psychology and Character
Education, University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, IN, pp. 166-200.
Davidson, M.L. (2005), “Harness the sun, channel the wind: the art and science of effective
character education”, in Lapsley, D.K. and Power, F.C. (Eds), Character Psychology and
Character Education, University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, IN, pp. 218-44.
Davis, M.H., Soderlund, T., Cole, J., Gadol, E., Kute, M. and Myers, M. et al. (2004), “Cognitions
associated with attempts to empathize: how do we imagine the perspective of another?”,
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, Vol. 30, pp. 1625-35.
Donnelley, S. (1995), “The art of moral ecology”, Ecosystem Health, Vol. 1, pp. 170-6.
Doris, J.M. (2002), Lack of Character: Personality and Moral Behavior, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge.
Doris, J.M. and Stich, S.P. (2005), “As a matter of fact: empirical perspectives on ethics”,
in Jackson, F. and Smith, M. (Eds), The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Analytic
Philosophy, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 114-52.
Emmons, R.A. (1986), “Personal strivings: an approach to personality and subjective well-being”,
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Vol. 51, pp. 1058-68.
Feather, N. (1990), “Bridging the gap between values and actions: recent applications of the
expectancy-value model”, The Handbook of Motivation and Cognition: Foundations of
Social Behavior, Vol. 2, pp. 151-92.
Festinger, L. (1957), A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance, Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA.
Flanagan, O. (1991), Varieties of Moral Personality: Ethics and Psychological Realism, Harvard
University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Frey, W. and O’Neill-Carillo, E. (2008), “Engineering ethics in Puerto Rico: issues and narratives”,
Science and Engineering Ethics, Vol. 14 No. 3, pp. 417-31.
Gorman, M.E., Mehalik, M.M. and Werhane, P.H. (2000), Ethical and Environmental Challenges to
Engineering, Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ.
Greene, A.D. and Latting, J.K. (2004), “Whistleblowing as a form of advocacy: guidelines for the
practitioner and organization”, Social Work, Vol. 49, pp. 219-30.
Gregg, G.S. (2005), The Middle East: A Cultural Psychology, Oxford University Press,
New York, NY.
Haidt, J. (2001), “The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist approach to moral
judgment”, Psychological Review, Vol. 108, pp. 814-34.
Haidt, J. (2008), “Morality”, Perspectives on Psychological Science, Vol. 3 No. 1, pp. 65-72.
Harmon, G. (1998/1999), “Moral philosophy meets social psychology: virtue ethics and the
fundamental attribution error”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Vol. 99, pp. 315-31.
Harrington, S.J. (1996), “The effects of codes of ethics and personal denial of responsibility on
computer abuse judgments and intentions”, MIS Quarterly, Vol. 20, pp. 257-78.
Hartshorne, H. and May, M.A. (1930), “A summary of the work of the character education
enquiry”, Religious Education, Vol. 25, pp. 607-19.
Good computing
273
Henderson, M.D., Gollwitzer, P.M. and Oettingen, G. (2007), “Implementation intentions and
disengagement from a failing course of action”, Journal of Behavioral Decision Making,
Vol. 20, pp. 81-102.
Higgins-D’Alessandro and Power, C.F. (2005), “Character, responsibility, and the moral self”,
in Lapsley, D.K. and Power, F.C. (Eds), Character Psychology and Character Education,
University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, IN, pp. 101-20.
Hofstede, G. (2003), Culture’s Consequences: Comparing Values, Behaviors, Institutions, and
Organizations across Nations, Sage, Thousand Oaks, CA.
Hogarth, R.M. (2001), Educating Intuition, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL.
Horowitz, L.M., Wilson, K.R. and Turan, B. (2006), “How interpersonal motives clarify the
meaning of interpersonal behavior: a revised circumplex model”, Personality and Social
Psychology Review, Vol. 10 No. 1, pp. 67-86.
Huff, C.W. (1996), “Practical guidance for teaching the social impact statement”, in Huff, C.W.
(Ed.), Proceedings of the 1996 Symposium on Computers and the Quality of Life, ACM
Press, New York, NY, pp. 86-90.
