ArticlePDF Available

Abstract

A new method was devised to test object permanence in young infants. Five- month-old infants were habituated to a screen that moved back and forth through a 180-degree arc, in the manner of a drawbridge. After infants reached habituation, a box was centered behind the screen. Infants were shown two test events: a possible event and an impossible event. In the possible event, the screen stopped when it reached the occluded box; in the impossible event, the screen moved through the space occupied by the box. The results indicated that infants looked reliably longer at the impossible than at the possible event. This finding suggested that infants (1) understood that the box continued to exist, in its same location, after it was occluded by the screen, and (2) expected the screen to stop against the occluded box and were surprised, or puzzled, when it failed to do so. A control experiment in which the box was placed next to the screen provided support for this interpretation of the results. Together, the results of these experiments indicate that, contrary to Piaget's (1954) claims, infants as young as 5 months of age understand that objects continue to exist when occluded. The results also indicate that 5-month-old infants realize that solid objects do not move through the space occupied by other solid objects.
Cognition, 20 (1985) 191-208 1
Object permanence in five-month-old infants*
RENCE BAILLARGEON**
University of Illinois
ELIZABETH S. SPELKE
University of Pennsylvania
STANLEY WASSERMAN
University of Illinois
Abstract
A new method was devised to test object permanence in young infants. Five-
month-old infants were habituated to a screen that moved back and forth
through a 180-degree arc, in the manner of a drawbridge. After infants reached
habituation, a box was centered behind the screen. Infants were shown two test
events: a possible event and an impossible event. In the possible event, the
screen stopped when it reached the occluded box; in the impossible event, the
screen moved through the space occupied by the box. The results indicated that
infants looked reliably longer at the impossible than at the possible event. This
finding suggested that infants (1) understood that the box continued to exist,
in its same location, after it was occluded by the screen, and (2) expected the
screen to stop against the occluded box and were surprised, or puzzled, when
it failed to do so. A control experiment in which the box was placed next to
the screen provided support for this interpretation of the results. Together, the
results of these experiments indicate that, contrary to Piaget’s (1954) claims,
infants as young as 5 months of age understand that objects continue to exist
when occluded. The results also indicate that 5-month-old infants realize that
solid objects do not move through the space occupied by other solid objects.
*This research was supported by a grant from the National Institute of Health (HD-13248) to ESS. The
data analysis was supported by a grant from the National Science Foundation (SES84-08626) to SW. While
working on this research, RI3 was supported by fellowships from the Natural Sciences and Engineering Re-
search Council of Canada and the Qu6bec Department of Education. We thank Judy Deloache and Bob
Reeve, for their careful reading of the manuscript; Marty Banks, Susan Carey, and Paul Harris, for helpful
comments on earlier versions of the manuscript; Wendy Smith Born, Sarah Mangelsdorf, and the members
of the Infant Lab at the University of Pennsylvania, for their help with the data collection; and Dawn Iacobucci,
for her help with the data analysis.
**Reprint requests should be sent to RenCe Baillargeon, Psychology Department, University of Illinois at
Urbana-Champaign, 603 East Daniel Street, Champaign, IL 61820, U.S.A.
OOlO-0277/85/$5.90 0 Elsevier Sequoia/Printed in The Netherlands
192 R. Baillargeon et al.
1. Background: Piaget’s theory
For adults, an object is an entity that exists continuously in time and space:
it cannot exist at two separate points in time without having existed during
the interval between them, and it cannot appear at two separate points in
space without having traveled from one point to the other. Do infants share
this conception of objects as temporally and spatially continuous? On the
basis of detailed observations of infants’ reactions to object disappearances,
Piaget (1954) concluded that they do not. For the young infant, Piaget main-
tained, each disappearance amounts to an annihilation and each reappear-
ance to a resurrection. An object is not a permanent entity that continuous
to exist while out of sight, but an ephemeral entity that is continually made
and unmade: “a mere image which reenters the void as soon as it vanishes,
and emerges from it for no objective reason” (p. 11).
Piaget discerned six stages in the development of the infant’s object con-
cept. He claimed that it is not until infants reach the fourth stage, at about
9 months of age, that they begin to endow objects with permanence, as
evidenced by their willingness to search for hidden objects. Piaget observed
that prior to stage 4, infants do not search for fully hidden objects. If an
attractive toy is covered with a cloth, for example, they make no attempt to
lift the cloth and grasp the toy, even though they are capable of performing
each of these actions. Beginning in stage 4, however, infants do remove
obstacles to retrieve hidden objects. In subsequent stages, infants come to
take into account visible (stage 5) and invisible (stage 6) displacements of
objects to find objects hidden in successive locations.
