ArticlePDF Available

Inseparability of Quantum Parameters

Authors:

Abstract

In this work, we show that 'splitting of quantum information' [6] is an impossible task from three different but consistent principles of unitarity of Quantum Mechanics, no-signalling condition and non increase of entanglement under Local Operation and Classical Communication. Comment: 9 pages, Presented in Quantum Computing Back Action in IIT Kanpur (2006). Accepted in International Journal of Theoretical Physics
arXiv:quant-ph/0602016v3 12 Jan 2007
Inseparability of Quantum Parameters
I.Chakrabarty
1
,S.Adhikari
2
,Prashant
3
,B.S.Choudhury
2
1
Herita ge Institute of Technology, Kolkata, India
2
Bengal Eng ineering and Science University, Howrah, India
3
Indian Institute of IT and Management, Indi a
Abstract
In this work, we show that ’splitting of quantum inf ormation’ [6] is an impos-
sible task from three different but consistent principles of unitarity of Quantum
Mechanics, no-signalling condition and non increase of entanglement u nder Local
Operation and Classical Communication.
PACS Numbers: 03.67.-a, 0 3.65.Bz, 89.70.+c
1 Introduction
In quantum information theory it is most important of knowing the various differences
between the classical and quantum information. Many operations which are feasible in
digitized information becomes an impossibility in quantum world [1-6]. This may be
probably due to the linear structure or may be due to the unitary evolution in quantum
mechanics. Regardless of their origin, these impossible operations are making quantum
information processing much more restricted than it’s classical counterpart. On the other
hand this restriction on many quantum infor matio n processing tasks is making quantum
information more secure. In the famous land mark paper of Wootters and Zurek it was
indranilc@indiainfo.com
1
shown that a single quantum cannot be cloned [1]. La t er it was also shown by Pati and
Braunstein that we cannot delete either of the two quantum states when we are provided
with two identical quantum states at our input port [2]. In spite of these two famous
’no-cloning’ [1] a nd ’no-deletion’ [2] theorem there are many other ’no-go’ theorems like
’no-self replication’ [3] , ’no-partia l erasure’ [5], ’no-splitting’ [6] and many more which
have come up. R ecent research has revealed that these theorems are consistent with dif-
ferent principles like principle of no-signalling and conservation of entanglement under
LOCC [7-9]. If we put it in a different way it means that if we violate these ’no-go’
theorems we will violate the principle of no-signalling and non increase of entanglement
under LOCC.
No-splitting theorem: It is a well known fact that there are many operatio ns which
are feasible in the classical world but doesn’t hold good in the quantum domain. These
we generally refer as ’General impossible operations’. ”No splitting Theorem” [6] (almost
equivalent to the ’No-Partial Erasure of Quantum Information’ [5])is yet another addition
to this set. It states that ’For an unknown qubit,quantum information cannot be split
into two complementing qubits,i.e. the information in o ne qubit is an inseparable entity.
An important application of splitting of quantum information is a construction of a gate
which can be used to reversibly split a parameter encoded in non orthogonal quant um
states , enabling the necessary quantum information compression and decompression re-
quired for optimal quantum cloning with multiple copies [10].
In this work our obj ective is different from [6] in the sense that here we will investigate
whether we can split two non orthogonal quantum states from three different but consis-
tent principles like, preservation of inner products under unitary evolutio n, the principle
of non increase of entanglement under LOCC and principle of no signalling . In other
words, unlike in ref [6], instead proving the splitting of quantum state from linearity, we
correlate this impossibility with other aspects like, unitarity ,restrictions on entanglement
processing and causality.
