ArticlePDF Available

On the relativistic invariance of a quantum theory based on beables

Authors:

Abstract

We discuss the question of the relativistic invariance of a quantum theory based on beables, and we suggest the general outlines of one possible form of such a theory.
On the Relativistic Invariance of a Quantum
Theory Based on Beables
D. Bohm and B.J. Hiley
Birkbeck College
Abstract
We discuss the question of the relativistic invariance of a quantum
theory based on beables and we suggest the general outlines of one
possible form of such a theory
It gives us great pleasure to write this article on the occassion of John Bell’s
sixtieth birthday, especially because he has shown a sustained and critical
interest in finding an interpretation of the quantum theory that is not based
on measuring instruments and observables, but rather on what he has called
beables. Non-relativistically it appears that there is no serious difficulty in
doing this [1, 2, 3]. However because of quantum nonlocality, the extension
to special relativity is not obvious. Nevertheless it raises some interesting
questions which we shall discuss in this paper and which we hope may help
resolve some of the problems pointed out by Bell [4].
We base our discussion on our proposed ontological approach [1, 2].
Briefly we assume the electron is a particle guided by the quantum field
according to the equation
pi=iS(1)
where piis the momentum of the ith particle and xiis its coordinate, while
Sis determined by
ψ(x1...xn, t) = R(x1. . . xn, t) exp ·i
¯hS(x1...xn, t)¸
Published in Foundations of Physics 21, 1-9, 1991.
1
With these assumptions it follows from Schr¨odinger’s equation that each
particle is acted on not only by the classical potential, but also by the
quantum potential
Q=¯h2
2mX
i
2
iR
R(2)
It is further assumed that in a statistical ensemble of systems with the same
wavefunction, i.e. in the same quantum state, the probability is given by
P(x1...xn, t) = R2(x1. . . xn, t) (3)
It also follows from Schr¨odinger’s equation that |ψ|2satisfies the conservation
equation
|ψ|2
∂t +X
i
i·iS
m|ψ|2¸= 0 (4)
This means that if P=|ψ|2initially, this will hold for all times.
We then extend our model to incorporate an additional stochastic com-
ponent of the velocity of the particles, in which vi= (iS)/m will now be
the mean velocity of the ith particle, while the stochastic component will be
ξiwhich varies at random. We show [5] that an arbitrary initial probability
distribution will then approach |ψ|2. With these assumptions it can then be
shown that all the usual statistical results of quantum theory follow. We are
able to do this without giving a primary role to measuring instruments or to
observables. Rather, everything, including the process of measurement it-
self, is discussed in terms of beables. These beables are the particle variables
and the wave function.
Because the quantum potential does not depend on the intensity of the
wave function but only on its form, it is possible to have a strong and direct
connection between distant particles. It is this connection that, in our inter-
pretation, explains the nonlocality implied by the failure of the predictions
of quantum theory to satisfy the Bell inequality [6]. This nonlocality further
implies an instantaneous connection, as has indeed been confirmed in the
experiments of Aspect et al. [7, 8]. The question at issue here is then that
of how such nonlocality is to be reconciled with relativity.
In order to bring this question into sharper focus, we outline here our
extension of the ontological interpretation of the quantum theory to a rel-
ativistic context [2, 5]. We begin with the one-particle Dirac equation. It
follows from this equation that there is a conserved charge-current density
whose time component is positive definite. This is
j=ψαψ;j0=ψψ(5)
2
with ∂j0
∂t +·j= 0 (6)
As in the nonrelativistic case, we assume a definite particle trajectory, but
now we define the velocity as
v=ψαψ
|ψ|2(7)
(It can easilty be shown that |v| ≤ c.)
Noting that j0is equal to the particle density, ρ, we obtain for the
conservation equation ∂ρ
∂t +·(ρv) = 0 (8)
Equation (7) may be taken instead of equation (1) as the guidance relation.
