ArticlePDF Available

Robert Rosen’s anticipatory systems

Authors:
  • Download my publications at

Abstract and Figures

Robert Rosen instituted a rigorously mathematical treatise on the subject of anticipatory systems, the theory of which provides the conceptual basis for foresight studies. This article is an expository introduction[1]. The ubiquity of anticipatory systems in Nature is explained. An anticipatory system’s present behavior depends upon ‘‘future states’’ or ‘‘future inputs’’ generated by an internal predictive model. This apparent violation of causality is, however, simply an illusion. The topic of anticipatory systems in particular, and methods of relational biology in general, provide important tools for forecasting and planning.
Content may be subject to copyright.
Robert Rosen’s anticipatory systems
A.H. Louie
Abstract
Purpose This article aims to be an expository introduction to Robert Rosen’s anticipatory systems, the
theory of which provides the conceptual basis for foresight studies.
Design/methodology/approach The ubiquity of anticipatory systems in nature is explained.
Findings Causality is not violated by anticipatory systems, and teleology is an integral aspect of
science.
Practical implications A terse exposition for a general readership, such as the present article, by
definition cannot get into too many details. For further exploration the reader is referred to the recent
book More than Life Itself by the author.
Originality/value The topic of anticipatory systems in particular, and methods of relational biology in
general, provide important tools for foresight studies. It is the author’s hope that this brief glimpse into the
world of relational biology piques the interest of some readers to pursue the subject further.
Keywords Research, Biology, Philosophical concepts
Paper type Conceptual paper
Preview
Robert Rosen instituted a rigorously mathematical treatise on the subject of anticipatory
systems, the theory of which provides the conceptual basis for foresight studies. This article
is an expository introduction[1]. The ubiquity of anticipatory systems in Nature is explained.
An anticipatory system’s present behavior depends upon ‘‘future states’’ or ‘‘future inputs’
generated by an internal predictive model. This apparent violation of causality is, however,
simply an illusion. The topic of anticipatory systems in particular, and methods of relational
biology in general, provide important tools for forecasting and planning.
Robert Rosen
Robert Rosen (1934-1998) was for many years one of the world’s foremost
theoretical biologists. He authored some 250 research papers and a dozen books,
concerned with both the development and the implications of the theory underlying
biological processes.
He very early began to develop the concept that biology should be based on notions of
function rather than structure, and that it was function that was of primary concern in
understanding the basis of life and of organism. He subsequently explored the possibilities
of building function-based models of biological processes. These turned out to be very
different from, and far more general than, reductionistic treatments based on structural
ideas. His teacher Nicolas Rashevsky, who initiated the first definitive study in this area, had
termed this approach ‘‘relational biology’’.
Among his many publications, these three books may be considered The Rosen Trilogy:
PAGE 18
j
foresight
j
VOL. 12 NO. 3 2010, pp. 18-29, Q Emerald Group Publishing Limited, ISSN 1463-6689 DOI 10.1108/14636681011049848
A.H. Louie is a
mathematical biologist
based in Ottawa, Canada.
The author gave two sessions of
tutorial on anticipatory systems
at FuMee 1 (2008) in Rovereto,
Italy. This article is a
condensation and transcription
into prose of these sessions’
PowerPoint slides. The subject is
Robert Rosen’s Anticipatory
Systems. The author's role is
that of an expositor, so what is
new in this article is the author's
presentation and not the
scientific content itself, the
originality of which, naturally,
belongs to Rosen. Aristotle said:
“When a thing has been said
once it is hard to say it
differently.” Some repetition of
what Rosen has already written
(which is worthy of repetition in
any case) is unavoidable. Let the
acknowledgement “Robert
Rosen said it first.” be the
disclaimer. The compilation,
interpretation, and delivery
contained in these two tutorial
sessions and hence this article,
however, are the author's own.
1. Fundamentals of Measurement and Representation of Natural Systems (1978);
2. Anticipatory Systems: Philosophical, Mathematical & Methodological Foundations
(1985); and
3. Life Itself: A Comprehensive Inquiry into the Nature, Origin, and Fabrication of Life (1991).
Therein lies the comprehensive treatise of Rosen’s science. (Henceforth I shall use the
abbreviation AS when referring to the book Anticipatory Systems, and use the term spelt out
in full when referring to the object ‘anticipatory system’’ itself[2].)Figure 1
‘What should we do now?’
To one degree or another, this ‘question of ought is the same question the biologist, the
economists, the political scientists, the urban planners, the futurists, and many others want
to know. However different the contexts in which these questions are posed, they are all alike
in their fundamental concern with the making of policy, and the associated notions of
forecasting the future and planning for it; in short, foresight. What is sought, in each of these
diverse areas, is in effect a technology of decision-making. But underlying any technology
there must be an underlying foundation of basic principles: a science, a theory. What is the
theory underlying a technology of policy generation? Rosen proposed that this is the theory
of anticipatory systems. Note that the concept of ‘‘anticipation’’ had not been new (see, for
example, Roberto Poli’s article in this issue), but the systemic study of anticipation was new
when Rosen wrote the book on it.
Now what is an anticipatory system? Here is Robert Rosen’s definition:
An anticipatory system is a natural system that contains an internal predictive model of itself and
of its environment, which allows it to change state at an instant in accord with the model’s
predictions pertaining to a later instant.
Note, in contrast, that a reactive system can only react, in the present, to changes that have
already occurred in the causal chain, while an anticipatory systems present behavior
involves aspects of past, present, and future. The presence of a predictive model serves
Figure 1
VOL. 12 NO. 3 2010
j
foresight
j
PAGE 19
precisely to pull the future into the present; a system with a ‘‘good’ model thus behaves in
many ways as if it can anticipate the future. Model-based behavior requires an entirely new
paradigm, an ‘anticipatory paradigm’’, to accommodate it. This paradigm extends but
does not replace the ‘reactive paradigm’ which has hitherto dominated the study of
natural systems. The ‘anticipatory paradigm’ allows us a glimpse of new and important
aspects of system behavior.
