ArticlePDF Available

Abstract

We review how the construct of the moral self has arisen within moral development theory and discuss the search for integrative linkages with other domains of psychology, including personality. Next, we describe moral personality and then programs and approaches to developing moral identity in children. Moral schema development and moral information‐processing research is outlined, including mapping expert‐novice differences. Finally, we conclude with two emerging integrative theories, one on educational intervention for moral skill development and the other a neurobiological model of moral functioning which draws on evolutionary themes in the development of a moral brain.
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:41 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
CHAPTER EIGHT
Moral Identity, Moral Functioning,
and the Development of
Moral Character
Darcia Narvaez and Daniel K. Lapsley
Contents
1. Introduction 240
2. Moral Self-Identity 241
2.1. Ethical Theory and Moral Development 241
2.2. Blasi on Moral Identity 243
2.3. Personality Theory 245
3. Development of Moral Self-Identity 250
3.1. Early Development of Moral Personality 251
3.2. Community and Context Models of Moral Identity 254
4. Schemas and Moral Information Processing 258
4.1. Moral Schemas 259
5. Moral Development as Ethical Expertise Development 260
5.1. An Integrative Framework for Moral Character Education 262
6. New Directions: Neuroscience and Moral Personality 263
6.1. Triune Ethics Theory: A Neurobiological Theory
of Moral Development 264
7. Conclusions 266
7.1. Experience Shapes Brain Biases 266
7.2. Moral Functioning is Multivariate 266
7.3. Moral Experts are Different from Novices 267
References 267
Abstract
We review how the construct of the moral self has arisen within moral develop-
ment theory and discuss the search for integrative linkages with other domains
of psychology, including personality. Next, we describe moral personality and
then programs and approaches to developing moral identity in children. Moral
schema development and moral information-processing research is outlined,
including mapping expert-novice differences. Finally, we conclude with two
emerging integrative theories, one on educational intervention for moral skill
Psychology of Learning and Motivation, Volume 50 #2009 Elsevier B.V.
ISSN 0079-7421, DOI: 10.1016/S0079-7421(08)00408-8 All rights reserved.
239
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:42 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
development and the other a neurobiological model of moral functioning which
draws on evolutionary themes in the development of a moral brain.
1. Introduction
There are few more pressing problems before psychological science
than to account for human moral functioning. This is because moral agency
is crucial to our conception of what it means to be a person (Carr, 2001 Au1
).
The belief in our own moral integrity is so central to our self-understanding
that often we are tempted to shield it from refutation by recourse to
sanitizing euphemisms and protective belts of denial, rationalization, and
special pleading (Bandura, 1999). Indeed, as Taylor (1989) put it, ‘‘being a
self is inseparable from existing in a space of moral issues’’ (p. 112).
The alignment of moral integrity with our sense of self-identity might be
one of those facts about ourselves that is so obvious that it hardly bears
examination something along the lines of fish being the last to discover
water. This might go part of the way to explain the odd fact that the moral
self does not have a long research tradition in psychology; but there are
other explanations as well. These explanations point to paradigmatic doubts
about whether the self is a legitimate construct for a behavioral science, and
doubts evident in the study of moral development about how ‘‘thick’’ a self
must be to render a rationally adequate moral judgment.
It does not help that psychological research is fragmented and that
relevant fields of study, or even research programs within fields, do not
easily talk with one another. The relevance of findings on, say, motivation,
social cognition, or personality is not drawn easily for understanding moral
motivation, moral cognition, or moral personality. The literatures on
expertise, decision making, and of cognitive science more generally provide
few explicit guidelines for understanding moral expertise, moral decision
making, and moral cognition. Although self-identity has attracted signifi-
cant research attention for decades, the frameworks of developmental and
social psychologists who study it have often bypassed each other. Similarly
research on temperament, attachment, and other developmental processes
is often silent on their implications for the moral domain. Research on
moral development has availed itself rarely of the theories, constructs, and
methods of other disciplines; and these other disciplines rarely speculate on
the developmental trajectories that bring one to adult functioning. More-
over, those interested in the educational implications of the self divide on
the purpose and pedagogy of moral-character education, and on the very
terms of reference for understanding the moral dimensions of selfhood (see
Lapsley and Narvaez, 2006). What is virtue, for example, as a psychological
construct? How is character to be understood as a dimension of personality?
240 Darcia Narvaez and Daniel K. Lapsley
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:42 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
Fortunately there are signs that the estrangement of the moral self from
the main currents of contemporary psychological research is coming to an
end. Although the search for integrative linkages is of longer standing (e.g.,
Lapsley and Power, 1988; Lapsley and Quintana, 1985), there is a discern-
ible increase in the pace and momentum of integrative research on moral
cognition and moral self-identity (Narvaez and Lapsley, in press). Indeed,
the ascendance of the moral self now animates integrative research at the
intersection of several provinces of psychology, and, along with increasing
research into the neuroscientific (Sinnott-Armstrong, 2008) and evolution-
ary bases of moral behavior (Narvaez, 2008b), the appearance of handbooks
on moral development (Killen and Smetana, 2005) and education (Nucci
and Narvaez, 2008), it is now clear that moral psychology is enjoying a
renascence of interest in many areas of research.
In this chapter, we review how the construct of the moral self has arisen
within developmental studies of moral judgment, and how the search for
integrative linkages with other domains of psychology, particularly with
social cognition and personality, took on a certain urgency after the mar-
ginalization or collapse of the dominant stage-and-structure (‘‘Piagetian’’)
approaches to moral development. We examine theoretical approaches to
moral self-identity and moral personality, along with their developmental
accounts, including a broader integrative theory that implicates evolution-
ary themes in the development of a moral brain.
2. Moral Self-Identity
In this section, we begin our exploration of moral self-identity by
examining briefly how it is considered in recent ethical theory. We then
trace how Augusto Blasi’s view of the moral personality has evolved out of
the problematic of moral development theory. We then describe theories of
moral personality that have arisen in recent decades.
2.1. Ethical Theory and Moral Development
On Frankfurt’s (1971, 1988) influential account a person (as opposed to a
wanton) has a self-reflective capacity to examine his or her own desires and
to form judgments with respect to them. A person cares about the desirabil-
ity of his or her desires (‘‘second-order desires’’) and wishes to conform
the will in accordance with them (‘‘second-order volitions’’). Similarly
Taylor (1989) argues that a person is one who engages in strong evaluation,
that is, makes careful ethical discriminations about what is better and worse,
higher and lower, worthy and unworthy; and these discriminations are
made against a ‘‘horizon of significance’’ that frames and constitutes our
Moral Identity, Moral Functioning, and the Development of Moral Character 241
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:42 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
self-understanding (Taylor, 1989). Hence on this view our identity is
defined by reference to things that have significance for us. Moreover,
according to Taylor (1989) it is a basic human aspiration to be connected
to something of crucial importance, to something considered good, worthy,
and of fundamental value; and this orientation to the good ‘‘is essential to
being a functional moral agent’’ (Taylor, 1989, p. 42).
Hence, modern ethical theory draws a tight connection between per-
sonhood, identity, and moral agency. Moreover, the core notions of
second-order desires and the identity-defining commitments of strong
evaluation have found their way into recent psychological accounts of
moral identity (e.g., Blasi, 2005; Lapsley, 2007). How it has done so is
best considered from an historical reconstruction of Kohlberg’s influential
theory of moral development, for the stage-and-structure approach cham-
pioned by Kohlberg did not always welcome self-identity constructs into its
theoretical fold, and for a number of reasons.
First, Kohlberg’s theory appropriated the Piagetian understanding of
stage. This entailed treating the moral stage sequence as a taxonomic
classification of different kinds of sociomoral operations and not as a way
of charting individual differences. Moral stages, on this account, are not
‘‘boxes for classifying and evaluating persons’’ (Colby et al., 1983, p.11).
Instead they describe forms of thought organization of an ideal rational
moral agent, an epistemic subject, and hence cannot be ‘‘reflections upon
the self’’ (Kohlberg et al., 1983, p. 36). For this reason, it is not possible to
use moral stages as a way of making ‘‘aretaic judgments’’ about the self (or of
others), that is, of making judgments about one’s moral worthiness as a
person.
Second, Kohlberg thought that the behavioral manifestation of character
traits could not be empirically confirmed. After all, the Hartshorne and May
(1928–1930) studies appeared to show that certain dispositions (‘‘honesty’’)
did not exhibit the cross-situational consistency thought necessary for
character traits. Third, deeply personological constructs were viewed as
obstacles to mature moral deliberation, or as sources of bias and backsliding
that had to be surmounted by the rational moral agent. This follows from a
Kantian view of the person as one beset by contending forces the force of
reason and the force of bodily desires and passions each slugging it out for
the control of the will (Johnson, 1993). If one links moral judgment too
closely to our deeper human nature to personality, to the self and its
desires, passions and inclinations, or to social particularities, relationships,
and identity-defining commitments, then one risks divorcing morality from
rationality. Self-identity and personality, on this view, are too adhesive to
bodily passions which can only compromise the universalizing tendencies
required of the ‘‘moral point of view’’ instantiated in the highest stages of
moral development. Finally, a focus on virtues and character traits was
thought to give aid and comfort to ethical relativism and was therefore a
242 Darcia Narvaez and Daniel K. Lapsley
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:43 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
poor guide to moral education. As Kohlberg and Mayer (1972, p. 479)
famously put it:
Labeling a set of behaviors displayed by a child with positive or negative
trait terms does not signify that they are of adaptive significance or ethical
importance. It represents an appeal to particular community conventions,
since one person’s integrity’ is another person’s stubbornness, [one person’s]
honesty in expressing your true feelings’ is another person’s insensitivity’to
the feelings of others.
Hence Kohlberg’s cognitive developmental approach to moral socialization
did not leave much room for dispositional factors, and required only a thin
conception of the ‘‘responsible self’’ in order to account for how moral
cognition gets translated into moral action. For Kohlberg the responsible
self is aware of the prescriptive nature of moral judgments and hence acts
upon them, though awareness of this link is most pronounced at the highest
stages of moral reasoning.
Of course, Kohlberg’s moral stage theory no longer sets the agenda in
moral development research despite the strength of empirical findings sup-
porting at least neo-Kohlbergian models of development (e.g., Rest et al.,
1999). The general decline of the Piagetian paradigm is one part of the
explanation for the marginalization of moral stage theory. Other explanations
point to factors internal to Kohlberg’s theory, such as doubts about how to
understand fundamental concepts, such as stage and structure (Lapsley, 2005).