2
2 Proo f of No-splitting theor em from three different
principle s:
I. From Unitarity of Quantum Mechanics: First of all we show that the ’No-
splitting theorem’is consistent with the unitary evolution of quantum theory. For this
purpose we will consider a pair of non orthogonal states [|ψ
1
(θ
1
, φ
1
)i, |ψ
1
(θ
2
, φ
2
)i], where
0 θ π and 0 φ 2π. These non o rt hogonal states are represented by points
on the Bloch sphere. Let us assume that the splitting of quantum information into
complementary parts is possible. If we consider a hypothetical machine which can split
quantum information in each of the non-orthogonal states into complementary part s, then
the action of the machine on the non-ortho gonal states [|ψ
1
(θ
1
, φ
1
)i, |ψ
1
(θ
2
, φ
2
)i] is defined
by the set of transformations:
|ψ
1
(θ
1
, φ
1
)i|ψ
2
i |ψ
1
(θ
1
)i|ψ
2
(φ
1
)i (1)
|ψ
1
(θ
2
, φ
2
)i|ψ
2
i |ψ
1
(θ
2
)i|ψ
2
(φ
2
)i (2)
where
|ψ
1
(θ
j
, φ
j
)i = cos(
θ
j
2
)|0i + sin(
θ
j
2
)e
(
j
)
|1i (3)
|ψ
2
(φ
j
)i = |ψ
21
i + e
(
j
)
|ψ
22
i (4)
|ψ
1
(θ
j
)i = cos(
θ
j
2
)|ψ
11
i + sin(
θ
j
2
)|ψ
12
i (5)
where j = (1, 2). Here |ψ
11
i, |ψ
12
i, |ψ
21
i, |ψ
22
i are non normalized states independent of
θ, φ. The unitarity of transformations will preserve the inner product .
hψ
1
(θ
1
, φ
1
)|ψ
1
(θ
2
, φ
2
)i =
hψ
1
(θ
1
)|ψ
1
(θ
2
)ihψ
2
(φ
1
)|ψ
2
(φ
2
)i (6)
The above equality will not hold for all values of (θ, φ). The equality will hold if
φ
2
= φ
1
+ and θ
1
± θ
2
= (2m + 1)π where m, n are integers(see appendix).This
equality corresponds to a situation where the quantum states are orthogonal. Thus we
see that the equality does not hold for all values of θ and φ and hence we conclude t hat
this kind of transformation doesn’t exist. We cannot split the quantum info r matio n for
3
two non orthogonal quantum states.
II. From Non Increase of Entanglement under LOCC and No signalling Condi-
tion: Next we show that splitting of quantum information is an imp ossible operation from
the principle of non increase of entanglement under LOCC. Let us consider an enta ng led
state shared by two distant part ies Alice and Bob, of the form
|ψi
AB
=
1
2
[|0i
A
|ψ
1
(θ
1
, φ
1
)i
B
+ |1i
A
|ψ
1
(θ
2
, φ
2
)i
B
]|ψ
2
i
B
(7)
where {|ψ
2
i} is the blank state attached to the Bob’s particle.