The idea of anticipation in science is controversial, because of ‘objective causality’
pronounced in the ‘‘Zeroth Commandment’’:
Thou shalt not allow future state to affect present change of state.
Anticipation is almost always excluded from study at every level of system theory[3]. The
reasons for this rest on certain basic methodological presuppositions which have underlain
‘science’ in the past few centuries:
B
the essential basis on which ‘‘genuine scientific inquiry’’ rests is the principle of causality
(which an anticipatory systems apparently violates); and
B
‘true objective science’ cannot be argued from final cause (but an anticipatory system
seems to embody a form of teleology).
We shall debunk these two characterizations of science in some detail below. But let us first
consider a few examples of anticipatory systems.
Biology is replete with situations in which organisms can generate and maintain internal
predictive models of themselves and their environments, and use the predictions of these
models about the future for purpose of control in the present. Much, if not most, biological
behavior is model-based in this sense. This is true at every level, from the molecular to the
cellular to the physiological to the behavioral, and this is true in all parts of the biosphere,
from microbes to plants to animals to ecosystems. But it is not restricted to the biological
universe; anticipatory behavior at the human level can be multiplied without end, and may
seem fairly trivial: examples range from avoiding dangerous encounters, to any strategy in
sports, and even to Linus’s waiting for the Great Pumpkin in the pumpkin patch on
Halloween[4]. Model-based behavior is the essence of social, economic, and political
activity. An understanding of the characteristics of model-based behavior is thus central to
any technology we wish to develop to control such systems, or to modify their model-based
behavior in new ways.
It should be clarified that anticipation in Rosen’s usage does not refer to an ability to ‘see’ or
otherwise sense the immediate or the distant future there is no prescience or psychic
phenomena suggested here. Instead, Rosen suggests that there must be information about
self, about species, and about the evolutionary environment, encoded into the organization
of all living systems. He observes that this information, as it behaves through time, is capable
of acting causally on the organism’s present behavior, based on relations projected to be
applicable in the future. Thus, while not violating time established by external events,
organisms seem capable of constructing an internal surrogate for time as part of a model
that can indeed be manipulated to produce anticipation. In particular, this ‘internal
surrogate of time’ must run faster than real time. It is in this sense that degrees of freedom in
internal models allow time its multi-scaling and reversibility to produce new information. The
predictive model in an anticipatory system must not be equivocated to any kind of
‘certainty’ (even probabilistically) about the future. It is, rather, an assertion based on a
model that runs in a faster time scale. The future still has not yet happened: the organism has
a model of the future, but not definitive knowledge of future itself.
Feedforward
Anticipatory behavior involves the concept of feedforward[5], rather than feedback. The
distinction between feedforward and feedback is important, and is as follows.
The essence of feedback control is that it is error-actuated; in other words, the stimulus to
corrective action is the discrepancy between the system’s actual present state and the state
PAGE 20
j
foresight
j
VOL. 12 NO. 3 2010
the system should be in. Stated otherwise, a feedback control system must already be
departing from its nominal behavior before control begins to be exercised.
In a feedforward system, on the other hand, system behavior is preset, according to some
model relating present inputs to their predicted outcomes. The essence of a feedforward
system, then, is that the present change of state is determined by an anticipated future state,
derived in accordance with some internal model of the world.
We know from introspection that many, if not most, of our own conscious activities are
generated in a feedforward fashion. We typically decide what to do now in terms of what we
perceive will be the consequences of our action at some later time. The vehicle by which we
anticipate is in fact a model, which enables us to pull the future into the present. We change
our present course of action in accordance with our model’s prediction. The stimulus for our
action is not simply the present percepts; it is the prediction under these conditions. I
emphasize again that ‘prediction’ is not prescience, but simply ‘output of an anticipatory
model’’. Stated otherwise, our present behavior is not just reactive; it is also anticipatory.
Model
The essential novelty in Rosen’s approach to anticipatory systems is that he considers them
as single entities, and relates their overall properties to the character of the models they
contain. There have, of course, been many approaches to planning, forecasting, and
decision-making, but these tend to concentrate on tactical aspects of model synthesis and
model deployment in specific circumstances. Rosen’s AS is not at all concerned with tactics
of this type. It deals with, instead, the behavioral correlates arising throughout a system
simply from the fact that present behavior is generated in terms of a predicted future
situation. It does not consider, for instance, the various procedures of extrapolation and
correlation that dominate much of the literature concerned with decision-making in an
uncertain or incompletely defined environment. AS is concerned rather with global
properties of model-based behavior, regardless of how the model is generated, or indeed of
whether it is a ‘good’’ model or not. In other words, AS looks at properties of an anticipatory
system, not how to build an anticipatory system.
A model, defined formally, is a commutative functorial[6] encoding and decoding between
two systems in a modelling relation[7]. Intuitively, we may just take the common-usage
meaning of ‘model’’:
B
a simplified description of a system put forward as a basis for theoretical understanding;
B
a conceptual or mental representation of a thing; or
B
an analog of different structure from the system of interest but sharing an important set of
functional properties.
Robert Rosen closed AS with these words:
The study of anticipatory systems thus involves in an essential way the subjective notions of good
and ill, as they manifest themselves in the models which shape our behavior. For in a profound
sense, the study of models is the study of man; and if we can agree about our models, we can
agree about everything else.
The crux in the formulation of a theory of anticipatory behavior is the conception of ‘‘model’’.
What is the nature of the relation between two systems that allows us to assert that one of
them is a model for the other? The essence of this property is that we may learn something
new about a system of interest by studying a different system that is its model. Roughly, the
essence of a modeling relation consists of specifying an encoding and a corresponding
decoding of particular system characteristics into corresponding characteristics of another
system, in such a way that implication in the model corresponds to causality in the system.
