Content uploaded by David Kolb
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by David Kolb on Dec 15, 2017
Content may be subject to copyright.
Hegelian Buddhist Hypertextual Media Inhabitation
or
Criticism in the Age of Electronic Immersion
(c) David Kolb, 1998
Our moment has absorbed the linguistic turn of modern epistemology, to
move now into a pictorial turn. . . . The challenge to the disciplines of Arts
and Letters is to invent or design the practice of this syncretic writing. . . .
The basic reality of the pictorial turn is that the site of invention of the next
stage in the evolution of writing is taking place within the institution of
entertainment. . . . Unfortunately the media literacy movement still
formulates this moment almost exclusively in terms of literacy, wanting to
make citizens more critical of what they consume in the media. (Gregory
Ulmer)
We know the gamers. The teenager hunched over the controller jumps, weaves, and kicks Super
Mario through the palace and on to a new level, or blasts his way through the Doom asteroid, or
lingers silently with the Myst moods and puzzles. He's immersed in the game.
We know the critics. The New York Times. Siskel and Ebert thumbs up or down. Academics
writing about novels. Plato banishing the poets. The critic stands apart from the game and issues
judgments.
The critics condemn the gamers. Get a life. Get some art. But in the media age will criticism (or
art) survive?
Art has been under pressure from economic and cultural normalizers throughout its history. In
this century, it has been attacked by artists themselves. Duchamp, Warhol, the avant-gardes and
neo-avant-gardes have been joined by philosophers and social theorists in questioning or
transgressing the categories of high art. The institution of criticism has scarcely fared better at
their hands, even as they stake out critical positions.
Art and criticism continue. Art institutions are going strong and are ever more efficiently
administered--not an altogether happy situation. In the culture industry we distinguish
dinnerware from ceramic art, illustration from painting, and soon mundane from artistic virtual
worlds. Such distinctions add market value and class identification. They may even have
intellectual content. But art has difficulties even wanting to maintain distinctions in the media
age.
As for criticism, it is often reduced to either information or showbiz. In the clamor of the media,
do we need critical standards to decide where to spend our time? We certainly need information,
since attention and time are scarce resources to be distributed wisely. Where once the tragedy
festival, the cathedral, or the nobility's display provided a focus for attention, we have an
oversupply of proffered foci. Our communities are not so local nor so homogeneous as before.
Which cathedral or opera or painting or cultural event will we involve ourselves with this week?
There is no one center that gathers "us" and "our" art. So we have lists that tell what events,
objects, experiences--what communities--we can expose ourselves to. Beyond TV Guide waits
The New Yorker, which lists and judges, and then The Nation and The New Criterion and many
others that only judge. Such voices often distinguish between proffered experiences that fit
smoothly into an audience's values and expectations, and those that oppose or challenge them.
That may be taken as a reason to avoid or to embrace the experiences.
I wonder about criticism directed at immersive cultural artifacts. This awkward term is meant to
gather those creations that open an explorable sensory context. Immersive artifacts encourage us
to ignore "outside" stimuli while we explore an offered environment. This might be a computer
game, or a virtual world, or a MUD, or a chat environment with a distinctive graphic atmosphere
and self avatars. We are beginning to build such artifacts, and the science fiction dream of lifelike
immersion will eventually come true.
Tonight, like every night for the past eight months, tens of thousands of
players will log on to Brittania, a fictional online universe. They'll come to
embroider upon make believe lives as healers, fighters, mages, and rogues.
And they'll stay--up to four hours each--because of the seductive quality of
pure immersion. . . . On some nights, more than 14,000 players are logged
on at once. More than half of them log on every day. . . . The towns,
forests, and dungeons of Brittania are more than just intricately rendered;
details are meaningful--you can pick up and read a book on the library
shelf or play a game of checkers in the tavern. . . . Britannia occupies some
32,000 screens, with 15 major cities, 9 shrines, 7 dungeons, and vast
stretches of uncharted wilderness. As more and more players put down
roots, the landscape . . . changes accordingly.