The reduced density matrix on Alice’s side is given by,
ρ
A
= T r
B
(|ψi
ABAB
hψ|) =
1
2
[I + |1ih0|(hψ
1
(θ
1
, φ
1
)|ψ
1
(θ
2
, φ
2
)i) +
|0ih1|(hψ
1
(θ
2
, φ
2
)|ψ
1
(θ
1
, φ
1
)i)] (8)
Let us assume that Bob is in possession of a machine which will split the quantum infor-
mation of his particle. The transformation describing the action of the machine is given
by equations (1) and (2) . Now after the application of the quantum info r matio n splitting
machine the entangled state (7) takes the form
|ψi
C
AB
=
1
2
[|0i
A
|ψ
1
(θ
1
)i
B
|ψ
2
(φ
1
)i
B
+ |1i
A
|ψ
1
(θ
2
)i
B
|ψ
2
(φ
2
)i
B
] (9)
The reduced density matrix on the Alice’s side after the application of the machine is
given by,
ρ
C
A
=
1
2
[I + |1ih0|(hψ
1
(θ
1
)|ψ
1
(θ
2
)i)(hψ
2
(φ
1
)|ψ
2
(φ
2
)i)
+|0ih1|(hψ
1
(θ
2
)|ψ
1
(θ
1
)i)(hψ
2
(φ
2
)|ψ
2
(φ
1
)i)] (10)
The respective la r gest eigen values of these two r educed density matrices are given by
λ
A
=
1
2
+
|p|
2
2
(11)
λ
C
A
=
1
2
+
|q|
2
|r|
2
2
(12)
4
where p = hψ
1
(θ
2
, φ
2
)|ψ
1
(θ
1
, φ
1
)i, q = h ψ
1
(θ
2
)|ψ
1
(θ
1
)i, r = hψ
2
(φ
2
)|ψ
2
(φ
1
)i. To show that
the amount of entanglement E(|ψi
AB
) and E(|ψi
C
AB
) o f the respective entangled states
before and after the splitting doesn’t increase, we must show that λ
A
< λ
C
A
. To show
λ
A
< λ
C
A
this we must show that,
|hψ
1
(θ
2
, φ
2
)|ψ
1
(θ
1
, φ
1
)i| <
|hψ
1
(θ
2
)|ψ
1
(θ
1
)i||hψ
2
(φ
2
)|ψ
2
(φ
1
)i| (13)
LHS : |cos(
θ
1
2
) cos(
θ
2
2
) + e
i(φ
1
φ
2
)
sin(
θ
1
2
) sin(
θ
2
2
)|
RHS : |cos(
θ
1
2
) cos(
θ
2
2
) + sin(
θ
1
2
) sin(
θ
2
2
)|
|1 + e
i(φ
1
φ
2
)
| (14)
Let
(φ
1
φ
2
) = k, cos(
θ
1
2
) cos(
θ
2
2
) = x (15)
sin(
θ
1
2
) sin(
θ
2
2
) = y (16)
where x and y are real quantities.
Now |hψ
1
(θ
2
, φ
2
)|ψ
1
(θ
1
, φ
1
)i| = | x+e
ik
y| = |[x+y cos(k)]+iy[sin(k)]| =
q
[x
2
+ y
2
+ 2xy cos(k)]
and |hψ
1
(θ
2
)|ψ
1
(θ
1
)i||hψ
2
(φ
2
)|ψ
2
(φ
1
)i| = (x + y)
q
2(1 + cos(k)).
Therefore A(say)=[|hψ
1
(θ
2
, φ
2
)|ψ
1
(θ
1
, φ
1
)i|]
2
[|hψ
1
(θ
2
)|ψ
1
(θ
1
)i||hψ
2
(φ
2
)|ψ
2
(φ
1
)i|]
2
= x
2
+
y
2
+2xy cos(k)2(x+y)
2
(1+cos(k)) = [x
2
+y
2
+4xy+2(x
2
+y
2
+xy) cos(k)] > 0 for some
values o f x,y,k. This implies that, λ
A
> λ
C
A
E(|ψi
C
AB
) > E(|ψi
AB
), as a consequence
of which we can say that the amount of entang lement will increase under local operation.
However we know that enta nglement is non increasing under such operations [ in general
one can only claim that it is conserved under a bilocal unitary operation ]. This gives rise
to contradiction. Therefore, it is clear that the principle of non increase of entanglement
under LOCC doesn’t a llow perfect splitting of nonorthogonal quantum states. This rules
out the existence of a hypothetical quantum information splitting machine, designed to
split the quantum information of a nonorthogonal quantum state .
5
Next we show tha t the splitting of quantum information is not possible from the principle
of no signalling. In other words we can say that if we assume perfect splitting of quantum
information it will violate the principle of no-signalling.