Thus in a precise mathematical sense a theorem about the model becomes a prediction
about the system. When these remarks are rigorously pursued, the result is a general theory
of the modeling relation. This theory has many important implications: to more general
situations of metaphor, to the way in which distinct models of a given system are related to
VOL. 12 NO. 3 2010
j
foresight
j
PAGE 21
each other, and to the manner in which distinct systems with a common model may be
compared.
The situation may be represented by Figure 2.
A modeling relation exists between the natural system N and the formal system F when there
is a congruence between their entailment structures. A necessary condition for congruence
involves all four arrows, and may be stated as ‘whether one follows path c or paths 1, i,
d
in
sequence, one reaches the same destination’’. Expressed graphically, this is:
!
¼
!
1
!
i
!
d
:
If this relation is satisfied, we say that F is a simulation of N.
If, in addition, inferential entailment i is itself entailed by the encoding 1 of causal entailment
c, i.e., if:
ð
!
c Þ
!
1 ð
!
i Þ
is also satisfied, then we say that F is a model of N, and N is a realization of F.
A simulation of a process provides an alternate description of the entailed effects, whereas a
model is a special kind of simulation that additionally also provides an alternate description
of the entailment structure of the mapping representing the process itself. It is, in particular,
easier to obtain a simulation than a model of a process.
Examples are in order. For instance, Claudius Ptolemy’s Almagest (c. 150
AD) contained an
account for the apparent motion of many heavenly bodies. The Ptolemaic system of
epicycles and deferents, later with adjustments in terms of eccentricities and equant points,
provided good geometric simulations, in the sense that there were enough parameters in
defining the circles so that any planetary or stellar trajectory could be represented
reasonably accurately by these circular traces in the sky. Despite the fact that Ptolemy did
not give any physical reasons why the planets should turn about circles attached to circles in
arbitrary positions in the sky, his simulations remained the standard cosmological view for
1,400 years. Celestial mechanics has since, of course, been progressively updated with
better theories of Copernicus, Kepler, Newton, and Einstein. Each improvement explains
more of the underlying principles of motion, and not just the trajectories of motion. The
universality of the Ptolemaic epicycles is nowadays regarded as an extraneous
mathematical artifact irrelevant to the underlying physical situation, and it is for this
reason that a representation of trajectories in terms of them can only be regarded as
simulation, and not as model.
As another example, a lot of the so-called ‘‘models’ in the social sciences are really just
sophisticated kinds of curve-fitting, i.e. simulations. These activities are akin to the assertion
that since a given curve can be approximated by a polynomial, it must be a polynomial.
Stated otherwise, curve-fitting without a theory of the shape of the curve is simulation; model
requires understanding of how and why a curve takes its shape.
Simulation describes; model explains.
Figure 2 The prototypical modeling relation
PAGE 22
j
foresight
j
VOL. 12 NO. 3 2010
Note that in common usage, the two words ‘‘simulation’ and ‘‘model’’ are often synonyms.
Some, alternatively, use ‘model’ to mean mathematical theory, and ‘simulation’ to mean
numerical computation. What I have presented above, however, are Robert Rosen’s
definitions, in precise category-theoretic terms, of these two words.
Natural law
It can be commonly agreed that no one, whether experimenter, observer, or theorist, does
science at all without believing that nature obeys laws or rules, and that these natural
regularities can be at least partly grasped by the mind. That nature obeys laws is often
subsumed under the notion of causality. The articulation of these causal laws or relationships
means, in brief, that one can establish a correspondence between events in the world and
propositions in some appropriate language, such that the causal relations between events
are exactly reflected in implication relations between corresponding propositions.
‘Law of Nature’’, or Natural Law, consists of two independent parts. The first of these
comprises a belief, or faith, that what goes on in the external world is not entirely arbitrary or
whimsical. Stated in positive terms, this is a belief that successions of events in that world are
governed by definite relations, termed causality. Without such a belief, there could be no
such thing as science. Causality and general ideas of entailment guarantee a kind of
regularity that one expects in nature and in science. Roughly, we are guaranteed that the
same causes imply the same effects. Therefore, in the causal world, one sees the operation
of laws in terms of which the events themselves may be understood.
The second constituent of Natural Law is a belief that the causal relations between events
can be grasped by the mind, articulated and expressed in language. This aspect of Natural
Law posits a relation between the syntactic structure of a language and the semantic
character of its external referents. This relation is different in kind from entailment within
language or formalisms (i.e. implication or inference, which relate purely linguistic entities),
and from entailment between events (i.e. causal relations between things in the external
world). Natural Law, therefore, posits the existence of entailments between events in the
external world and linguistic expressions about those events. Stated otherwise, it posits a
kind of congruence between implication (a purely syntactic feature of languages or
formalisms) and causality (a purely semantic, extra-linguistic constituent of Natural Law).
Summarily, Natural Law makes two separate assertions about the self and its ambience:
1. The succession of events or phenomena that we perceive in the ambience is not arbitrary:
there are relations (e.g. causal relations) manifest in the world of phenomena.
2. The posited relations between phenomena are, at least in part, capable of being
perceived and grasped by the human mind; i.e. by the cognitive self.
Science depends in equal parts on these two separate prongs of Natural Law. Part 1, that
causal order exists, is what permits science to exist in the abstract, and part 2, that this
causal order can be imaged by implicative order, is what allows scientists to exist. Both are
required.
In short, the logic, order, and regularity of the universe are intelligible.
Causality
The concept of anticipation has been rejected out of hand in formal approaches to system
theory, because they appear to violate causality. We have always been taught that we must
not allow present changes of state to depend on future states; the future cannot affect the
present. We now show that this restriction is simply an artifact of the Newtonian reactive
paradigm.
