ArticlePDF Available

Abstract

Set against the backdrop of the controversial UK Identity Card scheme, SayanKent’s recent play Another Paradise (2009) conjures up a future dystopian image of a biometrically-controlled Britain in which every citizen is reliant on biometric technology, ID cards and national databases not only as a means for functioning ineveryday life, but more so as a prerequisite for being able to “count” as a person at all. Kent’s message is trenchant and clear: with this extremely technocratic trend, toward which the world is apparently heading, comes a loss of agency, individuality, liberty and human touch. The play, as such, acts as a mouthpiece for conveying some of the major debates surrounding the adoption of biometric ID cards and highlighting the potentially dangerous ramifications of over-relying on technology for governing society. Much of these alarming concerns and potential implications are explored, somewhat satirically but nonetheless seriously, through the characters’manipulated, re-appropriated, mistaken, lost or stolen identities as well as through the concrete situations in the midst of which they find themselves as a result. (11) (PDF) Review of Another Paradise. Available from: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/225406239_Review_of_Another_Paradise
Review of Another Paradise
Btihaj Ajana
Received: 25 May 2009 / Accepted: 14 June 2009 / Published online: 1 October 2009
#
Identity Journal Limited 2009
Set against the backdrop of the controversial UK Identity Card scheme, Sayan
Kents recent play Another Paradis e (2009) conjures up a future dystopian image of
a biometrically-controlled Britain in which every citizen is reliant on biometric
technology, ID cards and national databases not only as a means for functioning in
everyday life, but more so as a prerequisite for being able to count as a person at
all.
Kents message is trenchant and clear: with this extremely technocratic trend,
toward which the world is apparently heading, comes a loss of agency, individuality,
liberty and human touch. The play, as such, acts as a mouthpiece for conveying
some of the major debates surrounding the adoption of biometric ID cards and
highlighting the potentially dangerous ramifications of over-relying on technology
for governing society. Much of these alarming concerns and potential implications
are explored, somewhat satirically but nonetheless seriously, through the characters
manipulated, re-appropriated, mistaken, lost or stolen identities as well as through
the concrete situations in the midst of which they find themselves as a result.
Who are you?
As a thesis play, Another Paradise raises many challenging and timely questions,
questions to do with the growing state surveillance, the neurotic securitisation of life,
the erosion of civil libe rties, and the systematic exclusion of those deemed not
worthy of belonging. But beside these empirically embedded concerns, there is a
highly philosophical question underpinning the play. That is, the age-old question
who are you?, which warrants some discussi on.
IDIS (2009) 2:319325
DOI 10.1007/s12394-009-0018-2
B. Ajana (*)
BIOS Centre, London School of Economics, Tower 2, 11th Floor Houghton Street, London WC2A
2AE, UK
e-mail: b.ajana@lse.ac.uk
Although basic and commonplace in itself, the question who are you? remains
as one of the most challenging, problematic, fluid and intricate questions to which
neither the philosophical discourses of metaphysics nor the technologies and
techniques of identification have been able to provide a fixed and conclusive
answer. Who are you? is indeed an abyssal question, as Carl Schmitt (1950) put
it. It is not because the word who stands for something that is ineffable,
unfathomable, unnameable and ungraspable, or something utterly secretive that only
the self can have an exclusive access to. Rather, it is because who is that which
indicates the incomparable uniqueness and the unrepeatable singularity of each and
everyone (Nancy 2000). And in so doing, it can only yield a response that is destined
to escape the linguistic confines of definition and challenge the technical
mechanisms of recognition. Inexorably then, the moment we want to say who
someone is, our very vocabulary leads us astray into saying what he is (Arendt
1957: 181), that is, the attributes and qualities which act as the content of ones
identity and function as qualifiers for membership, citizenship and so forth (see also
Kottman 2000: viii; Butler 2005: 31; Cavarero 2000; Ricoeur 1992). The conflation
of who and what is in fact an attestation to the inability of both philosophy and
technology to fully capture the ambivalence and double-sided character of identity
and to acknowledge the impossibility of fixing once and for all that which makes the
person irreducibly unique and singular. In Another Paradise, this is expressed quite
vehemently by one of the characters, Abigail Tomlin, whose identity is stolen and
re-appropriated, and as a result is no longer able to prove who she is insofar as what
she is (her name, her biometric information, etc.) does not match her file on the
national database:
ABI: Dont think you know me because you know what washing powder I
buy, or which TV channels I watch, or how many hotels Ive stayed in. Its
what that file doesnt tell you that counts. You might know how many lovers
Ive had but you dont know how much I loved them. You might know which
brand of chocolate I buy, but you dont know what I taste when I eat it. You
dont know my favourite joke, you dont know what cripples me with laughter
and youll never know which photograph I cry over. You think you know my
political persuasions but you dont know what burns inside me, what eats me
up, what consumes me with passion, what makes me who I am. Youwill
never know me.