Suppose we have a singlet state shared by two distant parties Alice and Bob . The singlet
state can be written in two different basis as
|χi =
1
2
(|ψ
1
i|
ψ
1
i |ψ
1
i|ψ
1
i)
=
1
2
(|ψ
2
i|
ψ
2
i |ψ
2
i|ψ
2
i) (17)
where {|ψ
1
i, |
ψ
1
i} and {|ψ
2
i, |ψ
2
i} are two sets of mutually orthogonal spin states (qubit
basis). Alice possesses the first particle while Bob possesses t he second particle. Alice can
choose to measure the spin in any one of the qubit basis namely {|ψ
1
i, |ψ
1
i}, {|ψ
2
i, |ψ
2
i}.
The theorem o f no signalling tells us that the measurement outcome of Bob are invari-
ant under local unitary transformation done by Alice on her qubit.The density matrix
ρ
B
= trρ
AB
= tr[(U
A
I
B
)ρ
AB
(U
A
I
B
)
] is invar ia nt under local unitary operation by
Alice . Hence Bob cannot distinguish two mixtures due to the unitary operation done
at remote place. One may ask if Bob split the quantum information of his particle and
if Alice measure her particle in either of the two basis then is there any possibility that
Bob know the basis in which Alice measure her qubit or in other words, is there any way
by which Bob using a perfect splitting machine can distinguish the statistical mixture in
his subsystem resulting from the measurement done by Alice. If Bob can do this then
signalling will take place, which is impossible. Hence now our ta sk is to show that the
splitting of information is an impossible task from no-signalling principle.
Let us consider a situation where Bob is in possession of a hypothetical quantum informa-
tion splitting machine. The unitary transformation describing the splitting of quantum
information fo r an input state |ψ
i
(θ, φ)i (where i=1,2) is defined as ,
|ψ
i
(θ, φ)i|Σi |ψ
i
(θ)i|Σ(φ)i
|
ψ
i
(θ, φ)i|Σi |ψ
i
(θ)i|Σ(φ)i (18)
6
where {|Σi} is the ancilla state a tt ached by Bo b .
After the application of the transformation defined in (18) by Bob on his particle the
singlet state defined by (17) including the ancilla state attached by Bob reduces to t he
form,
|χi|Σi |χi
S
=
1
2
[|ψ
1
(θ, φ)i|
ψ
1
(θ)i|Σ(φ)i
−|ψ
1
(θ, φ)i|ψ
1
(θ)i|Σ(φ)i] =
1
2
[|ψ
2
(θ, φ)i|
ψ
2
(θ)i|Σ(φ)i
−|ψ
2
(θ, φ)i|ψ
2
(θ)i|Σ(φ)i] (19)
After Bob applying t he splitting machine on his qubit, Alice can measure her particle
in two different basis. If Alice measures her particle in the basis {|ψ
1
i, |
ψ
1
i}, then the
reduced density matrix in the Bob’s subsystem (including ancilla) is given by,
ρ
BC
= tr
A
(ρ
ABC
)
=
1
2
{|
ψ
1
(θ)Σ(φ)ihψ
1
(θ)Σ(φ)|
+|ψ
1
(θ)Σ(φ)ihψ
1
(θ)Σ(φ)|} (20)
On the other hand if Alice measures her particle in the basis {|ψ
2
i, |
ψ
2
i} then the state
described by the reduced density matrix in the Bob’s side is given by,
ρ
BC
= tr
A
(ρ
ABC
)
=
1
2
{|
ψ
2
(θ)Σ(φ)ihψ
2
(θ)Σ(φ)|
+|ψ
2
(θ)Σ(φ)ihψ
2
(θ)Σ(φ)|} (21)
Since the statistical mixture in (20) and (21) are different, so this would have allowed Bob
to distinguish in which basis Alice has performed measurement, thus allowing for super
luminal signalling. However the criterion of ’No-signalling’ tells us that communication
faster than light is not possible. So we arrive at a contradiction, that is, the transfor-
mation defined in (18) is not possible in quantum world. This rules out the existence of
hypothetical machine like quantum information splitting machine.