Then if we assume probability density P=ρat any time, equation (8) will
guarantee that it will hold for all time.
The assumptions given here are sufficient to determine the one-particle
theory completely. It is evident that this theory is Lorentz invariant in
content because the Dirac equation is covariant and because from this it
follows that equation (8) is also covariant.
There is thus no real difficulty in finding a relativistically covariant ex-
tension of our interpretation of the quantum theory for the one-particle sys-
tem. However it does not follow that our further extension to a stochastic
model is also Lorentz invariant [5]. Indeed it is well known that there are, as
yet, unresolved difficulties in obtaining a consistent and covariant stochastic
process because the non-compactness of the Lorentz group prevents us from
defining a covariant velocity distribution in the way in which this can be
done nonrelativistically. However the interesting point here is that for an
equilibrium distribution in which Phas become equal to ρ=|ψ|2, we do
not need a relativistically covariant stochastic process. For it follows from
the analysis given in Bohm and Hiley [5] that P=|ψ|2will result even from
non-covariant assumptions on the stochastic process. All the experimen-
tal results available thus far follow from the equilibrium distribution alone.
This means that we can, in principle at least, obtain a statistically covariant
theory of the single particle with experimental results equivalent to those
given by the current relativistic quantum mechanics. Moreover we can do
this on the basis of an underlying stochastic process that is not relativisti-
cally covariant. At present there is evidently no way experimentally to rule
out this sort of theory.
3
To raise the question of nonlocality, we have to go to a many-particle
system [5]. Firstly we define the wave function of the many-body system to
be
ψ=ψi1...in...(x1. . . xn. . . t)
where inrepresents the four possible values of the index for the nth particle.
We take all particles at the same time t, noting that it can be shown that
this can be done in a covariant way [2, 5].
From the N-body Dirac equation it follows that
∂ψ ψ
∂t +X
n
n·ψαnψ= 0 (9)
where in the above we also sum over all the indices of all the particles. We
define the density ρ(x1. . . xn. . . t) = |ψ|2in the configuration space of all
the particles. The guidance relation for the nth particle is then
vn=ψαnψ
ρ(10)
If P=ρinitially, it follows that this will hold for all time. And if we assume
a suitable stochastic process, it further follows that an arbitrary initial value
of Pwill eventually approach ρ.
As long as we stay in a particular Lorentz frame, the above assump-
tions provide a consistent ontological interpretation of the many-body Dirac
equation. We should however add that, the wave function of all the fer-
monic particles (which are the only ones obeying the Dirac equation) will
have to be completely antisymmetric, so that the Pauli exclusion principle
will apply. Then as Dirac indeed proposed in his original work on this sub-
ject, the negative energy states of the vacuum are assumed to be full. ( It
can be shown that this approach is completely equivalent to the one that
treats fermions in terms of anticommuting annihilation and creation opera-
tors [9].) Pair production is then, of course, brought about by the transition
of a fermion from a negative to a positive energy state leaving behind a
‘hole’ with opposite quantum numbers, e.g. charge.
Although this theory is completely consistent when considered in any
one Lorentz frame, it is not completely covariant in content. However note
that the Dirac equation itself and the continuity equation (9) are Lorentz
covariant. The reason for this is that the guidance condition (10) has a
nonlocal significance. That is to say, changes in position of any one particle
4
will in general imply the possibility of corresponding instantaneous changes
in the velocities of all the particles no matter how far apart they may be.
This would seem at first sight to prevent us from extending our interpre-
tation to a relativistic context. However, one can see this is not so, if one
considers the fact that the statistical results of our theory depend only on
the invariance of the Dirac equation (and with it the equation (9)). Thus
we could assume a special favoured frame in which nonlocal contacts could
be instantaneous and in which there was a noncovariant stochastic process.