Huff, C.W. and Barnard, L. (n.d.), “Good computing: life stories of moral exemplars in the
computing profession”, IEEE Computers and Society (in press).
Huff, C.W. and Frey, W. (2005), “Moral pedagogy and practical ethics”, Science and Engineering
Ethics, Vol. 11, pp. 1-20.
Huff, C.W. and Rogerson, S. (2005), “Craft and reform in moral exemplars in computing”, paper
presented at ETHICOMP 2005, Linko
¨ping, September.
Hurtz, G.M. and Donovan, J.J. (2000), “Personality and job performance: the Big Five revisited”,
Journal of Applied Psychology, Vol. 85, pp. 869-79.
John, O.P. and Srivastava, S. (1999), “The big five trait taxonomy: history, measurement, and
theoretical perspectives”, in Pervin, L.A. and John, O.P. (Eds), Handbook of Personality:
Theory and Research, Guilford, New York, NY, pp. 139-53.
Johnson, J.A. (1999), “Persons in situations: distinguishing new wine from old wine in new
bottles”, European Journal of Personality, Vol. 13, pp. 443-53.
Jonas, E., Schulz-Hardt, S., Frey, D. and Thelen, N. (2001), “Confirmation bias in sequential
information search after primary decisions: an expansion of dissonance theoretical
research on selective exposure to information”, Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, Vol. 80, pp. 557-71.
Kant, I. (1965), Fundamental Principals of the Metaphysic of Ethics, Longmans, London.
Kierkegaard (1845/1958), Edifying Discourses, A Selection, Harper & Brothers, New York, NY.
Kohlberg, L. (1971), “From is to ought: how to commit the naturalist fallacy and get away with it
in the study of moral development”, in Mischel, T. (Ed.), Cognitive Development and
Epistemology, Academic Press, New York, NY.
Kohlberg, L. and Kramer, R. (1969), “Continuities and discontinuities in childhood and adult
moral development”, Human Development, Vol. 12, pp. 93-120.
Kuhn, T. (1962), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL.
Kupperman, J.J. (2005), “How not to educate character”, in Lapsley, D.K. and Power, F.C. (Eds),
Character Psychology and Character Education, University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, IN,
pp. 1-17.
Ladd, J. (1991), “The quest for a code of professional ethics: an intellectual and moral confusion”,
in Johnson, D. (Ed.), Ethical Issues in Engineering, Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ,
pp. 130-6.
JICES
6,3
274
Lapsley, D.K. and Narvaez, D. (2005), “Moral psychology at the crossroads”, in Lapsley, D.K. and
Power, F.C. (Eds), Character Psychology and Character Education, University of Notre
Dame, Notre Dame, IN, pp. 18-35.
Lapsley, D.K. and Narvaez, D. (2006), “Character education”, in Renninger, A. and Siegel, I. (Eds),
Handbook of Child Psychology, Vol. 4, Wiley, New York, NY, pp. 248-96.
LeVine, R. (1973), Culture, Behavior, and Personality, Aldine, Chicago, IL.
Li, S., Triandis, H.C. and Yu, Y. (2006), “Cultural orientation and corruption”, Ethics & Behavior,
Vol. 16 No. 3, pp. 199-215.
Little, B.R. (1983), “Personal projects: a rationale and method for investigation”, Environment
& Behavior, Vol. 15 No. 3, pp. 273-309.
Little, B.R. (1999), “Personal projects and social ecology: themes and variations across the life
span”, in Brandtsta
¨dter, J. and Lerner, R.M. (Eds), Action & Self-development: Theory and
Research through the Life Span, Sage, Thousand Oaks, CA, pp. 197-221.
Little, B.R. and Gee, T.L. (2007), “The methodology of personal projects analysis: four modules
and a funnel”, in Little, B.R., Salmela-Aro, K. and Phillips, S.D. (Eds), Personal Project
Pursuit: Goals, Action, and Human Flourishing, Lawrence Erlbaum, Mahwah, NJ,
pp. 51-94.
Little, B.R., Lecci, L. and Watkinson, B. (1992), “Personality and personal projects: linking big
five and PAC Units of analysis”, Journal of Personality, Vol. 60, pp. 501-24.