7
3 Conclus i on
In this work we show that the total information contained in the quantum state on
the Bloch-sphere cannot be written as the tensor product of the state containing the
information of the azimutha l angle and the state conta ining the information of the phase
angle. Therefore the quantum information can be rega rded as an inseparable entity or
in other words we can say that it is impossible to express the function of θ and φ as the
product of function of θ alone and function of φ alone. To justify the above statement, we
proved the no-splitting theorem from three different principles: (i) Unitarity of quantum
mechanics (ii) principles of non increase of entanglement under LO CC and (iii) Principle
of no signalling.
4 Acknowled gement
I.C acknowledges Prof C.G.Chakraborti, S.N.Bose Professor of Theoretical Physics, De-
partment of Applied Mathematics, University of Calcutta for being the source of inspi-
ration in carrying out research. S.A acknowledges CSIR project no.F.No.8/3(38)/2003-
EMR-1 for providing financial support . I.C and S.A would like to thank Dr.A.K.Pati for
useful discussion.
5 Appendix
hψ
1
(θ
1
, φ
1
)|ψ
1
(θ
2
, φ
2
)i = cos
θ
1
2
cos
θ
2
2
+e
i(φ
2
φ
1
)
sin
θ
1
2
sin
θ
2
2
, hψ
1
(θ
1
)|ψ
1
(θ
2
)i = cos
θ
1
2
cos
θ
2
2
+
sin
θ
1
2
sin
θ
2
2
, and hψ
2
(φ
1
)|ψ
2
(φ
2
)i = 1+e
i(φ
2
φ
1
)
. Now we have to show that, hψ
1
(θ
1
, φ
1
)|ψ
1
(θ
2
, φ
2
)i =
hψ
1
(θ
1
)|ψ
1
(θ
2
)ihψ
2
(φ
1
)|ψ
2
(φ
2
)i. This equality is possible only when
tan
θ
1
2
tan
θ
2
2
= e
i(φ
2
φ
1
)
(22)
Now by equating the real and imaginary parts of the above expression we get,
tan
θ
1
2
tan
θ
2
2
= cos(φ
2
φ
1
) (23)
sin(φ
2
φ
1
) = 0 (24)
8
On simplifying equation (19) we get, (φ
2
φ
1
) = ,where n = 0, ±1, ±2, ...... Using
(φ
2
φ
1
) = equation (17) reduces to the form tan
θ
1
2
tan
θ
2
2
= (1)
n+1
.
Now we consider two cases:
Case1. When n is even, tan
θ
1
2
tan
θ
2
2
= 1 (θ
1
θ
2
) = (2m + 1)π.
Case2. When n is odd, tan
θ
1
2
tan
θ
2
2
= 1 (θ
1
+ θ
2
) = (2m + 1)π. (where, m =
0, ±1, ±2, .....) Thus we see that the unitarity of the transformation is preserved only
when φ
2
= φ
1
+ and θ
1
± θ
2
= (2m + 1)π.
6 Reference
[1] W.K.Wootters and W.H.Zurek,Nature 299 (1982) 802-803.
[2] A.K.Pati and S.L.Braunstein Nature 404 (2000) 164.
[3] A.K.Pati and S.L.Braunstein, Quantum mechanical universal constructor,quantph/0303124
(2003).
[4] A.K.Pati, Phys. Rev. A 66, 062319(2002).
[5] A.K.Pati and Barry C. Sanders, No partial erasure of quant um information,quant-
ph/0503138
[6] D.Zhou.et.al, Quantum information cannot be split into complementary parts,quant-
ph/0503168
[7] A.K.Pati and S.L.Braunstein,Phys.Lett.A 315,208-212 (2003)
[8] I.Chattopadhyay.et.al.Phys. Lett. A, 351, 384-387 (2006).
[9] I.Chakrabarty,A.K.Pati,S.Adhikari,B.S.Choudhury, General Impossible Operations as
a consequence of principles of quantum info r matio n (under preparation).