While such computer-aided environments are the most obvious case, there are many other
immersive artifacts. A less interactive immersion is already available with films and TV, the latter
perhaps offering linked constellations of mini-worlds prefigured in the alliances among cable
channels. But high tech is not the only way to create immersion. Live action role playing games
such as Dungeons and Dragons, or Assassin and other extended games played by college
students, use everyday objects and spaces and their players' imagination to immerse their
participants in jointly maintained fictions. Series of books and TV programs may create a world
that is returned to and incites further exploration. In the media rush, some immersive artifacts
become brand names: Star Trek, Star Wars, or Disney stories. These sell repetitions of
themselves. But an immersive artifact is more than a brand name; it offers a world with room to
move about. Technology can enable that exploration in real time, often in the company of other
participants.
Such worlds assert themselves as relative totalities; yet they are part of our temporal experience
of many worlds, and part of the net that is coming into being. Whether we think in terms of a
walled-off world or a linked net of worlds they cause problems for criticism.
From Plato's attack on the Sophists down to postmodern complaints about consumer culture,
critics have worried about the power of rhetoric and image to mold beliefs and values while
suppressing critical examination. Immersive artifacts may manipulate people even more
thoroughly, shutting out the critical voice and keeping their inhabitants busy with no time to
think. To combat this danger, where should the critic stand, and how will the critical voice be
heard? Or is the critic's only choice to stand and speak?
Traditional criticism locates itself at a distance, immune to manipulation because based in clear
principles derived outside the images or artifacts being criticized. Often the critic seeks to
disengage from the object a set of propositions that can be attacked with the tools of logic and
argument. But criticism of art and imagery that reduces them to implicit arguments or networks
of beliefs has never been very successful. Try extracting the content of Shakespeare's Hamlet or
Michelangelo's David into argumentative form. Nor is such criticism adequate for today. The
media influence us on many levels only some of which are amenable to argumentative treatment.
Yet in our age of imagery run riot, there has been a reversal that would have surprised Plato and
Socrates. Rather than remaining the object of distanced criticism, art in this century has itself
developed explicit strategies for questioning attitudes and cultural power. Often these artistic
strategies involve the collaged juxtaposition of abruptly discontinuous fragments of imagery or
belief systems, violating the borders of cultural spheres. Both the heightening of boundaries and
the erasure of boundaries become critical tools within art. Other recent art highlights the
multiplicity behind apparent unities. The critical strategies I suggest in the text resemble these
artistic moves.
Distanced critical analysis does not work so well with immersive artifacts. Traditional criticism
does not easily reach their participants. This might not seem important to people used to
consulting authorities located in separated critical forums, but it is not enough to have distanced
analysis going on in its own enclave for its own specialized audience. How do participants-
consumers of immersive artifacts become more self-aware and make more nuanced judgments
than turning off the tube or modem? This will not happen by increasing the readership of
separated critical forums.
Nor is it likely to happen by inserting traditional critics into the nets or the immersive worlds. If
you want to do critical discussion where the people are--criticism of television on television, or
of hypertext in hypertext, or of a virtual world in the virtual world--you find that immersive
artifacts surround distance and use it for effect. Traditional criticism frames itself as distinct from
its framed object of analysis. But frames have become items within the flow rather than borders
around the fray.
The critic becomes part of the show. The expert's arguments become something to be enjoyed--
the more passionate the better. The spectators view the game, but their allegiances need not be
questioned. Standard critical stances and tools are co-opted. In an age of link buttons and of webs
without edges even separated critical forums can become one more channel in the media show.
This is an extreme version of a perennial problem. Socrates tried and failed to make people
distinguish him from the Sophists; he saw himself as a critic of performances; they saw him as
another dangerous performer. Immersive cultural artifacts make this situation worse because they
segment the common place of public meeting and discussion, fragmenting the agora where
Socrates once could encounter any citizen. Critical efforts to establish an authoritative meta-
agora above the fragmentation produce just one more place to visit.
So, where does the critic stand? Does the critic stand? Or move? The critic can get lost in the
funhouse, immersed in the artifact and playing by its rules, or the critic can wander lost on the
web, or the critic can stay distanced wielding outside principles and norms. These options do not
seem quite right. Can the immersed inhabitant truly judge? Can the wandering critic be heard?
Can the outside critic really know what is being judged? A common solution is the
anthropologist participant-observer-critic who enters an artifact or joins the net armed with
insights and principles from an outside framework. This critic then distributes judgments. Such
outside judgment remains important for many purposes, but I am seeking other modes of critical
interaction.
