ArticlePDF Available

The Author's Rights in Literary and Artistic Works

Authors:

Abstract

This paper suggests that authorship and creativity, which necessarily precedes the production of literary and artistic works, are products of authentic human expression that the law must encourage in order for works, contributing to the progress of science and the useful arts, to be produced. While the commercial market for literary and artistic works encourages the creation of diverse works to meet popular consumer demand, encouraging the production of works for the commercial market may however result in works, which may lack social, educational and cultural value or utility. Natural law philosophy, which advocates a natural order for society and the actions of men, has a lot to teach about the copyright system as a larger ethical and moral institution to promote the progress of society through the process of authentic authorship. The unique nature of creative works as quasi-public goods, which are not rivaled in consumption and generally non-excludable, requires the grant of exclusive rights to facilitate public dissemination of these works but the special role individual authorship and creativity plays in the production of these works render the rights of an author in the product of their creation as larger, and more encompassing, than the statutory economic incentives to publicly disseminate work. The author's reasons for creating a work may differ remarkably from his incentive to publicly distribute the work. While economic incentives offer authors market rewards that may facilitate the creation and dissemination of literary and artistic works, economic rights represent only a portion of rights, which the copyright system should recognize in the author. This paper makes the case for the recognition of property rights in the author's creation, which originating from an author undertaking of the act of creativity and authorship, is a right to the author's literary and artistic creation that is good against the world, and, which, if protected, will result in authentic expressions of greater significance upon the progress of science and the useful arts in society.
Northwestern Journal of Technology and Intellectual Property
)&.' 3,,. +-#&

Literary Property and Copyright
Alina Ng
Mississippi College School of Law
4#,+-#&#,+).!"--)1). )+ +()*(,,1)+-"0,-+(+#-2%+"))&) 0")&+&1)'')(,-",(*- )+#(&.,#)(
#()+-"0,-+().+(&) "()&)!1((-&&-.&+)*+-11(.-")+#2#-)+) )+-"0,-+(+#-2%+"))&) 0")&+&1)'')(,
)''(#--#)(
&#(! Literary Property and Copyright? 768 :>799 =;< 
"5*,,")&+&1)'')(,&0()+-"0,-+(.($-#*/)&#,,
Literary Property and Copyright
Alina Ng
October 2012
VOL. 10, NO. 7
© 2012 by Northwestern University School of Law
Northwestern Journal of Technology and Intellectual Property
N O R T H W E S T E R N
JOURNAL OF
TECHNOLOGY
AND
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
Copyright 2012 by Northwestern University School of Law Volume 10, Number 7 (October 2012)
Northwestern Journal of Technology and Intellectual Property
Literary Property and Copyright
By Alina Ng*
I. INTRODUCTION
¶1 Copyright laws emerged out of necessity when the earliest printing presses were
introduced into the book trade. After the Statute of Anne codified an assortment of
censorship, licensing, and trade-control rules to produce the world’s first copyright
statute in 1710,
1
it soon became clear in the United Kingdom and in the United States that
all rights in creative works were provided by statute.
2
Copyright laws have steadily
expanded since the Statute of Anne to protect owners of creative works. In the past
decade, attacks on these expansions by left-leaning critics have become visceral and
intense. As copyright owners assert absolute property rights over creative works and
critics argue that state interests operate to balance and limit statutory rights, perhaps the
terms of this debate might be clarified through a determination of whether copyrighted
material is property in a legal sense. If copyright is indeed property in a de jure sense, is
it the same thing as “literary property”? If so, then copyright law provides copyright
owners with the absolute right to own and control literary works in the same way that a
natural property right provides real property owners with the perpetual, exclusive, and
absolute right to own and control property to the exclusion of all others. The purpose of
this Article is to explore the notion of literary property, to determine whether literary
property may be equated with copyright, and, if so, to assess what the implications might
be for modern copyright law as it adapts to newly emerging technological, social, and
cultural trends.
¶2 In Part II, this Article examines the notion of literary property as a distinct legal
concept, which protects an author’s natural right in a manuscript because of the innate
connection between a creator and his work. This discussion shows that literary property
safeguards an author’s creative interests and expectations against the rest of society,
including printers and publishers who purchased the right to print the manuscript. Part III
considers whether literary property can be equated to the modern property right that
statutory copyright creates. Part III concludes that literary property and copyright are
distinct legal concepts, and proposes that the two different bases for recognizing
* Associate Professor of Law, Mississippi College School of Law; LLB (University of London), LLM
(University of Cambridge), JSM and JSD (Stanford Law School). The author is grateful to Mississippi
College for generous research support, editors of the Northwestern Journal of Technology and Intellectual
Property Law for excellent editorial work, and participants at the Association of Law, Property, and Society
Annual Meeting 2011, where an earlier draft of this Article was presented for helpful comments. As
always, this Article is dedicated to the author’s family.
1
For excellent studies on the history of the copyright system, see LYMAN RAY PATTERSON, COPYRIGHT
IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE (1968); MARK ROSE, AUTHORS AND OWNERS: THE INVENTION OF COPYRIGHT
(1993). See also BENJAMIN KAPLAN, AN UNHURRIED VIEW OF COPYRIGHT 137 (1966) (presenting a
concise account of the first 350 years of copyright law).
2
Wheaton v. Peters, 33 U.S. (8 Pet.) 591, 661 (1834); Donaldson v. Beckett, (1774) 1 Eng. Rep. 837
(H.L.) (Gr. Brit.).
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
532
ownership of creative worksnatural property and economic incentivesshould be
explicitly recognized as separate and distinct ideas to ensure clarity in policy that
determines legal entitlements to creative works. Part IV evaluates how such a separation
of natural property and economic incentives affects and shapes the debate of the elusive
balance between private rights and the public interest. Part IV surmises that a separation
of rights from incentives and the acknowledgement of specific norms recognizing
authors’ entitlements and obligations will allow the copyright system to realize its
constitutional goal of “promot[ing] the Progress of Science and useful Arts.
3
II. LITERARY PROPERTY AS A LEGAL CONCEPT
¶3 The full extent to which literary property can be said to safeguard an author’s
natural right over his own work may be a matter of pure academic speculation.
4
What
appears certain, however, is that literary property predates statutory copyright and
protects an author’s personal interest and individuality to a greater extent than an
industry-based entitlement intended to control the mass production and publication of the
work. Authors produced literature before the invention of the printing press made
copying cheap and easy, and, while plagiarists were often severely admonished for
representing someone else’s work as their own,
5
pirates, who reproduced works in their
totality, were often praised for preserving the integrity of the original work.
6
Thus, even
before copyright existed to protect commercial rights to print, publish, and distribute,
noneconomic incentives motivated authors to express themselves through poetry, songs,
and literature, expecting the community to respect the personal integrity of authors.
Conceivably, the author’s expectation that society will respect personal rights that protect
the author’s creative integrity exists independently of any printing privileges or rights to
print manuscripts that the state awards to some publishers and authors to encourage
development of a printing industry and capitalistic trade in literary and artistic works.
7
Before Gutenberg introduced the printing press, printing privileges and monopolies were
not needed to encourage the development of a publishing industry; nor were printing
licenses required to control the types of works.
8
It would have been clear without the
intense competition that moveable-type print technology introduced into the market for
3
U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8, cl. 8.
4
There does not appear to be evidence of actual protection of literary property, but the term has often
been used interchangeably with copyright to signify some proprietary or ownership right to the work. Mark
Rose, for example, refers to the early copyright struggle between booksellers in England as “the question of
literary property.” See ROSE, supra note 1, at 4. Lyman Ray Patterson and Stanley Lindberg, on the other
hand, suggest that literary property and copyright are essentially different things. See L. RAY PATTERSON &
STANLEY W. LINDBERG, THE NATURE OF COPYRIGHT: A LAW OF USERS RIGHTS 122 (1991). To them, the
rights of authors should not be treated as copyright but as a “companion body of law.” See id.
5
AUGUSTINE BIRRELL, SEVEN LECTURES ON THE LAW AND HISTORY OF COPYRIGHT IN BOOKS 9 (1899)
(“You may search through the huge compilations of Justinian without lighting upon a word indicative of
any right possessed by the author of a book to control the multiplication of copies; and yet books abounded
even before the invention of printing, and though the pirate escaped animadversion, not so the plagiarist.”).
6
MARCUS BOON, IN PRAISE OF COPYING 34 (2010).
7
JANE A. BERNSTEIN, PRINT CULTURE AND MUSIC IN SIXTEENTH-CENTURY VENICE 10 (2001)
(describing the emerging printing industry in Venice when the Venetian Senate granted the first printing
monopoly to Johannes de Spira).
8
For a discussion of state control of publishing activities to prevent sedition and heresy, see ROSE, supra
note 1, at 3132.
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
533
literary works
9
that, as a matter of natural law, the sole possessor of any rights to a
manuscript, poem, or song would be its author. Literary property seemed to protect the
author’s expression at natural law, while statutory rights to print and publish manuscripts
provide an economic incentive to invest in the printing industry. These separate rights
that emerge from entirely different sources, as evidenced by the relationship between
authors and publishers that developed when printing and publishing became a robust and
profitable trade in Europe and the United States, had served separate and distinct interests
in creative works.
A. Author’s Expectations and Publishing Norms
¶4 Although the notion of literary property has not been well defined in literature and
very little has been written specifically about literary property in the context of authors’
creative rights in their works,
10
it appears to be another source of rights and obligations
for the author. From historical evidence on authorpublisher relationships in the
developing book trade in late seventeenth century England, scholars have deduced that
literary property, as the right of the author, was a larger right that encompassed the
publisher’s copyright. The earliest preserved contractual agreement that transferred a
right to print from the author to his publisher was John Milton’s publication contract with
Samuel Simmons for Paradise Lost in April of 1667.
11
For the manuscript of Paradise
Lost, Milton received five pounds upon signing the contract and an additional five pounds
after each edition of the manuscript was sold.
12
The contract provided for the publication
of three editions of the manuscript of 1,300 copies each.
13
Both Milton and Simmons
agreed that these three editions would not run more than 1,500 copies each.
14
Scholars of
eighteenth century English literature consider the payment of twenty pounds to have been
an extremely modest payment for the manuscript of an epic poem at that time, but
evidence of the amount typically paid for the sale of a manuscript when Simmons
purchased Paradise Lost is too scant to conclusively determine that Milton was underpaid
for the poem.
15
Generally, a publisher’s unfair treatment of an author might indicate a
superior position in the authorpublisher relationship that would have allowed the
9
For a description on the impact of moveable-type printing presses on the literary market, see PAUL
STARR, THE CREATION OF THE MEDIA: POLITICAL ORIGINS OF MODERN COMMUNICATIONS 26 (2004)
(describing how a capitalistic market for the book trade developed as Gutenberg’s print technology spread).
10
The notions of literary property and authorship have been examined in relation to the
commodification of literature, and some scholars of law and literary studies have attributed the emergence
of literary property and authorship to the commodification of literature with the development of the book
market in the eighteenth century. See, e.g., ROSE, supra note 1, at 12; MARTHA WOODMANSEE, THE
AUTHOR, ART, AND THE MARKET: REREADING THE HISTORY OF AESTHETICS 2233 (1994); Peter Jaszi, On
the Author Effect: Contemporary Copyright and Collective Creativity, 10 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 293
(1992).
11
Peter Lindenbaum, Authors and Publishers in the Late Seventeenth Century: New Evidence on Their
Relations, 17 LIBRARY 250 (1995).
12
Peter Lindenbaum, Milton’s Contract, 10 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 439, 441 (1992).
13
Id.
14
Id.
15
There is some evidence that Milton’s contemporaries were paid much more for their work. Richard
Baxter, for example, received a total of £170 over a thirteen- to sixteen-year period for his Saint’s
Everlasting Rest. He received £10 for the first publication of the manuscript. There is also evidence, albeit
unreliable, that John Dryden received £20 for the manuscript of Troilus and Cressida in 1679. Id. at 442
43.
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
534
publisher to control all of the rights to print and sell manuscripts. But this did not appear
to be the case with Milton’s contract. On the contrary, Milton appeared to have superior
bargaining power in this arrangement, as the contract contained provisions that protected
Milton as an owner of specific property rights in the manuscript even after the right to
print the work had been assigned to Simmons.
¶5 Perhaps the most telling sign that Milton retained some form of literary property in
Paradise Lost after assigning the right to print to Simmons was that one of the clauses in
Milton’s contract allowed him to “demand an accounting of sales at reasonable
intervals.”
16
Should Simmons have failed to provide such accounting after Milton
demanded one, Simmons would have been required to pay him the five pounds for the
whole impression immediately, rather than after completing the sale of 1,300 copies.
17
This clause indicates that both Milton and Simmons thought the author possessed some
form of property right in the work even after the right to print it had been assigned.
Because only a co-owner of a property interest or a beneficiary in a trust relationship
could demand an accounting of sales,
18
it appears that both Milton and Simmons
considered the author of a manuscript to be its owner while the printer is put in the
position of a trustee for as long as the printer owned the limited right to print the work.
¶6 Professor Peter Lindenbaum furthermore points to the provision capping the
number of copies Simmons could print to suggest that Milton possessed some form of
property right in the work.
19
The provision capped the number of prints to 1,500 and
ensured that the printer’s profits would not disproportionately exceed the author’s.
20
This
further supports the claim that the printer’s right to reproduce the work was limited when
compared to the author’s more encompassing property right. Studying the same contract,
Lyman Ray Patterson observes that Milton agreed to refrain from interfering with
publication of the work, which Professor Patterson argues would be unnecessary if
assigning rights to the printer conveyed all existing legal rights in the work.
21
¶7 Milton’s publication contract for Paradise Lost provides rare and invaluable
evidence of literary property as an author’s right, acknowledged by both authors and
publishers, even before authors were recognized as capable of owning copyrights in their
work. Before the Statute of Anne was passed in 1710,
22
copyright, as the right to print,
publish, and vend literary works, could be owned only by printers and publishers who
were members of the Stationers’ Company, the trade guild regulating the book publishing
16
Id. at 443.
17
Id.
18
Magruder v. Drury & Maddox, 235 U.S. 106 (1914); Gillmor v. Gillmor, 694 P.2d 1037 (Utah 1984).
19
Lindenbaum, supra note 12, at 443.
20
Id.
21
PATTERSON, supra note 1, at 74. Patterson also examined two conveyances by the poet James
Thomson. Id. at 7475. The first was from Thomson to Millar, a publisher, which contained the specific
assignment of the right to print with the benefit of all additions, corrections, and amendments that Thomson
might make to the work after the assignment of the copyright. Id. at 74. The second conveyance from
Millan, a bookseller, to Millar granted the right to lawfully claim all profits from the printing and
publishing of the poems. Id. at 75. Patterson highlights that both conveyances emphasized the transfer of
different rights. Id. Thomson transferred the copyright together with what Patterson called “the author’s
creative rights”—the control over the work to make additions, corrections, and amendments
notwithstanding the ownership of copyright. Id. The emphasis on profits arising from the printing and
publishing of the poems in the second conveyance suggests that copyright was of a more limited nature
than the author’s right. Id.
22
Statute of Anne, 1710, 8 Ann., c. 19 (Eng.).
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
535
business.
23
Ownership of copyright in a book was recorded in the register book of the
Stationers’ Company by the stationer licensed by the Crown to print the book.
24
Authors,
who only rarely owned a copyright in their work that was entered into the company’s
register, were generally excluded from owning the right to print and publish their work.
Yet Milton’s publication contract suggests that authors had a more complex relationship
with their publishers than is commonly assumed, even before authors were recognized as
legitimate copyright holders by the Statute of Anne. One could deduce from Milton’s
contract that the author possessed creative and proprietary rights in the work as its
creatorrights that provided the author with ownership and control over the work even
after he sold it to the printer. These rights were separate and distinct from the publisher’s
copyright and were viewed as more limited rights to print and recover profits from sales
of the work.
¶8 Milton’s contract is not the only historical evidence that suggests authors had a
more encompassing right in their work than modern copyright provides. The publication
contracts between early American authors and their publishers after the passing of the
first U.S. copyright statute of 1790
25
also allude to an author’s continued proprietary and
creative control over their work, even after the sale of the manuscript and assignment to
the publisher.
26
For instance, the March 1868 publication contract between Ralph Waldo
Emerson and Ticknor & Fields (which later became Houghton Mifflin Company) for the
publication of May-Day and Other Pieces contained a clause that granted Ticknor &
Fields “the sole right to publish” the work for the duration of the agreement, which
appears to have been carved out of Emerson’s larger proprietary interest
27
and to provide
a written order for the printing of any additional editions that Ticknor & Fields
considered expedient.
28
Emerson had the option to terminate the contract at any time,
23
Russ VerSteeg, The Roman Law Roots of Copyright, 59 MD. L. REV. 522, 52628 (2000).
24
Early copyright was intertwined with Crown censorship policies as the government sought to control
the publication and distribution of what were considered heretical and seditious materials. The Stationers’
Company was the perfect body, and copyright the perfect instrument, to implement these policies through
an intricate system of licensing laws. See PATTERSON, supra note 1, at 11442.
25
Act of May 31, 1790, ch. 15, 1 Stat. 124, repealed by Copyright Act of 1909, ch. 320, 35 Stat. 1075.