[10] A.Chefles and S.M. Barnett , Phys. Rev. A 60,136 (1999).
9
... The no-go theorems satisfy the principle of no-signalling and non-increase of entanglement under Local Operation and Classical Communication. Violating the no-go theorems will thus violate the no-signalling principle and the principle of non-increase of entanglement under LOCC [3,[11][12][13]. In general, it is not possible to perform operations that act on the tensor product of an unknown state and a blank state at the input to produce tensor product of the original state along with the function of the original state as the output in the quantum world [2]. ...
... Examples of such operations are generating entangled states, quantum teleportation, etc. Conversely some tasks which are possible to achieve in the classical world become impossible in the quantum world [2]. These impossible operations make quantum information processing more restricted, however more secure when compared to classical information processing [3]. It is very essential to know the possible and impossible operations in quantum ...
Article
Full-text available
Applications of quantum mechanics in the computational and information processing tasks is a recent research interest among the researchers. Certain operations which are impossible to achieve in the description of quantum mechanics are known as no-go theorems. One such theorem is no-splitting theorem of quantum states. The no-splitting theorem states that the information in an unknown quantum bit is an inseparable entity and cannot be split into two complementary qubits. In this work, we try to find out the class of operators for which the splitting is possible in a probabilistic way. The work also aims to find the connection between the unitary operators and probabilistic splitting.
... It tells us that if two distant parties Alice and Bob, share an entangled state, neither Alice nor Bob cannot send signal faster than the speed of light to the other party by doing some local operation on their own subsystems. It had been already seen that if one assumes these impossible operations to be valid physical processes, one can have a super luminal communication between two distant parties sharing an entangled state [7,8,9,10,12,13,14,15,16,17,18]. These results also guarantees impossibility of such operations from the no signalling principle. ...
Article
Full-text available
In this work we investigate that whether one can construct single and two qubit gates for arbitrary quantum states from the principle of no signalling. We considered the problem for Pauli gates, Hadamard gate, C-Not gate.
Article
Full-text available
State-dependent cloning machines that have so far been considered either deterministically copy a set of states approximately or probablistically copy them exactly. In considering the case of two equiprobable pure states, we derive the maximum global fidelity of N approximate clones given M initial exact copies, where N>M. We also consider strategies that interpolate between approximate and exact cloning. A tight inequality is obtained that expresses a trade-off between the global fidelity and success probability. This inequality is found to tend, in the limit N⃗∞, to a known inequality that expresses the trade-off between error and inconclusive result probabilities for state-discrimination measurements. Quantum-computational networks are also constructed for the kinds of cloning machine we describe. For this purpose, we introduce two gates: the distinguishability transfer and state separation gates. Their key properties are described and we show how they may be decomposed into basic operations.
Article
Full-text available
A photon in an arbitrary polarization state cannot be cloned perfectly. But suppose that at our disposal we have several copies of a photon in an unknown state. Is it possible to delete the information content of one or more of these photons by a physical process? Specifically, if two photons are in the same initial polarization state, is there a mechanism that produces one photon in the same initial state and the other in some standard polarization state? If this could be done, then one would create a standard blank state onto which one could copy an unknown state approximately, by deterministic cloning or exactly, by probabilistic cloning. This could in principle be useful in quantum computation, where one could store new information in an already computed state by deleting the old information. Here we show, however, that the linearity of quantum theory does not allow us to delete a copy of an arbitrary quantum state perfectly. Though in a classical computer information can be deleted (reversibly) against a copy, the analogous task cannot be accomplished, even irreversibly, with quantum information.
Article
Full-text available
Arbitrary quantum states cannot be copied. In fact, to make a copy we must provide complete information about the system. However, can a quantum system self-replicate? This is not answered by the no-cloning theorem. In the classical context, Von Neumann showed that a `universal constructor' can exist which can self-replicate an arbitrary system, provided that it had access to instructions for making copy of the system. We question the existence of a universal constructor that may allow for the self-replication of an arbitrary quantum system. We prove that there is no deterministic universal quantum constructor which can operate with finite resources. Further, we delineate conditions under which such a universal constructor can be designed to operate dterministically and probabilistically.