However much the languages that we use to construct system models of whatever kind may
differ, in detail and emphasis, they all represent paraphrases of the language of Newtonian
VOL. 12 NO. 3 2010
j
foresight
j
PAGE 23
mechanics. Two separate ingredients are necessary for the process of system description;
they are:
1. a specification of what the system is like at any particular instant of time, with the
associated concept of the instantaneous state of the system; and
2. a specification of how the system changes state, as a function of present or past states
and of the forces imposed on the system, i.e. the dynamics.
The characterization of the instantaneous state involves the specification of an appropriate
set of state variables, while the characterization of how the system changes state involves a
specification of the equations of motion of the system. Another name of this Newtonian
reactive system is ‘‘dynamical system’’.
Succinctly, the assumptions of the Newtonian paradigm are:
1. A physical system is defined by its constitutive parameters, and is manifested as a
sequence of events in space and time. A system behavior is some property of such a
sequence.
2. The universe of events can be effectively partitioned into two distinct domains.
3. The first domain is characterized by regularity and order the province of natural law.
4. In the second domain no perceptible regularity is discernible the realm of initial
conditions.
5. Physics ¼ system laws þ initial conditions.
In this context, causality is ‘‘past implies present, and present implies future’’.
As long as we restrict ourselves to Newtonian dynamical equations under these
assumptions, which inextricably involve traditional view of causality, anticipatory systems
are clearly excluded from discussion. However, when we proceed to consider systems in
terms of relations between input-output pairs of mappings of time, we find that causality
needs only dictate natural regularities relating causes and effects, without necessarily
including a built-in forward-temporal restraint. Thus anticipatory behavior not only is
possible, but, because general input-output relations contain Newtonian dynamics as
special cases, it is actually less restrictive and therefore in some sense generic.
Teleology
We now consider the assertion that anticipatory systems involve teleology or final causes in
an essential way, and thus must be excluded from science. Feedforward behavior seems
telic, or goal-directed. The goal is in fact built in as part of the model that connects predicted
future states and present changes of state. But the very suggestion that a behavior is
goal-directed is repellent to many scientists, who regard it as a violation of the Newtonian
paradigm.
The formulation of this ‘teleophobic’ assertion goes back to Aristotle’s conception of
causality, in which four distinct kinds of ‘causes’ for any physical event are recognized.
Adapting this Aristotelian parlance to the above discussion, if we regard the current value of
an observable at an instant as such an event, and if we allow only Newtonian dynamical laws
to express relations between events, then we may say that:
B
the initial conditions are the material cause of the event;
B
the constitutive parameters of the system are its efficient cause; and
B
the system laws are its formal cause.
This assignment of three of the causes exhausts all the quantities and relations in the
Newtonian expression; hence the event can have no room for the fourth, final cause. This
observation is essentially the entire basis for asserting that scientific explanation (which is
posited in advance to be exclusively embodied in reactive relations) cannot involve final
PAGE 24
j
foresight
j
VOL. 12 NO. 3 2010
causes. Moreover, since final causes presuppose future states and/or future inputs, we must
according to this argument a fortiori exclude anticipatory systems.
However, already in physics we find numerous situations in which present events appear to
be determined by subsequent ones. Of course, such situations are not directly governed by
reactive laws. An obvious example is any system which obeys an ‘optimality principle’’,
such as Fermat’s principle in optics or Hamilton’s principle in mechanics; here the actual
path described by a physical process is as much determined by its terminal state as by its
initial one. A similar teleological aspect can be seen in Le Chatelier’s principle in physical
chemistry and in Lenz’s law of electricity. These principles express that in case of
disturbance, the system develops forces that counteract the disturbance and restore a state
of equilibrium; they are derivations from the principle of minimum effect. Further, the
transition of a system to a state of ‘minimal free energy’’, ‘maximum entropy’’, etc., involves
a tacit characterization of such a state as the final cause of motion toward it. Precisely the
same situation is encountered in probability theory, where the family of convergence
arguments, collectively called the law of large numbers, asserts that limiting probabilities
exert an apparent attractive force on the successive steps of a random process, even
though those steps are independent. In sum, even though dynamical laws in physics
express conventional views regarding causality, they are mathematically equivalent to
principles in which a future state acts retroactively on a present change of state.
We should note that hidden teleology by itself is not sufficient to define an anticipatory
system. An optimality- or otherwise determined future still constitutes a reactive system. An
anticipatory system needs to use the information from its predictive model to change the
present, so that a possibly different future from one that is originally predicted may result.
Anticipatory system
Having analyzed and dispensed with those formal arguments adduced to justify excluding
anticipatory systems from system theory, let us now be positive, and construct (necessarily
informally in this introductory exposition) a sample anticipatory system with some synthetic
arguments.
Let us suppose that we are given a system S that is of interest. S may be an individual
organism, or an ecosystem, or a social or economic system. For simplicity we shall suppose
that S is an ordinary (i.e. non-anticipatory) dynamical system. As we have seen, this fact
allows us to make predictions about the future states of S, from a knowledge of an initial state
and of the system input. Indeed, the dynamical law itself already expresses a predictive
model of S.
But let us embody a predictive model of S explicitly in another physical system M. We require
that if the trajectories of S are parameterized by real time, then the corresponding
trajectories of M are parameterized by a time variable that goes faster than real time. Thus,
any observable on M serves as a predictor for the behavior of some corresponding
observable of S at that later instant.
We shall now allow M and S to be coupled; i.e. allow them to interact in specific ways. For the
simplest model, we may simply allow the output of an observable on M to be an input to the
system S. This then creates a situation in which a future state of S is controlling the present
state transition in S. But this is precisely what we have characterized above as anticipatory
behavior. It is clear that the above construction does not violate causality; indeed, we have
invoked causality in an essential way in the concept of a predictive model, and hence in the
characterization of the system M. Although the composite system (M þ S) is completely
causal, it nevertheless will behave in an anticipatory fashion.
Similarly, we may construct a system M with outputs that embody predictions regarding the
inputs to the system S. In that case, the present change of state of S will depend upon
information pertaining to future inputs to S. Here again, although causality is in no sense
violated, our system will exhibit anticipatory behavior.