Indeed, what biometric technology can capture and make epistemologically
knowable and technically available about the person is merely the what aspect of
identity: physical characteristics, behavioural traits, institutionally assigned attribu-
tions, etc. This, of course, only constitutes half of the story. What remains
inaccessible through and untellable by biometrics is precisely that uniqueness of
the who wherein resi de the persons intentions, values, beliefs, desires, and
resistance itself. In this sense, Abigails defiant statement Youwill never know
me is a reminder that biometrics overzealous quest for capturing the uniqueness of
singularity and accessing the nexus of whoness is doomed to failure. For the very
premise of biometric technology is based upon a partial and restricted understanding
of identity that is informed by hyper-scientific discourses and technical practices
320 B. Ajana
whose aim is to simplify the meaning and function of identity, and to purge it
from its ambivalent, contextual, contingent and subjective dimension. And what
comes part and parcel of this technologisation of identity is the growing indifference
toward the embodied person herself; the bypassing of her self-attesting story in
favour of capturing, measuring and storing digital templates of her biological data.
Such a process partakes of what we may call, following on from Gilles Deleuze
(1992), the dividuation of individuals. That is to say, the practice by which they are
turned into dividuals; a series of abstract bits and d igits scattered around databases
and identified by thei r profiles, pin numbe rs, consumer data, credit scoring, etc.,
rather than their subjectivities (see also Rose 1999 and Haggerty and Er icson 2000).
As illustrated by this exchange between the characters Lisa Grundy (a customer
services employee at the Alien Registration Office) and Enoch Dawes (an accountant
who subsequently becomes a nobody after his identity was stolen):
LISA: Do you find that you are a black and white person?
Clarity. Polarity. Contrast. Definitives.
ENOCH: Clarity?
LISA: As opposed to subtle, nebulous, fluid, ambidextrous.
ENOCH: Ambidextrous?
LISA: Yes or no?
ENOCH: Like you re a somebody and Im a nobody?
LISA: Think of your ID card as the portal to you r digital soul. It links you to who
you are. As long as you are attached to a corresponding file on the database the
card could say you were a mouse and I would believe it. Even if you didnt look
like a mouse. Which you do, slightly. Even if you stood in front of me as you are
and your data told me you were Monty the Mouse I would accept that as true. I
would greet you as Monty and offer you a piece of cheese.
And again, as the character Captain Fisher (a female police captain specialising in
internal security) puts it:
FISHER: Mrs Tomlin, you have to appreciate that I work in a grey area where
people say all sorts of things. My job is not to take people on their word but on
what their card verifies. Verify, to establish the truth, accuracy, reality.
Verificare from the Latin verus, true. Thats why I like it. I dont have to
make difficult decisions. I can leave that to the judges and politicians.