Nevertheless since the equilibrium probability distribution, P=|ψ|2, is the
one that would hold for all present practical purposes, it would follow that
the statistical results of all the quantum mechanical experiments that we
can now do would be the same as in the usual interpretation and therefore
be covariant. Evidently it is impossible at this stage to give any evidence
that the above view is not correct.
In effect we are in this way led to a new model of quantum processes.
We begin by assuming what may be called a sub-relativistic level of stochas-
tic process which is also sub-quantum mechanical (in the sense that the
details of the stochastic process can never be revealed directly in any quan-
tum mechanical experiment). The current quantum theory and relativity
then follow only for the statistical results of the experiments. These do
not depend sensitively on the details of the underlying model, rather as the
laws of thermodynamics do not depend sensitively on the details of the un-
derlying atomic model. So at present, a wide range of sub-relativistic and
sub-quantum mechanical models is open to us.
To make our ideas a bit more definite, we could propose that the stochas-
tic process holds only down to some definite length, l0, which plays a role
similar to that of the mean free path for ordinary particles undergoing Brow-
nian motion. (As we shall bring out later, l0is probably of the order of the
Planck length.) For distances much greater than l0, the stochastic process
will be a good approximation. But for distances of the order of l0or less,
the stochastic treatment will fail and new qualities will reveal themselves.
One may expect, for example, for waves of length of the order of l0, the
current laws of quantum mechanics and relativity would break down even in
a statistical context (e.g. as the laws of macroscopic physics breaks down for
distances of the order of the mean free path.) This is at least one example
of the new kinds of experimental results that would be possible and that
could reveal the sub-relativistic and sub-quantum mechanical level.
Another possibility is that in the special frame in which instantaneous
contact is possible, the speeed of transmission of impulses is not infinite but
5
still very much greater than that of light. In this case even the statistical
predictions of the quantum theory would break down in measurements that
were accurate enough to respond to such very short time differences. (This
would almost certainly require accuracies far greater than available in the
Aspect et al. experiments [7, 8].) In this case one would find in an EPR
experiment, for example, that Bell’s inequality would be satisfied with the
use of instruments that responded to such short times, while they would not
be satisfied in measurements that did not do this. Measurements made in
such short times would in effect reestablish locality in the sub-relativistic
and sub-quantum level.
To carry out experiments of this kind one would have to do something
analogous to a Michelson-Morley experiment which however would involve
an EPR-type situation. Let us suppose the velocity of the earth relative to
the preferred frame is v. By measurements of EPR correlations at different
times of the year we could not only find out which is the preferred frame,
but also demonstrate the existence of the sub-relativistic and sub-quantum
mechanical level.
But what would a good surmise be for the value of v? One suggestion
is that the preferred frame should be the one that is at rest in a system
of coordinates in which the time axis connects the point in question to the
origin of the universe. It seems reasonable to suggest that this would be
close to the frame in which the 3Kradiation is isotropic. This is the sort
of velocity we have to measure relative to the earth.
Are there any reasons available at present which would lead us to suppose
the domain of relativity is limited? Actually there are some. Firstly it is
clear that Lorentz invariance fails for distances so large that the curvature of
space becomes significant. Generally this is dealt with by saying that Lorentz
invariance only holds in a tangent space mapping onto an infinitesimal part
of the actual manifold. But in this approach, Lorentz invariance should
become more and more applicable for shorter and shorter distances. However
one can give arguments showing that Lorentz invariance will also fail to hold
for very short distances as we approach Planck length.
To see how this comes about, let us consider a vector, vµ, of ordinary
length and regard it as made up of many smaller vectors δvµwhich are on
a straight line
vµ=X
i
δvµ
i
Suppose that we make a Lorentz transformation. Strictly speaking this
cannot be defined without giving the metric tensor gµν . But at very short
6
distances this tensor has large quantum fluctuations and does not reduce to
its simple diagonal form. The Lorentz transformation will then give us
v0µ=X²µαgαβ (xλ)δvβ
i
It is clear that what begins as a simple vector becomes transformed into a
rather foggy distribution of constituent elements which are not well defined.