26
Publication contracts that predate the 1790 Copyright Act would be ideal to show that authors clearly
had rights that were separate from the rights of publishers. There is, however, a paucity of contracts that
showed a clear distinction between author and publisher, in part because of certain personalities of well-
known authors writing at that time. Benjamin Franklin, for example, was a well-known author who wrote
before the first U.S. Copyright Act was passed. He was also a publisher, and printed and distributed his
own work. Hence, there was no need to address the separate rights of publisher and author. Thomas Paine
was also famous for his revolutionary work, Common Sense, but published it anonymously because of its
treasonous content. As such, there is no suggestion of the author’s separate claim to the contents of the
manuscript.
27
Contract for publication of May Day and Other Pieces between Ralph Waldo Emerson and Ticknor &
Fields cl. 2 (Mar. 4, 1868) (on file with Houghton Library, Harvard University); see also Contract for
publication of Uncle Tom’s Cabin, New Edition with Illustrations, a Bibliography and an Introductory
Account of the Work between Harriet Beecher Stowe and Houghton, Osgood & Co. cl. 6 (Nov. 21, 1878)
(on file with Houghton Library, Harvard University).
28
Clause 4 of the contract reads:
The said party of the first part [Emerson] shall deposit with such printers as the parties
hereto shall mutually agree upon, the stereotype plates of the said work, and whenever
the said parties of the second part [Ticknor & Fields] think it expedient to print an edition
of the said work, the said party of the first part shall give a written order for printing the
required number of copies, and no copies shall be printed from the plates of said work
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
536
which would require that he purchase all remaining copies in Ticknor & Fields’s
possession at cost.
29
It is notable that even given the Supreme Court’s 1834 decision of
Wheaton v. Peters, which held that authors do not have a common law property right
separate from the statutory right to print and publish,
30
Emerson’s contract protected the
author’s right to control the contents of his manuscript from any alteration or
modification by requiring the author to provide stereotype plates of the work and
authorization for the publication of any new editions. This right appears to be
independent of statutory copyright. The termination clause of the contract further
affirms, implicitly, the author’s proprietary right in his creative expression by protecting a
claim to restitution of the published work that should belong only to a property owner.
31
It would have made more business sense for Ticknor & Fields to require Emerson to
purchase the remaining stock at market price upon termination of the publication contract
and seek contractual damages for reliance loss.
32
However, this was not the agreement
between author and publisher in this case. By providing Emerson with the option to
terminate the contract at any time with only the penalty of purchasing the remaining stock
at cost, Ticknor & Fields appeared to recognize Emerson’s property right in the work
itselfa larger proprietary right that included the more limited statutory right to print that
was assigned to Ticknor & Fields in the publication contract with Emerson.
33
without such written order.
Contract for publication of May Day and Other Pieces, supra note 27, cl. 4.
29
Clause 6 of the contract reads:
The party of the first part can at any time terminate this agreement by giving to the
parties of the second part written notice of his intention so to do; and in the event of his
terminating this agreement, he shall purchase at its cost all the stock of the said work the
parties of the second part shall have on hand, paying therefor in cash.
Id. cl. 6.
30
Wheaton v. Peters, 33 U.S. (8 Pet.) 591 (1834).
31
See, e.g., GRAHAM VIRGO, THE PRINCIPLES OF THE LAW OF RESTITUTION 11 (2d ed. 2006) (arguing
that restitutionary claims vindicate property rights of its claimant, with which the defendant had interfered);
Hanoch Dagan, Restitutionary Damages from Breach of Contract: An Exercise in Private Law Theory, 1
THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 115, 12930 (2000) (arguing that the notion of property rights is a highly
contested concept that is open to competing interpretations, and hence, cannot be used as a basis to justify
claims of restitution); Douglas Laycock, The Scope and Significance of Restitution, 67 TEX. L. REV. 1277,
1279 (1989) (defining restitution as (1) a recovery based on unjust enrichment and (2) a restoration in kind
of a specific property). In Emerson’s case, the fact that the publisher would return printed copies of the
book to Emerson at cost price, even when Emerson terminated the agreement, suggests that the publisher
saw restitution as a way to restore Emerson’s property right in his expression contained in the work.
32
See L.L. Fuller & William R. Perdue, Jr., The Reliance Interest in Contract Damages, 46 YALE L.J.
52, 54 (1936) (The law “may award damages to the plaintiff for the purpose of undoing the harm which his
reliance on the defendant’s promise has caused him. [The] object is to put him in as good a position as he
was in before the promise was made. The interest protected in this case may be called the reliance
interest.”).
33
The publication contracts between Houghton Mifflin and other authors such as Harriet Beecher
Stowe, Henry David Thoreau, and Oliver Wendell Holmes show the same implicit recognition of an
author’s property rights in his work by the publisher in the reversion or destruction of stereotype plates
after termination of contract and in the promise to publish the work in ways that will affirm the author’s
creative personality. The publication contract for Harriet Beecher Stowe’s new edition of Uncle Tom’s
Cabin reads:
If, at the expiration of five years from date of publication, or at any time thereafter, the
demand for said work should not be sufficient in the opinion of the parties of the second
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
537
¶9 As a legal concept, the term literary property often connotes an individual right that
grants exclusive ownership of a work. Copyright cases suggest that there are three
distinct but interrelated characteristics of literary property, each of which will be
discussed below: literary property (1) conveys a proprietary right, (2) protects a creative
interest, and (3) arises from an author’s natural right. Literary property grants the author
proprietary rights in the work by recognizing the author’s expectation to maintain control
of the work even when it is subject to the Copyright Act. In 1985, for example, the
Supreme Court held that an author has the right to control the first public appearance of
unpublished expressions and that society’s expectation to have access to the work was
secondary to the right of the author.
34
Because the Copyright Act of 1976 protects works
as soon as they are fixed in a tangible medium of expression,
35
the Court’s decision to
deny the defense of fair use once the work has been fixed but remains unpublished
protects the author’s right to decide whether to publish a work as well as when, where,
and in what form. These common law rights fall outside the explicit rights in the
Copyright Act.
36
The right to confidentiality, privacy,
37
and creative control of the work
is a proprietary right that protects expression of the author’s personality and individuality.
part [Houghton, Osgood & Co.] to render its publication profitable, then this agreement
shall end, and the party of the first part [Stowe] shall have the right at his option, to take
from the parties of the second part, at cost, the stereotype or electrotype plates (and
engravings if any) of said work and whatever copies they may then have on hand; or,
should he fail to take said plates and copies at cost, then the parties of the second part
shall have the right to dispose of the copies on hand as they may see fit, free of copyright,
and to destroy the plates . . . .
Contract for publication of Uncle Tom’s Cabin, supra note 27, cl. 7. In the contracts for the publication
of Henry David Thoreau’s works entered between his younger sister, Sophia Thoreau, and Ticknor &
Fields was a clause that ensured the publishers printed and published the work “in good style.” Contract for
publication of Excursions between Sophia E. Thoreau and Ticknor & Fields (Sept. 1, 1863) (on file with
Houghton Library, Harvard University); Contract for publication of Letters of Henry D. Thoreau between
Sophia E. Thoreau and Ticknor & Fields cl. 3 (Mar. 20, 1865) (on file with Houghton Library, Harvard
University); Contract for publication of The Maine Woods between Sophia E. Thoreau and Ticknor &
Fields cl. 3 (May 2, 1864) (on file with Houghton Library, Harvard University); Contract for publication of
A Yankee in Canada with Anti-Slavery and Reform Papers cl. 3 (Sept. 3, 1866) (on file with Houghton
Library, Harvard University). The contracts for the publication of Oliver Wendell Holmes’s works have a
similar clause that the publisher print and publish the work “in good st yle.” Contract for publication of The
Autocrat of the Breakfast Table between Oliver Wendell Holmes and Ticknor & Fields cl. 3 (May 13,
1867) (on file with Houghton Library, Harvard University); Contract for publication of The Guardian
Angel between Oliver Wendell Holmes and Ticknor & Fields cl. 4 (Nov. 26, 1866) (on file with Houghton
Library, Harvard University); Contract for publication of Mechanism of Thought and Morals between
Oliver Wendell Holmes and Fields, Osgood & Co. cl. 3 (Dec. 7, 1870) (on file with Houghton Library,
Harvard University); Contract for publication of Poems by Oliver Wendell Holmes between Oliver Wendell
Holmes and Ticknor & Fields cl. 3 (May 13, 1867) (on file with Houghton Library, Harvard University).
34
Harper & Row, Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539 (1985).
35
17 U.S.C. § 102 (2006).
36
The specific rights that the Copyright Act recognizes are the rights to reproduction, distribution,
derivatives, and public performance and display. Id. § 106.
37
Samuel D. Warren & Louis D. Brandeis, The Right to Privacy, 4 HARV. L. REV. 193, 19899 (1890)
(“The common law secures to each individual the right of determining, ordinarily, to what extent his
thoughts, sentiments, and emotions shall be communicated to others. Under our system of government, he
can never be compelled to express them (except when upon the witness-stand); and even if he has chosen to
give them expression, he generally retains the power to fix the limits of the publicity which shall be given
them. The existence of this right does not depend upon the particular method of expression adopted. It is
immaterial whether it be by word or by signs, in painting, by sculpture, or in music.”) (footnotes omitted).
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
538
In essence, it is a personal right even if it is commercially valuable to the author and
publisher.
38
More importantly, the Court’s explicit protection of the creative space
necessary for an author to develop her ideas during the prepublication stage and polish
her work for public dissemination acknowledges the author’s personal interest in how the
work projects the author’s personality and individuality to the reading public.
39
Furthermore, the doctrine arising from a famous case between J.D. Salinger and Random
House protects an author’s right to control the use of unpublished letters that have been
made publicly available through library archives on the same principle that “[t]he
copyright owner owns the literary property rights, including the right to complain of
infringing copying” of the letters’ expression.
40
¶10 While literary property protects the proprietary interest of authors, the right is more
limited in scope in that it appears to protect only the authors’ creative interests in their
work. Generally, the commercial interests of authors are protected through statutory
copyright law,
41
but, at least in the United States, the creative rights of authors do not
receive the same degree of protection through the copyright statute.
42
The notion of
literary property, because of its genesis in the author’s natural right as the creator of the
work, protects creative rights: the author’s personal rights to protect his personality, as
expressed in the work, from distortion by others in society.
43
This right serves the
important function of ensuring that the author of a work can preserve the integrity of that
work once it is made publicly available because the work represents the author’s
personality and makes a unique contribution to society through the author’s authentic
expression. Given the important contribution that the author’s expression makes to
society, Professor Patterson argues it is in society’s interest to reciprocate by protecting
the author’s creative interest in that work.
44
Authors generally expect two things from
making their creative pursuits available to society: (1) payment for their work and (2)
38
See Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at 553 (“The right of first publication implicates a threshold decision by
the author whether and in what form to release his work. First publication is inherently different from other
§ 106 rights in that only one person can be the first publisher; . . . the commercial value of the right lies
primarily in exclusivity.”).
39
Id. at 555 (“The period encompassing the work’s initiation, its preparation, and its grooming for
public dissemination is a crucial one for any literary endeavor. The Copyright Act, which accords the
copyright owner the ‘right to control the first public distribution’ of his work echos [sic] the common law’s
concern that the author or copyright owner retain control throughout this critical stage. The obvious benefit
to author and public alike of assuring authors the leisure to develop their ideas free from fear of
expropriation outweighs any short-term ‘news value’ to be gained from premature publication of the
author’s expression.”) (citations omitted).
40
Salinger v. Random House, Inc., 811 F.2d 90, 94 (2d Cir. 1987).
41
17 U.S.C. § 106.
42
The creative rights of authors of works of visual art also receive some degree of protection under
§ 106A. See id. § 106A(a)(1)(A) (protecting authors from plagiarism by providing the right “to claim
authorship of that work,” also known as the right of attribution); id. § 106A(a)(1)(B) (protecting the right of
integrity by providing the right to prevent the use of the author’s name for work that the author did not
create); id. § 106A(a)(2) (protecting against misrepresentation by providing the right to prevent use of
“name as the author of a work in the event of a distortion, mutilation, or other modification of the work
which would be prejudicial to [the author’s] honor or reputation”); id. § 106A(a)(3)(A) (protecting authors
from intentional distortion, mutilation, or other modification of the work); id. § 106A(a)(3)(B) (protecting
against any destruction of work of recognized stature). This provision has very strict boundaries and is
limited in its application. What amounts to a “work of visual art” is defined narrowly under the Copyright
Act. See id. § 101.
43
Lloyd L. Weinreb, Copyright for Functional Expression, 111 HARV. L. REV. 1149, 1213 (1998).
44
PATTERSON, supra note 1, at 7071.
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
539
preservation of their creative personality and the integrity of their work (although authors
may be motivated to create for other reasons such as fame, notoriety, or to inspire social
and political reform). As the Copyright Act facilitates the work’s commodification to
garner rewards from the market, the noneconomic interests of authors can be protected by
an explicit recognition of literary (or creative) property through common law.
¶11 Literary property rights also arise from authors’ natural rights in their work and are
attributed to the relationship between an author and his work. The idea that authors own
property in their work because that work embodies their personal individuality predates
the earliest copyright statute
45
and was acknowledged not because of an existing social
convention but as a fundamental human right of individuals to own that which they create
through their labor.
46
In protesting censorship of literary work, John Milton proclaimed
that books “contain a potency of life in them to be as active as that soul was whose
progeny they are” as well as “preserve as in a vial the purest efficacy and extraction of
that living intellect that bred them,”
47
revealing the author’s understanding of his work as
an extension of his personality or individualityas a part of him. Even if the process of
literary creation inevitably builds upon existing works, the very act of mixing personal
expression with literary resources and ideas from the commons (or nature) creates an
author’s literary property right in the work that justifies authorial control over how the
work is used, particularly when the public use of the work goes against the author’s
intention for creating that work in the first place. Therefore, literary property is a right
that protects authors’ expectations separately from those of publishers, is proprietary in
nature, is limited to the protection of creative rights, and exists because of the natural
connection between an author and his work.
B. Literary Property as a Natural Right
¶12 Modern copyright law, which protects the economic rights of copyright owners,
whether author or publisher, is statutorily created. The legislature, courts, and scholars
have long recognized the economic role that statutory copyright plays in encouraging and
rewarding creative production for public benefit.
48
The genesis of literary property
45
The Statute of Anne 1710 was the first copyright statute to be passed in England and explicitly
recognized the right of authors to print, reprint, and publish literary works. See Statute of Anne, 1710, 8
Ann., c. 19 (Eng.).
46
The most familiar idea that supports the author’s natural right in the work is probably John Locke’s
passage in his Second Treatise on Civil Government that every man has property in his person, and when he
removes something out of nature to mix it with his own labor, he has property in it. JOHN LOCKE, THE
SECOND TREATISE ON CIVIL GOVERNMENT 20 (Prometheus Books 1986) (1690) (“Though the earth and all
inferior creatures be common to all men, yet every man has a ‘property’ in his own ‘person.’ This nobody
has any right to but himself. The ‘labour’ of his body, and the ‘work’ of his hands, we may say, are
properly his. Whatsoever, then, he removes out of the state of that Nature hath provided and left in it, he
hath mixed his labour with it, and joined to it something that is his own, and thereby makes it his
property.”).
47
JOHN MILTON, Areopagitica: A Speech for the Liberty of Unlicensed Printing to the Parliament of
England (1644), reprinted in PARADISE LOST: AN AUTHORITATIVE TEXT, SOURCES AND BACKGROUNDS,
CRITICISM 339, 342 (Gordon Teskey ed., 2005).
48
Fogerty v. Fantasy, Inc., 510 U.S. 517, 527 (1994) (“[C]opyright law ultimately serves the purpose of
enriching the general public through access to creative works . . . .”); Twentieth Century Music Corp. v.
Aiken, 422 U.S. 151, 156 (1975) (“Creative work is to be encouraged and rewarded, but private motivation
must ultimately serve the cause of promoting broad public availability of literature, music, and the other
arts.”); see also Steven Hetcher, Desire Without Hierarchy: The Behavioral Economics of Copyright
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
540
rights, which protect less tangible interests of a human creator such as personality and
identity, may be less certain. Statutory copyright developed as socio-economic
conditions evolved to create a demand for creative materials, which legal protection of
authors’ and publishers’ economic rights aim to meet.
49
This idea that printed materials
are receptacles containing an author’s intellect and creative personality draws a clear
distinction between, on one hand, an author’s expectation to have control of the
manuscript itself through some form of literary property (which protects the manuscript
in its entirety), and, on the other hand, an economic interest in publishing and selling the
work as one right from a bundle of rights (which stems from the author’s proprietary
interest or ownership of the manuscript).
50
¶13 Several normative narratives have been advanced to support the acknowledgement
of literary property as a natural right of the author. John Locke’s labor theory has often
been cited as support for the normative proposition that authors ought to have property
rights in the products of their creative labor.
51
Instrumental within this line of thinking is
Locke’s notion that individuals have property rights in and ownership of their person, and
hence the labor of one’s body and the work of one’s hand—when mixed with commonly
available resources from natureshould produce a thing that may be appropriated out of
nature and be protected as a proper subject matter of a property right.