VOL. 12 NO. 3 2010
j
foresight
j
PAGE 25
From the above remarks, we see that anticipatory behavior will be generated in any system
that:
B
contains an internal predictive model of itself and/or of its environment; and
B
is such that its dynamical law uses the predictions of its internal model in an essential way.
From this point of view, anticipatory systems can be viewed as a special class of adaptive
control systems.
There are many another modes of coupling, discussed in AS, which will allow S to affect M,
and which will amount to updating or improving the model system M on the basis of the
activity of S. We shall for the present example suppose simply that the system M is equipped
with a set E of effectors that operate either on S itself or on the environmental inputs to S,in
such a way as to change the dynamical properties of S. We thus have a situation of the type
shown in Figure 3, formulated as an input-output system.
An anticipatory system S entails the following:
B
S possesses a model subsystem M;
B
there is an orthogonality between the model M and the collection of observables of
S , M;
B
the rate of change (the adaptation) of observables of S , M depends on M;
B
the effect of the model M creates a discrepancy S would have behaved differently if M
were absent; and
B
M is a predictive model by looking at a present state of M, one obtains information
pertaining to a future state of S.
Errors
A natural system is almost always more than any model of it. In other words, a model is, by
definition, incomplete. As a consequence, under appropriate circumstances, the behavior
predicted by a model will diverge from that actually exhibited by the system. This provides
the basis for a theory of error and system failure on the one hand, and for an understanding
of emergence on the other. It is crucial to understand this aspect in any comprehensive
theory of control based on predictive models.
Anticipation can fail in its purpose. A study of how planning can go wrong is illustrative;
indeed the updating of models from lessons learned is the essence of an anticipatory
system. The causes of errors in anticipation may be categorized into:
B
bad models;
B
bad effectors; and
B
side effects.
Figure 3 Anticipatory system
PAGE 26
j
foresight
j
VOL. 12 NO. 3 2010
A bad model can result from technical, paradigmatical, or state-correspondence errors, all
due to improper functorial imaging of mappings. In short, faulty encodings lead to faulty
models. A proper choice of the internal predictive model M and the fine tuning of its updating
processes are evidently crucial to an anticipatory system’s success.
An effector E is defective when it is incapable of steering S, when it cannot appropriately
manipulate the state variables, or simply when it fails to accordingly react to the information
from M. Thus the careful construction of an anticipatory system also depends on the
selection, design, and programming of the effector system E, as well as on the partitioning of
the ‘‘desirable’ and ‘‘undesirable’’ regions of response.
Side effects arise because, essentially, structures have multiple functions and functions may
be carried out by multiple structures. Combined with the fact of incomplete models, the
consequence is that, in general, an effector E will have additional effects on S to those
planned, and the planned modes of interaction between E and S will be modified by these
extraneous effects.
The diagnosis and treatment of erroneous anticipatory systems are frequently analogous to
the procedures used in neurology and psychology.
We may further ask, how does a system generate predictive models? On this point we may
invoke some general ontogenic principles, by means of natural selection, to achieve some
understanding. And finally, given a system that employs a predictive model to determine its
present behavior, how should we observe the system so as to determine the nature of the
model it employs?
Lessons from biology
The conscious generation and deployment of predictive models for the purpose of control
are some of the basic intuitive characteristics of intelligence. However, precisely the same
type of model-based behavior appears constantly at lower levels of biological organization
as well. For instance, many simple organisms are negatively phototropic; they tend to move
away from light. Now darkness in itself is physiologically neutral; it has no intrinsic biological
significance (at least for non-photosynthetic organisms). However, darkness tends to be
correlated with other characteristics that are not physiologically neutral, such as moisture
and the absence of sighted predators. The tropism can be regarded biologically as an
exploitation of this correlation, which is in effect a predictive model about the environment.
Likewise, the autumnal shedding of leaves and other physiological changes in plants, which
are clearly an adaptation to winter conditions, are not cued by ambient temperature, but
rather by day length. There is an obvious correlation between the shortening day, which
again is physiologically neutral in itself, and the subsequent appearance of winter
conditions, which again constitutes a predictive model exploited for purposes of adaptive
control. Innumerable other examples of such anticipatory preadaptation can be found in the
biosphere, ranging from the simplest of tropisms to the most complex hormonal regulation
mechanisms in physiology.
Since feedforward or anticipatory control is as ubiquitous as it seems to be, a number of
fundamental new questions are posed to us. Among them are the following. Can we truly say
we understand the behavior of such a system if we do not know the model employed by the
system? How is it possible to determine the character of that model, in terms of measurements
or observations performed on the system? More generally, under what circumstances is it
possible for a system to contain an internal model of its world? What relations must exist
between a set of indicators (environmental signals) and system effectors that will allow an
effective feedforward control model to be constructed? How can the behaviors of different
systems, perceiving the same set of circumstances but equipped with different models, be
integrated? (This last is essentially the problem of conflict and conflict resolution.)
The questions just raised bear directly on the present search for forecasting and planning
technologies to guide our behavior in the political, social and economic realms. Tacit in this
search is the perception that our society and its institutions can no longer function effectively in
VOL. 12 NO. 3 2010
j
foresight
j
PAGE 27
a cybernetic or reactive mode; it must somehow be transformed into a predictive or
anticipatory mode. That is, it must become more like an organism, and less like a machine[8].
In dealing with various challenges in our world, properties of biological systems will provide
crucial insights. Robert Rosen was fond of saying ‘the first lesson to be learned from biology
is that there are lessons to be learned from biology’’. Indeed, considered in an evolutionary
context, biology represents a vast encyclopedia of how to solve complex problems
effectively; and also of how not to solve them. Biology provides us with existence proofs, and
specific examples, of cooperative rather than competitive activities on the part of large and
diverse populations. Biology is the science of the commonality of relations, and relationships
contain the essential meaning of life. These insights represent natural resources to be
harvested, resources perhaps even more important to our ultimate survival than the more
tangible biological resources of food and energy. But to reap such a harvest, we need to
fabricate proper tools. It is my belief that the conceptions of nature arising from relational
biology will help us learn how to make it so.