Locke, K.D. (2000), “Circumplex scales of interpersonal values: reliability, validity, and
applicability to interpersonal problems and personality disorders”, Journal of Personality
Assessment, Vol. 75, pp. 249-67.
Logan, G.D. (1985), “Skill and automaticity: relations, implications, and future directions”,
Canadian Journal of Psychology, Vol. 39, pp. 367-86.
McAdams, D.P. (1993), The Stories We Live by: Personal Myths and the Making of the Self,
W. Morrow, New York, NY.
McAdams, D.P. and Emmons, R.A. (1995), “Levels and domains in personality”, Journal of
Personality, Vol. 63, pp. 341-727.
McCrae, R.R. and Costa, P.T. (1999), “A five-factor theory of personality”, in Pervin, L.A. and
John, O.P. (Eds), Handbook of Personality: Theory and Research, Guilford, New York, NY.
McCrae, R.R., Costa, P.T. Jr, del Pilar, G.H., Rolland, J.P. and Parker, W.D. (1998), “Cross-cultural
assessment of the five-factor model: the revised NEO personality inventory”, Journal of
Cross-cultural Psychology, Vol. 29, pp. 171-88.
McGregor, I. and Little, B.R. (1998), “Personal projects, happiness, and meaning: on doing well
and being yourself”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Vol. 74 No. 2, pp. 494-512.
McKinnon, C. (2005), “Character possession and human flourishing”, in Lapsley, D.K. and
Power, F.C. (Eds), Character Psychology and Character Education, University of Notre Dame,
Notre Dame, IN, pp. 36-66.
MacIntyre, A. (1981/2007), After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory, 3rd ed., University of Notre
Dame Press, Notre Dame, IN.
Mannix, E. and Neale, M.A. (2005), “What differences make a difference? The promise and reality
of diverse teams in organizations”, Psychological Science in the Public Interest, Vol. 6,
pp. 31-54.
Markus, H. and Kitayama, S. (1991), “Culture and the self: Implications for cognition, emotion,
and motivation”, Psychological Review, Vol. 98, pp. 224-53.
Markus, H. and Nurius, P. (1986), “Possible selves”, American Psychologist, Vol. 41, pp. 954-69.
Good computing
275
Marnburg, E. (2000), “The behavioural effects of corporate ethical codes: empirical findings and
discussion”, Business Ethics: A European Review, Vol. 9, pp. 200-10.
May, L. (1996), The Socially Responsive Self: Moral Theory and Professional Ethics, University of
Chicago Press, Chicago, IL.
Milgram, S. (1974), Obedience to Authority, Harper & Row, New York, NY.
Mischel, W. (2004), “Toward an integrative science of the person”, Annual Review of Psychology,
Vol. 55, pp. 1-22.
Mischel, W., Shoda, Y. and Mendoza-Denton, R. (2002), “Situation-behavior profiles as a locus of
consistency in personality”, Current Directions in Psychological Science, Vol. 11, pp. 50-4.
Muraven, M. and Baumeister, R.F. (2000), “Self-regulation and depletion of limited resources:
does self-control resemble a muscle?”, Psychological Bulletin, Vol. 126, pp. 247-59.
Murray, H.A. (1938), Explorations in Personality: A Clinical and Experimental Study of Fifty Men
of College Age, Oxford University Press, New York, NY.
Narvaez, D. (2005), “The Neo-Kohlbergian tradition and beyond: schemas, expertise and
character”, in Pope-Edwards, C. and Carlo, G. (Eds), Nebraska Symposium on Motivation,
Vol. 51: Moral Motivation through the Lifespan, University of Nebraska Press, Lincoln,
NE, pp. 119-63.
Narvaez, D. and Lapsley, D. (2005), “The psychological foundations of everyday morality and
moral expertise”, in Lapsley, D.K. and Power, F.C. (Eds), Character Psychology and
Character Education, University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, IN, pp. 140-65.
Narvaez, D., Bock, T., Endicott, L. and Lies, J. (2004), “Minnesota’s community voices and
character education project”, Journal of Research in Character Education, Vol. 2, pp. 89-112.