Yet it also became clear that Kohlberg’s theory could not help us understand
the moral formation of children, nor provide guidance for parents about how
to raise children of a certain kind children whose personalities are imbued
with a strong ethical compass. Although the strictures of moral stage theory
forbid aretaic judgments, they come easier to most everyone else; and it was
the inability of moral stage theory to engage issues of character, selfhood, and
personality that contributed to its diminishing visibility in developmental
science, and to increasing recognition that the field was at an important
crossroads (Lapsley and Narvaez, 2005).
2.2. Blasi on Moral Identity
The relative neglect of self, identity, and personality in accounts of moral
development has now come to an end. Beginning with the pioneering
work of Blasi (1984, 1985), it is now evident that moral psychology is
catching up with ethical theory in proposing thicker conceptions of moral
personhood so that talk of moral self-identity and moral personality are now
commonplace (Blasi, 2005; Lapsley, 2007; Lapsley and Narvaez, 2004a;
Narvaez and Lapsley, in press; Walker and Frimer, in press).
Blasi’s contributions to moral psychology can be described usefully in
terms of five key themes that emerged in his writings. His early writings
Moral Identity, Moral Functioning, and the Development of Moral Character 243
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:43 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
focused on the Self Model of moral action and moral identity. Later he took
up the intentional self, the nature of moral character, and the development
of the moral will. Throughout this work Blasi is influenced clearly by the
notion of second-order desires (Frankfurt) and of the identity-defining
commitments of strong evaluation (Taylor).
The Self Model of moral action was developed in response to the
disappointing finding that moral judgment did not predict moral action
very strongly (Blasi, 1983). In contrast to Kohlberg’s position, Blasi argued
that moral action did not follow directly from a deontic judgment but was
instead filtered through a set of calculations that implicated the very integ-
rity of the self. According to Blasi (1983) moral structures are only indirectly
related to moral action. They serve to appraise the moral landscape, but do
not directly generate action. Just because an agent appraises the social
situation through the lens of sophisticated moral criteria does not guarantee
that the agent will also see the personal relevance of the situation, or even its
relevance for morality.
The Self Model holds that action is more likely to follow moral judg-
ment when moral considerations are deemed essential and core to one’s
personal identity. After one makes a moral judgment one must next filter
this judgment through a second set of calculations that speaks to the issue of
whether the self is responsible. Responsibility judgments attempt to sort out
the extent to which the morally good action is strictly necessary for the self.
Moreover, the criteria for reaching responsibility judgments are a matter of
individual differences insofar as it varies in accordance with one’s self-
definition. Is acting in this way so necessary for my self-understanding
that not to act is to lose the self? Are moral notions so central to my identity
that failing to act, or indulging in excusing rationalizations, is to undermine
what is core to my personhood? Blasi suggests that the cognitive motivation
for moral action springs from this sense of fidelity to oneself-in-action.
It springs from a tendency toward self-consistency, which he views as a
cognitive motive for objectivity and truth. It springs from a moral identity
that is deeply rooted in moral commitments commitments so deeply
rooted, in fact, that to betray these commitments is also to betray the self.
Hence moral action, and inaction, implicates the self in important ways.
As McFall (1987, p. 12) put it:
We all have things we think we would never do, under any imaginable
circumstances; some part of ourselves beyond which we will never retreat,
some weakness however prevalent in others that we will not tolerate in
ourselves. And if we do that thing, betray that weakness, we are not the persons
we thought: there is nothing left that we may even in spite refer to as I.
Unconditional moral commitments that are core, deep, and essential to our
self-understanding contributes to our sense of personal integrity-in-action.
These are the ‘‘deepest most serious convictions we have; they define what
244 Darcia Narvaez and Daniel K. Lapsley
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:43 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
we would not do, what we regard as outrageous and horrible; they are the
fundamental conditions for being ourselves, for the integrity of our char-
acters depends upon them’’ (Kekes, 1989, p. 167).
But moral identity is a dimension of individual differences, that is, it is
a way of talking about personality, but this time one’s moral personality
is grounded by reference to moral reasons. One has a moral identity to the
extent that moral notions, such as being good, being just, compassionate,
or fair, is judged to be central, essential, and important to one’s self-
understanding. One has a moral identity when one strives to keep faith
with identity-defining moral commitments, and when moral claims stake
out the very terms of reference for the sort of person one claims to be.
Blasi’s account of the moral personality, his elevation of the subjective
self-as-agent as an object of inquiry, his insistence on the rational, inten-
tional nature of distinctly moral functioning, and his integration of self and
identity with moral rationality and responsibility is a singular achievement
(Lapsley and Narvaez, 2004a). His theory of moral identity also has empiri-
cal consequences. It is invoked, for example, to explain the motivation of
individuals who sheltered Jews during the Nazi Holocaust (Monroe, 1994,
2001, 2003); and it underwrites a line of research on the psychological
characteristics of ‘‘moral exemplars’’ whose lives are marked by uncommon
moral commitment. For example, studies of adult (Colby and Damon,
1991) and adolescent (Hart and Fegley, 1995; Matsuba and Walker, 2004,
2005; Reimer, 2003) moral exemplars typically reveal that exemplars align
their self-conceptions with ideal moral goals and personality traits, and that
their moral action is undertaken as a matter of felt self-necessity.
Blasi returned long-forgotten concepts to the vocabulary of modern
psychology, including desire, will, and volition, and added new concepts,
such as self-appropriation and self-mastery. To date these concepts have
resisted straightforward translation into empirical research. Moreover there is
no consensus on how to measure moral identity, which is a centerpiece
of Blasian moral theory. Alternative approaches to moral identity have
emerged that while friendly toward the general Blasian framework nonetheless
have starting points other than the subjective self-as-agent.
2.3. Personality Theory
There is an emerging consensus that the study of moral rationality can no
longer be studied in isolation from the broader context of personality
(Walker and Hennig, 1998; Lapsley and Narvaez, 2004b). For too long
the study of moral judgment was pursued at the expense of studying the
moral agent as a whole person (Walker, 1999). As a corrective it seems
reasonable to insist that if moral self-identity (or ‘‘character’’) is a dimension
of individual differences, and if it is the moral dimension of personality, then
Moral Identity, Moral Functioning, and the Development of Moral Character 245
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:44 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
our accounts of these constructs must be compatible with well-attested
models of personality. But which model?
Modern personality theory provides a number of options. Cervone
(1991) argues, for example, that personality psychology divides into two
disciplines on the question of how best to conceptualize the basic units of
personality. One discipline favors trait/dispositional constructs, the second
discipline favors social-cognitive constructs. The traits/disposition approach
(e.g., Costa and McCrae, 1992) accounts for the structure of personality
in terms of between-person classification of interindividual variability.
Individual differences are captured in terms of ‘‘top-down’’ dispositional
constructs as might be found in latent variable taxonomies identified
through factor analysis, such as the Big 5 taxonomy (extraversion, neuroti-
cism, conscientiousness, agreeableness, and open-to-experience).
In contrast, the social-cognitive approach understands the structure of
personality in terms of intraindividual, cognitive-affective mechanisms, and
attempts to account for individual differences from the ‘‘bottom-up,’’ that
is, in terms of specific, within-person psychological systems that are in
dynamic interaction with changing situational contexts (Cervone, 2005;
Cervone and Tripathi, in press). Scripts, schemas, episodes, plans, proto-
types, and similar constructs are the units of analysis for social-cognitive
approaches to personality.
Cervone’s ‘‘two disciplines’’ of personality has been joined by the ‘‘new
Big 5’’ conceptualization proposed by McAdams and Pals (2006) as an
integrative framework for personality science. The framework begins with
the general evolutionary design for human nature (Level 1) as it is expressed
in broadband dispositional traits that are organized early in development
(Level 2). Later personality comes to include characteristic adaptations to
specific contextual demands (Level 3), and then self-defining narratives
(Level 4) that are expressed differentially in broader social and cultural contexts
(Level 5). In this framework the personality is layered, with evolutionary
biology at the bottom and sociocultural context at the top. Of most interest
here are the three middle layers, dispositional traits, characteristic adaptations,
and self-defining narratives.
At Level 2 are dispositional traits like the Big 5 that encode those
broadband variations in human behavior that have made a difference in
human evolutionary history (McAdams, in press). These dispositional traits
show cross-situational consistency and developmental continuity. But
personality also is responsive to exigencies of specific contextual settings,
and this pattern of responsiveness is captured by Level 3 ‘‘characteristic
adaptations.’’ These include a large tool box of motivational, social-
cognitive, and developmental constructs such as favored defense mechan-
isms, coping strategies, schemas of various kinds, personal projects, beliefs,
goals, values, and ideologies. Finally, atop Level 2 dispositions and Level 3
adaptations is the construction at Level 4 of a life narrative that pulls
246 Darcia Narvaez and Daniel K. Lapsley
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:44 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
together the elements of one’s biography into a story that yields ideally a
sense of unity, coherence, and purpose.
2.3.1. Personality Theory and Moral Personality
Recent research in moral psychology has appealed to both the Big 5
taxonomy (McAdams) and to social-cognitive theory (Cervone). For exam-
ple, Walker and his colleagues have attempted to understand the personality
of moral exemplars in terms of McAdams’ Big 5 taxonomy. In one study,
the personality of moral exemplars was found to orient toward conscien-
tiousness and agreeableness (Walker, 1999). Agreeableness also character-
ized young adult moral exemplars (Matsuba and Walker, 2005). In a study
of brave, caring and just exemplars (as recognized by the Canadian honors
system), Walker and Pitts (1998) found that brave exemplars aligned with a
complex of traits associated with extraversion; caring exemplars aligned
with agreeableness, and just exemplars with a mixture of conscientiousness,
emotional stability, and openness to experience. This pattern was largely
replicated by Walker and Hennig (2004).
In contrast to McAdams’ Big 5 characterizations of moral personality are
social-cognitive theories that appeal to the availability and accessibility
of social-cognitive knowledge structures, such as schemas, scripts, and pro-
totypes (Aquino and Reed, 2002; Aquino and Freeman, in press; Lapsley
and Narvaez, 2004b). From this perspective schemas (rather than traits) are
the cognitive carriers of dispositions (Cantor, 1990; Cantor and Kihlstrom,
1987). Schemas ‘‘demarcate regions of social life and domains of personal
experience to which the person is especially tuned and about which he or
she is likely to become a virtual ‘expert’’’ (Cantor, 1990, p. 738). Schemas
that are frequently activated should, over time, become chronically accessi-
ble. Moreover, there should be individual differences in the accessibility of
constructs just because of each person’s unique social developmental history
(Bargh et al., 1988).