Traditional critics bring to their task principles formulated outside the language of the work
being criticized. Such principles might concern the nature of art or of culture and discourse. They
might concern goals to which our creations should be subordinated. They might be principles of
form. To apply such principles to a cultural artifact, the critic reformulates or redescribes the
artifact in terms that will connect it with the principles. Formalist critics redescribe the object in
relation to ideal standards. Other critics might reformulate the artifact in a narrative about earlier
masterpieces, or about ongoing themes, or about class struggle or gender domination. One might
judge that a video game reinforces sexual stereotypes or an immersive world pushes the values
of consumption. But I want to suggest other critical modes that can operate inside the immersive
artifacts and on the nets. These other modes do not stand and pass judgment.
There are critical modes of inhabiting that do not reformulate the language of the artifact. They
stay within its language and rules and find there spaces for critical interventions. This is possible
because these modes do not accept a presupposition which lies behind both the fear of uncritical
immersion and the desire to establish critical distance. Both presuppose the control of meaning.
In this phrase the "of" should be understood both as the critic's ability to frame a stable meaning
to be studied, and the meaning's ability to control a world's inhabitants by surrounding them in a
seamless whole. Both presume that meanings can be woven into a single tight simply located
unity. If we question this unity or its stability, then inhabitation cannot be a simple submission; it
will have its distancings and porosities. Modes of criticism can live within these transitions and
distensions rather than on secure meta-platforms.
One such critical inhabitation is familiar enough. The image of the teenage boy immersed in a
video game gives way to the image of the teenage hacker finding ways to manipulate a computer
game. But he doesn't need to be a professed hacker; there are books available that give him
solutions to the Myst puzzles. There are utility programs that let him enjoy the thrill of the game
and also beat or change its rules. MUD wizards embody this doubled inhabitation. They live in
the MUD as both its participants and as its software engineers. This doubled role is a way of
being inside the artifact. Even when they are involved with issues of code and scripting, they are
not so much alternating being inside and outside the game, as they are inside in a way such that
the two aspects of that inhabitation feed off each other: programming the MUD by itself would
not be so fascinating if one did not also have a role in the virtual world, and the role becomes
more vivid as one gains power over the world's infrastructure.
Even passive media such as TV can stimulate such doubling: Soap Opera Digest offers its
readers both a deeper immersion in the plots and a sense of being behind the scenes examining
the production process. The passive media can open very actively shared areas: Star Trek shows
and movies give birth to fan-authored magazines and get-togethers that offer further explorations
of the shared world, looks behind-the-scenes, and a chance to create one's own story variations.
This kind of manipulative involvement allows you to criticize an immersive artifact within its
own parameters. You need not redescribe the artifact's rules and qualities in some distanced
critical discourse. Having power within the world you can make it be more what it already wants
to be. Or you can bend it gradually towards what you want it to be. The will to power is strong in
this mode of inhabitation. Control and self-affirmation are prized, with or without social
interaction. The standard image of the teenage hacker is of a loner, but this kind of activity can
also be intensely cooperative. Whether alone or social, this is not simple immersion, since the
doubled roles provide built-in room for discussion about the world as you inhabit it.
While the hacker can criticize and change arbitrarily large elements, hacker inhabitation does not
easily challenge the overall teleology of the immersive artifact. But this might happen if the
hacker creativity were joined with a sensitivity to the overall tenor of the immersive experience,
the feeling of its life, and the powers and relations it assembles. Does participation in the artifact
increase or weaken one's being? Such Deleuzean questions could direct activities as the hacker
morphs into the artist, gathering experiences and adding to the assemblage of events and
singularities.
Such immanent criticism can give some body to the hacker role. Deleuze's rhetoric of "lines of
flight" and "nomads" suggests fleeing rather than remaking the artifact. But in the case of digital
artifacts the way they are transmitted and constantly re-copied, re-entered, and linked means that
there is less difference between reforming and creating. One linked world can be a part of, and an
addition to, and a criticism of, another world.
Besides the hacker, there are other modes of immanent criticism that do not necessarily intervene
on the infrastructure of the immersive artifact. They motivate different activities within the
artifact, or different relations across nets of artifacts, and they change one's relations in the
artifact's world. Philosophically their presuppositions conflict with one another and with the
Deleuzian approach. It is not my purpose to settle such disputes here, but only to show that
immanent criticism is a real possibility.
Immersive artifacts involve internal motions across transitions, links, and differentiated contents.