So the whole idea of a simple Lorentz transformation of one line into another
breaks down and this especially so as we go to very short distances for which
the notion of tangent space has been assumed to apply. The idea of Lorentz
invariance becomes relevant only over intermediate distances for which the
fluctuations of gµν will average out to something relatively small, implying
that gµν can be taken as effectively constant.
All of this suggests that the Lorentz group may not be as fundamental
as has generally been assumed. If it is not valid in the domain of very large
distances, nor in the domain of very small distances, it may well cease to
be valid in yet other domains. The analysis given earlier suggests that even
at intermediate distances, it may cease to be valid for individual processes
involving beables wherever quantum nonlocality is important.
It is understandable that there may be a great deal of reluctance even
to contemplate giving up the notion that relativity and quantum mechanics
are universally valid. To do so however may give us significant advantages.
Firstly it provides a way of developing a point of view in which physical pro-
cesses are intuitively intelligible so that we do not have to restrict ourselves to
using mathematical algorithms for computing probabilities of experimental
results without giving any idea of how these results come about. Secondly
it permits us properly to confront the question of making a cosmological
theory that is compatible with quantum mechanics. In the conventional in-
terpretation there is no way to do this because the apparatus would have
to be outside the cosmos. (For further discusssion of these two points see
Bohm and Hiley [2] and Hiley [10]).
Finally it may help to resolve some of the difficulties in the quantum
treatment of special and general relativity. Recall that special relativity
leads to infinities. To be sure, these can be avoided by the algorithm of
renormalisation but this algorithm contradicts the initial starting point. So
the theory is ultimately not based on a set of logically coherent fundamental
principles, but rather on technical procedures brought in from outside such
principles merely for the sake of avoiding certain difficulties. On the other
hand if there is ultimately a preferred frame then there is no inconsistency in
7
assuming that there is a ‘cut off’ somewhere near the Planck length beyond
which the extrapolation of current laws is not appropriate. With regard
to general relativity, we also avoid unresolved difficulties arising from the
infinite fluctuations in gµν at short distances.
It therefore seems to us that it is worthwhile to keep open the options
that relativity and quantum theory may have limited domains of applica-
bility. At present there is, of course, no way to settle this issue, but still
keeping an open mind on this question seems to be the best approach.
We would further add that it is really a continuation of one of the basic
traditions of physics to consider the possibility of a deeper level out of which
emerges a very different level conforming to relativity and quantum theory.
A case in point is the assumption of a deeper atomic level as something
very different from the continuous macroscopic level of the older physics.
Einstein’s attempt to explain particles as singularities or pulses in a field is
another such case.
The new level always looks very different from the older one yet con-
tains the latter as a limiting case or as an approximation. Our proposed
new level is also very different from previous levels of physics. We explain
these differences elsewhere [1, 2] but here we shall mention that it contains
concepts that are very strange and new such as nonlocality and the activity
of information. It need hardly be surprising that behaviour as strange as
that of the quantum theory (and to some extent that of relativity too) would
have to come out of a deeper level that was very different in crucial ways
from those that have already been known.
References
[1] D. Bohm, B.J. Hiley and P.N. Kaloyerou. Phys. Reports 144, 321
(1987).
[2] D. Bohm and B.J. Hiley. The Undivided Universe (An Ontological In-
terpretation of Quantum Mechanics), Routledge, London (1991).
[3] J.S. Bell. Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics, Cam-
bridge University Press, Cambridge (1987).
[4] J.S. Bell. Op. Cit. Chapter 14.
[5] D. Bohm and B.J. Hiley. Phys. Reports 172, 93 (1989).
8
[6] J.S. Bell. Op. Cit. Chapter 2.
[7] A. Aspect, P. Grangier and G. Roger. Phys. Rev. Lett. 49, 91 (1982).
[8] A. Aspect, J. Dalibard and G. Roger. Phys. Rev. Lett. 49, 1804 (1982).