Hence schema accessibility shows interindividual variability but also
sustains patterns of individual differences over time, and is properly consid-
ered a personality variable (Higgins, 1996). For example, if schemas are
chronically accessible, then attention is directed selectively to certain fea-
tures of experience at the expense of others. It disposes one to select
schema-relevant life tasks, goals, or settings which, in turn, canalize and
maintain dispositional tendencies (which illustrate the reciprocal relation-
ship between persons and contexts). It encourages one to develop highly
practiced behavioral routines in those areas demarcated by chronically
accessible schemas, which provide ‘‘a ready, sometimes automatically avail-
able plan of action in such life contexts’’ (Cantor, 1990, p. 738).
Lapsley and Narvaez (2004b) and others (e.g., Aquino and Freeman, in
press) have invoked the social-cognitive framework to understand moral
Moral Identity, Moral Functioning, and the Development of Moral Character 247
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:44 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
personality. In this view, the moral personality is to be understood in terms
of the accessibility of moral schemas for social information processing.
A moral person, a person who has a moral character or identity, is one
for whom moral constructs is chronically accessible (moral chronicity),
where construct accessibility and availability are dimensions of individual
differences.
A social-cognitive model of moral personality has at least five attractive
features. First, it provides an explanation for the model of moral identity
favored by Blasi (1984) who argues that one has a moral identity just
when moral categories are essential, central, and important to one’s self-
understanding. A social-cognitive interpretation would add that moral
categories that are essential, central, and important for one’s self-identity
would also be ones that are chronically accessible for interpreting the social
landscape. These categories would be online, vigilant, easily primed, easily
activated, for discerning the meaning of events, for noticing the moral
dimensions of experience and, once activated, to dispose one to interpret
events in light of one’s moral commitments.
Second, this model accounts for the felt necessity of moral commitments
experienced by moral exemplars, their experience of moral clarity or felt
conviction that their decisions are evidently appropriate, justified, and true.
Typically moral exemplars report that they ‘‘just knew’’ what was required
of them, automatically as it were, without the experience of working
through an elaborate decision-making calculus (Colby and Damon, 1991).
Yet this is precisely the outcome of preconscious activation of chronically
accessible constructs that it should induce strong feelings of certainty or
conviction with respect to social judgments (Bargh, 1989; Narvaez and
Lapsley, in press).
Third, the social-cognitive framework is better able to account for the
implicit, tacit, and automatic features of moral functioning (Narvaez and
Lapsley, 2005). There is growing recognition that much of human decision
making is under nonconscious control (Bargh, 2005) and occurs with an
automaticity that belies the standard notions of rational, deliberative calcu-
lation (Bargh and Chartrand, 1999). Though this possibility offends tradi-
tional accounts of moral development, there is no reason to think that
automaticity is evident in every domain of decision making except the
moral domain. However, unlike the social intuitionist model (Haidt,
2001) which frontloads automaticity prior to judgment and reasoning as a
result of intuitions that are constitutive of human nature (and hence prior to
learning and enculturation) the social-cognitive approach to moral person-
ality locates automaticity on the backend of development as the result of
repeated experience, of instruction, intentional coaching, and socialization
(Lapsley and Hill, in press). It is the automaticity that comes from expertise
in life domains where we have vast experience and well-practiced behavioral
routines (Cantor, 1990).
248 Darcia Narvaez and Daniel K. Lapsley
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:45 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
Fourth, a social-cognitive model of the moral personality can account
for situational variability in the display of a virtue (Cervone and Tripathi, in
press). The accessibility of social-cognitive schemas underwrites not only
the discriminative facility in the selection of situationally appropriate behav-
ior, but also the automaticity of schema activation that contributes to the
tacit, implicit qualities often associated with the ‘‘habits’’ of moral character
(Lapsley and Narvaez, 2006).
Fifth, social-cognitive theory accords with the paradigmatic assumptions
of ecological ‘‘systems’’ models of development (Lerner, 2006). Both devel-
opmental systems and social-cognitive theory affirm that a dispositional
behavioral signature is to be found at the intersection of Person Context
interactions. Consequently, a preference for social-cognitive theory as a
way to conceptualize the moral personality reflects a strategic bet that it is
more likely to lead to robust integrative models of moral personality
development than are approaches driven by the Big 5. Similarly, Olson
and Dweck (2008) argue that the field of ‘‘social-cognitive development’’
(SCD) has strong integrative possibilities as it straddles the domains of social,
developmental, and cognitive psychology.
Recent research has attempted to document the social-cognitive dimen-
sions of moral cognition. For example, moral chronicity (chronic activation
of moral constructs in social information processing) appears to be a dimen-
sion of individual differences that influences spontaneous trait inference and
text comprehension (Narvaez et al., 2006). In two studies Narvaez et al.
(2006) showed that moral chronics and nonchronics respond differently to
the dispositional and moral implications of social cues. In addition, research
shows that conceptions of good character (Lapsley and Lasky, 2002) and of
moral, spiritual, and religious persons (Walker and Pitts, 1998) are organized
as cognitive prototypes.
Aquino and Reed (2002) proposed a model of moral identity that is
compatible with the tenets of social-cognitive theory. They define moral
identity as a self-schema that is organized around specific moral trait associa-
tions (e.g., caring, compassionate, fair, friendly, generous, helpful, hard-
working, honest, kind) that are closely linked in memory (in the manner of
spreading activation). They argue that moral identity has both a public and
private aspect. Privately, moral identity is a cognitive representation of the
moral self that reflects the degree to which moral traits are central to one’s
self-concept. Publicly, moral identity can be projected symbolically in the
forms of actions-in-the-world, or, alternatively, the degree to which the
traits are reflected in one’s public actions. The private aspect of moral
identity is labeled Internalization; the public aspect is labeled Symbolization.
These aspects are derived as subscales on an instrument that uses the nine
moral traits as ‘‘salience induction stimuli.’’ In some studies, these nine traits
are used as an experimental manipulation to prime the accessibility of moral
identity.
Moral Identity, Moral Functioning, and the Development of Moral Character 249
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:45 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
Aquino and Reed (2002) showed that both dimensions predicted self-
reported good deeds such as volunteering at a homeless shelter, organizing a
food drive, mentoring troubled youth, or visiting patients at a nursing home
‘‘in the past two years.’’ The self-importance of moral identity (‘‘Internali-
zation’’) was also a strong predictor of donating behavior in this study.
A strong sense of internalized moral identity predicts whether one will share
resources with outgroups or come to their aid (Reed and Aquino, 2003),
donate personal time for a charitable cause (Reed et al., 2007) or lie in a
business negotiation (Aquino and Freeman, in press). When individuals
with internalized moral identity do lie in a business negotiation, they are
strongly motivated to reduce its implication for the self by attempting
various strategies that serve to neutralize the sting of hypocrisy, such as
denial, denigrating the target, or minimizing the lie (Aquino and Becker,
2005). That said, when the self-importance of moral identity is high, it
undermines the effectiveness of moral disengagement mechanisms that
rationalize doing harm to others (Aquino et al., 2007).
3. Development of Moral Self-Identity
The literature on moral self-identity and the moral personality seems
largely preoccupied with sketching out what it looks like in its mature form
in adulthood. This is not inappropriate. Often it is useful, if not essential, to
get a handle on the telos of development before one can investigate the
possible developmental trajectories that gets one there (Kitchener, 1983).
Still, the relative paucity of work on the development of the moral self is
striking. This is due partly to the lack of interest in developmental ante-
cedents among personality, cognitive, and social psychologists, something
that an emergent field of SCD might remedy (Olson and Dweck, 2008).
But it is also due partly to a tendency among some development theorists
to treat moral acquisitions as a philosophical competency that must await
later stages of development. Or else to insist on such stringent and philoso-
phized conceptions of what counts as ‘‘moral’’ that extant and possibly
relevant developmental literatures are deemed unavailing and dismissed.
The moral self is isolated from other developmental processes and is treated
as some occult achievement that has a presumptive developmental history
but of which little can be said. Perhaps this is the negative side-effect of
starting with philosophical conceptions about what is ‘‘moral’’ about adult
moral personality and then trying to push this conception back in develop-
mental time in the search for antecedents. The result is a view we find
untenable, namely, that development brings a child to a tipping point at
which time he or she then becomes moralized. On this view attachment
processes, for example, or the organization of temperament or the child’s
250 Darcia Narvaez and Daniel K. Lapsley
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:45 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
expanding socio-emotional and cognitive competencies are not themselves
markers of the developing moral self nothing to see here but rather are
developmental achievements that are in need of something else (‘‘moraliza-
tion’’) before the moral domain takes notice.
Yet many extant literatures shed light on the foundation, emergence,
and trajectory of moral self development, although often they are not
unpacked to reveal their implications for moral development. Nonetheless
these literatures are forcing a reconsideration of certain views about young
children that have become calcified in the stage development literatures, for
example, the notion that infants lack an appreciation of subjectivity (cf.,
Repacholi, 1998), that toddlers are egocentric (cf., Gelman, 1979; Light,
1983), incapable of discerning intentions (cf., Nunez and Harris, 1998) or of
engaging in prosocial behavior (cf., Bar-Tal et al., 1982; Denham, 1986;
Dunn, 2006; Warneken and Tomasello, 2007), or of describing the self in
anything other than physicalistic or demographic terms (cf., Marsh et al.,
2002), and so on. ‘‘It was not long ago,’’ Thompson (2006, p. 25) remarked,
‘‘that characterizations of young children as egocentric, concrete, precon-
ventional, and preconceptual made this developmental period seem discon-
tinuous with the conceptual achievements of middle childhood and later.’’
This now discredited view of early childhood seemed to discourage
attempts to locate the early roots of moral self, personality and character
in the infancy, toddler, and early childhood years.