52
Another
normative narrative supporting the author’s property right in a work is Wilhelm Hegel’s
writings about property as an important attribute of freedom and thus necessary for the
development of the author as a social being, whose dignity and value as an individual
thrive on the ability to control resources from one’s external environment.
53
Hegel’s
Incentives, 48 U. LOUISVILLE L. REV. 817, 819 (2010) (describing legal scholars’ reliance on the incentive
theory as the primary motivation for creativity); Maureen Ryan, Fair Use and Academic Expression:
Rhetoric, Reality, and Restriction on Academic Freedom, 8 CORNELL J.L. & PUB. POLY 541, 544 (1999)
(“Given the Framers’ predilection for open inquiry and the high value they placed on innovation in ideas
and technology, it makes sense that the Framers’ focus in enacting the Copyright Clause was encouraging
maximum production and dissemination of new works.”).
49
See BERNSTEIN, supra note 7, at 1821 (describing how the commercialization of music printing in
sixteenth century Venice led music composers and publishers to seek printing privileges (an early form of
copyright) to commercialize their work and distribute it to the public); see also WOODMANSEE, supra note
10, at 5253 (describing how legal recognition of proprietary ownership of authors and publishers in the
work through legislation facilitated its distribution).
50
Scholars have noted this important distinction between ownership of the manuscript and ownership of
a right to print and sell the manuscript. See, e.g., L. Ray Patterson, Free Speech, Copyright, and Fair Use,
40 VAND. L. REV. 1, 29 (1987) (“The author, as creator of the new work, clearly had the right to ‘judge
when to publish, or whether he will ever publish,’ and nothing in the statute inhibited this right. The
bookseller, however, could own the copyright only by reason of assignment. Ownership by reason of
creation and ownership by way of assignment, of course, are subtantially [sic] different. Natural-law
arguments support the former, but not the latter.”).
51
See, e.g., Wendy J. Gordon, A Property Right in Self-expression: Equality and Individualism in the
Natural Law of Intellectual Property, 102 YALE L.J. 1533, 1540 (1993); Justin Hughes, The Philosophy of
Intellectual Property, 77 GEO. L.J. 287, 297 (1988); Linda J. Lacey, Of Bread and Roses and Copyrights,
1989 DUKE L.J. 1532, 1539; Weinreb, supra note 43, at 122223; Alfred C. Yen, Restoring the Natural
Law: Copyright as Labor and Possession, 51 OHIO ST. L.J. 517, 523 (1990).
52
LOCKE, supra note 46, at 20.
53
See Hughes, supra note 51, at 330; Christian G. Stallberg, Towards a New Paradigm in Justifying
Copyright: An UniversalisticTranscendental Approach, 18 FORDHAM INTELL. PROP. MEDIA & ENT. L.J.
333, 348 (2008); David Dante Troutt, I Own Therefore I Am: Copyright, Personality, and Soul Music in the
Digital Commons, 20 FORDHAM INTELL. PROP. MEDIA & ENT. L.J. 373, 389 (2010). For a more general
application of this idea to property law, see Margaret Jane Radin, Property and Personhood, 34 STAN. L.
REV. 957 (1982).
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
541
personality theory,
54
to a very large extent, forms the foundation for the protection of
certain inalienable moral rights owned only by the creator of a work in author’s rights-
centric jurisdictions, such as France and Germany. These rights, such as the rights of
attribution, integrity, disclosure, and withdrawal, protect the creator’s individuality or
personality which, subsumed by the work, should not be separated from the author as a
person and sold to another. In these jurisdictions, economic rights are completely
alienable from the creator of the work while moral or “personality-based” rights
55
(rights
that protect the personality and integrity of the author) remain attached to the creator and
can never be sold.
56
Apart from certain provisions in the Visual Artists Rights Act
57
and
specific state legislation,
58
moral rights are not generally recognized in the United
States.
59
Of course, Hegel, who wrote at the tail end of the German idealist period, was
also influenced by the work of Immanuel Kant
60
and Kant’s theory of property as an
acquired right to something held in common, over which one asserts a free will to
possess.
61
Intellectual property scholars have also relied on Kant to find support for an
author’s property right in the work.
62
¶14 Whether one relies on the works of Locke, Kant, or Hegel, one will arrive at the
same conclusion that there are natural rights that belong to the author and exist even if
they are not explicitly recognized by a legal system and made into a legal right. One may
agree that there is a natural right to life and that it is morally and ethically wrong to take
the life of another, even without laws making it a crime to commit murder.
63
Likewise,
in the same way that one may agree that, even in the absence of First Amendment
guarantees, it is morally and ethically wrong to impose undue restraints on another
person’s ability to speak freely because one recognizes an individual’s inherent right to
free speech, one may also agree that an individual in society has the right to own that
54
GEORG WILHELM FRIEDRICH HEGEL, HEGELS PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHT 45 (T.M. Knox trans., Oxford
University Press 1952) (1821) (“The principle that a thing belongs to the person who happens to be the first
in time to take it into his possession is immediately self-explanatory and superfluous, because a second
person cannot take into his possession what is already the property of another. Since property is the
embodiment of personality, my inward idea and will that something is to be mine is not enough to make it
my property; to secure this end occupancy is requisite.”) (endnote omitted).
55
Troutt, supra note 53, at 347.
56
For a comparison between both moral-rights based jurisdictions such as Germany and France and
economic-rights based jurisdictions such as the United States, see Neil Netanel, Copyright Alienability
Restrictions and the Enhancement of Author Autonomy: A Normative Evaluation, 24 RUTGERS L.J. 347
(1993).
57
See 17 U.S.C. § 106A (2006).
58
California Art Preservation Act of 1980, CAL. CIV. CODE § 987; New York Artists’ Authorship Act of
1984, N.Y. ARTS & CULT. AFF. LAW § 14.03.
59
Robert C. Bird, Moral Rights: Diagnosis and Rehabilitation, 46 AM. BUS. L.J. 407 (2009).
60
BERTRAND RUSSELL, A HISTORY OF WESTERN PHILOSOPHY 730 (2007).
61
IMMANUEL KANT, THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS 49 (Mary Gregor ed. & trans., Cambridge
University Press 1996) (1797) (“[A] right to a thing is a right to the private use of a thing of which I am in
(original or instituted) possession in common with all others.”) (footnote omitted).
62
ROBERT P. MERGES, JUSTIFYING INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY 7881 (2011); Thomas F. Cotter,
Pragmatism, Economics, and the Droit Moral, 76 N.C. L. REV. 1, 8 (1997); Kim Treiger-Bar-Am, Kant on
Copyright: Rights of Transformative Authorship, 25 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 1059, 1062 (2008).
63
However, criminal laws often reflect the standards of morality. Heidi M. Hurd, What in the World Is
Wrong?, 5 J. CONTEMP. LEGAL ISSUES 157, 208 (1994) (“[T]he doctrines that comprise the ‘special part’ of
the criminal law appear to track quite closely morality’s absolute prohibitions: we are, for example,
enjoined by both the criminal law and morality not to kill, rape, maim, torture, abuse, or frighten other
persons.”).
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
542
which he producedwhether produced through manual or intellectual labor.
64
In some
sense, a thing produced from intellectual labor may be more “connected” to the
personality or individuality of its creator than something created through manual labor.
The resulting product would be more deserving of a natural property right, allowing its
owner to control how society uses the product. Such a right should exist even if there are
no laws specifically protecting or recognizing that right.
¶15 There is a difference between a natural right and a legal right; one must take care
to distinguish between these two. A right created by law (a legal right) is a different type
of right than a basic, fundamental, or intrinsic right (a natural right). Sometimes legal
rights affirm natural rights, but not always. Laws prohibiting the willful taking of
another’s life, for example, affirm the individual’s natural human right to life. On the
other hand, laws facilitating genocidewhile still laws
65
do not. Whether the laws are
proper in the first place is beyond the scope of this Article.
66
For this Article’s purposes,
it suffices to note that the laws of a legal system can support, deny, or simply ignore
man’s natural expectation of a fundamental way of living, regardless of whether one
accepts the basic premise that an individual possesses certain natural and imprescriptible
rights. The copyright systema legal institution charged with the sole purpose of
promoting progress in society
67
—is no exception. Just because an author’s natural
expectation of literary property is not explicitly acknowledged by the copyright system
does not mean that it does not exist.
¶16 In English and American copyright systems, this expectation of a natural literary
property right appears to have been quashed by judicial application of early copyright
statutes. The earliest statutory codifications of copyright as an exclusive right to print,
publish, and distribute literary works in the United Kingdom and in the United States
occurred in the 1700s with the Statute of Anne and the 1790 Copyright Act, respectively.
Following the enactment of both statutes, the highest courts in each legal system declared
64
Eric R. Claeys, Jefferson Meets Coase: Land-Use Torts, Law and Economics, and Natural Property
Rights, 85 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 1379, 1402 (2010).
65
For accounts of the Nuremberg Laws, see, for example, MARION A. KAPLAN, BETWEEN DIGNITY AND
DESPAIR: JEWISH LIFE IN NAZI GERMANY (1998); LENI YAHIL, THE HOLOCAUST: THE FATE OF EUROPEAN
JEWRY, 19321945, at 6773 (Ina Friedman & Haya Galai trans., 1990).
66
This question about the moral content of laws strikes at the heart of legal theory and the study of what
law really is. Legal positivism postulates that laws do not necessarily have to abide by particular moral
standards for them to be considered proper and valid “laws.” The idea that men possess certain natural and
imprescriptible rights is nothing more than “rhetorical nonsense” and “nonsense upon stilts” to a legal
positivist. See JEREMY BENTHAM, Nonsense Upon Stilts, or Pandora’s Box Opened, or the French
Declaration of Rights Prefixed to the Constitution of 1791 Laid Open and ExposedWith a Comparative
Sketch of What Has Been Done on the Same Subject in the Constitution of 1795, and a Sample of Citizen
Sieyès, in THE COLLECTED WORKS OF JEREMY BENTHAM, RIGHTS, REPRESENTATION, AND REFORM:
NONSENSE UPON STILTS AND OTHER WRITINGS ON THE FRENCH REVOLUTION 317, 330 (Philip Schofield et
al. eds., 2002). Natural lawyers, on the other hand, see laws as necessarily embodying a specific moral
content. Laws that ignore or reject moral precepts of justice, fairness, or righteousness should not be
considered laws in the true senseeven if passed by the legislature or declared by the courts of a legitimate
legal system. The maxim lex injusta non est lex (“an unjust law is not a law”) defines a natural lawyer’s
position on this issue. See JOHN FINNIS, NATURAL LAW AND NATURAL RIGHTS 364 (2d ed. 2011). A
contemporary debate on this point is seen in Lon L. Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to LawA Reply to
Professor Hart, 71 HARV. L. REV. 630 (1958); H.L.A. Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and
Morals, 71 HARV. L. REV. 593 (1958).
67
Feist Publications, Inc. v. Rural Telephone Company, Inc., 499 U.S. 340, 349 (1991) (“The primary
objective of copyright is not to reward the labor of authors, but ‘[t]o promote the Progress of Science and
useful Arts’”).
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
543
that these statutes were the only sources of rights to literary works and explicitly denied
the existence of the author’s natural literary property right.
68
Following the House of
Lords’s decision, the United States Supreme Court announced in 1834 that Congress
creates all rights to literary works in the United Statesnone exist at common law, save
for a very specific and limited right to first publication for works that were not yet
published.
69
While these cases have been cited as settling the question of literary
property,
70
the specific factual scenarios from which these cases emerged raise
uncertainty as to the exact judicial determination about the nature of an author’s rights in
creative works. Donaldson v. Beckett involved a dispute between two booksellers over
the exclusive right to reprint James Thomson’s classic, The Seasonsa dispute that did
not involve the author.
71
The respondent, Thomas Beckett, on behalf of various London
booksellers and printers, claimed the exclusive right to print and make copies of the book
was a perpetual entitlement, which the publisher procured through the author’s
assignment of copyright.
72
The common law right at issue in this case was the specific
right to print and publish the work, which Thomson assigned to his publisher. The notion
of literary property, when used by booksellers and printers in this case, referred to the
rights to print, publish, and sellthe same specific rights protected under the Statute of
Anne. The question of literary property in Donaldson v. Beckett did not seek to
determine the character of an author’s natural expectation to have control over his
identity as expressed in the work. The questions posed were simply not structured to
answer what rights an author has over that which he creates. For example, the first legal
question asked “[w]hether, at common law, an author of any book or literary composition
had the sole right of first printing and publishing the same for sale, and might bring an
action against any person who printed, published, and sold the same without his
consent.”
73
Subsequent questions posed to the House were also not structured to answer
the question about the author’s rights.
74
Instead, the notion of authors’ natural rights was
68
See Wheaton v. Peters, 33 U.S. (8 Pet.) 591 (1834); Donaldson v. Beckett, (1774) 1 Eng. Rep. 837
(H.L.) (Gr. Brit.); see also U.S. Copyright Act 1790, 1 Stat. 124 (1790); Statute of Anne, 1710, 8 Anne,
c.19.
69
Wheaton, 33 U.S. (8 Pet.) at 661.
70
See, e.g., Oren Bracha, The Statue of Anne: An American Mythology, 47 HOUS. L. REV. 877, 889, 900
(2010) (“[T]he debate [on literary property] was formally concluded with the decision of the House of
Lords in Donaldson v. Becket . . . . While Wheaton v. Peters had some aspects that were peculiar to the
United States, the main question of copyright as a common law property right was identical to that litigated
in the British literary property debate, and most of the opposing sides’ arguments on this issue were
duplication of that debate. When a majority of the Supreme Court ruled against common law copyright,
hope of achieving recognition of absolute property rights through this channel dwindled.”) (footnotes
omitted); Michael J. Madison, Beyond Invention: Patent as Knowledge Law, 15 LEWIS & CLARK L. REV.
71, 86–87 (2011) (“Wheaton v. Peters was the first major opinion of the Court to deal with copyright, and
as copyright scholars know well, the Court concluded that the federal copyright statute, with its limited
term and scope of rights, extinguished the concept of literary property with respect to works that fell within
its scope. This brought American law into line with its English cousin [Donaldson v. Beckett].”); Marybeth
Peters, Constitutional Challenges to Copyright Law, 30 COLUM. J.L. & ARTS 509, 512 (2007) (stating that
“[t]he controversy over what was meant by ‘secure’ in the Copyright Clause was settled in Wheaton, and I
don’t believe anybody proposes to fight that battle again” on the Court’s decision that Congress was
legislating a new right instead of acknowledging an existing right in common law with the passing of the
1790 Copyright Act).
71
Donaldson, 1 Eng. Rep. 837, 838.
72
Id.
73
Id. at 846 (emphasis added).
74
For the five questions that the House of Lords was asked to answer, see id. at 84647.
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
544
introduced in the case to support the economic rights to print and publish creative
works.
75
The House rejected this notion in order to prevent booksellers’ monopolistic
control of the publishing industry.
76
The House never drew a distinction between
authors’ natural rights and publishers’ economic interests (that is, between literary
property and statutory privileges)
77
and the case should not be read as suggesting that the
only rights authors have in a work are explicitly provided by statute.
78
Similarly,
Wheaton v. Peters addressed specific facts that left the question of literary property
largely unanswered. The disputants in this case were Supreme Court reporters who asked
the Court to determine whether common law property rights protected the publication and
sale of previously reported decisions.
79
The Supreme Court decided this case in its
formative years, when Justices sought the widest dissemination of the law.
80
Deciding in
favor of a common law property right for a court reporter would have restricted free
speech and press in a newly formed country dedicated to the promotion of ideas and
debate for progress.
81
At that specific point in American history, the Court had no choice
but to decide that a perpetual property right in court reports would expire as soon as they
were published and that statutory copyright would protect the exclusive right to publish
and vend such reports after publication. Given the dispute over the exclusive rights of
publication and sale, the fact pattern in Wheaton v. Peters, as in Donaldson v. Beckett, did
75
The questions were structured to deal with the specific claim that booksellers had an exclusive right to
print and publish books purchased from individual authors in perpetuity. Edward Thurlow, the Attorney
General, in his opening remarks for Donaldson observed:
The booksellers . . . had not, till lately, ever concerned themselves about authors, but had
generally confined the substance of their prayers to the legislature, to the security of their
own property; nor would they probably have, of late years, introduced the authors as
parties in their claims to the common law right of exclusively multiplying copies, had not
they found it necessary to give a colourable face to their monopoly.
17 PARL. HIST. ENG., H.L. (1774) 953, 954 (Gr. Brit.).
76
Professor Patterson states this “was the only decision which would destroy the monopoly of the
booksellers, and there is little question that the decision was directly aimed at that monopoly.” PATTERSON,
supra note 1, at 177–78. Patterson then cites Lord Camden’s statement that “[a]ll our learning will be
looked [sic] up in the hands of the Tonsons and [sic] Lintons of the age, who will set what price upon it
their avarice chuses to demand, till the public become as much their slaves, as their own hackney compilers
are.” Id. at 178 (quoting 17 PARL. HIST. ENG. at 1000).