[9] S.S. Schweber, H.A. Bethe and F. de Hoffmann. Mesons and Fields,
Chapter 13, Row Peterson and Co., Illinois (1955).
[10] B.J. Hiley. “Cosmology, EPR Correlations and Separability”, in Bell’s
Theorem, Quantum Theory and Conceptions of the Universe, K.
Kafatos, Ed., Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht (1989).
9
... In that way we restrict the application of POILM to this foliation F 0 in order to preserve LIHVT. However, as stated by Hardy [13], Bohm [3,6,30], and Bell [1,3] there is no experiment that can be performed to determine what this preferred frame is (even if the absolute reference frame associated with the 2.7 K microwave cosmological background is often recalled [3,8] as a good candidate). Vigier and coworkers [7] also proposed to use the center of mass of the full particle ensemble to define a preferred frame in BM. ...
... Interestingly, whereas in BM the dynamics of particles guided by the quantum state is not fully Lorentz invariant the theory is still Lorentz invariant at the statistical level meaning that the Aether is thus essentially hidden. Nevertheless, while this preferred foliation proposal mixing Newtonian and Einsteinian concepts motivates alternative theories going far beyond present-day quantum mechanics and general relativity [3,7,8,30] it is difficult, or even impossible, not to see here a failure of the full deterministic hidden-variable program. In other words, assuming an Occam razor principle most researchers would better agree that deterministic hidden variables cannot be made to agree with Minkowsky space-time and thus should preferably be abandoned as an explanation of QN. ...
... We emphasize that our approach is not completely orthogonal to the one usually advocated and which is considering a preferred frame or foliation [3,24,25,30]. Indeed, while we cannot a priori forbid a Dirac distribution centered on a given direction n F 0 we can also imagine a Gaussian like distribution centered on such a direction. ...
Article
Full-text available
We review several no-go theorems attributed to Gisin and Hardy, Conway and Kochen purporting the impossibility of Lorentz-invariant deterministic hidden-variable model for explaining quantum nonlocality. Those theorems claim that the only known solution to escape the conclusions is either to accept a preferred reference frame or to abandon the hidden-variable program altogether. Here we present a different alternative based on a foliation dependent framework adapted to deterministic hidden variables. We analyse the impact of such an approach on Bohmian mechanics and show that retrocausation (that is future influencing the past) necessarily comes out without time-loop paradox.
... In that way we restrict the application of POILM to this foliation F 0 in order to preserve LI-HVT. However, as stated by Hardy [12], Bohm [3,6,27], and Bell [1,3] there is no experiment that can be performed to determine what this preferred frame is (even if the absolute reference frame associated with the 2.7 K microwave cosmological background is often recalled [3,8] as a good candidate in this context). Vigier and coworkers [7] also proposed to use the center of mass of the full particle ensemble to define a preferred frame in BM. ...
... Interestingly, whereas in BM the dynamics of particles guided by the quantum state is not fully Lorentz invariant the theory is still Lorentz invariant at the statistical level meaning that the Aether is thus essentially hidden. Nevertheless, while this preferred foliation proposal mixing Newtonian and Einsteinian concepts motivates alternative theories going far beyond present-day quantum mechanics and general relativity [7,8,3,27] it is difficult, or even impossible, not to see here a failure of the full deterministic hidden-variable program. In other words, assuming an Occam razor principle most researchers would better agree that deterministic hidden variables can not be made to agree with Minkowsky space-time and should thus preferably be abandoned as an explanation of QN. ...
Preprint
We review several no-go theorems attributed to Gisin and Hardy, Conway and Kochen purporting the impossibility of Lorentz-invariant deterministic hidden-variable model for explaining quantum nonlocality. Those theorems claim that the only known solution to escape the conclusions is either to accept a preferred reference frame or to abandon the hidden-variable program altogether. Here we present a different alternative based on a foliation dependent framework adapted to deterministic hidden variables. We analyse the impact of such an approach on Bohmian mechanics and show that retrocausation (that is future influencing the past) necessarily comes out without time-loop paradox.