Why did Piaget select infants’ search for hidden objects as marking the
beginning of object permanence? This question is important, because Piaget
observed several behaviors prior to stage 4 that are suggestive of object
permanence. For example, he noted that as early as stage 1 (O-l month),
infants may look at an object, look away from it, and then return to it several
seconds later, without any external cue having signaled its continued pre-
sence. In addition, Piaget observed that beginning in stage 3 (4-9 months),
infants anticipate the future positions of moving objects: if they are tracking
an object and temporarily lose sight of it, they look for in further along its
trajectory; similarly, if they are holding an object out of sight and accidentally
let go it, they stretch their arm to recapture it.
Piaget claimed that although these and other behaviors seem to reveal a
notion of object permanence, closer analysis indicates “how superficial this
interpretation would be and how phenomenalistic the primitive universe re-
mains” (p. 11). Prior to stage 4, Piaget maintained, the infant lacks a concept
of physical causality and regards all of reality as being dependent on his
Object permanence in infants 193
activity. When he acts upon an object, the infant views the object not as an
independent entity but as the extension, or the product, of his action. If the
object disappears from view, the infant reproduces or extends his action,
because he expects that his action will again produce the object. Proof for
Piaget that the infant regards the object as being “at the disposal” of his
action is that if his action fails to bring back the object, he does not perform
alternative actions to recover it. Beginning in stage 4, however, the infant
acts very differently. For example, if a ball rolls behind a cushion and he
cannot recapture it by extending his reach, he tries alternative means for
recovering it: he lifts the cushion, or pulls it aside, or gropes behind it.
According to Piaget, such activities indicate that the infant conceives of the
ball, not as a thing at the disposal of a specific action, but as a substantial
entity that is located out of sight behind the cushion and that any of several
actions may serve to reveal.
2. Tests of Piaget’s theory
In recent years, Piaget’s (1954) description of the sequences of changes in
infants’ search behavior has been tested by numerous investigators and has
been accepted with few modifications (see Gratch, 1975, 1976; Harris, 1985;
Schuberth, 1983, for reviews). Nevertheless, Piaget’s interpretation of this
sequence has been questioned. A number of authors (e.g., Bower, 1974;
Diamond and Goldman-Rakic, 1983) have suggested that young infants’ fail-
ure to search for hidden objects stems not from a lack of object permanence
but from an inability to perform coordinated actions. Perhaps ironically, sup-
port for this hypothesis comes from Piaget’s (1952) own work on the develop-
ment of action. Piaget found that the capacity to act in a coordinated manner
develops very slowly over the course of infancy. He noted that a major
milestone is achieved at about 9 months of age, when infants begin to coor-
dinate separate actions into means-ends sequences. In these sequences, in-
fants perform one action in order to create the conditions under which they
will be able to perform a second, independent action. Since Piaget’s (1954)
search task requires infants to coordinate two separate actions (one upon the
occluder and one upon the object), young infants could fail this task because
they are generally unable to perform such an action sequence.
A number of studies, notably by Bower (1967, 1972, 1974; Bower,
Broughton and Moore, 1971; Bower and,Wishart, 1972), have attempted to
investigate young infants’ conception of an object using methods that do not
require coordinated sequences of actions. Bower’s studies have yielded four
findings that seem to provide evidence for object permanence in infants well
194 R. Baillargeon et al.
below 9 months. First, 7-week-old infants were found to discriminate between
disappearances that signaled the continued existence of an object (e.g.,
gradual occlusion), and disappearances that did not (e.g., gradual dissolution
or sudden implosion) (Bower, 1967). Second, 2-month-old infants were found
to anticipate the reappearance of an object that stopped behind a screen,
“looking to that half of the movement path the object would have reached
had it not stopped” (Bower et al., 1971, p. 183). Third, 5-month-old infants
were found to show disruptions in their tracking when an object was altered
while passing behind a screen: they tended to look back at the screen, as
though in search of the original object (Bower, 1974; Bower et al., 1971).
Finally, 5-month-old infants were found to reach for an object that had been
“hidden” by darkening the room (Bower and Wishart, 1972).
Although suggestive, Bower’s findings do not provide conclusive evidence
for object permanence in young infants. First, methodological problems cast
doubts upon the validity of the results (Gratch, 1976; Harris, 1985). Second,
the results are open to alternative interpretations that do not implicate object
permanence. In particular, most of the results could be explained by Piagetian
theory in terms of the extension of an ongoing action or the reproduction of
a previous action. When infants reach for an object in the dark, they could
simply be extending an action initiated before the lights were extinguished.
Similarly, when infants anticipate the reappearance of an object, they could
be extending a tracking motion begun prior to the object’s disappearance.
Finally, when infants’look back at a screen, after a novel object has emerged
from behind it, they could be repeating a prior action of looking in that
direction, with the expectation that this action will again produce the original
object.
The first finding cited above cannot be explained in terms of the extension
or the reproduction of an action, but it, too, is open to other interpretations.