Take the stance of the Kohlberg paradigm on what constitutes a moral
action. A moral action, on this view, is an action undertaken for explicit
moral reasons. Moral action, under this definition, is most likely when one
discerns the moral norm and understands its prescriptive quality, and this is
most evident to individuals who are at the postconventional stages of moral
reasoning. Kohlberg’s team never studied toddlers or children. The age
range of their influential moral stage sequence begins much later in early
adolescence and extends to adulthood. So it is silent on what early child-
hood contributes to moral development (other than to assume a blanket
moral egocentrism), but leaves the impression that toddlers do not engage in
moral action thus defined or do not feel the prescriptive weight of the moral
law. The Kohlberg moral development sequence, then, is discontinuous
with the early child development processes, mechanisms, and acquisitions
that bring a child to its first Kohlbergian stage in late childhood or early
adolescence.
3.1. Early Development of Moral Personality
We now know, of course, that an intuitive morality is an early develop-
mental achievement. Soon after 18 months of age toddlers display an
awareness and responsiveness to normative standards across a wide range
of situations that includes, for example, their reacting with self-conscious
Moral Identity, Moral Functioning, and the Development of Moral Character 251
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:46 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
emotions and mark-directed behavior to a spot of rouge on their face when
looking in a mirror (Lewis and Brooks-Gunn, 1979); their expectations
about daily routines and events (Fivush et al., 1992), or for how persons
should act; or their negative reaction and concern to objects that are
disfigured, broken or marred in some way (Kagan, 2005).
What’s more toddlers have an early grasp of the different standards
of obligation that obtain in moral and conventional violations (Smetana,
1997) and for how prescriptive rules apply to different situations (Harris
and Nunez, 1996). They are aware of how things ought to be. They are
cognizant of adult standards and the notions of responsibility and account-
ability (Dunn, 1988). Clearly toddlers seem to be aware of a wide range of
conventional norms, and these serve as the foundation of an emerging
intuitive morality that belies a greater moral capacity than has been credited
to them (Thompson, in press). Indeed, the ‘‘relationships and other influ-
ences experienced in the early years set the context for the growth of an
empathic humanistic conception toward others, balanced self-concept,
capacities for relational intimacy, social sensitivity, and other capacities
conventionally viewed as achievements of middle childhood and adoles-
cence’’ (Thompson, 2006, p. 25).
The development of moral self-identity, of moral personality, and char-
acter, then, is a banal developmental achievement in the sense that it results
from ordinary developmental processes and mechanisms. The moral self
emerges in the dynamic transaction between the inductive capacities and
other personal qualities of the child and the familial and relational interac-
tions that provide the context for development. As a result theoretical
accounts of the developing moral self must take into account various person
variables, including temperament, self-regulation skills, theory of mind, and
conscience, but also contextual-relational variables, including attachment
security and the parental interactions that support it.
Kochanska and her colleagues (Kochanska, 2002a; Kochanska and
Aksan, 2004; Kochanska et al., 2004; Kochanska et al., 1995) have shown
how the moral self might emerge at the intersection of Person Context
interactions. They proposed a two-step model of emerging morality that
begins with the quality of parent–child attachment. A strong, mutually
responsive relationship with caregivers orients the child to be receptive to
parental influence (Kochanska, 1997a, 2002b).
This ‘‘mutually responsive orientation’’ (MRO) is characterized by
shared positive affect, mutually coordinated enjoyable routines (‘‘good
times’’), and a ‘‘cooperative interpersonal set’’ that describes the joint
willingness of parent and child to initiate and reciprocate relational over-
tures. It is from within the context of the MRO, and the secure attachment
that it denotes, that the child is eager to comply with parental expectations
and standards. There is ‘‘committed compliance’’ on the part of the child
to the norms and values of caregivers which, in turn, motivates moral
252 Darcia Narvaez and Daniel K. Lapsley
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:46 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
internalization and the work of ‘‘conscience.’’ This was documented in a
recent longitudinal study. Children who had experienced a highly respon-
sive relationship with mothers over the first 24 months of life strongly
embraced maternal prohibitions and gave evidence of strong self-regulation
skills at preschool age (Kochanska et al., 2008).
Kochanska’s model moves, then, from security of attachment (MRO) to
committed compliance to moral internalization. This movement is also
expected to influence the child’s emerging internal representation of the
self. As Kochanska et al. (2002a) put it:
Children with a strong history of committed compliance with the parent
are likely gradually to come to view themselves as embracing the parent’s
values and rules. Such a moral self, in turn, comes to serve as the regulator of
future moral conduct and, more generally, of early morality (p. 340).
But children bring something to the interaction, too, namely, their temper-
ament. Kochanska (1991, 1993) argues that there are multiple pathways to
conscience and that one parenting style is not uniformly more effective
regardless of the temperamental dispositions of the child. In particular, she
suggests that children who are highly prone to fearful reactions would profit
from gentle, low power-assertive discipline. This ‘‘silken glove’’ approach
capitalizes on the child’s own discomfort to produce the optimal level of
anxiety that facilitates the processing and retention of parents’ socialization
messages. But for ‘‘fearless’’ children another approach is called for, not the
‘‘iron hand,’’ which would only make the fearless child angry, highly
reactive, and resistant to socialization messages (Kochanska et al., 2007),
but rather one that capitalizes on positive emotions (rather than on anxiety).
Hence there are at least two pathways to the internalization of con-
science. For fearful children, it leads through the soft touch of gentle
discipline; for fearless children, it leads through the reciprocal positive
parent–child relationship. This has now been documented in a number of
studies (Kochanska, 1997b; Kochanska et al., 2005).
How does Kochanska’s model of the emergent moral self relate to
characterizations of adult moral self-identity reviewed earlier? Recall that
Blasian moral identity requires the moralization of self-regulation (‘‘will-
power’’) and integrity by moral desires. The moral personality, at its highest
articulation, is driven by a sense of ‘‘wholeheartedness,’’ by which Blasi
(2005) means that ‘‘a general moral desire becomes the basic concern around
which the will is structured’’ (p. 82). Wholehearted commitment to a moral
desire, to the moral good, becomes an aspect of identity to the extent that not
to act in accordance with the moral will is unthinkable.
But how do children develop wholehearted commitment to moral
integrity? What is the source of moral desires? How do children develop
the proper moral desires as second-order volitions? What are the develop-
mental pathways that bring us to the moral personality envisioned by Blasi’s
Moral Identity, Moral Functioning, and the Development of Moral Character 253
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:46 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
theory? We suggest that Kochanska’s model is a good place to start. The
developmental source of the moral personality lies in the shared, positive
affective relationship with caregivers. It emerges as a precipitate of the
‘‘cooperative interpersonal set’’ the mutual responsiveness and
shared ‘‘good times’’ that characterize the interpersonal foundation of
conscience.
This linkage is likely be resisted by Blasian moral theory because of the
presumption that Kochanska’s moral self only brings one to mere compliance
or mere internalization and therefore misses the subjective, agentic qualities
of the mature moral will. But the compliance of the emergent moral self is
not submission but rather a perceptual bias, an act of commitment that is
motivated by strongly charged, mutually shared, positive affective interper-
sonal relationships with caregivers. The desire to be moral, in other words,
is deeply social and therefore deeply emotional. There must be a develop-
mental source for the moral desires of the subjective self-as-agent, and these
arise from interpersonal relationships of a certain kind that are sustained over
time by social institutions by families, classrooms, schools, and neighbor-
hoods, characterized by affective bonds of attachment and community.
Indeed, there is strong evidence that caring classroom environments char-
acterized by strong bonding to teachers and school, and an abiding sense of
community, is associated with prosocial behavior and many positive devel-
opmental outcomes (Lapsley and Narvaez, 2006, for a review).
3.2. Community and Context Models of Moral Identity
One limitation of Blasi’s framework is that it is does not give much attention
to the social dimensions of self-identity. Kochanska helps us understand that
the source of self-control, integrity, and of moral desires is deeply relational;
moral self-identity emerges within a history of secure attachment. If
true, such a model underscores the importance of attachment to teachers
(Watson, 2008), school bonding (Catalano et al., 2004; Libby, 2004), and
caring school communities (e.g., Payne et al., 2003; Solomon et al., 1992) as
bases for continued prosocial and moral development. For example, Payne
et al. (2003) showed that when a school is organized and experienced as a
caring community its students report higher levels of bonding to school and
greater internalization of community goals and norms which are related to
less delinquency. Elementary school children’s sense of community leads
them to adhere to the values that are most salient in the classroom (Solomon
et al., 1996). At the same time, when high school students perceive a moral
atmosphere they report more prosocial and less norms-transgressive behav-
ior (Brugman et al., 2003). These findings show that secure attachments
promote committed compliance and lead to internalization of norms and
standards at every age.
254 Darcia Narvaez and Daniel K. Lapsley
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:47 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
3.2.1. Just Community
We examine two research programs to show the importance of community
beyond the family for moral identity development. First, Power (2004) and
Power and Higgins-D’Alessandro (2008) argue that the community is
critical for understanding the moral dimensions of the self insofar as the
self ‘‘does not experience a sense of obligation or responsibility to act in
isolation but with others within a cultural setting’’ (p. 52). Power brings to
the problem of self-identity a long interest in how classrooms and schools
can be transformed into ‘‘just communities’’ (Power et al., 1989). In a just
community there is a commitment to participatory, deliberative democracy
but in the service of becoming a moral community. Members of a commu-
nity a classroom or school commit to a common life that is regulated
by norms that reflect moral ideals. These shared norms emerge as a product
of democratic deliberation in community meetings. Here, the benefits and
burdens of shared lived experience are sorted out in a way that encourages
group solidarity and identification. One’s identification with the group and
its communal norms generate a moral atmosphere that conduces to moral
formation. Hence moral self-identity is a matter of group identification and
shared commitment to its value-laden norms. The moral self identifies with
the community by speaking on behalf of its shared norms and by taking on
its obligations as binding on the self.
Group identification is not simply awareness that one is a member of a
group, but rather that one is responsible for the group. The responsible self
is a communal self that takes on obligations and duties as result of shared
commitment to group norms. In order to illustrate a possible trajectory in
the development of the moral communal self, Power (2004) adapted Blasi’s
(1988) typology of identity (identity as observed,managed, and constructed )as
understood from the perspective of the subjective self-as-agent. In an early
phase, one simply acknowledges that one is a member of a group and is
bound thereby to group norms (identity observed ). Then, one speaks up
more actively in defense of a group norm, and urges the community to
abide by its commitments (identity managed ). Finally, one takes ‘‘legislative
responsibility for constructing group norms’’ (p. 55; identity constructed).