Article
Full-text available
We prove a general limitation in quantum information that unifies the impossibility principles such as no-cloning and no-anticloning. Further, we show that for an unknown qubit one cannot design a universal Hadamard gate for creating equal superposition of the original and its complement state. Surprisingly, we find that Hadamard transformations exist for an unknown qubit chosen either from the polar or equatorial great circles. Also, we show that for an unknown qubit one cannot design a universal unitary gate for creating unequal superpositions of the original and its complement state. We discuss why it is impossible to design a controlled-NOT gate for two unknown qubits and discuss the implications of these limitations. Comment: 15 pages, no figures, Discussion about personal quantum computer removed
Article
State-dependent cloning machines that have so far been considered either deterministically copy a set of states approximately or probablistically copy them exactly. In considering the case of two equiprobable pure states, we derive the maximum global fidelity of N approximate clones given M initial exact copies, where N>M. We also consider strategies that interpolate between approximate and exact cloning. A tight inequality is obtained that expresses a trade-off between the global fidelity and success probability. This inequality is found to tend, in the limit N → ∞, to a known inequality that expresses the trade-off between error and inconclusive result probabilities for state-discrimination measurements. Quantum-computational networks are also constructed for the kinds of cloning machine we describe. For this purpose, we introduce two gates: the distinguishability transfer and state separation gates. Their key properties are described and we show how they may be decomposed into basic operations.
Article
If a photon of definite polarization encounters an excited atom, there is typically some nonvanishing probability that the atom will emit a second photon by stimulated emission. Such a photon is guaranteed to have the same polarization as the original photon. But is it possible by this or any other process to amplify a quantum state, that is, to produce several copies of a quantum system (the polarized photon in the present case) each having the same state as the original? If it were, the amplifying process could be used to ascertain the exact state of a quantum system: in the case of a photon, one could determine its polarization by first producing a beam of identically polarized copies and then measuring the Stokes parameters1. We show here that the linearity of quantum mechanics forbids such replication and that this conclusion holds for all quantum systems.
Article
It is known that if one could clone an arbitrary quantum state then one could send signals faster than the speed of light. Here, we show that deletion of an unknown quantum state for which two copies are available would also lead to superluminal signalling. However, the (Landauer) erasure of an unknown quantum state does not allow faster-than-light communication.
Article
In complete erasure any arbitrary pure quantum state is transformed to a fixed pure state by irreversible operation. Here we ask if the process of partial erasure of quantum information is possible by general quantum operations, where partial erasure refers to reducing the dimension of the parameter space that specifies the quantum state. We prove that quantum information stored in qubits and qudits cannot be partially erased, even by irreversible operations. The ‘no-partial erasure’ theorem applies to spin and bosonic coherent states, and continuous variable quantum information schemes as well. Our theorem suggests an integrity principle that quantum information is indivisible.
Article
Non-existence of universal flipper for arbitrary quantum states is a fundamental constraint on the allowed operations performed on physical systems. The largest set of qubits that can be flipped by a single machine is a great circle of the Bloch-sphere. In this Letter, we show the impossibility of universal exact-flipping operation, first by using the fact that no faster than light communication is possible and then by using the principle of “non-increase of entanglement under LOCC”. Interestingly, in both the cases, there is no violation of the two principles if and only if the set of states to be flipped, form a great circle.
Article
We prove a new impossibility for quantum information (the no-splitting theorem): an unknown quantum bit (qubit) cannot be split into two complementary qubits. This impossibility, together with the no-cloning theorem, demonstrates that an unknown qubit state is a single entity, which cannot be cloned or split. This sheds new light on quantum computation and quantum information. Comment: 9 pages, 1 figure