Seen in this light, the power struggle, which unfolds in the domain of biometric
technology and ID cards, can then be articulated as a struggle around, and at times
between, two competing onto-epistemic registers of truth. On the one hand, there is
the truth that is distilled from the persons bodily particularities with the aim to
officially estab lish an institutionally governable and controllable identity- the one
that is required by state bureaucracy: a stable, objective, unambiguous and thing-
like identity (Aas 2006: 147). On the other hand, there is the truth that stems from
the narrative, biogr aphic and self-attesting dimension of identity, i.e. from the
persons story. While the former can be seen as belonging to the realm of the what,
the latter is an expression of the dimension of who. Increasingly, and especially
Review of Another Paradise 321
within the rationa lity und erpinn ing biom etr ic technol ogy and iden tity card s,
there is a fundamental epistemological suspicion towards the story, and with it,
the growing occlusion of selfhood and the redundancy of whoness itself.
Therefore,
[a] talking individual, who owns the body, is in fact seen as unnecessary and,
even more importantly, insufficient for identification. Now only the body can
talk in the required ways, through the unambiguous and cryptic language of
codes and algorithms. When a body provides the p assword, a world of
information opens. Databases begin to talk. On the other hand, when the
individual talks, the words are only met with suspicion.
ibid.: 154
It should be noted at this point that the distinction between the what and the
who aspects of identity is not to be understood as a sharp and clear-cut dichotomy.
For in the concrete sense, these dimensions continuously interact with each other and
in ways that are by no means mutually exclusive: institutional identity ascri ptions
(citizenship, membership, etc.) certainly shape some aspects of the life story of the
person, just as the narrative accounts one gives about oneself when asked the
question who are you? may contain, affect and be affected by, elements that
belong to the sphere of the what (as in the case with the narrat ive identity of the
asylum seeker and the refugee). Yet and in terms of biometrics, there is an
evident imbalance in the relationship that mediates between these two dimensions of
identity insofar as the knowledge that is produced through biometric procedures is
not a knowledge based on mutual communication, but on one-way observation. It
is clearly knowledge marked by a power relation (ibid.: 153). It thus favours the
forms and discourses of truth that emerge out of official sources and technical
operations rather than from personal accoun ts. In Another Paradise,thisis
demonstrated, with much satire, through various situations whereby the card and
the file end up overriding the life and the personal reality of the characters by
forcing them to adjust to the new identities they are officially assigned. For instance,
Enoch Dawes who adopts the re-appropriated identit y of Abigail Tomlin, gets treated
as Abigail by everyone (including Abigails husband ) despite the visual evidence of
his gender:
LISA: Look, this is a good ID. You ll love it. Once you get used to it. Now go
home. (Hands him the printout). Theres your new address. Bank details.
Potted history, employment record. National insurance number. Date of birth.
All sort of interesting things.
ENOCH: I cant just walk into another life.
LISA: This is you now.
ENOCH: Look at it. No one will believe me.
LISA: Of course they ll believe you.
ENOCH: But I ve stolen somebody.
LISA: You cant do anything about it now. Cheer up. It could have been a lot
worse. Imgladits all worked out. Enjoy your new life, Mrs A bigail Tomlin.
Abi.
322 B. Ajana
Coventry, a non-place
LISA: Every sovereign state has its Coventry. Its the price we pay for
freedom.
Coventry features in the play as the place where the unidentified/unidentifiable and
the biometrically unqualified are sent. It is reminiscent of what Giorgio Agamben
(1998) refers to as the space of exception; a peculiar non-place which is a by-
product of too much organisation and excessive orderliness. It exists both inside and
outside the state: inside, in terms of its physical presence that marks its inclusion
within the states boundaries, and outside insofar as it is excluded from its regular
social and juridico-political procedures and structure. It is like a mezzanine space of
sovereignty (Nyers 2003: 1080) whose exclusion in an inclusive exclusion (an
exceptio) and whose function is to contain those who are categorised as non-
citizens; those who are [c]onstituted as threshold political beings [ and] defined
precisely through their liminal status that places them on the outskirts of the
community (Zylinska 2004: 530). In Another Paradise, the non-place aspect and
the exceptio character of Coventry are represented in terms of its absence on the
official map, as well as through the kind of activities performed within it and the
type of people who dwell in it:
ENOCH: I stole a map.