Power (2004) argues that the democratic process challenges members to
appropriate community group membership into one’s personal identity. He
writes:
This appropriation is rational and critical and is not a passive internalization
of group norms and values. Moreover, the appropriation of membership in
the community is to be based on the ideals of the community. In this sense
the identification with the community not only allows for but encourages a
critical stance toward its practices and commitment to change it (p. 55).
Class meetings are now a well-entrenched element of instructional
best practice, particularly at the elementary school level. Giving students
Moral Identity, Moral Functioning, and the Development of Moral Character 255
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:47 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
‘‘voice-and-choice’’ about classroom practices, giving them an opportunity
to share, to cooperate, to discuss, to take joint responsibility, are recognized
as important elements of character education (Lapsley and Narvaez, 2006).
But these salutary practices are still some distance from the goal of partici-
patory democratic decision making. Indeed most schools and classrooms
who endorse caring classroom communities as a moral educational goal
could not fairly be called ‘‘just communities’’ in the sense envisioned by
Power and his colleagues.
One problem is that the demands of academic accountability and the
pressure to make adequate yearly progress on mandated state examinations
tends to squeeze intentional, deliberate approaches to moral character
education out of the curriculum. Teachers find it difficult even to reserve
the ‘‘homeroom period’’ for building moral community. For this reason,
Power and his colleagues have targeted youth sports programs as an alterna-
tive location for moral character intervention. Here children and adoles-
cents might experience teams as a moral community, and coaching as a form
of moral education. Their program, called ‘‘Play Like a Champion’’ (2008),
teaches coaches to build an engaging team climate that emphasizes moral
principles (justice, tolerance, respect, and cooperation) using child-centered
strategies to advance the full personal development of the child.
3.2.2. Moral Development in Poor Neighborhoods
We turn to a second research program that underscores the importance of
community for moral identity development. Hart and Matsuba (in press) are
concerned mostly with how the larger contextual settings, such as poor
urban neighborhoods, influence enduring personality characteristics, and
the suite of mediating factors. The influence is not encouraging. Poor urban
neighborhoods generally provide a context that works against the formation
of moral identity or the commitment to moral projects. For example, living
in high-poverty neighborhoods tends to undermine moral attitudes and
values such as tolerance for divergent viewpoints (Hart et al., 2004). It
undermines personality resilience, and is associated with family dysfunction,
stress, and increases in problem behavior (Hart et al., 2003).
Moreover, very poor neighborhoods particularly those marked by
high levels of child saturation are less able to provide opportunities for
productive engagement in the community. This is because poor neighbor-
hoods are relatively lacking in the rich network of organizations that
support projects with moral goals. Indeed, adolescents in poor communities
form fewer connections with these institutions than do children in affluent
communities. They report fewer affiliations with clubs, teams, and youth
organizations (Hart and Matsuba, in press), and fewer opportunities for
volunteering. Institutional density, then, is a critical factor that influences
the availability of identity-defining options for adolescents. Opportunities
to engage in projects that facilitate the formation of moral identity are not
256 Darcia Narvaez and Daniel K. Lapsley
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:47 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
evenly distributed across communities, neighborhoods, and social strata,
which suggests that when it comes to the possibilities for structuring
moral identity there is an element of moral luck (Nagel, 1979; Williams,
1971) in the way one’s moral life goes (Hart, 2005).
3.2.3. Community Service and Social Capital
Of course the association between thin networks of community organiza-
tions and depressed rates of volunteering in very poor, child saturated
neighborhoods does suggest a possible intervention strategy. There is
mounting interest, for example, in providing service learning and commu-
nity service opportunities for youngsters in poor urban neighborhoods as a
way of changing moral and civic attitudes and the sense of self-identity.
These forms of community service are associated with positive develop-
mental outcomes (Hart et al., 2008). In one study, social opportunities to
interact frequently with others in the community through social institu-
tional structures (church, community meetings) predicted voluntary com-
munity service in a nationally representative sample of adults (Matsuba et al.,
2007).
Community service may be both a catalyst for moral development but
also a signal of moral identity. In a longitudinal study, Pratt et al. (2003)
constructed a moral self-ideal index that was based on participants’ endorse-
ment of a set of six personal qualities (trustworthy, honest, fair, just, shows
integrity, and good citizen). At age 19 participants who had endorsed a high
moral self-ideal were more likely to participate in community activities. But
it was the community involvement that led to subsequent endorsement of
moral self-ideals. A strong moral self-ideal did not lead to community
involvement but was its result. This suggests that the best way to influence
attitudes and values is to first change behavior in this case in the direction of
greater community involvement (Pancer and Pratt, 1999). As Pratt et al.
(2003) put it, ‘‘community involvement by adolescents leads to the devel-
opment of some sort of sense of identity that is characterized by a greater
prominence of moral, prosocial values’’ (p. 579). And it does not seem to
matter whether youth involvement is one of service learning or simple
volunteering, or whether the service is voluntary or mandated (Hart et al.,
2008). In sum, service learning and volunteering increases social capital and
community participation, thereby deepening the connection of adolescents
to social institutions that provide a context for the construction of prosocial
commitments and moral self-identity. And this implicates institutional
density as a critical mediating variable.
Power’s work with youth sports underscores the importance of com-
munity and neighborhood effects on moral identity. This theme is pro-
nounced in Hart’s (2005) and Hart and Matsuba (in press) model of moral
identity. Hart’s model is the closest thing we have to a developmental
systems theory, one that articulates the multiple layers of influence on
Moral Identity, Moral Functioning, and the Development of Moral Character 257
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:48 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
moral identity that includes the endogenous, dispositional factors of the
developing child, the family dynamics in which he or she is raised, and the
neighborhood in which the family resides. For Hart (2005) the constituents
of moral identity fall under two broad headings. Under the heading of
‘‘enduring characteristics’’ are personality and family constituents that are
relatively stable and hard to change. Under the heading of ‘‘characteristic
adaptations’’ are factors that mediate the relationship between enduring
characteristics and moral identity. One such factor, ‘‘moral orientation,’’
includes attitudes, values, and the capacity for moral deliberative compe-
tence and reflection, particularly the tendency to appreciate the prescriptive
quality of moral judgments.
We have seen that in Blasi’s theory moral identity requires that self-
regulation and integrity be infused with moral desires. How moral desires are
structured depends importantly on experience with caregivers (Kochanska),
the practice of community (Power), and on neighborhood characteristics
that influence the resources required for identity exploration (Hart). What is
clear from these research programs is that a moral self takes time and experi-
ence to develop, and requires cultivation from those with more social
experience.
Particular experiences appear to make the difference in the development
of a child’s moral identity and moral understanding. What is the mechanism
for change? How does experience influence moral decisions and choices?
Schema theory provides an answer.
4. Schemas and Moral Information Processing
According to schema theories of development and understanding,
schemas are the key structures that reflect ongoing changes in under-
standing. Schemas (generalized knowledge structures) develop first from
sensorimotor experience, forming embodied knowledge that underlies
thought and language (Lakoff and Johnson, 1999). The individual inter-
prets subsequent experience according to existing schemas (assimilation)
and modifies them in kind and number in response to new information
(accommodation) in a continuous process of growth, change, and equili-
bration (Piaget, 1970). For example, children with warm responsive parents
build positive, prosocial schemas about relating to others that they apply to
future relationships; children with community service experience build
schemas of self-efficacy in helping others, leading them to continue the
practice as adults.
Essentially, a schema is a cognitive mechanism that operates in one or
more brain systems (Neisser, 1976), including memory systems, such as
procedural or declarative knowledge (Hogarth, 2001; Kesner, 1986), and
258 Darcia Narvaez and Daniel K. Lapsley
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:48 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
types of reasoning, such as analogical and/or intuitive reasoning (Ericsson
and Smith, 1991; Hogarth, 2001). Schemas organize an individual’s opera-
tional activities, processing current experience according to concurrent
goals (Piaget, 1970; Rummelhart, 1980; Taylor and Crocker, 1981), influ-
encing perception, as well as decision making and reasoning (Girgenrize
et al., 1999).
Schemas develop from experience, and different types of experience
cultivate different types of schemas. This holds true for moral schemas
as well.
4.1. Moral Schemas
Life experiences transform moral schemas of all kinds, including schemas for
moral perspective taking, moral self-efficacy, and schemas for moral action
(Narvaez, 2006). Moral judgment development involves transformations in
how an individual construes obligations to others, reorganizing moral
schemas about how it is possible to organize cooperation (Rest et al.,
1999). With greater social experience (especially experiences that increase
perspective taking), an individual’s sense of moral obligation expands,
moving from concern for self, to concern for known others, to concern
for the welfare of strangers. Research with the Defining Issues Test (DIT)
(Rest, 1979; requires a 12-year-old reading level) has compiled results from
tens of thousands of respondents showing that there is progression from a
preference for the Personal Interest Schema in junior high (Kohlberg’s
stages 2 and 3), to a preference for the Maintaining Norms Schema in
high school (similar to Kohlberg stage 4), to a preference for Postconven-
tional Schema in graduate school (similar to Kohlberg’s stages 5 and 6; Rest
et al., 1999). (For more on schemas and moral judgment see Narvaez and
Bock, 2002.) Moral judgment development is stimulated by particular
experiences, such as intense diverse social experience (Rest, 1986) and
interventions that use moral dilemma discussion (Rest and Narvaez,
1994). Some experiences can depress scores on moral judgment measures,
such as fundamentalist ideology (Narvaez et al., 1999a).
4.1.1. Measuring Effects of Moral Schemas on Information
Processing: Development and Expertise
Everyday discourse processing requires domain-specific schema activation
for comprehension to take place (e.g., Alexander et al., 1989). Lack of
appropriate background knowledge when processing information in texts
leads to poor understanding (Bransford and Johnson, 1972), misrecall and
even distortion to fit with preexisting schemas (Bartlett, 1932; Reynolds
et al., 1982; Steffensen et al., 1979). Low-knowledge readers form inade-
quate mental models of the text, which leads to erroneous elaborations and
inferences during recall (Moravcsik and Kintsch, 1993).
Moral Identity, Moral Functioning, and the Development of Moral Character 259
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:48 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
Moral discourse processing is also influenced by differences in schema
development. In research examining the influence of moral judgment
schemas on moral information processing, Narvaez (1998) found that
moral judgment sophistication among adolescents over and above age
influenced what was accurately and inaccurately recalled when remember-
ing narratives about moral situations. Similarly, when tested for theme
comprehension in children’s moral stories, children did not grasp messages
as intended by the author or understood by adult readers, taking away more
simplistic, concrete messages based on limited schema development; even at
age 11 less than half of participants understood the intended theme (Narvaez
et al., 1998; Narvaez et al., 1999b). Before adulthood, life experience as
measured by age, plays a large role in moral discourse comprehension.