Imagine a strongly temporalized inhabitation that lets those moves happen and pays minute
attention to them, yet also lets their borders and connections and flows be as in-betweens but not
as fixed oppositions. The attempts of one content or virtuality to define itself as total or primary
or separate are taken as just that, attempts, to be noted rather than accepted or rejected.
Interaction, infection, interpenetration among the contents or stages are not repressed for the sake
of some tightly held identity, nor insisted upon to attack identity. Imagine a letting-be that refuses
to be drawn along but does not hold back, that allows languages and movements to be
themselves but, because it does not have to be identified with any particular result, is not pulled
about by the unfoldings and not seized or divided in the conflicts. It is an alert seeing where
things go and where they end, what feelings and experiences they create, and where the content
clutches and clings and opposes and tries to be more than it can be. Such an inhabitation does not
rest on any particular content or principle as a base. It is less vulnerable to manipulation and
distraction because it does not grasp at any bait but only observes it as such. It is made possible
by the spacing inherent in temporal experience and the open texture of meanings. Because there
is no clinging to current rules and definitions this mode of inhabitation can accept influences
across borders and echoes from other worlds. The artifact is not reformulated, but one refuses to
be stopped at borders or to cling to official purposes.
The Buddhists have a word for this attitude: non-attachment, neither clutching nor rejecting.
They have a word for the process: mindfulness. They have a word for its effect: compassion. And
a word for what it leads to: skillful means.
This attentive self may not seem critical enough, for it does not stand off and judge. But this
mode of inhabitation criticizes, by noticing them, attempts to grasp or to divide or to force
integration; it refuses to be drawn into desires for totality. It offers resistance without aversion.
Nor need non-attachment be purely contemplative. If intervention happens, it could be like the
Buddha's actions told in the Jataka stories. For instance: in an earlier lifetime two future
Buddhas, Maitreya and Gautama, encountered a starving tigress with her suffering cubs. Rather
than fleeing the snarling beast, Maitreya set off to find food for her. This stretches the rules of the
game for dealing with wild animals. But then, when he returned, Maitreya discovered that
Gautama had taken a still more unusual and decisive action: he had fed himself to the hungry
tigress. Such an action is outrageous according to the norms of the everyday world, and so
challenges our motives and norms. The bodhisattva's action resembles that of the poet making a
new metaphor and changing language. It makes new voices audible and opens up new shapes of
life. This is a different spirit than the will to power of the standard MUD wizard. It might open
up the social practices in shared worlds, making people aware of new possibilities and new ways
of being. This might question the normative frames within which people are acting, or repurpose
their activities and change the stakes.
There are other modes of immanent criticism that are more oriented to the detailed structure of
meanings within an artifact. One such mode could be derived from Hegel. In the introduction to
his Phenomenology of Spirit Hegel raises the age-old problem of the criterion: how can we find
ways to criticize our self-conceptions and cultural productions when the criteria that we invoke
are themselves cultural productions in need of justification by still other criteria? Hegel avoids
the threatened regress by refusing the demand for foundational criteria. He suggests a process of
just looking. Letting a self-conception or a cultural artifact be itself can be a way of letting its
internal tensions and contradictions express themselves. We could raise questions about Hegel's
theory and the necessity of the sequence of self-conceptions he presents, but his mode of
criticism suggests a way to inhabit immersive cultural artifacts. Hegel would say: you don't need
to import criteria from outside, because the artifact already has a built-in self-understanding and
goal. Let this show its dialectical transformations and loss of self-certainty.
Might there be a kind of self-criticism that happens when the artifact tries to be itself? The point
is not that the artifact aims at some effect but falls short. Rather its goal is part of a self-
conception that covertly depends on other relations not yet included within the self-conception.
Falsely absolutizing its situation, a mode of living does not see its constitutive dependencies and
inter-relations. When it tries to realize itself in this narrowly conceived way and world, it fails
and develops an enlarged self-conception. Self-conceptions and cultural forms can reveal their
connections even when they do not know them.
Hegel is more concerned with overall modes of being in the world than with the details of
individual cultural artifacts. He studies the ways that cultures, religions, or artistic genres
develop out of one another. But this is not wholly distinct from studying the shapes taken by
shared inhabitation of virtual worlds, even those as impoverished as current computer games.