Neal, D.T., Wood, W. and Quinn, J.M. (2006), “Habits – a repeat performance”, Current Directions
in Psychological Science, Vol. 15, pp. 198-202.
Nietzsche, F.W. (1954), The Philosophy of Nietzsche, Modern Library, New York, NY.
Oliner, S.P. and Oliner, P. (1988), The Altruistic Personality: Rescuers of Jews in Nazi Europe,
Collier Macmillan, New York, NY.
Oyserman, D., Bybee, D. and Terry, K. (2006), “Possible selves and academic outcomes: how and
when possible selves impel action”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Vol. 91,
pp. 188-204.
Perrinjaquet, A., Furrer, O., Usunier, J.C., Cestre, G. and Valette-Florence, P. (2007), “A test of the
quasi-circumplex structure of human values”, Journal of Research in Personality, Vol. 41,
pp. 820-40.
Pervin, L.A. and John, O.P. (Eds) (1999), Handbook of Personality: Theory and Research, Guilford,
New York, NY.
Piaget, J. (1965), The Moral Judgment of the Child, Free Press, New York, NY.
Pincoffs, E.L. (1971), “Quandary ethics”, Mind, Vol. 80, pp. 552-71.
Pincoffs, E.L. (1986), Quandaries and Virtues: Against Reductivism in Ethics, University of
Kansas Press, Lawrence, KS.
Pritchard, M. (1991), On Becoming Responsible, University of Kansas Press, Lawrence, KS.
Pritchard, M. (1996), Reasonable Children: Moral Education and Moral Learning, University of
Kansas Press, Lawrence, KS.
Pritchard, M. (1998), “Professional responsibility: focusing on the exemplary”, Science and
Engineering Ethics, Vol. 4, pp. 215-34.
JICES
6,3
276
Pritchard, M.S. (2006), Professional Integrity: Thinking Ethically, University of Kansas Press,
Lawrence, KS.
Rest, J.R. (1979), Development in Judging Moral Issues, University of Minnesota Press,
Minneapolis, MN.
Rest, J.R. (1986), Moral Development: Advances in Research and Theory, Praeger, New York, NY.
Rest, J.R. and Narvaez, D. (Eds) (1994), Moral Development in the Professions: Psychology and
Applied Ethics, Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ.
Roberts, B.W., Walton, K. and Viechtbauer, W. (2006), “Patterns of mean-level change in
personality traits across the life course: a meta-analysis of longitudinal studies”,
Psychological Bulletin, Vol. 132, pp. 1-25.
Robinson, J.P., Shaver, P.R. and Wrightsman, L.S. (Eds) (1991), Measures of Personality and
Social Psychological Attitudes, Academic Press, San Diego, CA.
Roccas, S., Sagiv, L., Schwartz, S.H. and Knafo, A. (2002), “The big five personality factors and
personal values”, Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, Vol. 28 No. 6, pp. 789-801.
Rohan, M.J. (2000), “A rose by any name? The values construct”, Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, Vol. 4 No. 3, pp. 255-77.
Ross, L. and NIbsbett, R.E. (1991), The Person and the Situation: Perspectives of Social
Psychology, McGraw-Hill, New York, NY.
Schwartz, S.H. (1994), “Are there universal aspects in the structure and contents of human
values?”, Journal of Social Issues, Vol. 50, pp. 19-45.
Schwartz, S.H. and Bilsky, W. (1990), “Toward a theory of the universal content and structure of
values: extensions and cross-cultural replications”, Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, Vol. 58 No. 5, pp. 878-91.
Schwartz, S.H. and Boehnke, K. (2004), “Evaluating the structure of human values with
confirmatory factor analysis”, Journal of Research in Personality, Vol. 38, pp. 230-55.
Sheilds, D.L. and Bredemeier, B.L. (2005), “Can sports build character?”, in Lapsley, D.K. and
Power, F.C. (Eds), Character Psychology and Character Education, University of Notre
Dame, Notre Dame, IN, pp. 121-39.