LISA: I dont need to know that.
ENOCH: Coventry isnt on it. Its just a blur, an MOD restricted area. Look.
(Thrusts a map at her.) No Coventry. You told me it existed.
LISA: Coventry?
ENOCH: A cash economy no questions and no cannibalism.
LISA: A state of mind.
ENOCH: So I went to the blur.
LISA: Its just a saying, being sent to Coventr y.
ENOCH: Ive been to Coventr y Why is it a blur? Tell me.
LISA: It doesnt exist.
ENOCH: Coventry does exist. Its real. What are you hiding?
LISA: When the biometric identity scheme phase 3 was instigated, the whole
population was finally put onto the national database. But there were many
people living in this country who didn t fulfil the exacting requirements of
citizenship. So, the government, having invested billions in the program,
requisitioned a small city in the Midl ands to dump the leftovers in. Coventry, a
haven for aliens.
According to Agamben (1998: 109), what binds the life of those considered as
non-citizens to sovereign power is the notion of the ban; a relation of exception
that is both inclusive and exclusive of life and in which the banned is made subject
to the rule of the law while being excluded from it and abandoned by it: He, who
has been banned is not, in fact, simply set outside the law and made indifferent to it,
but rather abandoned by it, that is, exposed and threatened on the thres hold in which
life and law, outside and inside, become indistinguishable (ibid.: 28).
Review of Another Paradise 323
ENOCH: They just left them there?
LISA: Up the creek without a paddle.
ENOCH: No communication with the outside world.
LISA: Its shielded. A measure of containment.
ENOCH: And no one has to prove who they are, just names.
LISA: Just names, can you imagine?
ENOCH: Nothing but a blur.
Importantly, this rationality of abandonment and exception is not tantamount to
the casting out of politics or the cancellation of what is deemed as the norm. Instead
it is regarded as an integral part of normal politics itself and a condition of
possibility for its actualisation and organisation. As Rajaram and Grundy-Warr
(2004: 34, 36) argue, the condition of exemption by which the normal political
space is declared entails that the norm is dependent on its exempted other []itis
through the appropriation and control of the excluded, in effect its inclusion with its
threat ameliorated, that the sovereign law maintains itself. Lisa Grundys above-
mentioned statement, about Coventry being the price one pays for freedom, is indeed
indicative of the intimate and co-dependent relationship between exception and the
norm, between the sovereign inside and its (imagined) dangerous outside. It also
echoes the neoliberal modality of governing through freedom, which takes as its
premise the logic of individual autonomisation, that is, the governing of individuals
as subjects of freedom (see Rose 1999; Miller and Rose 2008; van Munster 2005).
Freedom, as such, is seen as both an objective to strive for and a resource to be
enabled and managed through the myriad of techniques and technologies such as
biometrics and ID cards. Concurrently, in the neoliberal style of governing, freedom
also involves the control and monitoring of that which poses a (potential) threat to its
exercise, and the (inclusive) exclusion of those who cannot be entrusted to enjoy
freedom (van Munster 2005: 6). Coventry, in this regard, can be seen as an extension
to such techniques and strategies, and a constitutive element to the maintenance of
the norm. This, insofar as it represents a means by which residual otherness and its
perceived dangerousness are regulated and contained with the aim to facilitate the
exercise of freedom (of access and mobility, for instance) for those who qualify as
belonging citizens and to minimise the supposed disturbance and threat of those who
do not.
Perhaps the plays most sinister message, and one that mostly resonates with
Agambens alarming accounts, is to do with the fine and fragile line that
distinguishes between citizens and non-citizens. In a society that is overly dependent
on technology rather than politics for organising the life of its inhabitants, there is
always the looming danger of turning exception into the norm, rendering every
citizen as a potential non-citizen; every identity as a suspect identity, and maki ng the
space of exception, such as that of Coventry, the fundamental paradigm of the city
itself.