Imagine then a mode of letting-be within a space created by the self-conception and grammar
and values implied in the artifact. It makes that space explicit and reveals inbuilt tensions and
motions. It is alert to how the possibilities change as the self-comprehension tries to realize itself.
Inhabiting an immersive artifact in this way would be to stay within the artifact's terms as they
change, adding only a memory and a description of the transitions. This creates a narrative in
which the current self-understanding is only one phase.
The classic over-narrative of this sort is Hegel's story about how the necessary structure of our
being is the coming to self-consciousness of that necessary structure itself. But Hegel is not
alone. There are more recent modes descended from Hegel that also remain with the language or
system of the inhabited artifact but refuse to take that language or system as fixed or final.
One such mode of inhabitation would act in the artifact's world somewhat in the manner in
which Derrida reads a text: attentive to slippages and to covert dependencies on devalued and
supplementary elements. Seek the ways in which the world's unities come about as effects in a
field that these unities do not dominate even though they announce themselves as doing so. The
deconstructive inhabitant looks to perform gestures that put stress on the standard rules and
divisions and make them show their slippages and covert dependencies. She might reuse and
recombine bits of the world in unexpected ways, making unconventional moves or links that
seem inappropriate but reveal hidden connections or put pressure on invisible walls.
This mode might lead to a local equivalent of what hypertext theorists have called "writing all
over the interface." Items that are part of the machinery of an artifact's world (menus, lists, maps,
configuration files, margins, indices, and so on) can be made part of its poetry. This brings the
inhabitant up short against machinery that refuses to stay in its subordinate role, and opens it to
new possibilities. For instance, in Michael Joyce's hypertext short story Woe, the names of the
links on the maps are arranged so that they read as poems. Some of the clues in John McDaid's
portrait-adventure-detective-story-world, Uncle Buddy's Phantom Funhouse, are to be found by
viewing the hypercard coding. In the title essay of his collection,Writing at the Edge, George
Landow collects many transgressive and playful re-uses of what might have been only
background machinery. In artifacts such as MUDs where the infrastructure is available, such
interventions could help question and undercut the naturalness of wholes and transitions that get
taken for granted even in such completely artificial environments.
I have suggested modes of inhabitation that do not reformulate immersive artifacts into a foreign
critical language. Yet in their different ways they refuse to take asserted unities and structures as
final. They sense borders without getting caught in fixed oppositions. They let meanings develop
and cross and criticize their prior selves. They take unities and closures and oppositions as
effects within a relational network rather than as given poles and borders. They react to the
overreaching built into such effects. If closure is an effect rather than a given, these modes of
criticism let this be shown within the net or the artifact's own terms, rather than reformulating the
artifact and subsuming it within another closure set up by exterior principles or narratives.
There are philosophical battles to be fought over the relative priorities and the possible
reductions of one mode to another. I am taking no sides in such disputes here; my point is that
these offer less distanced ways to have critical effects. Deciding which modes are more
fundamental than others is an important task, but such a decision would not reduce them all to a
single mode.
But what kind of effects might these have on the inhabitant-user or on the immersive artifact?
The kinds of critical interventions depend on the degree of interactivity possible in an
environment. The classic video game Pacman has one control, for the direction of movement of
the player's representative on the screen. Speed and activity are not variable. Nintendo and Sega
game units have controls that can vary the direction and timing of several activities. Games that
allow verbal input bring more possibilities of control and intervention, as with Adventure and its
descendants, but they can only parse simple commands. This changes when the computer
becomes a medium of interpersonal interaction. MUDs and MOOs allow indefinitely many kinds
of interventions. As technology for virtual reality matures there will be a similar range from
passive VR rides to mutually created and modifiable virtual worlds.
Because of their relatively free sociality, MUDs and their future VR parallels offer the widest
possibility for critical inhabitation. The active attention suggested above could sensitize users to
dependencies and rigidities built into their world. This could change the inhabitants' stance
within the world, the way they relate to other inhabitants, and eventually the rules and features of
the environment itself. Deviant behavior could make points about accepted norms. Rooms could
be built that open new possibilities. Conventions could be challenged verbally or by other
consciousness-raising maneuvers. MOO software often contains explicit tools for enhancing
debate about the structure and rules of the MOO itself.
A jointly composed hypertext web offers analogous possibilities. For instance, I might criticize
your contributions to the text not by direct argument against them, but by linking them in
unexpected ways or by reusing them in an unexpected context.