Shoda, Y. and Mischel, W. (1998), “Personality as a stable cognitive-affective activation network:
characteristic patterns of behavior variation emerge from a stable personality structure”,
in Miller, S.J. and Lynn, C. (Eds), Connectionist Models of Social Reasoning and Social
Behavior, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers, Mahwah, NJ.
Solomon, R.C. (2003), “Victims of circumstances? A defense of virtue ethics in business”, Business
Ethics Quarterly, Vol. 13, pp. 43-62.
Solomon, R.C. (2005), “What’s character got to do with it?”, Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research, Vol. 71 No. 3, pp. 648-55.
Tangney, J.P. (2002), “Humility”, in Snyder, C.R. and Lopez, S.J. (Eds), Handbook of Positive
Psychology, Oxford University Press, New York, NY, pp. 411-9.
Taylor, C. (1985), Philosophy and the Human Sciences. Philosophical Papers 2, Cambridge
University Press, New York, NY.
Trevin
˜o, L.K. (1986), “Ethical decision making in organizations: a person-situation interactionist
model”, The Academy of Management Review, Vol. 11, pp. 601-17.
van Es, R. and Smit, G. (2003), “Whistleblowing and media logic: a case study”, Business Ethics:
A European Review, Vol. 12, pp. 144-50.
Victor, B. and Cullen, J. (1988), “The organizational bases of ethical work climate”,
Administrative Science Quarterly, Vol. 33, pp. 101-25.
Good computing
277
Vroom, V. and Jago, A. (2007), “The role of the situation in leadership”, American Psychologist.
Special Issue: Leadership, Vol. 62 No. 1, pp. 17-24.
Walker, L.J. and Frimer, J.A. (2007), “Moral personality of brave and caring exemplars”, Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology, Vol. 93 No. 5, pp. 845-60.
Weaver, G.R., Trevin
˜o, L.K. and Agle, B. (2005), “‘Somebody I look up to’: ethical role models in
organizations”, Organizational Dynamics, Vol. 34, pp. 313-30.
Webb, T.L. and Sheeran, P. (2006), “Does changing behavioral intentions engender behavior
change? A meta-analysis of the experimental evidence”, Psychological Bulletin, Vol. 132,
pp. 249-68.
Weiss, S.M., Malone, R.E., Merighi, J.R. and Benner, P. (2002), “Economism, efficiency, and the
moral ecology of good nursing practice”, The Canadian Journal of Nursing Research,
Vol. 34, pp. 95-119.
Wood, M. (2005), “The fallacy of misplaced leadership”, Journal of Management Studies, Vol. 42
No. 6, pp. 1101-21.
Wood, W., Tam, L. and Witt, M.G. (2005), “Changing circumstances, disrupting habits”, Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology, Vol. 88, pp. 918-33.
Zimbardo, P. (2007), The Lucifer Effect: Understanding How Good People Turn Evil, Random
House, New York, NY.
Further reading
Bandura, A. (1999), “Moral disengagement in the perpetration of inhumanities”, Personality and
Social Psychology Review, Vol. 3.
Costa, P.T. Jr and McCrae, R.R. (1998), “Six approaches to the explication of facet level traits:
examples from conscientiousness”, European Journal of Personality, Vol. 12, pp. 17-134.
Huff, C.W. and Barnard, L. (2007), “A performance model of virtue”, poster presented at the
Innovations in the Scholarship of Teaching and Learning Conference, Northfield, MN,
February.
Walzer, M. (1994), Thick and Thin, University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, IN.