Notes
1. A terse exposition for a general readership, such as the present article, by definition cannot get into
too many details. It is the author’s hope that this brief glimpse into the world of relational biology
piques the interest of some readers to pursue the subject further. For further exploration the reader
is referred to the recent book More Than Life Itself by the author (Louie, 2009).
2. Rosen wrote AS in the first six months of 1979. I became his PhD student just as he finished the first
draft. I was one of the first to read it, so I have been associated with the subject right from the
beginning. For a variety of external reasons, the book was not published until 1985. The Pergamon
Press book is long out of print, although one may be able to find copies in university libraries (or from
a resourceful used-book dealer).
3. Note the singular form system in ‘system theory’’: not ‘‘systems theory’’. This last usage is an error
that became accepted when it had been repeated often enough, a very example of ‘‘accumulated
wrongs become right’’. Just think of ‘set theory’’, ‘group theory’’, ‘number theory’’, ‘category
theory’’, etc. Of course one studies more than one object in each subject! Indeed, one would say in
the possessive ‘theory of sets’’, ‘‘theory of groups’’, ‘theory of numbers’’, ‘theory of categories’’,
. . .; one says ‘theory of systems’ for that matter. But the point is that when the noun of a
mathematical object (or indeed any noun) is used as adjective, one does not use the plural form.
4. Just in case some readers may not be aware of the reference: Linus is a character from Charles
M. Schulz’s Peanuts (q United Feature Syndicate, Inc.), the most popular comic strip in the world for
50 years. Linus gets one holiday ahead of himself, and anticipates the arrival of the Great Pumpkin
on Halloween: ‘On Halloween night, the Great Pumpkin rises out of the pumpkin patch, and flies
through the air with his bag of toys for all the good children in the world!’’. This is an example of an
anticipatory system in which the predictive model is somewhat faulty, and the faster time line goes a
little too fast. For a quick review one may seek out a video of the 1966 television special ‘It’s the
Great Pumpkin, Charlie Brown!’’.
5. A more proper contrastive word of ‘‘feedback’ should have been ‘‘feedforth’’, but ‘feedforward’ is,
alas, ingrained terminology in control system theory.
6. For the readers not acquainted with the word ‘functorial’’ (it being a concept from the mathematical
theory of categories), they may simply take it to mean ‘pertaining to a mapping that takes into
account the processes involved in addition to inputs and outputs’’.
7. The topic of my second tutorial session at FuMee 1 was the modeling relation. There is only room in
the present article, however, for a small fraction of that particular exposition. The reader is referred to
AS (if a copy can be found), Rosen (1991), and Louie (2009) for a detailed treatment of the subject,
which is considered by Rosen to be the point of departure of science.
8. As the British geneticist and evolutionary biologist J.B.S. Haldane once said, there are four stages in
the development of people’s reaction to a new scientific idea: (1) This is arrant nonsense. (2) This is
interesting but controversial. (3) This is true, but trivial. (4) I always said so. With regards to Rosen’s
science, when I was his graduate student 30 years ago, the world was definitely in stage 1; I think it
has now progressed to somewhere in stage 2.
PAGE 28
j
foresight
j
VOL. 12 NO. 3 2010
References
Louie, A.H. (2009), More than Life Itself: A Synthetic Continuation in Relational Biology, Ontos Verlag,
Frankfurt.
Rosen, R. (1991), Life Itself: A Comprehensive Inquiry into the Nature, Origin, and Fabrication of Life,
Columbia University Press, New York, NY.
Further reading
Rosen, R. (1978), Fundamentals of Measurement and Representation of Natural Systems,
North-Holland, New York, NY.
Rosen, R. (1985), Anticipatory Systems: Philosophical, Mathematical & Methodological Foundations,
Pergamon Press, Oxford.
About the author
A.H. Louie is a mathematical biologist. His premier interest is in pure mathematical biology:
conception and abstract formulations. This area of research is called relational biology, the
school of Nicholas Rashevsky and Robert Rosen. Dr Louie has just finished writing a book on
the subject. More than Life Itself: A Synthetic Continuation in Relational Biology was
published in 2009 by Ontos Verlag.
VOL. 12 NO. 3 2010
j
foresight
j
PAGE 29
To purchase reprints of this article please e-mail: reprints@emeraldinsight.com
Or visit our web site for further details: www.emeraldinsight.com/reprints
... Ehresmann, 1966;Bell, 1981;Landry, 1995;Awodey, 2006;Borceux,, 2008;Schmidt, 2011;Schmidt andWinter, 2014, Riehl, 2016). Two category-theoretical approaches are of particular interest for the formal implementation of Integral Biomathics: Memory Evolutive Systems, MES Vanbremeersch, 1987, 2007), and Relational Biology, RB (Louie, 2009(Louie, , 2013, with the last one being a continuation of Robert Rosen's work on the subject (Rosen, 1958a(Rosen, /b, 1959(Rosen, , 1991(Rosen, , 1999) and on anticipatory systems (Rosen, 1985;Louie 2010;Ehresmann, 2017). Both of them represent specific incarnations of CT for biology as synergetic syntheses of a number of mathematical theories (partially ordered sets, lattices, graphs, categories, adjacency matrices, interacting entailment networks, etc.). ...