When there are fewer modes of input within the artifact, or its infrastructure is not available
except to the hacker, there are still critical possibilities. It may be possible to break the rules and
create new behaviors, or to stimulate a metagame within the game. In a shared game there still
might be occasions for bodhisattva-like or deconstructive moves that go against the teleology of
the game and open up unexpected modes of sociality. Remember Gautama and the tigress. Would
one really try laying down one's arms in a combat game like Doom? This would make little sense
in the solo version, because the computer cannot acknowledge such a move, but even such solos
can prompt reflection. In a social version that allowed enough flexibility in responses, refusing to
fight might challenge the players to interact in new ways. Espen Arseth points out that shared
interactive worlds are not best conceived as "games," since "Any system that must regulate its
discourse by social pressure and convention rather than by clearly defined regulations is more
than a game--both more real and more perilous."
In cases where the artifact's structure and goals are fixed, such as Myst and other solo CD-ROM
adventures, only the hacker mode of inhabitation can change the immersive world itself. But the
other modes I discussed can change the attention of the user, who would be more aware of the
structure of the world and the interplay among its parts and values. These modes emphasize how
the temporality of the experience allows but overflows borders, including the borders of the
game.
Solo computer games may seem far from the world of high art, but the player's concentration on
the game resembles the quasi-religious attitude enjoined on us in front of approved masterpieces.
Just as recent theory undermines that passive reception of art, so it could affect the consumption
of immersive artifacts.
Even games that are quite limited may still offer opportunities for changes in the attitude or
stance of the players. In SimCity the underlying algorithms are chaotic, so there is no one state
that wins the game--the aim is to plan and administer a survivable city. This could lead to
discussion among players about what makes a city livable. In solo video arcade games one has
only limited interactions against implacable opposition. But it is still possible to change one's
own mode of inhabitation, which is never as simple as it might seem: consider how people play
different arcade games one after another, making comparisons and judging the current state of
the art.
Similar linkage effects also occur where inhabitation may appear totally passive, as in channel
and web surfing. Even the most passive immersive artifacts, such as theme park VR rides, still
offer the possibility of different awareness during the experience. That awareness need not be a
constant comparison with what is outside, but could be awareness of interior relations and
spacings and connections, as described above. Such more critical active attention could affect the
evolving experience.
But can changes of attention really have potentially critical effects? Several objections will help
clarify the issues. The first objection is that immersive media are experienced in a state of
distraction. Not because we are doing something else (though some media can be used as
wallpaper) but because the media are immersive, that is, they provide an environment that is
richer than any single focus. The whole experience could be in a state of distraction. Think of a
child in an amusement park running from thrill to thrill without ever fully attending to any one
event because each is so infected with the lure of the next and with the contentless promise of
even greater to come. TV and web surfing can bring this distraction either with the child's
eagerness or with a desultory boredom. Such distraction increases our chances of being
manipulated, since it reduces awareness of meanings or connections other than those now being
fed to us. This shows how immersive technology can inhibit the attention needed by critical
inhabitation.
However, the crucial issue is not distraction but forgetting. Even a distracted state can be
mindfully experienced as such in the Buddhist mode, or inhabited in its transitions and demands.
The real enemy of critical inhabitation is a sequence that drops its past as it goes. Although the
modes of inhabitation I have suggested do not demand a meta-stance outside the artifact, they do
require resolute attentiion to the movement and the temporality of experience. They fight
forgetting and quick thrills.
Hacking gamers or MUD wizards slow down and work on the rules and infrastructure, then
speed up to slalom through part of the world. There is Buddhist attention to qualities and
temporal passage. There can be attention to the quality of the experience, even to its speed and
distraction, if that is what is going on, as well as to the links and associations and carry-overs
across the sequence. Hegelian and deconstructive modes demand more active remembering.
Their attention is not as wide as in the Buddhist mode but is more focused on just those
connections and transformations ignored in the quick thrill.
A second objection is almost the reverse of the first. If distraction leads to under-attention, there
can also be over-attention. Immersive artifacts can get us over-focused on specific problems and
goals, with no slowing down to smell the virtual roses or consider contextual structures and
associations. Or the immediacy of some desired thrill or sexuality can narrow our focus to the
present gratification, forgetting past developments and future consequences.