Among adults, life experience also matters. Extensive, coached immer-
sion in a domain increases the sophistication and organization of schemas,
usually termed ‘‘expertise’’ (Sternberg, 1998). Experts and novices have
been compared using reading tasks, distinguishing novices from experts in
multiple domains (e.g., Singer et al., 1997; Spilich et al., 1979). Schema
effects can be studied between novices and experts in moral judgment using
discourse-processing tasks, distinguishing the effects of general development
from studied expertise (Narvaez and Gleason, 2007). As an ill-structured
domain
1
(King and Kitchener, 1994), the complexity of moral functioning
may be better studied with discourse processing because of the variety of
schemas that can be brought to the task.
Knowledge in virtually every domain can be characterized as that in
which expertise can be developed, including domains of study in school
(Bransford et al., 1999). In the domain of morality, there are many sub-
domains beyond moral judgment; these can also be viewed as domains in
which expertise can be fostered.
5. Moral Development as Ethical
Expertise Development
Taking the view of the mind sciences today and looking back, one can
see that the ancients (e.g., Aristotle, 1988; Mencius, 1970) considered virtue
as a form of expertise. The virtuous person is like an expert who has a set
of highly cultivated skills, perceptual sensibilities, chronically accessible
schemas for moral interpretation, and rehearsed sequences for moral action.
Moral exemplars display moral wisdom (knowing the good) and practical
1
Domains can be parsed as ‘‘ill-structured’’ domains, characterized by uncertainty about the problem,
feasibility of actions and goodness of solution, or ‘‘well-structured’’ domains, like baseball, which are
completely specified in terms of possible actions and outcomes (Chase and Simon, 1973).
260 Darcia Narvaez and Daniel K. Lapsley
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:49 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
wisdom (knowing how to carry it out in the situation). In contemporary
terms, the expert has sets of procedural, declarative, and conditional knowl-
edge that are applied in the right way at the right time. Expertise is being
used to characterize knowledge in every domain, including the moral
domain (see Narvaez, 2005, 2006, for more details and references).
Experts and novices differ from one another in several fundamental ways.
Experts have more and better organized knowledge (Sternberg, 1998) that
consists of declarative (explicit), procedural (implicit) and conditional
knowledge, much of which operates automatically. In brief, experts know
what knowledge to access, which procedures to apply, how to apply them,
and when. Expert perception picks up underlying patterns novices miss,
including affordances for action (Neisser, 1976). Adaptive experts use intui-
tion as well as explicit knowledge to come up with innovative solutions to
problems in their domain (Hatano and Inagaki, 1986).
In the realm of morality, expertise can take different forms. Using Rest’s
four-component model of moral behavior, we can map expert behavior in
the four processes required for moral action to take place: ethical sensitivity,
ethical judgment, ethical focus, and ethical action or implementation
(Narvaez and Rest, 1995; Rest, 1983). Experts in Ethical Sensitivity can
speedily and precisely discern the elements of a moral situation, to take the
perspectives of others and determine what role they might play. Experts in
Ethical Judgment access multiple tools for solving complex moral problems.
They can reason about duty and consequences, and draw up rationale for
one course of action or another. Experts in Ethical Focus cultivate ethical
identity that leads them to prioritize ethical goals. Experts in Ethical Action
know how to maintain focus and take the steps to complete the ethical
action. Experts in a particular virtue have highly tuned perceptual skills for
it, more complex and multiply organized knowledge about it, have highly
automatized responses. Expertise is a set of capacities that can be put into
effective action as skilled coping in the situation.
Expertise in moral reasoning and virtue can be cultivated like other
skills. Experts have explicit, conscious understanding of the domain as well
as intuitive, implicit knowledge. Experts in training receive instruction that
builds skills and theoretical understanding simultaneously. They are
immersed in situated practice while being coached by someone with
more expertise. They are immersed in well-functioning environments
that provide corrective feedback so that appropriate intuitions are formed.
In other words, expert-education in a particular domain cultivates delibera-
tive understanding and intuitions simultaneously (Abernathy and Hamm,
1995). During expert training, interpretive and action frameworks are
learned to automaticity, perception is honed to chronically accessed con-
structs (Hogarth, 2001).
Childrenare virtual novices in nearly every domain (Bransford et al., 1999).
In many aspects of morality, children are novices too. Novice-to-expert
Moral Identity, Moral Functioning, and the Development of Moral Character 261
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:49 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
instruction for ethical development brings together virtue development,
reasoning and emotion, intuition, and deliberation.
5.1. An Integrative Framework for Moral Character Education
A framework that attempts to bring together all the elements of ethical
character development for educators, parents, and community members is
the Integrative Ethical Education model (full references and explanation in
Narvaez, 2006, 2008a).
2
It proposes five empirically derived steps for ethical
character development. These have been applied in school settings (Narvaez
et al., 2004) but may be applied in any setting and with any age.
First, adults establish caring relationships with the child. Human brains
are wired for emotional signaling and emotional motivation (Greenspan and
Shanker 2004; Lewis et al., 2000; Panksepp, 1998). Caring relationships
drive school and life success (Masten, 2003; Watson, 2008). Moral exem-
plars indicate an early history with supportive caregivers (Walker and
Frimer, in press).
Second, adults establish a climate supportive of excellence in achieve-
ment and in ethical character. Social climates and cultures influence percep-
tions and behavior (Power et al., 1989). Caring schools and classrooms are
associated with multiple positive outcomes for students related to achieve-
ment and prosocial development (e.g., Catalano et al., 2004; Solomon et al.,
2002).
Third, adults foster ethical skills across activities (e.g., curriculum and
extracurriculum) based on skills in ethical sensitivity, judgment, focus, and
action, as mentioned above (see Narvaez, 2006 or Narvaez et al., 2004, for
skills lists). Educators use a novice-to-expert pedagogy in which intuitions
are developed through imitation of role models and timely and appropriate
feedback, immersion in activity with mentor guidance, and the practice of
skills and procedures across multiple contexts (Narvaez et al., 2003).
Through theoretical explanation and dialogue, adults coach the child (the
deliberative mind) in selecting activities and environments that foster good
intuitions (the intuitive mind). Adults guide the child in developing a
prosocial self-narrative of positive purpose and community responsibility
(Stipek et al., 1992).
Fourth, adults encourage student self-authorship and self-regulation, the
type of self-monitoring skills experts demonstrate (Zimmerman, 1998).
2
The expertise development approach was initially developed in the Minnesota Community Voices and
Character Education project, 1998–2002, a collaboration between the Minnesota Department of Education
(formerly the Department of Children, Families, and Learning) and the University of Minnesota with funds
from the U.S. Department of Education (USDE OERI Grant # R215V980001). Using materials provided by
the project designers and teacher-designed lessons, the skills approach had a significant effect on students in
schools that implemented broadly over 1 year time in contrast to a comparison group and to low implementing
schools (see Narvaez et al., 2004). Project materials may be obtained from the first author.
262 Darcia Narvaez and Daniel K. Lapsley
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:49 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
Adults help children understand that they themselves have to answer the
central life question, who should I be? The final responsibility for character
development lies with them. In an enriched moral environment, students
are provided with tools for self-regulation in character formation. When
solving problems, successful students learn to monitor the effectiveness of
their strategies and when necessary to alter their strategies to meet their goals
(Anderson, 1989). Aristotle believed that mentors are required for character
cultivation until the individual is able to self monitor, subsequently main-
taining virtue through the wise selection of friends and activities.
Fifth, adults work together to build communities that coordinate sup-
port and relationships across institutions to foster resiliency. Truly demo-
cratic ethical education empowers all involved educators, community
members, and students as they ally to learn and live together. It is in
community living that persons develop ethical skills and self-regulation for
both individual and community actualization (Rogoff et al., 2001). It is a
community who establishes and nourishes the individual’s moral voice,
providing a moral anchor, and offering moral guidance as virtues are
cultivated. When the connections among children’s life spaces of home,
school, and community are strengthened, children are adaptationally
advantaged (Benson et al., 1998).
An increasing number of scientists are realizing that adaptational advan-
tage arises early in life, at least from birth if not from conception (Gluckman
and Hanson, 2004). There appear to be epigenetically sensitive periods for
particular brain system development in which environments switch genes
on or off for life (e.g., Champagne and Meaney, 2006). The wiring of
neurobiological systems appears to matter for moral functioning as well.
6. New Directions: Neuroscience and
Moral Personality
As knowledge about human development increases, so too has interest
in the neurobiology of human behavior. For example, the neurobiology of
infant attachment is far more important than previously realized for lifetime
brain development and emotion regulation (Gross, 2007). There appear to
be critical periods for fostering the systems that lead to sociality (Karr-Morse
and Wiley, 1997). Developmental psychology finds that emotion regulation
development begins neonatally and crucially depends on the caregiver to
coregulate the infant’s emotions while the brain establishes its systems
(Lewis et al., 2000; Schore, 1994). The caregiver acts as an ‘‘external
psychobiological regulator’’ (Schore, 2001, p. 202) socially constructing
the brain (Eisenberg, 1995). The mammalian brain and nervous system
depend for their neurophysiologic stability ‘‘on a system of interactive
Moral Identity, Moral Functioning, and the Development of Moral Character 263
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:50 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
coordination, wherein steadiness comes from synchronization with nearby
attachment figures’’ (Lewis et al., p. 84 Au2
). Otherwise mammals can develop
erratic systems that are easily thrown off kilter in reaction to everyday
stressors (Hofer, 1994).
The field of affective neuroscience is demonstrating the centrality of
well-wired emotions for optimal brain functioning. ‘‘Emotive circuits
change sensory, perceptual, and cognitive processing, and initiate a host of
physiological changes that are naturally synchronized with the aroused
behavioral tendencies characteristic of emotional experience’’ (Panksepp,
1998, p. 49). Evidence for the importance of infancy and early childhood to
establish a mammalian brain’s emotional circuitry has been accumulating
since Harlow’s (1986) experiments. In fact, recent research documents the
critical importance of early caregiving on cognition (Greenspan and
Shanker, 2004), personality formation (Schore, 2003a,b), as well as gene
expression in emotional circuitry (e.g., Weaver et al., 2002).