... Now we will see it can. Another way of extending the approach into the relativistic domain has already been presented in Bohm and Hiley [34], however that method did not include spin. ...
Article
Full-text available
The reality of Bohm's intellectual journey is very different from what is often claimed by the proponents of "Bohmian Mechanics" and others as we will explain in this paper. He did not believe a mechanical explanation of quantum phenomena was possible. Central to his thinking, and incidentally to Bohr's also, was the notion of 'unbroken wholeness', a notion that is crucial for understanding quantum properties like quantum nonlocality. His proposals were based on a primitive notion of `process' or `activity', producing a more 'organic' approach to quantum phenomena. He published many papers outlining these new ideas, some plausible, some less so, but was not able to develop a coherent mathematical structure to support the work. Over the last ten years much of that missing mathematics has been put in place. This paper will report this new work, concentrating on providing a coherent overview of the whole programme.
... The possibility that the description of individual quantum processes may have noncovariant features is therefore not ruled out by experiment; the only experimental requirement that must be met is that the statistical predictions be covariant. This has led Bohm to suggest that Lorentz covariance may hold only at the statistical level, whilst noncovariant features may arise at the level of individual processes ( [5] page 118), [11] and ([6] chapter 12). ...
Article
We develop an ontological interpretation for the electromagnetic field. We shall see that the wave functional has a natural interpretation as the probability density for a given field configuration. The electromagnetic field is therefore to be regarded as a “field” (always) without a particle-like nature. In developing a model of the electromagnetic field as a continuous field distribution, it becomes necessary to explain how, in interactions with matter, the field manifests itself in a descrite particle-like way. To this end we describe in detail the photoelectric and Compton effects, usually considered as experimental evidence for the particle-like nature of the electromagnetic field. As illustrations of our model, we consider two experiments which over the years have played a central role in conceptual discussions of the quantum theory: the two-slit and EPR experiments.
Chapter
This talk contains comments on some current attempts to solve the measurement problem of quantum theory. In the next section I explain what this problem actually is, i.e. what it is for the purpose of this talk (it is not always clear that when people refer to the measurement problem they mean the same thing), and mention some of the solutions that seem to be available. Models involving explicit collapse mechanisms are then considered. In section 3, I discuss the possible allowed values for the time and size scales of the collapse, and note that (in principle at least) there is interesting physics involved in measuring the effects of collapse. A particular version of the continuous localisation model is considered in section 4, and it is recast in a form that requires the existence of a “trajectory”, very similar to that of the de Broglie-Bohm model, although playing a different role in the theory. This new form strongly suggests that there should be some underlying mechanism causing the collapse, and it also implies that the problems of locality and Lorentz-invariance in the spontaneous-collapse models are not different in nature to those found in hidden-variable models.
Chapter
The term quantum nonlocality appears in various guises in the literature. Broadly speaking it denotes a form of quantum mechanical action at a distance, when a distant influence is counterintuitive because of the absence of a classically describable form of physical mediation. At the outset we must emphasize that a discussion of nonlocality cannot begin unless we clearly define the notion of spatial separation between relevant physical events involving localized entities. Yet this defies a precise definition if we remain confined within the standard framework of quantum mechanics, where wave functions are only abstract symbols for computing observable probabilities.
Chapter
As known, the Klein-Gordon equation describe the behaviour of relativistic spinless particles.
Article
The third edition of Quantum Non-Locality and Relativity has been carefully updated to reflect significant developments, including a new chapter covering important recent work in the foundations of physics. • A new edition of the premier philosophical study of Bell's Theorem and its implication for the relativistic account of space and time • Discusses Roderich Tumiulka's explicit, relativistic theory that can reproduce the quantum mechanical violation of Bell's inequality. • Discusses the "Free Will Theorem" of John Conway and Simon Kochen • Introduces philosophers to the relevant physics and demonstrates how philosophical analysis can help inform physics.