There is no avoiding the need for awareness on more dimensions than the immediate task or
thrill. But it is possible to focus on the task or thrill without losing sight of its context and
presuppositions, though this takes a more complex temporal rhythm. Criticism takes effort,
though in this case it is not the effort of constructing a separate critical discourse. It takes
advantage of the internal differentiation built into our temporal experience of meanings and
activities.
A third objection comes from a different direction but has the same answer. We can be caught--
the remote control and the mouse both liberate and enslave. They bring flexibility yet predefine
our reach. They empower the subject to say "no" to this or that presentation even as they pin the
subject within their particular network of presentations. The user can turn off the machine, but
while it is connected the administrators of content will try to keep the user within their set of
linked channels or sites. A cow, or a mind, can be controlled by giving it a big enough field to
wander in. The fences remain.
This objection would be more powerful if we were indeed caught within a single artifact. But if
the remote control and the mouse pin us within a labyrinth, it already contains multiple worlds
and artifacts. That multiplicity and its border crossings can challenge pre-planned meanings and
excitations. Even if there were no choice at all, that would still not forbid critical attention. John
Cage composed several pieces of music in which radio stations were tuned in and out on a fixed
schedule. Listeners heard segments of whatever happened to be being broadcast on those
stations. Cage created attention and connection. You might call his creation a kind of controlled
surfing, but it encouraged a complex attention. The individual segments were heard three ways at
once: as particular sounds with their timbres and qualities, as recognizable types of programs,
and as segments in Cage's work that played off one another and generated meanings across the
discontinuities within the piece.
If one were to channel or web surf with such dimensions of attention, new meanings would be
created by the juxtapositions even if one could not choose the elements in the series. There is no
control of meaning, so even channel surfing can generate new meaning across its conflicts and
contrasts. What is needed is attention within the sequence itself, rather than instant forgetting in
the search for thrills.
What I have been doing, in effect, is trying to move the conception of immersive media toward
the kind of attentive literacy sought for the links and crossings of hypertext. Hypertext offers
more than a sequence of on-off commands with the remote. There is always linking, mixture, and
memory. These can be experienced attentively without being formulated in another language.
Further technological advances will allow active linking rather than passive reception, with
individual or group creation of new content. This is already beginning on the web with those
millions of home pages. Imagine them becoming home worlds. Linking would become even
more a mode of expression and creativity. We might have something resembling what Vannevar
Bush prophesied: worlds that were trails of references, collections, critical comparisons--but all
of these involving much more than just the information that was Bush's concern. Imagine the
construction of immersive collages, virtual space conceptual art installations including one
another, new meta-artworks, super-Rauschenbergs using duplicative and linking technology.
These would benefit from the kind of critical inhabitations I have been discussing.
With the technology available in the past hundred years, art developed the self-critical strategies
already mentioned for examining its own conventions, institutions, and context. Those
techniques of self-reference, collaged juxtaposition, disconnection and impertinent connection,
ironic reuse could well become tools of self-expression and self-criticism on a more mundane
level. Advertisements are already re-forming our sensitivities in that direction.
You might object that it is more likely that all the links will be premade corporate products. I
think not. But even in that worst case remember John Cage. There would still be no total control
by meaning, nor control of the generation of meaning. There will always be temporal sequence,
and its mixture and border crossings. There can still be critical attention to meaning beyond what
is intended by the makers. So there will always be room at least for self-criticism of the user, and
possibly for unexpected interventions against the grain.
The modes I have described do not do away with the need for distanced argumentative criticism.
Political and cultural criticism may need to back off from immersive artifacts and reformulate
them within larger narratives and critical vocabularies. But that is not the only way. Meaning
cannot be controlled; it opens new possibilities inside the immersive artifact. I have suggested
modes that invoke this openness of meaning and the temporality of our experience. The allow the
creativity of impertinent moves. The critical sensitivities involve more than sets of propositions
and their inferential connections. We will be impoverished if we envision all criticism on the
model of a logical argument, or on the model of a judicial examination.
I began with two images, the gamer and the critic. Here is another: the writer creates a
hypermedia novel or cyberdrama, hoping the readers will become immersed, but it is also an
active hypertext, so readers are expected to add to the web. The critic enters the web and loses
her meta-position, but she joins everyone in the possibility of reflection and the movements of
meaning.