Yet despite this bleak picture and ominous accounts, both Kents play and
Agambens thesis manage to leave a room for hope and potentiality. Curiously, it
seems that it is precisely within these zones of indistinction (between exception and
norm, life and non-life, citizen and non-citizen, city and camp, etc.) that the possibility
for resistance might exist and that the resuscitation of the political might take place. For
324 B. Ajana
instance, Coventry, against all odds, becomes the sole place where a sense of community
and human touch still subsist, unfettered by the need for identification and unburdened
by the imperative to constantly prove onesentitlements.
To a certain extent, then, Another Paradise has succeeded in interweaving the
different concerns surrounding biometric technology and ID cards together with the
enduring philosophical questions regarding identity, rights and belonging. And in
this sense, it has undoubtedly done what a thesis play has to do: exposing some of
the most pertinent, problematic and controversial socio-political issues of our time,
and stimulating further thinking and debate.
References
Aas KF. The body does not lie: identity, risk and trust in technoculture. Crime Media Culture. 2006;2:2.
Agamben G. Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life, Stanford University Press, 1998.
Arendt H. The human condition. Chicago: Chicago University Press; 1957.
Butler J. Giving an account of oneself. New York: Fordham University Press; 2005.
Cavarero A. Relating narratives: storytelling and selfhood. London and New York: Routledge; 2000.
Deleuze G. Postscript on the Societies of Control. http://pdflibrary.files.wordpress.com/2008/02/
deleuzecontrol.pdf, 1992.
Haggerty KD, Ericson RV. The Surveillant Assemblage. Br J Sociol. 2000;51:4.
Kent S. Another Paradise. Kali Theatre Production, 2009.
Kottman PA. Translator Introduction. In Relating Narratives: Storytelling and Selfhood, Cavarero. A.,
London: Routledge, 2000.
Miller P, Rose N. Governing the present: administering economic, social and personal life. Cambridge:
Polity; 2008.
Nancy J-L. Being singular plural. Stanford: Stanford University Press; 2000.
Nyers P. Abject Cosmopolitanism: the politics of protection in the anti-deportation movement. Third
World Q. 2003;24:6.
Rajaram PR, Grundy-Warr C. The irregular migrant as homo sacer: migration and detention in Australia,
Malaysia, and Thailand. Int Migr. 2004;42:1.
Ricoeur P. Oneself as another. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press; 1992.
Rose N. Powers of Freedom: Reframing political thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1999.
Schmitt C. Ex capitivitate salus. Cologne: Greven Verlag; 1950.
Van Munster R. The EU and the Management of Immigration Risk in the Area of Freedom, Security an
Justice. University of Southern Denmark Political Science Publications, 2005.
Zylinska J. The universal acts. Judith Butler and the biopolitics of immigration. Cult Stud. 2004;18:4.
Review of Another Paradise 325
ResearchGate has not been able to resolve any citations for this publication.
Article
Full-text available
The securitisation of migration in Western states has resulted in an array of restrictive laws and policies that raise important questions about the relationship between protection and the political. New technologies of control (such as detention) and strategies of exclusion (such as deportation) are rapidly undermining—indeed, effectively criminalising—national cultures of asylum. This article critically analyses how these measures are being contested and countered by the anti-deportation activism of undocumented non-citizen people in Canada. How are these campaigns re-casting the question of ‘protection’ in the face of deportation efforts by the Canadian state? This is a significant issue because the capacity to decide upon matters of inclusion and exclusion is a key element of sovereign power. In the case of asylum seekers, the ability to decide who will and will not be provided with protection is interpreted in this paper as a focal point where the state (re)founds its claim to monopolise the political. Consequently, disputes over who has the authority to protect, who will be protected, and under what terms and conditions, can reveal new problematisations as well as new ways of thinking and acting politically. Employing the conceptual framework of abject cosmopolitanism, this article seeks to understand how these campaigns are, and are not, reformulating the terms of political community, identity and practice.