77
Patterson, supra note 50, at 18 (“[I]t is important to remember what copyright entailed and did not
entail at that time. At the time copyright owners had the exclusive right to publish works as those works
were written, but only for a limited period of timefourteen years with a possible renewal term of an
additional fourteen years. Copyright owners did not have the exclusive right to prepare derivative works,
such as abridgements, translations, or digests. The distinction between the use of the copyright and the use
of the work, therefore, was fundamental.”).
78
PATTERSON, supra note 1, at 174 (“The actual holding of the Donaldson case is that the author’s
common-law right to the sole printing, publishing, and vending of his works, a right which he could assign
in perpetuity, is taken away and supplanted by the Statute of Anne. The case did not hold that the author’s
rights at common law consisted only of the right of printing, publishing, and vending his works . . . .”).
79
Wheaton v. Peters, 33 U.S. (8 Pet.) 591, 59394 (1834).
80
See Craig Joyce, “A Curious Chapter in the History of Judicature”: Wheaton v. Peters and the Rest of
the Story (of Copyright in the New Republic), 42 HOUS. L. REV. 325 (2005).
81
Id. at 384–85 (“In a case that saddened and pained the Justices themselves even as they rendered a
decision indispensable to the progress of a national jurisprudence, the Court assured that henceforth
American law should be owned by no oneand thus owned by all, for the benefit of all. In retrospect, in a
nation dedicated to free speech, free press, and the widest possible dissemination and debate of facts and
ideas, the outcome could not have been otherwise.”).
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
545
not give the Court the opportunity to consider the broader natural rights of an author
beyond his statutory rights to publish and sell his work.
82
¶17 Whether one chooses to believe that judges create binding law or merely declare
existing law as cases come before them,
83
one jurisprudential point remains to be made
for the purposes of this Article. The author’s literary property right in the work does not
cease to exist simply because copyright statute or judicial decisions do not explicitly
acknowledge that right exists by lawa natural right exists even without legal
affirmation. An author’s literary right at common law would be evidenced through
customary practices, as with the publication contracts discussed, and through natural
expectations that evolve from the interactions of authors with their publishers and the
public. The author’s expectation of a literary property right cannot be nullified by a more
limited recognition of a specific right to publish and sell the work. Statutes, which are
enacted for specific policy purposes, and case law, which is peculiar to distinctive factual
patterns, cannot possibly represent the full spectrum of rights that may arise from an
individual’s creation of a literary or artistic work. The enactment of a law by Congress
that denies the humanity of men may be law, but that would not change the natural fact
that men are human beings by nature. In the same way, a literary property right, if it
exists as a natural right, does not have to be expressly validated by positive copyright law
for it to be a legitimate expectation or interest. The express recognition of particular
statutory privileges to publish and sell a work exclusively should not be taken to suggest
that these privileges constitute all of the rights that authors have in their work. Nor
should it be assumed that literary property and statutory copyright are mutually exclusive
principles protecting separate interests of an author at different times along a seamless
continuum of events that begins at the initial conception of a creative idea and that ends
with the dissemination of the expression to the public. It is important to see how the
distinction between an author’s natural interest in how the work is used and economic
82
See PATTERSON & LINDBERG, supra note 4, at 64 (“[Wheaton’s] holding was a simplistic solution to a
complex problem: How to protect the author’s interest in his or her work without at the same time
providing the bookseller an unregulated monopoly. This monopoly, of course, is based on the fallacy that
ownership of the work is ownership of the copyright and vice versa . . . .”).
83
Whether judges create or merely declare the law is a contentious issue in jurisprudence. John
Chipman Gray, for example, is well known for his belief that judges create, rather than discover, the law.
See JOHN CHIPMAN GRAY, THE NATURE AND SOURCES OF THE LAW 96 (1909) (“[T]he absurdity of the
view of Law preëxistent to its declaration is obvious.”); see also THE OXFORD COMPANION TO THE
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES 321 (Kermit L. Hall et al. eds., 2d ed. 2005) (“Sometimes judges
make federal common law to govern specific issues, as when they fill a gap in a federal statutory
scheme.”). Other scholars are inclined to believe that judges merely declare existing laws or norms that are
discoverable or act in the capacity of a rule-making agency of the state. See HANS KELSEN, GENERAL
THEORY OF LAW AND STATE 150 (Anders Wedberg trans., Lawbook Exchange 2009) (1945) (arguing that
courts always apply pre-existing law, stating that the view “that there is no law existing before the judicial
decision and that all law is created by the courts” is false); see also H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW
132 (1961) (“In a system where stare decisis [the doctrine of precedent] is firmly acknowledged, this
function of the courts is very like the exercise of delegated rule-making powers by an administrative
body.”). For a natural-rights oriented perspective on this issue, see RONALD DWORKIN, TAKING RIGHTS
SERIOUSLY 87 (1977) (“[J]udicial decisions enforce existing political rights,” which “depe nd[] upon both
the practice and justice of [a civil society’s] political institutions.”). This issue on the role of courts,
however, bears very little impact on the discussion in this Article, which aims to demonstrate the existence
of a broader literary right besides the rights recognized by copyright statutes and case law. Whether statute
and precedent are morally right or not, and whether they accurately represent law and norms, is beyond the
scope of this Article. It suffices to assume that a literary property right is a natural right that may or may
not be affirmed by the legislature or judiciary.
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
546
interests, naturally arising from the work’s publication and public dissemination, is
blurred when courts state that literary property only protects a right to first publication
before a work is published and that statutory copyright protects the author’s exclusive
rights to print and sell the work post-publication.
84
Literary property would be an interest
that authors continue to have even after a publisher commits to publishing and
disseminating their work. Accepting that there could possibly be a natural right that
protects an author’s literary property will result in significant changes to copyright
jurisprudence because this will, as Professor Lyman Ray Patterson believes, clarify the
inconsistency in ideas and values, which plague copyright law.
85
C. Protecting Authors’ Identity and Creative Rights
¶18 The acceptance of the author’s natural literary property right raises a new set of
normative questions that must be answered: (1) what would literary property rights
protect?; (2) would such rights be alienable in the same way as statutory copyright?; and
(3) how would natural rights, if not explicitly recognized by the copyright system, be
statutorily protected? These questions should be answered carefully if the protection of
an author’s literary property at common law is to reconcile some of the inconsistencies
among institutional values (such as whether copyright should protect the author or
promote learning) that Professor Patterson identified in the copyright system.
86
Furthermore, the disparity in expressive power among authors, publishers, and consumers
of creative works, which could fundamentally affect society’s ability to learn, conduct
research, and communicate, potentially hampering the progress of science and useful arts
in the long run,
87
may be narrowed by solutions to these normative questions. Also,
copyright pessimists in England and the United States, who see authors’ rights as an
extension of the copyright monopoly in a creative work, might resist the proposition to
create a literary property right for authors.
88
Commentators, such as then-Professor (now
84
See, e.g., Caliga v. Inter Ocean Newspaper Co., 215 U.S. 182, 188 (1909) (“At common-law the
exclusive right to copy existed in the author until he permitted a general publication. Thus, when a book
was published in print, the owner’s common-law right was lost. At common-law an author had a property
in his manuscript, and might have an action against any one who undertook to publish it without authority.
The statute created a new property right, giving to the author, after publication, the exclusive right to
multiply copies for a limited period.”); Tribune Co. of Chi. v. Associated Press, 116 F. 126, 127 (C.C.N.D.
Ill. 1900) (“Literary property is protected at common law to the extent only of possession and use of the
manuscript and its first publication by the owner . . . . With voluntary publication the exclusive right is
determined at common law, and the statutory copyright is the sole dependence of the author or owner for a
monopoly in the future publication.”).
85
PATTERSON, supra note 1, at 220 (“There is little doubt that a recognition of authors’ creative rights
could reshape American copyright law, not by changing fundamental ideas, but by bringing those ideas into
proper recognition and perspective, and doing so consistently with the copyright statute.”).
86
Id. at 181 (the four basic ideas that Patterson identified as underlying early American copyright law
are: (1) to protect the author’s rights; (2) to promote learning; (3) to provide order in the book trade as a
government grant; and (4) to prevent harmful monopolies).
87
See, e.g., John M. Kernochan, Practical Limitations on Authors’ Rights, 24 COLUM.-VLA J.L. & ARTS
263, 26768 (2001); Jessica Litman, Real Copyright Reform, 96 IOWA L. REV. 1 (2010); Neil Weinstock
Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283 (1996); Pamela Samuelson,
Copyright and Freedom of Expression in Historical Perspective, 10 J. INTELL. PROP. L. 319 (2003).
88
Borrowing a term coined by Paul Goldstein to describe a position taken regarding the fundamental
purpose of copyright laws. See PAUL GOLDSTEIN, COPYRIGHTS HIGHWAY: FROM GUTENBERG TO THE
CELESTIAL JUKEBOX 11 (rev. ed. 2003) (“[C]opyright pessimists . . . see copyright’s cup as half empty:
they accept that copyright owners should get some measure of control over copies as an incentive to
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
547
Justice) Breyer, have expressed doubt regarding the necessity of copyright incentives to
encourage the production of artistic works.
89
These commentators may challenge the
claim that literary property rights must be recognized to protect the author’s natural
noneconomic interest in the work. Possible objections to the notion of authors’ literary
property rights as proposed here can be broadly characterized into three distinct camps:
(1) that literary property will support greater expansion of exclusive rights over creative
works; (2) that the protection of the author’s natural rights will affirm the unrealistic
notion of the romantic author; and (3) that the subject matter of literary property
(information) should be available for public use. However, this Article argues that these
objections are unsustainable if one gives careful thought to the scope of literary
property’s protection and what its recognition will accomplish in the copyright system.
1. Objections to Protecting Author’s Literary Property Rights
¶19 The first objection to a notion of literary property is based on the idea that some
may use the recognition of this right to justify the expansion of copyright. English
booksellers historically argued to expand economic rights to the exclusive use of the
work based on moral and ethical arguments in favor of authors’ rights. Similarly, the
normative argument for literary property was, and continues to be, utilized by
corporations and entities other than the author to justify the expansion and perpetuation
of an economic monopoly to profit from the publication and sale of the work to the
public.
90
More recently, some have used such normative arguments to endorse
Congress’s extension of the copyright term for an additional twenty years
91
to benefit not
just individual authors, but media publishers and corporate copyright owners as well.
The objection to the notion of literary property on this basis may be allayed by clarifying
that the rights of the individual author, rooted in natural law, are fundamentally distinct
from the statutory grant that legislatures provide to facilitate the dissemination of creative
works to the public by protecting economic investments.
92
There should be no
produce creative works, but they would like copyright to extend only as far as is necessary to give this
incentive, and treat anything more as an encroachment on the general freedom of everyone to write and say
what they please.”).
89
Stephen Breyer, The Uneasy Case for Copyright: A Study of Copyright in Books, Photocopies, and
Computer Programs, 84 HARV. L. REV. 281, 282 (1970) (“It would be possible, for instance, to do without
copyright, relying upon authors, publishers, and buyers to work out arrangements among themselves that
would provide books’ creators with enough money to produce them. Authors in ancient times, as well as
monks and scholars in the middle ages, wrote and were paid for their writings without copyright
protection.”).
90
John Tehranian, Parchment, Pixels, & Personhood: User Rights and the IP (Identity Politics) of IP
(Intellectual Property), 82 U. COLO. L. REV. 1, 15 (2011); Diane Leenheer Zimmerman, Information as
Speech, Information as Goods: Some Thoughts on Marketplaces and the Bill of Rights, 33 WM. & MARY L.
REV. 665, 705 (1992); see also Patterson, supra note 50, at 52 (“[T]he notion of copyright as property
serves as the basis for the continued expansion of copyright to the benefit of the entrepreneur.”).
91
See Deven R. Desai, The Life and Death of Copyright, 2011 WIS. L. REV. 219, 224 (discussing
arguments put forth to support the Copyright Term Extension Act); Jane C. Ginsburg et al., The
Constitutionality of Copyright Term Extension: How Long Is Too Long?, 18 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J.
651, 694 (2000) (“If you provide the proper incentives today, it will not enhance my productivity in the
past, but it may promote my productivity in the future. In other words, I may stay and continue to write or
do my scholarly thing today because, yesterday, Congress enacted a statute that enhances my reward.”).
92
WILLIAM M. LANDES & RICHARD A. POSNER, THE ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF INTELLECTUAL
PROPERTY LAW 3741 (2003).
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
548
intellectual or logical bridge between an author’s natural right to the protection of his
individuality in a society and the economic rights that the state grants to encourage
creative production. Once it becomes clear that the author’s natural rights and copyright
have distinctly separate legal definitions, it is likely that the fear of perpetual extension of
copyright (as the exclusive rights to print and disseminate creative works instead of the
right to control use of content) will subside due to the awareness of copyright’s inability
to control public uses of a work’s content. Such control over the use of a work’s content
would only belong to the author.
¶20 The second potential objection to protecting the author’s literary property stems
from commentators, who have rejected the commonly accepted version of the solitary
author from the Romantic period as an unrealistic representation of how authors and
creator produce creative works in reality. These conceptions envisioned the author
producing works from thin air or through divine inspiration and epitomizes the greatness
and splendor of pure human creativity. Northrop Frye described this individual creator as
being “interested in himself, not necessarily out of egotism, but because the basis of his
poetic skill is individual, and hence genetic and psychological,”
93
which provides an
excellent premise for the recognition of literary property. Sheer creative genius, as the
thinking goes, should be rewarded and encouraged through the Copyright Act’s grant of
exclusive rights. The grant is temporary so that once these rights expire, the products of
such creative genius becomes accessible to the general public.
94
¶21 The problem with this line of thinking is that its faith in the genius creator, who
produces a unique and highly original work and is thus entitled to certain rights, runs
contrary to expressed skepticism about the author being personally and solely responsible
for his creative expression. Michel Foucault, for example, famously described the
individual author as a culturally concocted “fiction” to provide discourses with particular
social statuses or modes of existing in society. The author is not someone who creates
from an inspired source of intelligence and freely shares his creation with the world, but
rather one who appropriates and controls the proliferation of discourses in society
through the claim of authorship.
95
Similarly, Roland Barthes, who famously proclaimed
the death of the author, suggests that a reader should interpret a text independently of the
author’s background and experience. To Barthes, placing emphasis on the author to
93
NORTHROP FRYE, ANATOMY OF CRITICISM: FOUR ESSAYS 60 (1957).
94
Sony Corp. of Am. v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, 429 (1984) (stating that temporary
rights of copyright law are “intended to motivate the creative activity of authors and inventors by the
provision of a special reward, and to allow the public access to the products of their genius after the limited
period of exclusive control has expired”); United States v. Paramount Pictures, Inc., 334 U.S. 131, 158
(1948) (“[R]eward to the author or artist serves to induce release to the public of the products of his
creative genius.”); Fox Film Corp. v. Doyal, 286 U.S. 123, 127–28 (1932) (“A copyright . . . is ‘at once the
equivalent given by the public for benefits bestowed by the genius and meditations and skill of individuals
and the incentive to further efforts for the same important objects.’”) (quoting Kendall v. Winsor, 62 U.S.
(21 How.) 322, 328 (1858)).
95
Michel Foucault, What Is an Author?, in TEXTUAL STRATEGIES: PERSPECTIVES IN POST-
STRUCTURALIST CRITICISM 141, 159 (Josué V. Harari ed., 1979) (“We are used to thinking that the author
is so different from all other men, and so transcendent with regard to all languages that, as soon as he
speaks, meaning begins to proliferate, to proliferate indefinitely. The truth is quite the contrary: the author
is not an indefinite source of significations which fill a work; the author does not precede the works, he is a
certain functional principle by which, in our culture, one limits, excludes, and chooses; in short, by which
one impedes the free circulation, the free manipulation, the free composition, decomposition, and
recomposition of fiction.”).
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
549
understand a text is misplaced; instead, Barthes felt that textual interpretation should
focus on the readers as the recipients and interpreters of the work.
96
Legal scholars have
proposed theories similar to those of Foucault and Barthes, contending that the author is a
socially constructed metaphor to serve a particular cultural purpose, which is to support
the commodification of literature in the eighteenth century
97
and establish the author’s
proprietary ownership over original expressions.
98
In turn, the fulfillment of these
cultural goals, supports the expansion of copyright to include most intellectual creation,
and the enforcement of proprietary rights prevents social uses of the work for education,
development, and progression in society.
99
Yet, contrary to the fear that property rights
will stifle innovation, this Article argues that literary property rights will promote societal
progress through the encouragement of authentic expressions that will have a more
positive and constructive impact on how society develops.
¶22 Creative works that do not necessarily promote progress and diversity in expression
might have a detrimental effect on society. In reality, authors promote progress in society
by expressing themselves in an authentic manner. Why would critics use the fact that all
creators borrow from their predecessors and surroundings in the act of creation to debunk
the myth of the Romantic author and then decry the expansion of copyright? The notion
of the Romantic author might, as suggested by Professor Lionel Bently, introduce
reasonable limitations to copyright expansion.
100
The notion that authorship emanates
96
ROLAND BARTHES, The Death of the Author, in IMAGE, MUSIC, TEXT 142, 148 (Stephen Heath trans.,
1977) (“[A] text is made of multiple writings, drawn from many cultures and entering into mutual relations
of dialogue, parody, contestation, but there is one place where this multiplicity is focused and that place is
the reader, not, as was hitherto said, the author. The reader is the space on which all the quotations that
make up a writing are inscribed without any of them being lost; a text’s unity lies not in its origin but in its
destination.”).