6.1. Triune Ethics Theory: A Neurobiological Theory
of Moral Development
Indications are that early experience has a bearing on moral development as
well, in particular, the propensities for compassion and appreciation of
others. Fundamental to the shaping of emotion for a moral life is the
caregiving received in early life. Triune Ethics Theory (Narvaez, 2008b)
draws on evidence from neuroscience, anthropology, and other human
sciences to postulate that three general ethical motivations arise from the
neurobiological substrates of human evolution and influenced by early
experience: Security, Engagement, and Imagination. The ’’environment
of evolutionary adaptedness’’ (EEA) (Bowlby, 1988), as anthropologists
have recently spelled out (Hewlett and Lamb, 2005), plays a large role in
framing the emerging evidence on the effects of early experience on lifelong
propensities, including moral functioning.
The Security Ethic is rooted in the oldest parts of the brain, involving
the R-complex or the extrapyramidal action nervous system (Panksepp,
1998), structures of the brain that focus on survival through safety, domi-
nance, and status (MacLean, 1990). These systems are mostly hardwired and
become the default when systems underlying the other ethics are underde-
veloped or damaged. Situationally, when a person is threatened this ethic is
likely to be activated, marshaling defense and offense (fight or flight),
suppressing capacity for empathy (Mikulincer and Shaver, 2005), and exhi-
biting less flexible thinking (Stout, 2007). Long-term dispositional effects on
personality occur as well; extensive stress, abuse or neglect in the early years
can bring about a personality dominated by the Security Ethic (Henry and
Wang, 1998; Karr-Morse and Wiley, 1997). On the positive side, the
264 Darcia Narvaez and Daniel K. Lapsley
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:50 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
Security Ethic, worthwhile for occasional crises, engenders the values of
loyalty, hierarchy, self-control of softer emotions, and following precedent.
The second ethic, the Engagement Ethic, is rooted in the neurobiological
systems that Darwin (1871/1981) identified as the source for humans’ ‘‘moral
sense’’ the visceral-emotional nervous system on the hypothalamic-limbic
axis which underlie mammalian parental care and social bonding (Panksepp,
1998). These systems rely on warm, responsive caregiving for their develop-
ment (e.g., Schore, 1994). Involving multiple limbic and subcortical struc-
tures and neurotransmitters (see Moll et al., in press), these structures underlie
values of compassion, social harmony, and togetherness. Children develop a
sense of security through intersubjectively safe and close nurturing (Field and
Reite, 1985; Schore, 1994) that allows the systems related to the Engagement
Ethic to develop properly. For example, the oxytocin that accompanies
breastfeeding and snuggling is a pacifying and bonding agent (Carter, 1998;
Perry et al., 1995; Young et al., 2001). Through a secure attachment and from
extensive experiences of reciprocity and social exchange (Kochanska and
Thompson, 1997; Laible and Thompson, 2000), children develop a sense
of engaged enactive participation in social life, rooted in sensorimotor
sensibilities for justice (Lerner, 2002). Physiologically, the Security Ethic
and the Engagement Ethic are incompatible; the former is related to increased
stress hormones (norepinephrine/adrenaline) while the latter is related to
calming hormones (e.g., oxytocin).
The Imagination Ethic, controlled primarily by the more recent com-
ponents of the brain (neocortex, especially prefrontal cortex) collaborates
with and coordinates the other two ethics. It has the capacity (when
cultivated appropriately with responsive caregiving) for valuing universality,
concern for outsiders, and conceptualizing alternative sophisticated resolu-
tions of moral problems. Although more detached from the basic emotional
drives of the other ethics, the Imagination ethic generally is motivated
implicitly by one of the other ethics. Whereas the open-heartedness of the
Engagement ethic feeds an imagination of helpfulness and altruism, the self-
protective rigidity of the Security Ethic fosters an imagination toward
defense and perhaps offense. Children develop an ethical imagination
when caregivers provide in situ modeled and guided training of prosocial
perception and action (enactive learning) in their actions and words.
In brief, TET Au3
points to what is fundamental for optimal moral develop-
ment: neonatal and early childhood experiences, similar to those of the
environment of evolutionary adaptedness (Bowlby, 1988; Hewlett and
Lamb, 2005), that shape brain structures and brain wiring for general and
for moral functioning. Moral learning involves developing unconscious
‘‘somatic markers’’ (Damasio, 1994) for what are good and not-so-good
actions: ‘‘embodied (sensorimotor) structures are the substance of experience’’
which ‘‘motivate conceptual understanding and rational thought’’ (Varela,
1992/1999, p. 16). From recurrent patterns of sensory motor activity,
Moral Identity, Moral Functioning, and the Development of Moral Character 265
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:50 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
general cognitive structures, including moral cognitive structures, emerge.
In emphasizing the importance of early experience, TET advocates social
policies and practices that support children, families and communities, and
which build moral brains.
7. Conclusions
The field of moral development has traveled beyond a narrow focus
on moral judgment to include the moral self across the lifespan. No longer
relegated to an individual’s conscious moral reasoning, the scope has moved
beyond the individual and her decision making or his virtue. Moral devel-
opment and moral action are embedded in community contexts. Moral
functioning is assumed to involve the whole brain and multiple systems
inside and outside the individual. As moral psychology and the study of
moral persons expands across domains of psychology and human sciences,
the field will generate more intricate theories that offer more specific
guideposts for fostering moral persons and communities. We draw three
conclusions that bear on research into moral functioning generally.
7.1. Experience Shapes Brain Biases
First, brains are differentially shaped by experience. The processing of any
type of morally relevant information is mediated by the schemas that
individuals have developed through social experience from early life and
onward. When individuals have been immersed in social environments that
promote self-concern, especially during sensitive periods, it is likely that
their schemas for processing moral information differ from those in loving,
responsive environments. The latter build personalities that are agreeable
and conscientious. So, for example, Amish cultures who emphasize submis-
sion, solidarity and kindness (Kraybill, 1989) will also foster brains that view
the world differently from cultures that emphasize competition, dominance,
and individuality. Particular environments promote particular brain func-
tioning and biases. It is likely that most psychological studies in the United
States examine biases cultivated by the particular individualistic society in
which the participants were raised and that therefore do not represent the
full evolved palette of moral capacities.
7.2. Moral Functioning is Multivariate
Second, moral judgments comprise only one element of moral functioning
(which also includes moral perception, sensitivity, motivation/focus, and
implementation), an element that weakly predicts moral action (and what is
266 Darcia Narvaez and Daniel K. Lapsley
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:51 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
morality if it is not evident in action?). Studying moral judgments in the
laboratory tap into an aspect of moral functioning that represents declarative
or semantic knowledge that is not necessarily tied to self-concept or self-
responsibility or behavior. Moral identity may provide the greatest predic-
tive power to moral behavior because it has its roots in lived relationships.
Studying moral functioning in more ecologically valid ways, such as with
moral discourse processing (Narvaez, 1999), may allow for a greater under-
standing of the range of moral performance.
7.3. Moral Experts are Different from Novices
Third, examining differences in expertise offers a promising area of research.
From long immersion in the domain (10 years or 10,000 h; Simon and
Chase, 1973), experts build schemas that become automatically accessed and
applied. Chronic schema use is linked to automatic or chronic accessibility of
a construct, as true for morality as for any domain. Community-nominated
moral exemplars demonstrate a chronic merging of personal and moral goals
(Colby and Damon, 1991). Building chronicity through immersion and
guided experience such as democratic participation (Power) or community
service (Hart) are promising paths to building moral personality and
improved moral functioning (see Narvaez, 2005). Interventions should
include the full range of moral skill development, from moral perception
and sensitivity to moral action skills.
On a precautionary note, it appears that most laboratory research of
moral functioning is conducted on college students. It is not clear that
people under the age of 30 or so have fully developed capacities in the
prefrontal cortex, a key player in moral functioning (Luna et al., 2001), so
researchers of moral functioning in college students should keep in mind
that mature adults with intact brain function likely behave differently.
Novices are easily dumbfounded and college students are fairly inexperi-
enced about life. Studying adults would provide a better look at mature
moral functioning (Blasi, in press). However, adults may have sophisticated
capacities in a specific type of moral expertise (e.g., action) and not another
(e.g., judgment), and so research should examine what brings about these
differences and what implications they have for moral functioning generally.
REFERENCES
Abernathy, C. M. and Hamm, R. M. (1995). Surgical Intuition. Hanley & Belfus,
Philadelphia Au4
.
Alexander, P. A., Pate, P. E. and Kulikowich, J. M. (1989). Domain-Specific and Strategic
Knowledge: Effects of Training on Students of Differing Ages or Competence Levels.
Learning and Individual Differences, 1, 283–325.
Moral Identity, Moral Functioning, and the Development of Moral Character 267
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:51 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
Anderson, L. M. (1989). Learners and Learning, in edited by Reynolds, M. C. (ed.),
Knowledge Base for the Beginning Teacher (pp. 85–99). Pergamon Press, Oxford.
Aquino, K. and Becker, T. E. (2005). Lying in Negotiations: How Individual and Situational
Factors Influence the Use of Neutralization Strategies. Journal of Organizational Behavior,
26, 661–679.
Aquino, K. and Freeman, D. (in press). Moral Identity in Business Situations: A Social-
Cognitive Framework for Understanding Moral Functioning, in edited by Narvaez, D.
and Lapsley, D. K. (eds.), Moral Personality, Identity and Character: An Interdisciplinary
Future. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.
Aquino, K. and Reed, A., II (2002). The Self-Importance of Moral Identity. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 83, 1423–1440 Au5
.
Aquino, K., Reed, A., Thau, S. and Freeman, D. (2007). A Grotesque and Dark Beauty:
How Moral Identity and Mechanisms of Moral Disengagement Influence Cognitive and
Emotional Reactions to War. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 43, 385–392.
Aristotle (1988). Nicomachean Ethics in Ross, W.D. (trans.) Oxford, London.
Bandura, A. (1999). Moral Disengagement in the Perpetration of Inhumanities. Personality
and Social Psychology Review, 3(3), 269–275.
Bargh, J. A. (2005). Bypassing the Will: Toward Demystifying the Nonconscious Control of
Social Behaviour, in edited by Hassin, R. R., Uleman, J. S., and Bargh, J. A. (eds.), The
New Unconscious (pp. 37–60). Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
Bargh, J. A. and Chartrand, T. L. (1999). The Unbearable Automaticity of Being. American
Psychologist, 54(7), 462–479.