... Key innovations to be addressed in future would be the inclusion of the formalization of: i) both the exo-physical (third-person) and endo-physical 37 (phenomenological, first-person) description of the system (Atmanspacher and Dalenoort, 1994;Ehresmann and Gomez-Ramirez, 2015); ii) a second-order dynamic logic for the observer-participant (Jerzak, 2009;Khrennikov and Schumann, 2014;Simeonov, 2015); iii) a multi-level system emergence and development (Kauffman, 1993;Kauffman, 2009;Merelli et al., 2012;Longo et al., 2012;Kauffman, 2015); iv) a multi-dimensional flow of time (Cole, 1980(Cole, , 1981Strnad, 1980Strnad, , 1981 as well as v) treatment of anticipation (Rosen, 1985;Louie, 2010;Ehresmann, 2013 and vi) retrocausality (Pegg, 2008;Price, 2012;Matsuno, 2016). These characteristics are going to be investigated in a series of research projects towards creating a well-grounded general theory of living systems (Simeonov et al., 2012b) based on the WLIMES frame (Ehresmann and Simeonov, 2012;Simeonov and Ehresmann, 2017). ...
Article
Full-text available
The goal of this paper is to advance an extensible theory of living systems using an approach to biomathematics and biocomputation that suitably addresses self-organized, self-referential and anticipatory systems with multi-temporal multi-agents. Our first step is to provide foundations for modelling of emergent and evolving dynamic multi-level organic complexes and their sustentative processes in artificial and natural life systems. Main applications are in life sciences, medicine, ecology and astrobiology, as well as robotics, industrial automation, man-machine interface and creative design. Since 2011 over 100 scientists from a number of disciplines have been exploring a substantial set of theoretical frameworks for a comprehensive theory of life known as Integral Biomathics. That effort identified the need for a robust core model of organisms as dynamic wholes, using advanced and adequately computable mathematics. The work described here for that core combines the advantages of a situation and context aware multivalent computational logic for active self-organizing networks, Wandering Logic Intelligence (WLI), and a multi-scale dynamic category theory, Memory Evolutive Systems (MES), hence WLIMES. This is presented to the modeller via a formal augmented reality language as a first step towards practical modelling and simulation of multi-level living systems. Initial work focuses on the design and implementation of this visual language and calculus (VLC) and its graphical user interface. The results will be integrated within the current methodology and practices of theoretical biology and (personalized) medicine to deepen and to enhance the holistic understanding of life.
... Autonomous systems not only need to be able to react to changes in their environment, but also to act proactively with respect to their own purposes. A proactive and anticipatory system contains "a predictive model of itself and/or its environment, which allows it to change state at an instant in accord with the model's predictions pertaining to a later instant" (Nadin, 2017;Louie, 2010). Proactive computing is currently understood as an evolution away from interactive computing, towards human-(un)supervised pervasive computing scenarios (Tennenhouse, 2000). ...
Article
Digital Twins are an important concept in the comprehensive digital representation of manufacturing assets, products, and other resources, comprising their design and configuration, state, and behaviour. Digital Twins provide information about and services based on their physical counterpart’s current condition, history and predicted future. They are the building blocks of a vision of future Digital Factories where stakeholders collaborate via the information Digital Twins provide about physical assets in the factory and throughout the product lifecycle. Digital Twins may also contribute to more flexible and resilient Digital Factories. To achieve this, Digital Twins will need to evolve from today’s expert-centric tools towards active entities which extend the capabilities of their physical counterparts. Required features include sensing and processing their environment and situation, pro-actively communicating with each other, taking decisions towards their own or cooperative goals, and adapting themselves and their physical counterparts to achieve those goals. Future Digital Twins will need to be context-aware, autonomous, and adaptive. This paper aims to establish a roadmap for this evolution. It sets the scene by proposing a working definition of Digital Twins and examines the state-of-the-art in the three topics in their relation to DTs. It then elaborates potentials for each topic mapped against the working definition, to finally identify research gaps allowing for the definition of a roadmap towards the full realisation of autonomous, context-aware, adaptive Digital Twins as building blocks of tomorrow’s Digital Factories.
... Yet, they are forced to share territory at least in UK cities where every second house has a cat. In order to avoid fighting with each other, cats precisely anticipate [58][59] and share space and time in such a manner that they rarely meet. ...
Article
Full-text available
Forty-two years ago, Capra published "The Tao of Physics" (Capra, 1975). In this book (page 17) he writes: "The exploration of the atomic and subatomic world in the twentieth century has …. necessitated a radical revision of many of our basic concepts" and that, unlike 'classical' physics, the sub-atomic and quantum "modern physics" shows resonances with Eastern thoughts and "leads us to a view of the world which is very similar to the views held by mystics of all ages and traditions." This article stresses an analogous situation in biology with respect to a new theoretical approach for studying living systems, Integral Biomathics (IB), which also exhibits some resonances with Eastern thought. Stepping on earlier research in cybernetics(1) and theoretical biology,(2) IB, has been developed since 2011 by over 100 scientists, from a number of disciplines who have been exploring a substantial set of theoretical frameworks. From that effort, the need for a robust core model utilizing advanced mathematics and computation adequate for understanding the behavior of organisms as dynamic wholes was identified. At this end, the authors of this article have proposed WLIMES (Ehresmann and Simeonov, 2012), a formal theory for modeling living systems integrating both the Memory Evolutive Systems (Ehresmann and Vanbremeersch, 2007) and the Wandering Logic Intelligence (Simeonov, 2002b). Its principles will be recalled here with respect to their resonances to Eastern thought.
Chapter
What is the nonprofit sector and why does it exist? Collecting the writing of some of the most creative minds in the field of nonprofit studies, this book challenges our traditional understanding of the role and purpose of the nonprofit sector. It reflects on the ways in which new cultural and economic shifts bring existing assumptions into question and offers new conceptualizations of the nonprofit sector that will inform, provoke, and inspire. Nonprofit organization and activity is an enormously important part of social, cultural, and economic life around the world, but our conceptualization of their place in modern society is far from complete. Reimagining Nonprofits provides fresh insights that are necessary for understanding nonprofit organizations and sectors in the 21st century.