97
WOODMANSEE, supra note 10, at 37. Professor Woodmansee explains that eighteenth-century
theorists stopped thinking of the author as a craftsman inspired by God in order to establish a commercial
market in literary works:
They minimized the element of craftsmanship (in some instances they simply discarded
it) in favor of the element of inspiration, and they internalized the source of that
inspiration. That is, the inspiration for a work came to be regarded as emanating not from
outside or above, but from within the writer himself. ‘Inspiration’ came to be explicated
in terms of original genius, with the consequences that the inspired work was made
peculiarly and distinctively the productand the propertyof the writer.
Id.
98
JAMES BOYLE, SHAMANS, SOFTWARE, AND SPLEENS: LAW AND THE CONSTRUCTION OF THE
INFORMATION SOCIETY 54 (1996) (“Originality became the watchword of artistry and the warrant for
property rights.”); Peter Jaszi, Toward a Theory of Copyright: The Metamorphoses of “Authorship, 1991
DUKE L.J. 455, 472 (“The ‘authorship’ concept, with its roots in notions of individual self-proprietorship,
provided the rationale for thinking of literary productions as personal property with various associated
attributes including alienability.”).
99
Carys J. Craig, Reconstructing the Author-self: Some Feminist Lessons for Copyright Law, 15 AM. U.
J. GENDER SOC. POLY & L. 207, 228, 230 (2007) (“The authorship myth that animates copyright discourse
supports calls for wide protection and generates complacency around the expanding domain of intellectual
property and the corporate ownership that dominates the intellectual realm. . . . The problem highlighted
here is the power of the individual authorship trope to occlude discussion of the social, educational, or
cultural value of downstream or derivative uses of protected works. Because copyright’s concept of the
work resides in independent, original production, the work of a second-generation producer cannot compete
equally as a ‘work’ of social value that merits protection; the social importance or the cultural value of the
second text barely comes within the cognizance of the law.”) (footnotes omitted).
100
See Lionel Bently, R. v The Author: From Death Penalty to Community Service, 32 COLUM. J.L. &
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
550
from a human author and not a corporate persona would set limits to the type of work that
may be protected, the level or threshold of protection, the breadth of rights granted, the
length of protection, and the distribution and enforcement of rights.
101
The notion of
authorship will also provide new direction for copyright reform.
102
Moreover, the
connection of an author with his work through the notion of literary property would make
the author directly responsible for his creation and its impact on society. Deconstructing
the notion of romantic authorship to point out flaws in the legal system and suggest that
most authors create by reusing works that have already been created ignores the
importance of original and authentic expressions and produces a social expectation that
creative works should be alike. When authors are not expected to be original, they would
more likely than not produce the same types of works that have little influence on society
and the progress of science and useful arts. Making authors identify with their creations
through a Romantic vision of authorship and the notion of literary property will likely
result in the production of authentic expressions that will positively impact society’s
progression.
103
¶23 The third possible objection to the notion of literary property is that information
the subject matter of its protectionshould be a resource that is held commonly by
society and not subjected to private property. From an economic viewpoint, property
rights counter the overuse that usually follows when a limited resource is commonly held.
The “tragedy of the commons,”
104
where everyone consumes a resource without caring
for it or investing in it until it is depleted completely, may best be avoided by the
allocation of private property rights, which defines ownership and draws boundaries
around the resource to limit its overuse through a clear right to exclude. However, some
scholars point out that there are merits to having particular resources held in common
105
and identify the under-exploitation of a resource as a serious problem when too many
ARTS 1 (2008).
101
See id. at 92103.
102
Id. at 103.
103
See, e.g., Netanel, supra note 56, at 429. Professor Netanel suggests that an author not only has
rights but responsibilities towards society:
Truly, the author has a duty to the community, as well as to herself, to use language in a
manner that reflects her own ideas and sensitivities. This requires that the author speak
with personal integrity, and with a measure of respect and awe for the significance and
power of her enterprise. She must recognize that each exercise of her artistic discretion
embodies a moral decision that obliges her to produce her best work in her own unique
way. At a minimum, the author is obliged to take responsibility for her work. She should
not abdicate to another the right to determine whether and in what form her work is
communicated to the public. She has a certain duty to maintain her autonomy and
authenticity of expression in the face of opposing political, social or market pressures.
Id. (footnote omitted).
104
The classic explanation of the tragedy of the commons is the overexploitation and consumption of a
common resource that ultimately leads to its depletion. See Garrett Hardin, The Tragedy of the Commons,
162 SCIENCE 1243 (1968).
105
Carol Rose, The Comedy of the Commons: Custom, Commerce, and Inherently Public Property, 53
U. CHI. L. REV. 711, 723 (1986) (property rights sometimes vests with the general public instead of a
private individual where it facilitates socialization among members of a society; here there is no tragedy of
the commons as there is benefit to having resources publicly owned as society as a whole benefits from the
sharing of that particular resource).
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
551
property rights protect a given resource.
106
In certain cases, a resource that serves a
particular social function may be considered inherently public property. Speech is a
prime candidate for protection as public property, given its role in helping communities
and society govern themselves.
107
Against this background, intellectual property scholars
have emphasized the need for an “intellectual commons” that is free from the restraints of
private property ownership to allow society to use information and creative resources
freely.
108
¶24 The argument for recognizing literary property as a natural right protected by law
might also generate disapproval from critics of copyright expansionism. These critics
argue that the increase of property rights in resources that should be public property
would limit the public domain, which contains information, ideas, and knowledge not
subject to intellectual property protection that are freely available for creative reuse.
109
The importance of freedom of information in intellectual creation has inspired a few
intellectual property scholars to work on constructing a “cultural commons” to manage
informational resources and support the pooling and sharing of these resources.
110
Protecting the author’s literary property could be seen as potentially supporting the
expansion of proprietary rights in informational resources that should rightfully be
available to society as part of the cultural commons.
¶25 Despite critic’s fear of expansionism, literary property would not limit the use of
creative expression, as feared by critics of copyright expansionism. First, the expansion
of copyright is unlikely to affect the use of creative works if rights are exercised in a
reasonable and moderate fashion. An author, for example, should enforce literary
property rights only if a use of his work undermines his integrity or personalitywho he
106
Id. at 74950 (identifying holdouts and monopolies as primary problems with privatization). For the
leading legal work on the anticommons, see Michael A. Heller, The Tragedy of the Anticommons: Property
in the Transition from Marx to Markets, 111 HARV. L. REV. 621, 624 (1998) (“When there are too many
owners holding rights of exclusion, the resource is prone to underusea tragedy of the anticommons.
Legal and economic scholars have mostly overlooked this tragedy, but it can appear whenever governments
create new property rights.”) (footnote omitted).
107
Rose, supra note 105, at 778.
108
Dan Hunter, Cyberspace as Place and the Tragedy of the Digital Anticommons, 91 CAL. L. REV. 439,
50001 (2003) (applying anticommons analysis to use of Internet space); see also Niva Elkin-Koren,
Copyrights in CyberspaceRights Without Laws?, 73 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1155, 119394 (1998) (applying
anticommons analysis to intellectual property); Michael A. Heller & Rebecca S. Eisenberg, Can Patents
Deter Innovation? The Anticommons in Biomedical Research, 280 SCIENCE 698 (1998) (discussing how
privatization of biomedical research and patenting of research results could lead to overlapping patent
claims that restrict access to biomedical information).
109
Scholars have called for the resistance against the second enclosure movement into the public
domain. See, e.g., Yochai Benkler, Free as the Air to Common Use: First Amendment Constraints on
Enclosure of the Public Domain, 74 N.Y.U. L. REV. 354 (1999) (describing how information is becoming
subject to private control); James Boyle, The Second Enclosure Movement and the Construction of the
Public Domain, 66 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 33, 37 (2003) (“We are in the middle of a second enclosure
movement. It sounds grandiloquent to call it ‘the enclosure of the intangible commons of the mind,’ but in
a very real sense that is just what it is. True, the new state-created property rights may be ‘intellectual’
rather than ‘real,’ but once again things that were formerly thought of as either common property or
uncommodifiable are being covered with new, or newly extended, property rights.”) (footnote omitted);
Lawrence Lessig, The Architecture of Innovation, 51 DUKE L.J. 1783 (2002); see also LEWIS HYDE,
COMMON AS AIR: REVOLUTION, ART, AND OWNERSHIP (2010) (stating that history and convention demands
easy access to common knowledge and information).
110
Michael J. Madison, Brett M. Frischmann & Katherine J. Strandburg, Constructing Commons in the
Cultural Environment, 95 CORNELL L. REV. 657 (2010); see also Lawrence B. Solum, Questioning
Cultural Commons, 95 CORNELL L. REV. 817 (2010) (commenting on the idea of a “cultural commons”).
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
552
is as a creatorand contradicts his intention for producing and distributing the work to
society. Second, the placement of checks and balances, such as subjecting the exercise of
rights to a reasonable standard and insisting that rights cannot be used to harm legitimate
public interests in the use of the work, into the law as it expands may be sufficient to
address the problems associated with property expansion. Literary property should not
be considered a threat to the prerequisite freedom some scholars see as essential to
second-generation creativity. Literary property connects an author with his work on a
visceral level because it protects the author’s individuality and personality rather than a
share of the copyright market. A property right in the work that gives an author
autonomous control over his individual expression should encourage authors to create
their best work, in a responsible way for society’s benefit and to instill the desire in
creators of new works to use a predecessor’s work responsibly without infringing on
literary property rights. Similarly, adopting a literary property right would not enclose
the commons; rather it would encourage the production of works that are more authentic,
which will ultimately increase cultural and informational resources in the public domain.
2. The Subject-Matter of Literary Property
¶26 A literary property right as proposed in this Article would not protect an author’s
commercial interest, although it may well support its existence.
111
The right to
commercially exploit a work has been capably addressed by copyright legislation, in that
the creator of a work is the first owner of copyright. Conversely, literary property
protects the author’s identity and personality as expressed and contained in a published
work.
112
Thus, the subject matter of literary property would be the author’s creative
interest as held by the work. Hence, Milton’s contractual obligation to refrain from
interfering with the publication of his work was an agreement to not enforce a literary
property right. If the right protects the author’s personality and creative identity, rather
than the economic aspects of literary and artistic production, there will be very little room
for authors to abuse such a right and foreclose reasonable societal uses of the work. Yet,
at the same time, protecting the author’s integrity and autonomy frees the author from
worrying about abuse of the work and allows for greater authenticity in expression.
¶27 The motivation for human creativity should not be reduced to economic or
monetary values. As scholars have pointed out, authors, unlike publishers, may be driven
and inspired by non-monetary considerations.
113
There is a dire need to harness these
111
A more specific right to use property, such as a right to commercially exploit, should be based on a
broader entitlement in the property. PATTERSON, supra note 1, at 10 (“The stationer’s copyright can be
analogized to a perpetual lease of personal property, a manuscript or copy . . . for one specific purpose, that
of publishing. The right of publishing, however, did not vest the ownership of a work itself in the ordinary
sense, for this would have given the holder of the right of publishing other rights incident to ownership.”);
see also id. at 218 (“The creative interest is a natural right of the author . . . . While that natural right was
deemed to be the economic interest of the author, it was not so limited.”).
112
Jane C. Ginsburg, Creation and Commercial Value: Copyright Protection of Works of Information,
90 COLUM. L. REV. 1865, 1884 (1990).
113
ROBERTA ROSENTHAL KWALL, THE SOUL OF CREATIVITY: FORGING A MORAL RIGHTS LAW FOR THE
UNITED STATES (2010); Julie E. Cohen, Creativity and Culture in Copyright Theory, 40 U.C. DAVIS L.
REV. 1151 (2007) (describing creative inspiration as culturally inspired); Roberta Rosenthal Kwall,
Inspiration and Innovation: The Intrinsic Dimension of the Artistic Soul, 81 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 1945
(2006) (identifying spiritual and inspirational motivations for creativity); Lydia Pallas Loren, The Pope’s
Copyright? Aligning Incentives with Reality by Using Creative Motivation to Shape Copyright Protection,
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
553
noneconomic motivations for creativity and channel them into literary and artistic
production. Originality should not be attacked as being unrepresentative of the reality of
creative production. Second, third, and fourth generation creators, who build upon and
reuse the works of earlier authors, may still be original in their presentation and
interpretation of existing works.
114
This Article proposes that the law should not
underestimate the power of many individuals expressing themselves in authentic and
sincere ways to impact the progress of society in a profoundly positive manner;
protecting the author’s creative interest is the first step in that direction. The protection
of creative interests is particularly important, in part because the Internet and digital
technologies cause authors’ integrity and autonomy to become more vulnerable. The
victimization of one’s avatar in the virtual game Second Life,
115
the defacement of
artwork distributed online,
116
can damage an author’s reputation and leave society with
inauthentic works or misleading information.
117
Currently, an author has no real legal
recourse to prevent or correct such online violations against his creative identity.
118
69 LA. L. REV. 1 (2008) (recognizing that the creation of some works may be motivated by non-monetary
incentives and proposing that for such works, fair use be more readily available as a defense against
infringement); Diane Leenheer Zimmerman, Copyrights as Incentives: Did We Just Imagine That?, 12
THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 29 (2011) (questioning the actual link between commercial incentives and
creativity); see also YOCHAI BENKLER, THE WEALTH OF NETWORKS: HOW SOCIAL PRODUCTION
TRANSFORMS MARKETS AND FREEDOM (2006) (describing how digital networks encourage creativity that
produces non-proprietary work with no real monetary rewards).
114
One can be entirely original in how one reinterprets existing artwork and literature.
115
Farnaz Alemi, An Avatar’s Day in Court: A Proposal for Obtaining Relief and Resolving Disputes in
Virtual World Games, 11 UCLA J.L. & TECH., Fall 2007 (describing how an avatara representation of
who one is in an online communitycan be victimized by other players without any real legal
consequence).
116
The defacement of artwork may be an act of artistic rebellion against conventional cultural
representations. See Sonia K. Katyal, Semiotic Disobedience, 84 WASH. U. L. REV. 489, 493 (2006)
(Professor Katyal describes the vandalism and defacement of public messages as a trend towards “semiotic
disobedience,” where “today’s generation seeks to alter existing intellectual property by interrupting,
appropriating, and then replacing the passage of information from creator to consumer. . . . [T]hese recent
artistic practices . . . often involve the conscious and deliberate re-creation of property through
appropriative and expressive acts that consciously risk violating the law that governs intellectual or tangible
property.”); Michael L. Rustad, Private Enforcement of Cybercrime on the Electronic Frontier, 11 S. CAL.
INTERDISC. L.J. 63, 80 (2001) (describing defacement of company websites as “a form of political activism
against globalism and corporate control of the Internet” and hackers of Internet-posted materials as
“reject[ing] societal ideas of intellectual property”).
117
Deliberately altering information and data that an author has shared online will misinform the
author’s targeted audience, who will expect reliable information. See Blodwen Tarter, Information
Liability: New Interpretations for the Electronic Age, 11 COMPUTER/L.J. 481, 484 (1992) (“Information
consumers want reliable data on which to base decisions. . . . With the advent of broad electronic
distribution of data, however, has come an attitude change. . . . [T]he myth of machine infallibility seems
to create a demand for a higher standard of quality for machine-readable data than for traditionally
distributed information.”). As more and more information and data become accessible through the Internet,
there is a greater responsibility for authors of information and knowledge to make sure that data distributed
online is reliable and accurate. See J.H. Reichman & Paul F. Uhlir, A Contractually Reconstructed
Research Commons for Scientific Data in a Highly Protectionist Intellectual Property Environment, 66
LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 315 (2003) (describing the need for accurate, reliable, and accessible data in
scientific research).
118
Some remedies may be available through the online service provider’s end user license agreement or
terms of service. The adequacy of these remedies to protect an author’s creative interest is questionable as
these agreements regulate the relationship between service provider and user and are enforced by the
service provider. Courts have yet to decide on the enforceability of these agreements in a court of law
although courts have decided that shrink-wrap licenses are enforceable. See Vernor v. Autodesk, Inc. 621
F.3d 1102 (9th Cir. 2010); ProCD, Inc. v. Zeidenberg, 86 F.3d 1447 (7th Cir. 1996). Courts have also
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
554
¶28 Because a literary property right protects an author’s creative interest, the right
should not be alienable in the same way as statutory copyright rights. Many scholars who
believe that authors should have creative and personality rights to the use of their work
see these personal rights as inalienable because they protect an author’s individuality or
personality as expressed in a work.
119
This is not surprising, since the author’s literary
property right, with its genesis in natural law and the idea of personal autonomy, would
fall within a category of rights that scholars and the law have long thought to be
inalienable, such as the rights to life, personal liberty, and protection from gratuitous
pain, as well as the satisfaction of basic needs, such as water, food, and healthcare.
120
An
author’s expression personifies his individuality and is so essential to the author
flourishing as an autonomous creator capable of making positive contributions to society
that all authentic expressions cannot, and should not, be treated as marketable
commodities. Because it is impossible to subtract an author’s sense of self from
authentic and sincere self-expressions, a literary property right protecting such expression
should not be alienable
121
even if an author enters into a contract to sell that right.