Corresponding author
Chuck Huff can be contacted at: huff@stolaf.edu
JICES
6,3
278
To purchase reprints of this article please e-mail: reprints@emeraldinsight.com
Or visit our web site for further details: www.emeraldinsight.com/reprints
Chapter
Ethics is an important perspective in project work. For a research and development project, ethics plays a key role when creating a shared understanding of societal goals and the intended long-term impacts of the project. It is an essential part of designing novel solutions and an integral part of conducting research. However, ethics is typically an area dedicated to ethics experts only, even though it would be important to embed it in the work of all project participants. In a European project on smart manufacturing, we have pursued to involve the whole project consortium to discuss and consider ethics in design and research throughout the project. This paper describes our ethical approach and the results of the engagement activities. Finally, we discuss the practical means we applied to create awareness and commitment towards ethics.KeywordsEthicsDesign EthicsResearch EthicsCo-creationIndustrial Work
Chapter
Personal Health Monitoring (PHM) uses electronic devices which monitor and record health-related data outside a hospital, usually within the home. This paper examines the ethical issues raised by PHM. Eight themes describing the ethical implications of PHM are identified through a review of 68 academic articles concerning PHM. The identified themes include privacy, autonomy, obtrusiveness and visibility, stigma and identity, medicalisation, social isolation, delivery of care, and safety and technological need. The issues around each of these are discussed. The system / lifeworld perspective of Habermas is applied to develop an understanding of the role of PHMs as mediators of communication between the institutional and the domestic environment. Furthermore, links are established between the ethical issues to demonstrate that the ethics of PHM involves a complex network of ethical interactions. The paper extends the discussion of the critical effect PHMs have on the patient’s identity and concludes that a holistic understanding of the ethical issues surrounding PHMs will help both researchers and practitioners in developing effective PHM implementations.1
Chapter
The development of educational technologies is enhancing a distinctive feature of learning environments: the learner’s personalized environment. However, the current literature in e-learning seems to neglect an important discussion: will individuals (learners and lecturers) and organizations face an enhancement concerning ethical dilemmas due to this evolution? To promote this discussion, this paper builds on a consideration of e-learning definition and its ethical dilemmas, and human-centred learning concept and its dimensions, to examine the implications of integrating social and cultural contexts. By examining the evolution of e-learning management systems the argument progresses to a discussion of the relationships between pedagogy and ethics. By framing evidence at different scales, the authors critically reflect on the ethical dilemmas embedded in e-learning systems. The discussion concludes with advocating the adoption of an extension of “three P” mode of pedagogy to become the “P3E” model: personalization, participation, productivity, lecturer’s ethics, learner’s ethics, and organizational ethics.
Chapter
The development of educational technologies is enhancing a distinctive feature of learning environments: the learner’s personalized environment. However, the current literature in e-learning seems to neglect an important discussion: will individuals (learners and lecturers) and organizations face an enhancement concerning ethical dilemmas due to this evolution? To promote this discussion, this paper builds on a consideration of e-learning definition and its ethical dilemmas, and human-centred learning concept and its dimensions, to examine the implications of integrating social and cultural contexts. By examining the evolution of e-learning management systems the argument progresses to a discussion of the relationships between pedagogy and ethics. By framing evidence at different scales, the authors critically reflect on the ethical dilemmas embedded in e-learning systems. The discussion concludes with advocating the adoption of an extension of “three P” mode of pedagogy to become the “P3E” model: personalization, participation, productivity, lecturer’s ethics, learner’s ethics, and organizational ethics.
Chapter
The development of educational technologies is enhancing a distinctive feature of learning environments: the learner’s personalized environment. However, the current literature in e-learning seems to neglect an important discussion: will individuals (learners and lecturers) and organizations face an enhancement concerning ethical dilemmas due to this evolution? To promote this discussion, this paper builds on a consideration of e-learning definition and its ethical dilemmas, and human-centred learning concept and its dimensions, to examine the implications of integrating social and cultural contexts. By examining the evolution of e-learning management systems the argument progresses to a discussion of the relationships between pedagogy and ethics. By framing evidence at different scales, the authors critically reflect on the ethical dilemmas embedded in e-learning systems. The discussion concludes with advocating the adoption of an extension of “three P” mode of pedagogy to become the “P3E” model: personalization, participation, productivity, lecturer’s ethics, learner’s ethics, and organizational ethics.