Bar-Tal, D., Raviv, A. and Goldberg, M. (1982). Helping Behaviour among Pre-School
Children. Child Development, 16, 516–524.
Bartlett, F. C. (1932). Remembering. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, England.
Benson, P., Leffert, N., Scales, P. and Blyth, D. (1998). Beyond the ‘‘Village’’ Rhetoric:
Creating Healthy Communities for Children and Adolescents. Applied Developmental
Science, 2(3), 138–159.
Blasi, A. (1984). Moral Identity: Its Role in Moral Functioning, in edited by Kurtines, W. M.
and Gewirtz, J. J. (eds.), Morality, Moral Behavior and Moral Development (pp. 128–139).
John Wiley & Sons, New York.
Blasi, A. (1985). The Moral Personality: Reflections for Social Science and Education, in
edited by Berkowitz, M.W. and Oser, F. (eds.), Moral Education: Theory and Application
(pp. 433–443) Au6
.
Blasi, A. (1988). Identity and the Development of the Self, in edited by Lapsley, D.K. and
Power, F.C. (eds.), Self, Ego and Identity: Integrative Approaches, (pp. 226–242). Springer-
Verlag, New York.
Blasi, A. (2004). Neither Personality Nor Cognition: An Alternative Approach to the
Nature of the Self. in edited by Lightfoot, C, Lalonde, C, and Chandler, M (eds.),
Changing Conceptions of Psychological Life (pp. 3–26). Lawrence Erlbaum Associates,
Mahwah, NJ.
Blasi, A. (2005). Moral Character: A Psychological Approach. in edited by Lapsley, D.K and
Power, F.C (eds.), Character Psychology and Character Education (pp. 18–35). University of
Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, IN.
Blasi, A. (in press) Moral Reasoning and the Moral Functioning of Mature Adults, in
Narvaez, D. and Lapsley, D. K. (eds.), Moral Personality, Identity and Character: An
Interdisciplinary Future. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.
Bowlby, J. (1988). A Secure Base: Parent-Child Attachment and Healthy Human Development.
Basic Books, New York.
Bransford, J. D. and Johnson, M. K. (1972). Contextual Prerequisites for Understanding:
Some Investigations of Comprehension and Recall. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal
Behavior, 11, 717–726.
268 Darcia Narvaez and Daniel K. Lapsley
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:52 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
Bransford, J. D., Brown, A. L. and Cocking, R. R. (eds.) (1999). How People Learn: Brain,
Mind, Experience, and School. National Academy Press, Washington, DC.
Brugman, D., Podolskij, A. J., Heymans, P. G., Boom, J., Karabanova, O. and Idobaeva, O.
(2003). Perception of Moral Atmosphere in School and Norm Transgressive Behavior in
Adolescents: An Intervention Study. International Journal of Behavioral Development, 27(4),
289–300.
Cantor, N. (1990). From Thought to Behavior: ‘‘Having’’ and ‘‘Doing’’ in the Study of
Personality and Cognition. American Psychologist, 45, 735–750.
Cantor, N. andKihlstrom, J. (1987). Personality and Social Intelligence. Prentice-Hall, Englewood
Cliffs, NJ.
Carter, C. S. (1998). Neuroendocrine Perspectives on Social Attachment and Love. Psycho-
neuroendocrinology, 23(8), 779–818.
Catalano, R. F., Haggerty, K. P., Oesterle, S., Fleming, C. B. and Hawkins, J. D. (2004).
The Importance of Bonding to School for Healthy Development: Findings From the
Social Development Research Group. Journal of School Health, 74, 252–261.
Cervone, D. (2005). Personality Architecture: Within-Person Structures and Processes.
Annual Review of Psychology, 56, 423–452.
Cervone, D. and Tripathi, R. (in press). The Moral Functioning of the Person as a Whole: On
Moral Psychology and Personality Science, in edited by Narvaez, D. and Lapsley, D. K.
(eds.), Moral Personality, Identity and Character: An Interdisciplinary Future. Cambridge
University Press, New York.
Champagne, F. A. and Meaney, M. J. (2006). Stress during Gestation Alters Maternal Care
and the Development of Offspring in a Rodent Model. Biological Psychology, 59,
1227–1235.
Chase, W. and Simon, H. (1973). Perception in Chess. Cognitive Psychology, 4, 55–81.
Chiesi, H., Spilich, G. and Voss, J. (1979). Acquisition of Domain-Related Information in
Relation to High and Low Domain Knowledge. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal
Behavior, 18, 257–273.
Colby, A. and Damon, W. (1991). Some Do Care. Free Press, New York.
Costa, P. T. and McCrae, R. R. (1992). NEO PI-R Professional Manual. Psychological
Assessment, Odessa, FL.
Cotterill, R. (1998). Enchanted Looms. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, England.
Damasio, A. (1994). Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain. Avon, New York.
Darwin, C. (1871/1981). The Descent of Man. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.
Denham, S. A. (1986). Social Cognition, Prosocial Behavior and Emotion in Preschoolers:
Contextual Validation. Child Development, 57, 194–201.
Dunn, J. (1988). The Beginnings of Social Understanding. Harvard University Press, Cambridge,
MA.
Eisenberg, L. (1995). The Social Construction of the Human Brain. American Journal of
Psychiatry, 152, 1563–1575.
Emmons, R. A. (1986). Personal Strivings: An Approach to Personality and Subjective
Well-Being. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 51, 1058–1068.
Ericsson, K. A. and Smith, J. (1991). Toward a General Theory of Expertise. Cambridge
University Press, New York.
Field, T. and Reite, M. (1985). The Psychobiology of Attachment and Separation. Academic
Press, New York.
Fivish, R., Kuebli, J. and Chubb, P. A. (1992). The Structure of Event Representations:
A Developmental Analysis. Child Development, 64, 188–201.
Frankfurt, H. (1971). Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person. Journal of Philosophy,
68, 5–20.
Frankfurt, H. (1988). The Importance of What We Care About. Cambridge University Press,
New York.
Moral Identity, Moral Functioning, and the Development of Moral Character 269
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Comp. by: NVeluProof0000867192 Date:14/10/08 Time:19:29:52 Stage:First
Proof File Path://pchns1301/WOMAT/Production/PRODENV/0000000001/
0000010684/0000000016/0000867192.3D Proof by: QC by: ProjectA-
cronym:bs:PLM Volume:50008
UNCORRECTED PROOF
Gelman, R. (1979). Preschool Thought. American Psychologist, 34, 900–905.
Girgenrizer, G. and Todd, P. M. and ABC Research Group. (1999). Simple Heuristics That
Make Us Smart. Oxford University Press, New York.
Gluckman, P. and Hanson, M. (2004). The Fetal Matrix: Evolution, Development and Disease.
Cambridge University Press, New York.
Greenspan, S. I. and Shanker, S. I. (2004). The First Idea. Da Capo Press, Cambridge, MA.
Gross, J. J. (ed.) (2007). Handbook of Emotion Regulation. Guilford Press, New York.
Haidt, J. (2001). The Emotional Dog and Its Rational Tail: A Social Intuitionist Approach to
Moral Judgment. Psychological Review, 108(4), 814–834.
Harlow, H. (1986). From Learning to Love. Praeger Press, New York.
Harris, P. and Nunez, M. (1996). Understanding of Permission Rules by Preschool Children.
Child Development, 67, 1572–1591.
Hart, D. (2005). The Development of Moral Identity, inedited by Carlo, G and Edwards, C.P.
(eds.), Nebraska Symposium on Motivation, Vol. 51, Moral Motivation Through the Lifespan
(pp. 165–196). University of Nebraska Press, Lincoln.
Hart, D. and Fegley, S. (1995). Altruism and Caring in Adolescence: Relations to Moral
Judgment and Self-Understanding. Child Development, 66, 1346–1359.
Hart, D. and Matsuba, K. (in press). Urban Neighborhoods as Contexts for Moral
Identity Development, in edited by Narvaez, D. and Lapsley, D. K. (eds.), Moral
Personality, Identity and Character: An Interdisciplinary Future. Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge, UK.
Hart, D., Atkins, R. and Donnelly, T. M. (2006). Community Service and Moral Develop-
ment. in Killen, M. and Smetana, J. (eds.), Handbook of Moral Development
pp. 633–656). Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Mahwah, NJ.
Hart, D., Matsuba, K. and Atkins, R. (2008). The Moral and Civic Effects of Learning to
Serve, in edited by Nucci, L. and Narvaez, D. (eds.), Handbook on Moral and Character
Education (pp. 484–499). Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, New York.
Hartshorne, H. and May, M. A. (1928–1930). Studies in the Nature of Character, Vol. 1.
Studies in Deceit, Vol. 2 (with J. B. Maller, 1929), Studies in Service and Self-Control, Vol. 3
(with F. K. Shuttleworth, 1930), Studies in the Organization of Character. Macmillan,
New York.
Hatano, G. and Inagaki, K. (1986). Two Courses of Expertise. Child Development and
Education in Japan, 262–272.
Henry, J. P. and Wang, S. (1998). Effects of Early Stress on Adult Affiliative Behavior.
Psychoneuroendocrinology, 23(8), 863–875.
Hofer, M. A. (1994). Hidden Regulators in Attachment, Separation, and Loss, in edited by
Fox, N.A. ( Emotion Regulation: Behavioral and Biological Considerations. Monographs of the
Society for Research in Child Development, 59, 192–207.
Hogarth, R. M. (2001). Educating Intuition. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Johnson, M. (1993). Moral Imagination: Implications of Cognitive Science for Ethics. University of
Chicago Press, Chicago.
Kagan, J. (2005). Human Morality and Temperament, in edited by Carlo, G. and
Pope-Edwards, C. (eds.), Moral Motivation through the Lifespan. Nebraska Symposium on
Motivation, Vol. 51 (pp. 1–32). University of Nebraska Press, Lincoln, NE.
Kekes, J. (1989). Moral Tradition and Individuality. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.
Kesner, R. (1986). Neurobiological Views of Memory, in edited by Martinez, J. and Kesner,
R. (eds.), Learning and Memory: A Biological View (pp. 399–438). Academic Press,
New York.
Killen, M. R., and Smetana, J. R.eds.) (2005). In Handbook of Moral DevelopmentLawr-
ence Erlbaum Associates, Mahwah, NJ.
270 Darcia Narvaez and Daniel K. Lapsley
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12