122
Therefore, the rights that are alienable under the Copyright Act are specific rights to use
the work and not the expression contained in the work in the same way that freedom and
liberty are not alienable (one cannot sell oneself into slavery), whereas skill and labor are
enforced open-source licenses. See Jacobsen v. Katzer, 535 F.3d 1373 (Fed. Cir. 2008).
119
See, e.g., PATTERSON, supra note 1, at 219 (“The author . . . may appropriately be given broader
protection than the publisher for the purpose of protecting his creative interest. This interest is unique and
appropriate for the author alone, and it should be recognized as a personal right, which is inalienable.”);
Netanel, supra note 56, at 409–30 (arguing that an author’s right to autonomy should be inalienable
because of power imbalances, the personal connection between creator and work, paternalism, and
communitarian principles that are prevalent in the copyright system). The Copyright Act has also made the
right to terminate grants of copyright under § 203(a)(5) inalienable. For discussion, see Peter S. Menell &
David Nimmer, Pooh-Poohing Copyright Law’s “Inalienable” Termination Rights, 57 J. COPYRIGHT
SOCY U.S.A. 799, 814 (2010) (describing Congress’s policy of protecting authors from agreements made
from a weaker bargaining position under § 203). The Supreme Court has also affirmed the inalienable
termination right of the author as provided by that statutory provision. See N.Y. Times Co. v. Tasini, 533
U.S. 483, 495 n.3 (2001) (referring to § 203(a)(5) as “inalienable authorial right to revoke a copyright
transfer”); Stewart v. Abend, 495 U.S. 207, 230 (1990) (“The 1976 Copyright Act provides a single, fixed
term, but provides an inalienable termination right.”) (citing 17 U.S.C. §§ 203, 302 (2006)).
120
See Anita L. Allen, Privacy, Surrogacy, and the Baby M Case, 76 GEO. L.J. 1759, 178889 (1988)
(citing DIANA T. MEYERS, INALIENABLE RIGHTS: A DEFENSE (1985)).
121
See Margaret Jane Radin, Market-Inalienability, 100 HARV. L. REV. 1849, 190506 (1987)
(suggesting that some personal attributes cannot be separated and sold in the market place). Professor
Radin explains:
Universal commodification undermines personal identity by conceiving of personal
attributes, relationships, and philosophical and moral commitments as monetizable and
alienable from the self. A better view of personhood should understand many kinds of
particulars—one’s politics, work, religion, family, love, sexuality, friendships, altruism,
experiences, wisdom, moral commitments, character, and personal attributesas integral
to the self. To understand any of these as monetizable or completely detachable from the
person . . . is to do violence to our deepest understanding of what it is to be human.
Id.
122
RANDY E. BARNETT, THE STRUCTURE OF LIBERTY: JUSTICE AND THE RULE OF LAW 7879 (1998)
(arguing that one cannot enter into a contract to sell oneself into slavery because the object of the right
freedomcannot be transferred); see also TERRANCE MCCONNELL, INALIENABLE RIGHTS: THE LIMITS OF
CONSENT IN MEDICINE AND THE LAW 89 (2000) (reviewing cases to establish that the inalienable right not
to be killed cannot be contracted away even if the contract was freely entered into).
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
555
(one can contract to work and employment). While statutory rights are often assigned by
authors to publishers, literary property should always remain with the individual creator.
The right is inherently tied to the author’s personality, an intrinsic and distinguishing
attribute of the author, regardless of whether the work is newly conceived or a
reinterpretation of another author’s work. Each author’s distinctive personal mark in the
work should also secure the creative interests of its author. In this light, the “question of
literary property” is less a commercial struggle between booksellers, as Mark Rose
articulated,
123
and more the separation of authors’ identities from publishers’ identities
that should have been long disconnected.
¶29 More important than whether the author’s literary property can be alienated is the
question of how such a natural right, when not explicitly recognized by the copyright
system, can be used to protect an author’s interest. Philosophers who advocate legal
positivism resist the legal recognition of a right merely because a social, cultural, or
human expectation exists as a natural right. Bentham, for example, rejected and
denounced France’s Declaration of the Rights of Man in 1789, famously saying that
“[r]ight, the substantive right, is the child of law: from real laws come real rights,” but
only imaginary rights can come from imaginary laws,” which he called the “laws of
nature.”
124
But other philosophers, who were highly regarded positivists, have
acknowledged the possible existence of natural rights that can give birth to legal rights.
One well-known scholar in U.S. jurisprudence, H.L.A. Hart, believed that moral or
natural rights impose morally justifiable limitations on other people’s freedom in order to
achieve equal distribution of human freedom across a given society.
125
However, the
existence and social recognition of natural rights does not necessarily impose an
obligation on the state to convert these rights into legal rules, although states may take
steps to give natural rights actual legal force. While the recognition of a natural right,
such as the literary property of the author, may inspire social support and even
government endorsement, such conversion of a natural right into law can be a
complicated undertaking. Institutional commitment to enforcing a natural right as a legal
right would necessarily follow this conversion. But as Amartya Sen points out, social
criticism, open discussion, and cultural change may be effective ways of protecting and
enforcing natural rights without legislative action.
126
Sen observes that natural human
rights, such as a woman’s right to voice her opinion about how her family is raised and
cared for, has “far-reaching ethical and political relevance,” which may be better
addressed “by means of social criticism as well as public debates and agitation.”
127
123
ROSE, supra note 1, at 4 (quoting FRANCIS HARGRAVE, IN DEFENCE OF LITERARY PROPERTY 7 (2d
ed. 1774) (Gr. Brit.)).
124
JEREMY BENTHAM, Anarchical Fallacies; Being an Examination of the Declarations of Rights Issued
During the French Revolution, in 2 THE WORKS OF JEREMY BENTHAM 489, 523 (John Bowring ed.,
Edinburgh, William Tait 1843); see also Amartya Sen, Rights, Laws and Language, 31 OXFORD J. LEGAL
STUD. 437, 439 (2011) (internal quotation marks omitted) (discussing Bentham’s views on natural rights).
125
H.L.A. Hart, Are There Any Natural Rights?, 64 PHIL. REV. 175, 178 (1955) (“[I]t is I think a very
important feature of a moral right that the possessor of it is conceived as having a moral justification for
limiting the freedom of another and that he has this justification not because the action he is entitled to
require of another has some moral quality but simply because in the circumstances a certain distribution of
human freedom will be maintained if he by his choice is allowed to determine how that other shall act.”).
126
Sen, supra note 124, at 44143 (discussing how natural rights have been more effectively enforced
without legal rules and sanctions).
127
Id. at 443.
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
556
Similarly, the author’s natural right in his expression may be better protected and
enforced by international organizations, such as the United Nations Educational,
Scientific, and Cultural Organization or non-governmental bodies, research centers, and
academic institutions leading a change in social and cultural mindsets. It would,
however, still be worthwhile to consider the protection and enforcement of literary
property as a legal right that the author alone holds. There are two avenues to give legal
force to an author’s natural right: (1) Congress could pass specific legislation (or amend
the copyright statute); or (2) courts could develop specific case law on authors’ rights.
3. Making the Author’s Natural Right a Legal Right
¶30 The primary objection to making the author’s natural right a legal right is the
curtailment of other individual freedoms, such as the freedom to express one’s self or
assert personal or political viewpoints. Explicitly protecting literary property as a legal
right would make it unlawful to destroy an artist’s painting or deface a sculpture outside
the specific provisions of § 106A of the Copyright Act.
128
But, as Professor Katyal
points out, the destruction and vandalism of creative works may also be a “profoundly
expressive” form of “semiotic disobedience.”
129
If so, some may fear that the right to
free expression could be limited to ensure authorial autonomy and security. But even if
an author’s natural right in his expression provides a moral justification to limit freedom
of speech, amending copyright legislation to introduce literary property as a natural right
would be practically impossible under current practices. As Professor Jessica Litman
points out, the legislative process for copyright law occurs at a negotiation table primarily
with industry-dominated players with primarily economic interests.
130
Therefore, one of
the greatest challenges to introducing a moral and natural right into copyright legislation,
as proposed in this Article, is its introduction in the negotiation process in copyright
legislation drafting. Unless there are significant voices pushing for a change in copyright
legislation to protect the author’s rights during the negotiation process, the resulting
legislation will be silent on the natural rights issues that authors may care about.
131
Statutory recognition of a creative right for authors would likely promote progress in the
arts by providing authors greater security in how their expressions may be used and
would likely advance society and culture by encouraging the production of authentic
expressions. However, the fact that such a right may infringe on other freedoms and
constitutional guarantees, such as freedom of speech and freedom of the press, may be an
impediment to its recognition.
128
See 17 U.S.C. § 106A (2006).
129
Katyal, supra note 116, at 56869.
130
Jessica D. Litman, Copyright, Compromise, and Legislative History, 72 CORNELL L. REV. 857, 860
61 (1987) (“Indeed, the statute’s legislative history is troubling because it reveals that most of the statutory
language was not drafted by members of Congress or their staffs at all. Instead, the language evolved
through a process of negotiation among authors, publishers, and other parties with economic interests in the
property rights the statute defines.”); Jessica Litman, Copyright Legislation and Technological Change, 68
OR. L. REV. 275, 278 (1989) [hereinafter Litman, Copyright Legislation and Technological Change]
(describing how the process of drafting copyright statutes through negotiations among industry
representatives became entrenched in copyright law-making); see also JESSICA LITMAN, DIGITAL
COPYRIGHT (2001).
131
Litman, Copyright Legislation and Technological Change, supra note 130, at 299 (describing how
interests that were absent from the bargaining table were shortchanged in the compromises that emerged
throughout the various legislative enactments).
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
557
¶31 Perhaps it makes more sense to rely on courts to develop case law on the author’s
rights. Then, courts could develop case law on the author’s creative interest as they arise
on a case-by-case basis. The development of the law in this area “will require perceptive
analysis and careful distinction,” which Professor Patterson believes courts are in the best
position to do.
132
Further, Professor Patterson postulates that federal courts would be a
better avenue than state courts to develop the author’s creative interest, since federal
copyright law expressly preempts state copyright law.
133
This Article argues that state
courts might not be preempted from developing case law on the author’s rights under
§ 301 of the Copyright Act for two reasons.
134
First, the author’s creative right is not a
right that is equivalent to the exclusive rights protected by § 106.
135
Arguably, the rights
in § 106, including the right to derivative works right under § 106(2), protect economic
interests that are vastly different from the author’s creative interest, which protects the
author’s personality and individuality. Second, literary property protects the author’s
personality represented in the work (such as stylistic preferences and artistic forms), as
opposed to the expression in the work itself. An author’s creative work is protectable
subject matter under §§ 102 and 103. But authorial expressions that take special form,
such as a work that an author specifically creates to teach and educate children, will not
be protected under these provisions if their ideas are used for a purpose that is completely
in opposition to the intention of the author, such as to propagate violence among children.
Allowing courts to make normative and prescriptive judgments that would introduce
moral and ethical principles that protect authors in the copyright system would require
one to assume that judges have an overriding duty to decide cases based on a set of
sociopolitical norms that uphold principles of justice and fairness. This is particularly
true where legislation has not explicitly integrated these principles. The author of this
Article has argued elsewhere that the copyright system may be understood as a loosely
formed political contract for social development, which provides identifiable norms that
could guide judges confronted with a difficult copyright case.
136
Hypothetically, a judge
could decide, according to the moral and ethical convictions of society, that literary and
artistic works can be used and produced for the purposes of promoting progress, and
come to a decision that reflects these convictions and protects the author’s creative
interest. If the legal system has an underlying integrity that is built on unitive principles,
which represents the legal system’s commitment to creating a “genuine [community]
rather than a bare community,”
137
it is possible that the courts could have a role in
protecting the natural rights of authors while keeping in mind copyright’s institutional
goal of promoting artistic progress.
132
PATTERSON, supra note 1, at 220.
133
Id. at 219.
134
See 17 U.S.C. § 301 (2006) (establishing the criteria for federal preemption of state copyright law).
135
See id. § 301(b)(3) (indicating that preemption does not apply to “rights that are not equivalent to any
of the exclusive rights within the general scope of copyright as specified by section 106”).
136
See ALINA NG, COPYRIGHT LAW AND THE PROGRESS OF SCIENCE AND THE USEFUL ARTS (2011).
137
RONALD DWORKIN, LAWS EMPIRE 214 (1986).
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
558
III. COMMON LAW PROPERTY AND STATUTORY COPYRIGHT
¶32 Would copyright law become redundant if the law were to protect literary property
as a common law right of the author as suggested in this Article? As discussed in Part II,
the suggestion that the author’s literary property be protected as a natural right may invite
criticism from copyright pessimists, who may consider the protection of literary property
as an expansion of rights that would further limit the public’s ability to access creative
works for use. Additionally, many scholarly works have focused on the apparent conflict
between the grant of a property right to encourage creative production and the need for
access to creative works to feed the wheel of progress.
138
Much of this literature sees the
flaws of a system that needs reform,
139
especially when the Internet and digital
technologies have increased the user’s ability to interact with the work as a new and
legitimate form of free expression.
140
Copyright scholars and practitioners seem to
continue to view the copyright system as inadequate in dealing with technological
progress that brings advances, not only of science and useful arts, but also of society,
culture, and the way political discourse is conducted. When Benjamin Kaplan began his
1966 James S. Carpentier Lecture at Columbia University School of Law, he stated that:
As a veteran listener at many lectures by copyright specialists over the past
decade, I know it is almost obligatory for a speaker to begin by invoking the
“communications revolution” of our time, then to pronounce upon the
inadequacies of the present copyright act, and finally to encourage all hands to
cooperate in getting a Revision Bill passed.
141
This quote indicates that Professor Kaplan may have had an unquestioning resignation
that the copyright system has failed to promote progress and is thus in dire need of
reform.
¶33 Literary property rights could, however, further the institutional goals of the
copyright system rather than prevent progress, as some have feared. A literary property
right could bridge the gap between the interests of those involved (such as authors,
publishers, and society) and the ultimate institutional interest of promoting progress in a
legal system that lacks authentic creations that make positive contributions to the
trajectory of social progress and cultural development. The rights provided under the
Copyright Act serve a particular purpose: to encourage publication and distribution of
creative works in a society in need of creative materials. Without these statutory rights,
the proper economic investments will not be made to convert an author’s expression into
literary and artistic works that may then be distributed to society for use in education,
138
Keith Aoki, Authors, Inventors and Trademark Owners: Private Intellectual Property and the Public
Domain Part I, 18 COLUM.-VLA J.L. & ARTS 1, 810 (1993) (describing the growing body of legal
commentators since 1981 who have become interested in how the expansion of intellectual property rights
affect the public domain).
139
See, e.g., Litman, supra note 130; Shira Perlmutter, Freeing Copyright from Formalities, 13
CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 565 (1995); Peter K. Yu, Digital Copyright Reform and Legal Transplants in
Hong Kong, 48 U. LOUISVILLE L. REV. 693 (2010).
140
See LAWRENCE LESSIG, REMIX: MAKING ART AND COMMERCE THRIVE IN THE HYBRID ECONOMY 69
(2008) (describing a method of creation that uses the Internet and digital technologies, which “remixes”
portions of works created across multiple media to produce a new work).
141
KAPLAN, supra note 1, at 1.
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
559
research, cultural programs, and study. Indeed, very few authors are able to reach the
masses without financial support from a publisher. The statutory rights provided by the
Copyright Act serve this important publishing and distributive function. Literary
property, on the other hand, would serve a completely different function. It would
encourage authors to create authentically and share their work with the public without
fear that the work will be misused or abused once it is distributed into society. It would
also provide legal affirmation of the author’s expectation to be able to express himself.
Both copyright and literary property encourage publication and distribution of creative
works, as well as the creation of authentic expression, ultimately promoting the progress
of science and useful arts.
A. Copyright as an Economic Incentive to Publish
¶34 Statutory rights under the copyright system facilitate investment in publishing and
disseminating literary and artistic works by providing exclusive rights to the copyright
owner. Generally, because creative works are considered to be “public goods,” and
therefore subject to free-riding, where a copier may produce subsequent copies of a work
at marginal cost without paying its actual price,
142
the law provides copyright owners
with the exclusive right to reproduce, make derivatives, distribute, and publicly perform
and display the work to exclude non-paying members of the public and encourage the
initial investment in the work. These exclusive rights protect the positive act of making
literary and artistic works available to society to promote the progress of science and
useful arts by allowing the copyright owner to recover fixed costs for the first production
of a work and subsequent marginal costs of production when the original work is
reproduced for reprinting, binding, distribution, and dissemination to the public. Without
copyright protection giving its owners exclusive rights, non-paying members of society
will benefit from the investments made by the copyright owner and use the work without
paying for it, thereby benefitting from what economists call a positive externalitya
transaction spillover into society that provides a benefit but which is also not accounted
for in the price of the good.
143
Some scholars point out that free-riding on positive
externalities, or spillovers, provides long-term benefits toward the legal system’s goal of
progress to argue that they should not be internalized by the copyright owner.
144
However, this Article argues that these exclusive rights encourage the publication and
dissemination of creative works by copyright owners who may otherwise invest their
resources in other efforts.