Book
What does it mean to lead a moral life? This book offers a provocative outline for a new ethical practice—one responsive to the need for critical autonomy and grounded in a new sense of the human subject. It takes as her starting point one's ability to answer the questions “What have I done?” and “What ought I to do?” The book shows that these questions can be answered only by asking a prior question, “Who is this who is under an obligation to give an account of itself and to act in certain ways?” Because I find that I cannot give an account of myself without accounting for the social conditions under which I emerge, ethical reflection requires a turn to social theory. In three chapters, the book demonstrates how difficult it is to give an account of oneself, and how this lack of self-transparency and narratibility is crucial to an ethical understanding of the human. In brilliant dialogue with Adorno, Levinas, Foucault, and other thinkers, it eloquently argues the limits, possibilities, and dangers of contemporary ethical thought. The book offers a critique of the moral self, arguing that the transparent, rational, and continuous ethical subject is an impossible construct that seeks to deny the specificity of what it is to be human. We can know ourselves only incompletely, and only in relation to a broader social world that has always preceded us and already shaped us in ways we cannot grasp. If inevitably we are partially opaque to ourselves, how can giving an account of ourselves define the ethical act? And doesn't an ethical system that holds us impossibly accountable for full self-knowledge and self-consistency inflict a kind of psychic violence, leading to a culture of self-beratement and cruelty? How does the turn to social theory offer us a chance to understand the specifically social character of our own unknowingness about ourselves? By recasting ethics as a project in which being ethical means becoming critical of norms under which we are asked to act, but which we can never fully choose, the book illuminates what it means for us as “fallible creatures” to create and share an ethics of vulnerability, humility, and ethical responsiveness.
Book
The literature on governmentality has had a major impact across the social sciences over the past decade, and much of this has drawn upon the pioneering work by Peter Miller and Nikolas Rose. This volume will bring together key papers from their work for the first time, including those that set out the basic frameworks, concepts and ethos of this approach to the analysis of political power and the state, and others that analyse specific domains of the conduct of conduct, from marketing to accountancy, and from the psychological management of organizations to the government of economic life. Bringing together empirical papers on the government of economic, social and personal life, the volume demonstrates clearly the importance of analysing these as conjoint phenomena rather than separate domains, and questions some cherished boundaries between disciplines and topic areas. Linking programmes and strategies for the administration of these different domains with the formation of subjectivities and the transformation of ethics, the papers cast a new light on some of the leading issues in contemporary social science modernity, democracy, reflexivity and individualisation. This volume will be indispensable for all those, from whatever discipline in the social sciences, who have an interest in the concepts and methods necessary for critical empirical analysis of power relations in our present.
Article
The article suggests that surveillance of the body is gradually becoming a major source of identification, as well as a vital element of late-modern mechanisms of social exclusion. The increasing demand for technological verification of identity is a result of intricate connections between our notions of the self, order, efficiency and security. Behind the growing acceptance of these new technologies, such as biometric passports, biometric ID cards, drug testing, and DNA databases, are fears connected to those who may have a ‘stolen identity’, are unidentified, or ‘identity-less’, such as potentially fraudulent welfare recipients, ‘identity thieves’, terrorists, immigrants and asylum seekers. However, unlike Foucault's disciplinary power, the latest technologies no longer see the body as something that needs to be trained and disciplined, but rather as a source of unprecedented accuracy and precision. Bodies become ‘coded’ and function as ‘passwords’. This form of identification is particularly relevant since its mode of operation enables identification and denial of access at-a-distance, thus fitting perfectly into the contemporary modes of disembedded global governance.
Article
Drawing on official acts of Western multicultural democracies - predominantly the UK Nationality, Immigration and Asylum Act (2002) and its accompanying documents and actions - this article investigates, via an engagement with Judith Butler, the constitution of 'the biopolitics of immigration'. It also argues that the biopolitics of immigration both presupposes - in the form of an injunction - and produces a certain ethics: what the author calls, drawing on Butler's work, 'an ethics of bodies that matter'. This 'ethics of bodies that matter' will be seen as a source of political hope; it will guarantee the possibility of enacting differently the political acts that regulate the issues of asylum, immigration and nationality.