Article
Quantum mechanics began with the solution of the problem of blackbody radiation by Planck`s quantum hypothesis: In the interaction of light with matter, energy can only be exchanged between the light in a cavity and the atoms in the walls of the cavity by the discrete amount E = hν, (1) where h is Planck`s constant and ν is the frequency of the light. Einstein in his treatment of the photoelectric effect reinterpreted this equation to mean that a beam of light consists of particles (light quanta) with the preceding energy. Hence Einstein changed the meaning of E in Eq. (1) from that of the energy exchanged between atom and light to the energy intrinsic to the particles inside the light beam itself, independent of its interaction with atoms. Later, the name photon was given to these light quanta. The Compton effect supported this particle view point of light by demonstrating that photons carried momentum, as well as energy. Therefore, the waveparticle duality of quanta made its first appearance in connection with the properties of light. It would seem that the introduction of the concept of the photon as a particle would necessarily also introduce the concept of locality into the quantum world, because particles are point-like entities and, and, hence, are seemingly local in nature. However, in light of observed violations of Bell`s inequalities, exactly the opposite seems to be the case. Here we review some recent results in quantum optics that elucidate nonlocality and other fundamental issues in quantum mechanics. 155 refs., 17 figs.
Article
Full-text available
The linear-polarization correlation of pairs of photons emitted in a radiative cascade of calcium has been measured. The new experimental scheme, using two-channel polarizers (i.e., optical analogs of Stern-Gerlach filters), is a straightforward transposition of Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen-Bohm gedankenexperiment. The present results, in excellent agreement with the quantum mechanical predictions, lead to the greatest violation of generalized Bell's inequalities ever achieved.
Article
We review the causal interpretation of quantum mechanics and show how it provides an ontological description of physical processes in terms of beables, not observables. We explain how this provides a clear intuitive picture of physical processes in which measurements do not play a fundamental role thereby avoiding some of the conceptual problems that are inherent in the usual approach to quantum mechanics particularly when applied to quantum cosmology. A brief outline of how our approach can be extended to included spin and Lorentz invariance is also given. One of the central features of the causal interpretation is that it illustrates clearly the role of non-locality which arises in EPR-type correlations. We finally discuss the consequences of these correlations for relativity and for the apparent dominance of locality in the universe.
Article
Correlations of linear polarizations of pairs of photons have been measured with time-varying analyzers. The analyzer in each leg of the apparatus is an acousto-optical switch followed by two linear polarizers. The switches operate at incommensurate frequencies near 50 MHz. Each analyzer amounts to a polarizer which jumps between two orientations in a time short compared with the photon transit time. The results are in good agreement with quantum mechanical predictions but violate Bell's inequalities by 5 standard deviations.
Article
We review the stochastic interpretation of the quantum theory and show that, like the causal interpretation it necessarily involves non-locality. We compare and contrast our approach with that of Nelson. We then extend the stochastic interpretation to the Pauli equation. This lays the ground for a further extension to the Dirac equation and therefore enables us to discuss this interpretation in a relativistic context. We find that a co consistent treatment of non-locality can be given and that it is indeed possible further to regard this non-locality as a limiting case of a purely local theory in which the transmission of what we have called active information is not restricted to the speed of light. In this case both quantum theory and relativity come out as very good statistical approximations. However, because this basically local theory implies that these latter are not exactly valid, it is possible to propose tests that could in principle distinguish such a theory from the current theories.
Vacuum or holomovement,” inBell's Theorem, Quantum Theory and Conceptions of the Universe
  • B J Hiley
  • B. J. Hiley
  • A Aspect
  • P Grangier
  • G Roger
A. Aspect, P. Grangier and G. Roger. Phys. Rev. Lett. 49, 91 (1982).