¶35 The protection of statutory rights under the current copyright system maximizes
collective social welfare by ensuring scarce resources are allocated in the most
economically efficient way. This idea that granting exclusive rights in literary and
artistic creations will result in more of their production is intuitive from an economic
perspectiveauthors will not produce if their works may be easily appropriated by the
public, especially when the product of their creativity is essentially non-excludable and
142
Wendy J. Gordon, Authors, Publishers, and Public Goods: Trading Gold for Dross, 36 LOY. L.A. L.
REV. 159, 164 (2002).
143
Jeffrey L. Harrison, A Positive Externalities Approach to Copyright Law: Theory and Application, 13
J. INTELL. PROP. L. 1, 9 (2005).
144
See Brett M. Frischmann & Mark A. Lemley, Spillovers, 107 COLUM. L. REV. 257, 258 (2007); Mark
A. Lemley, Property, Intellectual Property, and Free Riding, 83 TEX. L. REV. 1031 (2005).
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
560
non-rival,
145
and therefore, subject to use without payment. Harold Demsetz’s famous
1967 article, “Toward a Theory of Property Rights,” exemplifies the economic approach
towards property-like entitlements in literary and artistic works.
146
Demsetz argues that
property rights facilitate the internalization of externalities, and often new property rights
emerge when the benefits of internalizing externalities outweigh the costs of that
internalization. This usually occurs when new technology is developed and new markets
open.
147
To Professor Demsetz, a newly formed and growing marketthe fur trade
was the impetus that led to the establishment of well-defined private hunting territory
among the Montagnes Indians,
148
just as the emerging book market was the source of the
establishment of exclusive copyright in literary works during the seventeenth and
eighteenth century in England. Garrett Hardin’s “The Tragedy of the Commons,”
published a year later, makes a related point: unless some form of institutional
governance sets aside common resources to be privately controlled, men, being
economically rational creatures, are likely to take as much out of the commons as
possible to maximize their gains and to put in as much waste as possible without having
to bear the cost of cleaning the commons, without investing in building it up.
149
As a
result of each person acting their own self-interest, limited resources that are available to
all will be depleted.
150
As some lawyers see it, the purpose of the institution of private
property is to protect the commons from complete depletion through overuse.
151
¶36 Both Professor Demsetz’s and Professor Hardin’s articles provide a neoclassical
justification that supports the privatization of creative works and the expansion of
property-like rights in information and knowledge. The logic is difficult to deny: if
creative works are too easily appropriated, authors and publishers will not invest time or
money to produce or disseminate creative works to the public when there are no
guarantees of a return on investment. Without exclusive rights in such works to prevent
their free use by the public, creativity and innovation would likely decline. By protecting
the commercial value in the work through the exclusive rights under § 106, the law
provides economic incentives to encourage creators of literary and artistic works to
produce works and disseminate them to society.
152
While termed a “property right” that
protects commercial investments from spillovers into a market, statutory copyright is
intended to serve a larger goala temporary monopoly is granted to the copyright owner,
but these exclusive rights are to stimulate artistic creativity for society’s general good.
145
The exact “public good” nature of creative works has been explored elsewhere. See Christopher S.
Yoo, Copyright and Public Good Economics: A Misunderstood Relation, 155 U. PA. L. REV. 635 (2007).
For the purposes of this Article, it suffices to say that creative works cannot be excluded and are non-rival
as a broad economic principle.
146
See Harold Demsetz, Toward a Theory of Property Rights, 57 AM. ECON. REV. (PAPERS & PROC.)
347 (1967).
147
Id. at 350.
148
Id. at 351.
149
Hardin, supra note 104.
150
Id.
151
Hanoch Dagan & Michael A. Heller, The Liberal Commons, 110 YALE L.J. 549, 55960 (2001)
(“[T]he conventional wisdom for many social scientists is that commons property generally leads to
tragedy. This claima truism of first-year law classesis usually introduced as one of the strongest
justifications for the institution of private property.”) (footnote omitted).
152
See Mark A. Lemley, Ex Ante Versus Ex Post Justifications for Intellectual Property, 71 U. CHI. L.
REV. 129 (2004) (discussing the economic arguments for intellectual property).
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
561
Statutory rights do not preserve a “commons” from overuse as property rights are
commonly thought to do. Functionally, statutory rights make sure that creative works are
generated and distributed to the public to increase the common repository of knowledge
as soon as a work’s copyright expires. The knowledge commons is enriched with the
expiration of the property rightthere is no real depletion of the commons, the tragedy
that Professor Hardin feared.
153
As such, statutory rights in literary and artistic creations,
as state-granted incentives to encourage the creation of artistic works, might be better
understood as a collection of disaggregated legal interests to use creative works in
specific ways that will facilitate publication and dissemination to the public. Therefore,
statutory copyright, while considered as a property right, is not an ownership right in a
work as an object for possessory control against the rest of the worldan in rem right as
traditionally understood.
154
Rather, it is an in personam right that defines a specific legal
relationship between author, publisher, and user of a work as that relationship applies to
the publication and distribution of a specific work. Despite the general acceptance
among property scholars that property relates to a bundle of rights that performs various
state-prioritized functions and has nothing to do with property as a legally defined
boundary drawn around a thing to effectively exclude the rest of the world from its use,
155
this same idea may not have influenced copyright jurisprudence as muchgiven the
general thought of statutory copyright as a property right in a work. On this point, the
author of this Article has suggested elsewhere that property rights under the present
copyright law would be more appropriately classified as “economic privileges.”
156
These
privileges should be recognized as in personam rights establishing specific contract-type
relationships among parties responsible for producing, publishing, distributing, and using
the work in the copyright system. They should not be seen as creating absolute interests
in the work as a privatized resource and should be treated differently from the author’s
literary property rights, which are distinct rights in rem.
157
¶37 Because statutory copyright is designed to encourage investments in creative
works, these rights might not encourage the creation of authentic works in the same way
the recognition of literary property would. The emphasis that neoclassical economics
places on market rewards as the best mechanism to efficiently allocate resources for
production, publication, and distribution of creative works has long-term consequences
for the kind of literary and artistic works that are produced. The neoclassicist’s
assumption that economic incentives are positively correlated with creative production is
153
See Shubha Ghosh, The Fable of the Commons: Exclusivity and the Construction of Intellectual
Property Markets, 40 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 855 (2007).
154
Conventionally an in rem right meant a right “against a thing” in Latin. See Thomas W. Merrill &
Henry E. Smith, The Property/Contract Interface, 101 COLUM. L. REV. 773, 782 & n.28 (2001). However,
this term has been clarified by Wesley Hohfeld to mean “one of a large class of fundamentally similar yet
separate rights, actual and potential, residing in a single person (or single group of persons) but availing
respectively against persons constituting a very large and indefinite class of people.” WESLEY NEWCOMB
HOHFELD, FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS AS APPLIED IN JUDICIAL REASONING AND OTHER LEGAL
ESSAYS 72 (Walter Wheeler Cook ed., 1919) (footnote omitted).
155
Thomas W. Merrill & Henry E. Smith, What Happened to Property in Law and Economics?, 111
YALE L.J. 357, 365 (2001) (“The conception of property as an infinitely variable collection of rights,
powers, and duties has today become a kind of orthodoxy.”).
156
See Alina Ng, Rights, Privileges, and Access to Information, 42 LOY. U. CHI. L.J. 89, 104 (2010).
157
Id.
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
562
still unproven.
158
Even accepting that assumption as true, there are still other, and
perhaps more dire, effects of an overreliance on market incentives to generate authorial
creativity and productivity.
¶38 The first upshot of a market-centric approach to the copyright system is that it
portrays the act of creativity and authorshipthe expression of an author’s individual
experience and personalityas a primarily economically driven activity. It is possible
that this may cause the public to treat works of authorship and other creative works as a
commercial commodity, resulting in less respect for the process of creative authorship
when these works are used.
159
Second, the market-based approach may have blurred the
important distinction between property and statutory rights and allowed copyright owners
(such as publishers, distributors, and printers, who may have financially invested in the
work but not been involved in its creation) to assert exclusive property-like rights in the
expressive content of the work against the public.
160
Property rights in an author’s
creation define ownership rights in the work itself and involve a unique right in rem to
exclude. Only the creator of the work ought to be able to assert this right. Third, the
market-based approach establishes the commercial market as a new patron of authors and
artists, compelling creators of literary and artistic works to produce works for the public.
To ensure that they are remunerated for their works through the market, authors and
artists may produce works that appeal to the general masses at the expense of producing
works of authentic authorship. As more authentic works of authorship are a result of an
artist’s expressive individuality, they may be of greater authorial value to the progress of
science and useful arts in society.
161
¶39 When considering the protection of literary property rights of authors, it is useful to
evaluate the effectiveness of the copyright market in producing authentic forms of
authorship that will contribute towards the advancement of knowledge or the progress of
society. Macaulay expressed immense faith in the copyright system when he commented
that the system would free authors from the patronage of ministers and nobles by
providing an alternative source of payment for their work.
162
Macaulay believed that
“men whose profession is literature, and whose private means are not ample” should be
“remunerated for their literary labour” through the copyright system so that “valuable
158
See Zimmerman, supra note 113.
159
Séverine Dusollier, The Master’s Tools v. The Master’s House: Creative Commons v. Copyright, 29
COLUM. J.L. & ARTS 271, 290 (2006). In this article, Dusollier argues that “consumerism is as much a
threat to copyright as the increasing commodification of copyright.” Id. She goes on to state that “[t]urning
copyrighted works into commodities has recast the public as individual consumers, and focusing on
consumers makes explicit the recognition of a copyright regime that considers creative works solely as
commodities to be exchanged in a market.” Id.
160
Mark A. Lemley, The Economics of Improvement in Intellectual Property Law, 75 TEX. L. REV. 989,
1033 (1997). Professor Lemley argues that the derivative right in paragraph (2) § 106 should remain an
author’s right, and states that “it seems odd that a legal provision that ostensibly exists for the benefit of
creators (artists or authors, for example) should confer rights instead on the owners of intellectual property
rights. As anyone who has ever published a book, a screenplay, or a song can attest, authorship and
ownership are not necessarily the same thing.” Id.
161
The author of this Article has explored the idea of “authentic authorship” in a previous work.
Although deeper analysis of the idea is warranted, see Alina Ng, The Author’s Rights in Literary and
Artistic Works, 9 J. MARSHALL REV. INTELL. PROP. L. 453, 48688 (2009) for a preliminary discussion.
162
Thomas Babington Macaulay, A Speech Delivered in the House of Commons on the 5th of February,
1841, in FOUNDATIONS OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY 309, 310 (Robert P. Merges & Jane C. Ginsburg eds.,
2004).
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
563
books” would be supplied to society.
163
However, it is important to note that when the
copyright market replaces the rich and noble as the author’s patron, a separate set of
problems arise. The author, instead of being bound to create works of literature and art
for a human patron, is now bound to produce for a corporate or marketplace patron.
¶40 Recording contracts between performing artists and recording companies are just
one example of the constraints that the marketplace and corporate patronage impose on
creativity today.
164
But the effects of market-based constraints on authorial creativity
were felt as far back as the eighteenth century, when a market for literature emerged in
Germany. German playwright and philosopher Johann Christoph Friedrich Schiller
broke off from the patronage of the Duke of Württemberg when the possibility of selling
his works on the market presented itself.
165
Schiller referred to the reading public as his
“school, [his] sovereign, [and his] trusted friend” and began his career as a professional
writer by “appealing to no other throne than the human spirit.”
166
The literary market,
however, turned out to be indifferent and unrewarding to Schiller’s more authentic and
intellectually demanding philosophical works on ethics, aesthetics, and reason. The fame
and economic rewards Schiller yearned for from the public were, to a certain extent, only
acquired by creating works that the public demanded at that time, such as historical
narratives rather than the philosophical works that were Schiller’s forte.
167
Schiller never
found the reward he expected from the literary market, and in 1792, he accepted the
patronage of the Danish Duke of Augustenburg, who gave him the intellectual freedom
necessary to produce more authentic forms of authorship. Schiller, reflecting on his
experience with the literary marketplace, noted that the demands of the market for works
that appealed to a wide segment of the paying public was, in reality, irreconcilable with
the demands of authentic expression.
168
¶41 Unfortunately, contemporary copyright markets could be just as unreceptive to
literary and artistic works that do not conform to the expectations of popular culture or
carry widespread appeal because authors and creators who seek to make a living by
selling their works to the public may have to exchange personal authorial or artistic
integrity for contemporary and more popular creations. When the copyright system treats
creative works as marketable commodities instead of personal expressions of creativity, it
may leave individual creators with little choice but to compromise their own artistic
authenticity and integrity. To a large extent, courts’ reluctance to make artistic
judgments about creative works in deciding eligibility for copyright protection mitigates
some of the harshness of the marketplace for authentic creations.
169
Some authors may
willingly surrender the economic rewards of the marketplace to engage in more authentic
163
Id.
164
Todd M. Murphy, Crossroads: Modern Contract Dissatisfaction as Applied to Songwriter and
Recording Agreements, 35 J. MARSHALL L. REV. 795, 81617 (2002) (discussing the contractual
relationship between recording artists and their recording companies).
165
WOODMANSEE, supra note 10, at 40.
166
Id. at 41 (quoting, as translated, FRIEDRICH SCHILLER, SCHILLERS WERKE, NATIONALAUSGABE
(Herbert Meyer et al. eds., 1958)).
167
Id. at 82.
168
Id. at 84.
169
Bleistein v. Donaldson Lithographing Co., 188 U.S. 239, 251 (1903) (“[S]ome works of genius
would be sure to miss appreciation . . . until the public had learned the new language in which their author
spoke. . . . [T]he etchings of Goya or the paintings of Manet” may not have evoked the public’s admiration
“when seen for the first time.”).
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
564
pursuits of expression.
170
However, where an author does not make that deliberate
decision, the copyright market will mold creative expression to satisfy the demands of
popular public tastes, which could prevent the production of more authentic works that
may have greater influence on how science and useful arts advance.
¶42 The final point to make about copyright as an incentive to produce and secure
rewards from the market, is that it protects the owner and not just the author of the work.
Even though the Copyright Act recognizes the author as the first owner of a copyright,
171
the exclusive rights that are protected under § 106 are fully transferrable
172
and may be
owned by an owner of copyright through an assignment of rights from the author.
173
This
has resulted in a concentration of ownership rights in the intermediaries who disseminate
works of the author to his readers, but whose primary interest in the work may be purely
commercial in nature and misaligned from the institutional goals of the copyright
system.
174
Unlike authors, who create works as a form of personal expression, and users,
who consume works for enjoyment, inspiration, learning, research, and so on, a publisher
does not have an interest in the work as an expression of creativity. Rather, a publisher is
interested in the work itself as a marketable commodity that may provide profits. The
commoditization of creative works to capture social benefits or positive externalities
from the production of creative works is a natural consequence of statutory copyright.
Although the exclusive rights under § 106 are intended to facilitate dissemination of
creative expressions of individual creators through the market to ultimately benefit the
public and advance science and useful arts, these rights have a tendency to secure the a
monopoly position of the intermediary publisher for the publication and distribution of
works.
175
Without competition for the publication and distribution of works in the
market, it becomes increasingly difficult to “clear rights” before using a copyrighted
work, causing a “chilling effect” on creativity and innovation that depends on the use of
creative works from earlier generations.
176
Protecting economic interests in the
170
The recognition from producing outstanding work may be a noneconomic incentive to produce works
that are more authentic. See Catherine L. Fisk, Credit Where It’s Due: The Law and Norms of Attribution,
95 GEO. L.J. 49, 56 (2006) (“Even when the author, inventor, discoverer, or artisan made little or no money
from the work itself, it has long been an honor to be credited with good work. Great artists of all kinds
have destroyed work that they thought did not measure up to their standards, even when they might have
profited more (at least in the short term) from selling their lesser works rather than destroying them.”).
171
17 U.S.C. § 201(a) (2006).
172
Id. § 201(d).
173
Id. § 106 (stating that the “owner of copyright” has the exclusive right to reproduce the work, make
derivatives, perform and publicly display, and perform publicly by way of digital audio transmission).
174
See, e.g., Fred H. Cate, The Technological Transformation of Copyright Law, 81 IOWA L. REV. 1395,
1458 (1996) (describing the interests of information providers in “strong, even unconstitutional, levels of
copyright protection”); Jeffrey Stavroff, Damages in Dissonance: The “Shocking” Penalty for Illegal
Music File-Sharing, 39 CAP. U. L. REV. 659 (2011) (such as seeking statutory damages against non-
commercial infringers); Joshua N. Mitchell, Note, Promoting Progress with Fair Use, 60 DUKE L.J. 1639,
1656 (2011) (stating that “Congress has appeared susceptible to lobbying pressure from industry groups . . .
which push for increasedand not obviously progress-promotingprotections, to the detriment of
Congress’s constitutional responsibilities”) (footnote omitted).
175
Edmund W. Kitch, Elementary and Persistent Errors in the Economic Analysis of Intellectual
Property, 53 VAND. L. REV. 1727, 1735 (2000) (defining economic monopoly as “hav[ing] the exclusive
right to sell into a market without competition”).