Article
Full-text available
1 ‫ی‬ .) ‫مهارت‬ ‫از‬ ‫کی‬ ‫می‬ ‫که‬ ‫هایی‬ ‫این‬ ‫در‬ ‫تواند‬ ‫سازمانی‬ ‫شهروندی‬ ‫رفتار‬ ‫کند‬ ‫کمک‬ ‫کارکنان‬ ‫و‬ ‫سازمان‬ ‫به‬ ‫زمینه‬ 1 ‫است‬ ‫سازمان‬ ‫از‬ ‫بسیاری‬ ‫در‬ ‫کارکنان،‬ ‫رفتار‬ ‫نوین‬ ‫الگوی‬ ‫عنوان‬ ‫به‬ ‫که‬ ‫بکار‬ ‫ها‬ (‫است‬ ‫رفته‬ 2 ، 3 ‫شناختی‬ ‫جامعه‬ ‫مهم‬ ‫ابعاد‬ ‫از‬ ‫یکی‬ ‫شهروندی‬ ‫رفتار‬ .) 2 ‫پژوهش‬ ‫و‬ ‫است‬ ‫سازمانی‬ ‫می‬ ‫نشان‬ ‫ها‬ ‫سازمان‬ ‫که‬ ‫دهد‬ ‫تاکید‬ ‫که‬ ‫هایی‬ ‫بیش‬ ‫سالم‬ ‫دارند‬ ‫سازمانی‬ ‫شهروندی‬ ‫رفتار‬ ‫بر‬ ‫تری‬ ‫موفق‬ ‫و‬ ‫تر‬ ‫هستند‬ ‫تر‬ (4 .) ‫برخی‬ ‫محققان‬ ‫به‬ ‫که‬ ‫داوطلبانه،‬ ‫فردی‬ ‫رفتار‬ ‫را‬ ‫سازمانی‬ ‫شهروندی‬ ‫رفتار‬ ‫کارایی‬ ‫و‬ ‫است‬ ‫نشده‬ ‫برانگیخته‬ ‫پاداش‬ ‫رسمی‬ ‫سیستم‬ ِ ‫توسط‬ ‫صریح‬ ‫طور‬ ‫می‬ ‫افزایش‬ ‫را‬ ‫سازمان‬ ‫تعر‬ ‫دهد،‬ ‫کرده‬ ‫یف‬ (‫اند‬ 5 ‫شهروندی‬ ‫رفتار‬ .) ‫کمک‬ ‫از‬ ‫انواعی‬ ‫شامل‬ ‫سازمانی،‬ ‫می‬ ‫اختیاری‬ ‫و‬ ‫غیررسمی‬ ‫های‬ ‫که‬ ‫باشد‬ ‫تحریم‬ ‫به‬ ‫توجه‬ ‫بدون‬ ‫کارمند،‬ ‫پاداش‬ ‫و‬ ‫ها‬ ‫فردی‬ ‫عنوان‬ ‫به‬ ‫و‬ ‫رسمی‬ ‫های‬ ‫آن‬ ‫آزاد‬ ‫آن‬ ‫انجام‬ ‫از‬ ‫یا‬ ‫و‬ ‫داده‬ ‫انجام‬ ‫را‬ ‫ها‬ ‫می‬ ‫خوداری‬ ‫ها،‬ (‫نماید‬ 6 .) ‫ر‬ ‫عنوان‬ ‫به‬ ‫را‬ ‫شهروندی‬ ‫رفتار‬ ‫محققان‬ ‫ضرورت‬ ‫از‬ ‫که‬ ‫فتاری‬ ‫رسمی‬ ‫های‬ ‫می‬ ‫فراتر‬ ‫سازمان‬ ‫است‬ ‫کرده‬ ‫تعریف‬ ‫است‬ ‫سودمند‬ ‫سازمان‬ ‫برای‬ ‫و‬ ‫رود‬ (7 ‫در‬ ‫سازمانی‬ ‫شهروندی‬ ‫رفتار‬ .) 5 ‫دوستی‬ ‫نوع‬ ‫بعد‬ 3 ‫ک‬ ِ ‫وجدان‬ ، ‫ـــــ‬ ‫اری،‬ ‫چکیده‬ ‫زمینه:‬ ‫ضرورت‬ ‫از‬ ‫که‬ ‫رفتاری‬ ‫عنوان‬ ‫به‬ ‫شهروندی‬ ‫رفتار‬ ‫می‬ ‫فراتر‬ ‫سازمان‬ ‫رسمی‬ ‫های‬ ‫سازم‬ ‫برای‬ ‫رود‬ ‫است‬ ‫سودمند‬ ‫ان‬ ‫توجه‬ ‫مورد‬ ‫همواره‬ ‫است‬ ‫گرفته‬ ‫قرار‬ ‫محققان‬ .