Article
This paper is a reflection on how evaluators could approach theories of change through a foresight lens. It explores the role of assumptions and especially anticipatory assumptions in how we design our theories of change. It argues for a more open approach, a transdisciplinary approach to the multiple knowledges we bring to bear. It goes on to argue that if we do not build and use our imaginations to think differently about the future than the past, as evaluators we risk being trapped in findings and recommendations that assume continuity in a highly discontinuous world.
Chapter
Choice control by higher order constraints operating through downward causation occurs when physical conditions are underdetermined by laws and permitted by boundary conditions. Life creates a web of “enablements”: newly available econiches to expand into. Competition creates cooperation. Adaptive systems—with expectations “built in”—in learning and cognition function by incorporating feed forward modeling into cybernetic (feedback) control. Economic orders have no agency, so do not anticipate: they are sources of information for cognizing agents. Adaptive behavior is (downward) causal (push from past), not teleological (pull from future). Physical theory also requires a duality of descriptions. Rules of behavior are not laws of nature.KeywordsAdaptive systemsNegative rulesEnablementsDownward causation
Chapter
Study of how we come to know—the nature of modeling and anticipation of our unpredictable, often dangerous environment—is the province of evolutionary epistemology. Constructivism depends upon knowledge being static or non-evolutionary and therefore cannot address the unforeseen and unknown in either our behavior or acquisition of knowledge. It has no anticipatory or feedforward mechanisms for the unanticipated. Likewise, constructivism has no mechanism for addressing error—either its detection or correction. Social or market orders (e.g., science) are sources of information used by agents to generate knowledge and to detect error. Trying to control science or the market by top-down intervention falsifies knowledge claims, fails to detect error, and reduces productivity in society. Socialism is not scientific, it kills inquiry by controlling its output.KeywordsAnticipatory systemsError eliminationCreativityControl
Chapter
The limits of prediction pose a critical risk for any organisation making long-range decisions about its strategy and investments. The accuracy of our forecasts degrades progressively due to the combined effects of complexity and uncertainty, compounded by the passage of time. Scenarios become useful in the zone beyond the limits of standard prediction. However, we question whether it is really the case that scenarios must only start where prediction ends. Do most organisations that invest in scenario planning have no expectation that the scenarios created will provide a credible picture of what the future might be like? Instead, we view scenarios as anticipatory systems with a distinctive type of predictive model, where prediction is not based on probability, but plausibility. The zone of plausibility is a space in which scenarios provide evidence-based, broad-brush, but targeted, prediction. We contend that other objectives for scenarios, (such as futures consciousness, or re-perception) are necessary but secondary to scenarios’ predictive work in the zone of plausibility. Importantly, we argue that if we abandon hope that our scenarios will provide a constrained form of prediction, then we fail to harness the potential that scenarios can offer—when they are plausible, rigorous, and robust.
Article
Full-text available
Full paper available, open access, https://doi.org/10.1002/ffo2.11 The concept of chronotope was introduced in the 1920s by the Russian neurophysiologist A.A. Ukhtomsky, and extensively used by Mikhail Bakhtin in his analysis of the development of literary forms. Chronotope structures the possibilities for meaningful action and different chronotopes thus generate different forms of agency and future. In this paper, three approaches to foresight are analyzed, showing how their different chronotopes lead to different ways of understanding the future. We differentiate between probabilistic, possibilistic and constructivist frameworks for foresight. Probabilistic approaches are shown to rely on recursive chronotopes that capture future as a repetition of the past. Possibilistic approaches, here exemplified by the “gold standard” Schwartz/GBN scenario method, are shown to rely on narrative chronotopes that can tell stories of emergent futures and the impact of innovation. Scenario methods, however, describe changes in the environment as forces and trends in a recursive chronotope. As a result, they have limited capacity to address qualitative novelty. In contrast to possibilistic and probabilistic approaches, a constructivist dialogical approach described in this paper explicitly aims at integrating qualitative novelty and radical innovation as important elements of foresight. Constructivist foresight does not aim for “knowing” the future; instead, it aims at creating the future. Knowing when to use these different forms of foresight is an important element in strategy and policy development.
Chapter
Effective anticipation is a fundamental characteristic of highly reliable organizations. In Rosen’s anticipatory theory of complex systems, all living systems and virtually all other complex systems require anticipatory models to maintain an organized state. This paper provides an overview of Rosen’s anticipatory theory of complex systems and presents a conceptual framework for applying this framework to improve safety and quality in healthcare. Organizational interventions based on this theory could include education of clinicians, patients, and families on how anticipatory complex systems function and improve safety in clinical environments, and systems interventions to promote optimal concordance between a team’s model of a clinical situation and the actual clinical situation. Enhanced general understandings of anticipatory complex systems and of their failure modes could help reduce communications failures that are a common cause of serious adverse events.
Book
A. H. Louie’s More Than Life Itself is an exploratory journey in relational biology, a study of life in terms of the organization of entailment relations in living systems. This book represents a synergy of the mathematical theories of categories, lattices, and modelling, and the result is a synthetic biology that provides a characterization of life. Biology extends physics. Life is not a specialization of mechanism, but an expansive generalization of it. Organisms and machines share some common features, but organisms are not machines. Life is defined by a relational closure that places it beyond the reach of physicochemical and mechanistic dogma, outside the reductionistic universe, and into the realm of impredicativity. Function dictates structure. Complexity brings forth living beings.
This area of research is called relational biology, the school of Nicholas Rashevsky and Robert Rosen. Dr Louie has just finished writing a book on the subject
  • R Rosen
Rosen, R. (1985), Anticipatory Systems: Philosophical, Mathematical & Methodological Foundations, Pergamon Press, Oxford. About the author A.H. Louie is a mathematical biologist. His premier interest is in pure mathematical biology: conception and abstract formulations. This area of research is called relational biology, the school of Nicholas Rashevsky and Robert Rosen. Dr Louie has just finished writing a book on the subject. More than Life Itself: A Synthetic Continuation in Relational Biology was published in 2009 by Ontos Verlag.