176
For clear chilling effect of a still tentative copyright on public use of the work, see Robert Spoo,
Note, Copyright Protectionism and Its Discontents: The Case of James Joyce’s Ulysses in America, 108
YALE L.J. 633, 662 (1998) (“[T]he purported copyright in Ulysses, unless it is recognized as illusory, will
likewise receive a twenty-year reprieve from the public domain and will continue to exert a chilling effect
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
565
distribution and sale of artistic works could be a hindrance, rather than an impetus, to
public access to creative works in all formsartwork, music, literature, software
programs, visual works, and research materialsif one is not clear that the statutory
protections for copyright owners serve as an incentive to make works available to the
public in furtherance of a prioritized goal and should be exercised with that goal in mind.
Perhaps relabeling the exclusive rights as statutory privileges that entitle the copyright
owner to sell and distribute the work exclusively for the purposes of furthering an
institutionally identified priority (in other words, progress) may prevent the exercise of
§ 106 rights that would take away from copyright’s goals. The key to keeping on track
with the goal of progress is a deeper understanding of the different facets of a property
right and how the exercise of § 106 rights are limited by this understanding.
B. The Different Facets of a Property Right
¶43 Many property scholars believe, on some fundamental level, that property rights are
about establishing boundaries around resources through exclusive control of that resource
by the property owner. William Blackstone is often quoted as providing the
quintessential definition of what a property right should look likeit is a “sole and
despotic dominion which one man claims and exercises over the external things of the
world, in total exclusion of the right of any other individual in the universe.”
177
Some
scholars argue that this right to exclude is the defining characteristic of a property right
its sine qua non.
178
Indeed, without a right to exclude others from trespass, theft, and use
of the property, the notion of property would be meaningless. The right to exclude
provides normative meaning to the concept of ownership in a society.
179
The idea of
property as a right to exclude is also an integral part of copyright jurisprudence.
180
However, scholars have also come to understand property as a legal term that defines
different legal relationships among members of society in relation to a particular
resource. Property is not, per se, a right in the resource itself.
181
Given that property law
defines the relationship between the owner of a resource against the rest of the world,
some scholars hypothesize that the strength of property rights varies on a continuous
scale and that the state utilizes them strategically depending on the size of the resource,
the range of activities that the owner of a resource is allowed, the cost of monitoring and
upon publishers well into the next century. The effects of monopoly will go on being felt: Readers will
pay noncompetitive prices for Estate-approved editions of Ulysses; scholars will be discouraged from
producing alternative versions of the novel in print and electronic-text formats. In particular, the benefits
of digitalization and cyberspace will be lost or muted where Ulysses is concerned.”).
177
2 WILLIAM BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES ON THE LAWS OF ENGLAND 34 (William G. Hammond
ed., 8th ed. 1890); see also Carol M. Rose, Canons of Property Talk, or, Blackstone’s Anxiety, 108 YALE
L.J. 601, 601 (1998).
178
Thomas W. Merrill, Property and the Right to Exclude, 77 NEB. L. REV. 730, 730 (1998).
179
Id. at 732.
180
See Niva Elkin-Koren, Copyright Policy and the Limits of Freedom of Contract, 12 BERKELEY TECH.
L.J. 93, 99 (1997) (“Copyright law overcomes [free-riding] and encourages creation by providing creators
with a legal right to exclude others. It allows them to use the power of the federal government to exclude
non-payers and to deter potential free-riders. By legally excluding non-payers, the law allows creators to
collect fees for the use of their works and secure a return on their investment.”).
181
Merrill, supra note 178, at 731–32 (“[T]he institution of property is not concerned with scarce
resources themselves (‘things’), but rather with the rights of persons with respect to such resources.”).
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
566
enforcing those rights, and the fluctuating value of the resource.
182
Property rights
exclusionary on one extreme and organizational or governmental on the other
183
provide signals or information to society as to how a particular resource is to be used. As
property rights are used by the government to define the relationship between the
property owner and the resource more clearly, society’s conduct toward the resource will
be more effectively managed.
184
¶44 Statutory rights under § 106, even though they are “exclusive,” should not be
exercised in an exclusionary way in light of what property scholars think is the
functionality of property. In the copyright system, some scholars see creative production
as a privatized activity that should be subject to public values
185
and the advancement in
science and arts as depending on the public’s ability to access and use knowledge and
information easily. Therefore, to these scholars, the application of the statutory rights
cannot feasibly be seen as exclusionary in the sense that the public should be denied
access to the work unless the copyright owner grants the public permission to access the
work. Professors Hardin and Demsetz’s concern that resources in the commons will be
depleted through overexploitation does not apply to creative works. As exclusionary
rights are often used to deal with the problem of over exploitation, there is no necessity
for its use to prevent public access to creative resources because, unlike natural resources
that are susceptible to depletion through overuse, creative resources are not scarce and
will not deplete through overexploitation.
186
In fact, new generations of authors and
creators need to be able to use collective knowledge, research findings, and documented
experiences to guide their own explorations and experiments in creating new materials
for society. The exercise of the rights under § 106, if exclusionary in practice, will make
the development of culture, accessible education, or economic growth difficult, if not
impossible. Hence, on the spectrum of property functionality Professor Smith developed,
statutory copyright would not lie on the exclusionary rule pole, but at the organizational
or governance pole, where each specific entitlement that accrues to the copyright owner
is carefully articulated. As Professor Smith points out, this contradicts a more
exclusionary function of a patent right that denies access to a patent for those who do not
have permission to use the patent.
187
¶45 If one thinks of copyright as functioning on a different scale than patent (the other
form of intellectual property designed to advance the progress of science and useful arts),
it may become clear that statutory copyright is not about denying public access for the
182
See Henry E. Smith, Exclusion Versus Governance: Two Strategies for Delineating Property Rights,
31 J. LEGAL STUD. S453, S454 (2002).
183
Id. at S455 (Professor Henry Smith labels the two polar ends of property functionality on a spectrum
of rights of varying degrees. He states that “exclusion and governance are strategies that are at the poles of
a continuum of methods of measurement, which we can add to the more familiar continuum from private
property through the commons to open access.”).
184
Id. at S473 (“Rights are precise or specified to the extent that they protect attributes by preventing a
range of unauthorized actions. The result is that if one surveyed states of the world in which actors
undertake a range of unauthorized behaviors, the return to the owner of the right will show less variance the
more precise the right is; precision contributes to greater security of the right.”).
185
Shubha Ghosh, Deprivatizing Copyright, 54 CASE W. RES. L. REV. 387 (2003).
186
Smith, supra note 182, at S485 (“[E]xclusion is the basic first pass at addressing potential problems
of overexploitation.”).
187
Henry E. Smith, Intellectual Property as Property: Delineating Entitlements in Information, 116
YALE L.J. 1742, 178687 (2007).
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
567
purposes of establishing the creative work’s value.
188
The value of a copyrighted work is
often clear—it is the value a reader would be willing to pay for the use of an author’s
expression, which the market readily sets.
189
Where the market fails, copyright law has
the built-in mechanism of fair use to correct the failure.
190
The structure of copyright
law, with clearly enumerated rights under § 106, lends itself to specific rules of
governance that manage societal use of creative works. Thus, statutory copyright, in a
property sense does not establish perimeters or a fence around a limited resource, but
rather creates a bridged connection between authors and their readers to serve a very
specific institutional goal. It is not intended to grant exclusionary rights, nor is it
intended to create an open access public right to literary and artistic works. Rather, it is
intended to provide heavy regulation of how works are published, disseminated, and
used.
¶46 Recognizing that statutory rights in literary and artistic works serve to govern and
regulate various uses and interests, both economic and noneconomic (including
recreational, research-related, and educational uses), in creative works will clarify how
one should think about the literary property rights of the author. Statutory rights affirm a
basic economic principle underlying the copyright system: by granting a bundle of
entitlements to creative works to copyright owners exclusively under § 106, investments
in the publication and dissemination of creative works to the public will be made.
Producers of creative works will be more willing to invest in publication and distribution
if they have exclusive rights to use the work. In a classical Coasean fashion, the
Copyright Act allows the market to ultimately decide who may use a particular work,
how that work may be used, and when it may be used by providing the exclusivity
needed for contractual bargains to occur among authors, publishers, and users so that
rights to use the work may be efficiently allocated.
191
To a large extent, scholars
influenced by Coase have abandoned the idea of property as a right against the rest of the
world and embraced property as a state device to allocate use rights. The concept of
property as “a bundle of rights,” institutionalized by new institutional economics,
embraces the idea that contractual relationshipsand not a general right to excludelie
at the heart of property law.
192
The focus on contractual relations between the owner of a
right and identifiable parties to that contract changes the understanding of property from
188
See id. at 1802–03 (the difficulty in valuing patented inventions and the “multidimensional nature of
the activities” surrounding patent use compels the use of an exclusionary, and not a governance, strategy).
189
See David W. Barnes, The Incentives/Access Tradeoff, 9 NW. J. TECH. & INTELL. PROP. 96, 116
(2010) (describing how information is usually provided to users at a fixed price).
190
Wendy J. Gordon, Fair Use as Market Failure: A Structural and Economic Analysis of the Betamax
Case and Its Predecessors, 82 COLUM. L. REV. 1600 (1982).
191
PATRICIA AUFDERHEIDE & PETER JASZI, RECLAIMING FAIR USE: HOW TO PUT BALANCE BACK IN
COPYRIGHT 39 (2011) (describing the impact of Ronald Coase’s work on copyright and the principles of
fair use); Dan L. Burk & Julie E. Cohen, Fair Use Infrastructure for Rights Management Systems, 15
HARV. J.L. & TECH. 41, 47 n.19 (2001) (“We suspect that if the Court [in Sony Corp. of America v.
Universal City Studios, Inc.] had held provision of VCRs to be contributory infringement, a market for
video recorders and video rentals still would have emerged. Under a Coasean theory of arbitrage, assuming
manageable transaction costs, if there were money to be made from the sale of VCRs, one would expect
home electronics manufacturers to negotiate a license from the copyright holders.”); Frank H. Easterbrook,
Cyberspace Versus Property Law?, 4 TEX. REV. L. & POL. 103, 111 (1999) (arguing that technology
“mov[es] us closer to the world in which the Coase Theorem prevails” and bargaining about intellectual
property becomes easier).
192
Merrill & Smith, supra note 155, at 37678.
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
568
a right in a resource against the rest of the world into an abstract collection of aggregated
rights that do not represent real ownership rights in things. In this light, statutory
copyright, embodying various use rights under § 106, does not relate as much to a right in
the work against an infinite and unidentifiable group of people, but to a right to the
exclusive use of the work that is enforceable against a single person or a small number of
identifiable persons who use the work without paying the contract price. It facilitates the
transfer of creative works to individuals in society who put the work to its most valuable
use and resolves disputes among authors, publishers, and consumers of creative works.
But it does not protect the author’s creative personality, as expressed in the work, from
abuse when the work is distributed to an infinite and unidentifiable group of people, as a
property right would.
C. Conceptual Differences Between Property and Copyright
¶47 The conventional view is that the owner of property has certain rights to those
resources which he owns. For example, property owners have a right in rem, a right or an
interest in the property or thing, which is good against the rest of the world.
193
In rem
rights create an entitlement to control access to, or use of, a resource that may be
enforceable against an unlimited and indefinite group of people, who individually owe a
duty to refrain from accessing or using that resource. Commentators on the law
distinguish an in rem right from an in personam right. In personam rights represent
personal interests that an individual possesses by virtue of a personal or contractual
relationship with the person who owes the corresponding duty. In personam rights are
personal to the right-holder and they neither pertain to, nor convey, property ownership in
a thing.
194
An owner of real property, for example, has rights in rem in the land he owns
and is entitled to enforce a right to exclude all others from trespassing on his land. The
rest of the world owes a specific duty to respect this right of the property owner to
exclude others from encroaching upon the land. The right the property owner exercises
stems from ownership of the land and is attached to the land. Contrast this with a lien on
land as a security to recover payment of a debt. The right to repayment of a debt is an in
personam right against the debtor even though a security interest given as collateral for
the debt may create an interest in rem to secure payment of the debt.
195
The lien holder’s
right is therefore a personal right, or a right in personam, traceable to the creditor-debtor
relationship between lien holder and property owner.
¶48 This distinction between in rem and in personam rights offers insight into the
conceptual differences between literary property and copyright. The author’s natural
right in his expression establishes an entitlement to creative works that excludes everyone
in societyan indefinite class of individualsfrom using the work in a way that would
damage an author’s creative personality or mar its quality and purpose. Protecting an
author’s creative interest by creating a literary property right in his expression contained
in his work creates an in rem right, which means the right is enforceable against the rest
193
1 BLACKSTONE, supra note 177, at 331 (defining an in rem right as “the right to a definite thing
against all the world”).
194
Id. (defining an in personam right as “the right against certain persons, though not to a definite
thing”).
195
In re Rountree, 448 B.R. 389, 407 n.10 (Bankr. E.D. Va. 2011).
Vol. 10:7] Alina Ng
569
of the world. The right would lie on the exclusionary pole of property entitlement that
Professor Smith spoke about.
196
Indeed, it makes sense to protect the author’s creative
interest and personality through an exclusionary rule. The author’s expression cannot be
easily valuedwhile creative works may have a market value in the price that a
consumer would willingly pay, how can anyone put a market price on the expressive
qualities of individuals such as Monet, Beethoven, or Shakespeare, or in more
contemporary times, creators such as Hernan Bas,
197
Joshua Bell,
198
or the late Samuel
Beckett?
199
It would seem more probable that an exclusionary right would protect
creative interests better by requiring that the rest of the world respect the expressive
qualities of the person who created the work. In this sense, the creator’s interest would
be protected by a property rule that, if infringed, should be remedied through the grant of
an injunction.
200
The economic rights that the law grants authors and copyright owners,
including the right to exclusively reproduce, distribute, make derivatives, publicly
perform and display, and digitally transmit the work, are personal rights to use the work
that stem from ownership of copyrightnot the workthat allows for the recovery of
profits from sale and distribution of the work. These rights create entitlements to sell and
distribute the work exclusively and create an in personam right against a specific
individual or entity that infringes this personal right.
¶49 Statutory rights only entail a personal right to recover payment for the use of the
work and not an absolute right to exclude the whole of society from using the work. As
such, when statutory rights are infringed, the proper remedy should be damages that are
consistent with the protection of an entitlement through a liability, and not a property
rule.
201
This makes equal sense toorights to sell and distribute works are more easily
valued through the market by how much the public is willing to pay for the work.
Movies, CDs, individual music downloads through iTunes, books, subscription services,
and other forms of creative works on the market have a somewhat fixed and marginally
variable price. As such, it would be more reasonable to tailor specific governance-type
rules for economic rights on the other end of Professor Smith’s property scale to facilitate
easy transfer and bundling of rights in literary and artistic works for public use.
¶50 These two distinct rights in literary and artistic worksin rem and in personam
rightsensure that creators are granted the autonomy to authentically express and at the
same time effectively disseminate these works to the public through the market. In rem
rights encourage creativity and expression without the constraints that might otherwise
exist if creators fear abuse of their creativity by the public when the work is distributed.
196
See generally Smith, supra note 182.
197
For a collection of Bas’s recent work, see HERNAN BAS & MARK COETZEE, WORKS FROM THE
RUBELL FAMILY COLLECTION, DECEMBER 5, 2007NOVEMBER 28, 2008 (2007).
198
See JOSHUA BELL, http://www.joshuabell.com/ (last visited Jan. 27, 2012) (providing a sample of
Bell’s music).
199
See ANTHONY CRONIN, SAMUEL BECKETT: THE LAST MODERNIST (1997).
200
See Guido Calabresi & A. Douglas Melamed, Property Rules, Liability Rules, and Inalienability:
One View of the Cathedral, 85 HARV. L. REV. 1089, 1105 (1972) (“In our framework, much of what is
generally called private property can be viewed as an entitlement which is protected by a property rule. No
one can take the entitlement to private property from the holder unless the holder sells it willingly and at
the price at which he subjectively values the property.”). As a general rule, an injunction would be
available where an entitlement protected by a property rule is removed from its owner without the owner’s
permission.
201
Id.
NORTHWESTERN JOURNAL OF TE CH NO LO GY AND IN TELLECTUAL PROPERTY [ 20 1 2
570
In personam rights encourage wide dissemination of these works to the public. The
sovereign right of the creator as property owner of a work allows the creator to deny
access to the work based on an absolute right to exclude when he assesses a use to
undermine his creative personality. When the creator of a creative work considers a use
to undermine his rights in such a fashion, he may enforce his exclusionary right against
the infringer. This right is good against the world and applies to an infinite number of
individuals who owe a corresponding duty to refrain from infringing the creative rights of
the author. An economic right, however, does not include the right to exclude as a
property right does, but rather originates from a contractual relationship between the
author and society to make the work available or accessible for market value.
202
As this
distinction between property (in an in rem sense) and copyright (in an in personam sense)
does not appear as doctrine in copyright lawat least not since Donaldson v. Beckett and
Wheaton v. Peters
203
dismissed the notion of literary propertythere is little normative
guidance to provide answers to the question of how authors, copyright owners, and
consumers of literary and artistic works should treat entitlements to literary and artistic
works.
¶51 Statutory rights that create specific rights for copyright owners to use creative
works have been labeled property rights, giving rise to the assumption that such rights are