Article
While advertising processes are complex and changing, the same ethical problems endure, including those relative to organizational challenges. Yet research affords little attention to challenges influencing ethical awareness in advertising, such as those related to new business. In response to the call for an organizational approach to advertising ethics, ethnographic field work and 45 one-on-one interviews were conducted regarding perceptions of advertising ethics, organizational challenges, and the relationship between the two. Findings suggest that financial pressures related to new business challenges influence how members perceive ethics such as advertising harmful products.
Chapter
What challenges do students face in preparing to practice responsible engineering in a global world? How can students be brought to recognize and avoid pitfalls like paternalism? One answer to this question comes from an unlikely source. While satirizing telescopic philanthropy, Charles Dickens lays down the conditions that a curriculum in global engineering ethics must address. One must “adapt [one’s] mind to those very differently situated,” address other cultures “from suitable points of view,” cultivate a “delicate knowledge of the heart,” and realize that “good intentions alone” are not enough. This essay situates teaching engineering ethics in a global context by outlining the pitfalls students must learn to avoid, putting forward moral imagination as a means to recognize and work around these pitfalls, and showing how moral imagination informs the different modes of engineering moral expertise. This paper will conclude with three learning modules that address some of the pedagogical challenges posed by moral imagination.
Article
Full-text available
Personal Projects Analysis (B. R. Little, 1983) was adapted to examine relations between participants’ appraisals of their goal characteristics and orthogonal happiness and meaning factors that emerged from factor analyses of diverse well-being measures. In two studies with 146 and 179 university students, goal efficacy was associated with happiness and goal integrity was associated with meaning. A new technique for classifying participants according to emergent identity themes is introduced. In both studies, identity-compensatory predictors of happiness were apparent. Agentic participants were happiest if their goals were supported by others, communal participants were happiest if their goals were fun, and hedonistic participants were happiest if their goals were being accomplished. The distinction between happiness and meaning is emphasized, and the tension between efficacy and integrity is discussed. Developmental implications are discussed with reference to results from archival data from a sample of senior managers.
Book
For over a decade the Middle East has monopolized news headlines in the West. Journalists and commentators regularly speculate that the region’s turmoil may stem from the psychological momentum of its cultural traditions or of a “tribal” or “fatalistic” mentality. Yet few studies of the region’s cultural psychology have provided a critical synthesis of psychological research on Middle Eastern societies. Drawing on autobiographies, literary works, ethnographic accounts, and life-history interviews, The Middle East: A Cultural Psychology offers the first comprehensive summary of psychological writings on the region, covering works by psychologists, anthropologists, and sociologists written in English, Arabic, and French. Rejecting stereotypic descriptions of the “Arab mind” or “Muslim mentality,” Gary Gregg adopts a life-span development framework, examining influences on development in the context of recent work in cultural psychology, and compares Middle Eastern patterns less with Western middle class norms than with those described for the region’s neighbors: Hindu India, sub-Saharan Africa, and the Mediterranean shore of Europe. The psychological writings overwhelmingly suggest that the region’s strife stems much less from a stubborn adherence to tradition and resistance to modernity than from widespread frustration with broken promises of modernization - with the slow and halting pace of economic progress and democratization. A sophisticated account of the Middle East’s cultural psychology, this book provides students, researchers, policy-makers, and all those interested in the culture and psychology of the region with invaluable insight into the lives, families, and social relationships of Middle Easterners as they struggle to reconcile the lure of Westernized life-styles with traditional values.
Book
This book is a provocative contribution to contemporary ethical theory challenging foundational conceptions of character that date back to Aristotle. John Doris draws on behavioral science, especially social psychology, to argue that we misattribute the causes of behavior to personality traits and other fixed aspects of character rather than to the situational context. More often than not it is the situation not the nature of the personality that really counts. The author elaborates the philosophical consequences of this research for a whole array of ethical theories and shows that, once rid of the misleading conception of motivation, moral psychology can support more robust ethical theories and more humane ethical practices.