One interpretation, mentioned by Bower et al. (1971), apparently has its
source in Piaget: “Piaget (personal communication) has rightly objected that
the methods used were insufficient to demonstrate that the infants were re-
sponding to objects as such, rather than to perceptual configurations which
contained the object as an undifferentiated element” (p. 182). Another in-
terpretation is that infants discriminate between permanence and imperma-
nence sequences on the basis of superficial expectations about the way objects
typically disappear, rather than on the basis of a belief in object permanence.
In their daily environment, infants often see objects occlude one another but
they rarely, if ever, see objects implode from view or dissolve into the air.
Hence, infants could respond differently to occlusions than to implosions or
dissolutions because occlusions are the only type of disappearance that is
familiar to them.
Object permanence in infants 195
3. The present experiment
Because of the difficulties associated with Piaget’s and Bower’s tasks, we
sought a new means of testing object permanence in young infants. Like
Bower, we chose not to rely on manual search as our index of object perma-
nence. However, we tried to find an index that could not depend on (1) the
extension or reproduction of an action, or (2) knowledge about superficial
properties of object disappearances.
The method we devised was rather indirect. It focused on infants’ under-
standing of the principle that a solid object cannot move through the space
occupied by another solid object (“solidity principle”). Infants’ understanding
of this principle was tested in a situation involving a visible object and an
occluded object. If infants were surprised when the visible object appeared
to move through the space occupied by the occluded object, it would suggest
that they took account of the existence and the location of the occluded
object. In other words, evidence that infants applied the solidity principle
would also provide evidence that they possessed object permanence.
In the experiment, a box was placed on a surface behind a wooden screen.
The screen initially lay flat, so that the box was clearly visible. The screen
was then raised, in the manner of a drawbridge, thus hiding the box from
view. Infants were shown two test events: a possible event and an impossible
event. In the possible event, the screen moved until it reached the occluded
box, stopped, and then returned to its initial position (see Figure 1A). In the
impossible event, the screen moved until it reached the occluded box-and
then kept on going as though the box were no longer there! The screen
completed a full 180-degree arc before it reversed direction and returned to
its initial position, revealing the box standing intact in the same location as
before (see Figure 1B). To adults, the possible event is consistent with the
solidity principle: the screen stops when it encounters the box. The impossible
event, in contrast, violates the principle: the screen appears to move freely
through the space occupied by the box. Note that adults would not perceive
the event as impossible if they did not believe that the box continued to exist,
in its same location, after it was occluded by the screen.
To test infants’ perception of these events, we used a habituation
paradigm. Infants were habituated to the screen moving back and forth
through a 180-degree arc, with no box present. After infants reached habitu-
ation, the box was placed behind the screen, and infants were shown the
possible and impossible events. Our reasoning was as follows. If infants un-
derstood that (1) the box continued to exist, in its same location, after it was
occluded by the screen, and (2) the screen could not move through the space
occupied by the box, then they should perceive the impossible event to be
196 R. Baillargeon et al.
Figure 1. Schematic representation of the possible and impossible test events used in
the principal experiment.
A. Possible Event
B. Impossible Event
novel, surprising, or both. On the basis of the commonly-held assumption
that infants react to novel or surprising events with prolonged attention, we
predicted that infants would look longer at the impossible than at the possible
event. On the other hand, if infants did not understand that the box continued
to exist after it was occluded by the screen, then they should attend to the
movement of the screen without concerning themselves with the presence of
the box in its path. Since the screen movement was the same in the impossible
and the habituation events (in both events the screen moved through a 180-
degree arc), we predicted that infants would look longer at the possible event,
which depicted a novel, shorter screen movement.
There was one foreseeable difficulty with the design of our experiment.
Infants might look longer at the impossible than at the possible event, not
because they understood the underlying structure of the events, but because
they found the 180-degree movement intrinsically more interesting than the
120-degree movement. To check this possibility, we ran a control experiment
that was similar to the first experiment except that the box was placed behind
and to the side of the screen, out of its path of motion. Therefore, neither
the 180- nor the 120-degree screen movement violated the solidity principle.
We reasoned that if infants in the first experiment looked longer at the impos-
sible event because they found the 180-degree movement intrinsically more
interesting than the 120-degree movement, then infants in the control exper-
iment should look longer at the 180-degree event. On the other hand, if
infants in the first experiment looked longer at the impossible event because
they viewed it as impossible, then infants in the control experiment should
look equally at the 180- and the 120-degree events, since neither was impos-
Object permanence in infants 197
sible, or they should look longer at the 120-degree event, since it involved a
novel screen movement.
4. Method
4.1. Principal experiment
4.1.1. Subjects
Subjects were 21 full-term infants ranging in age from 4 months, 24 days
to 5 months, 26 days (mean age: 5 months, 12 days). An additional 7 infants
were eliminated from the experiment, 3 because of experimenter error and
4 because of fussiness. All infants were from the Philadelphia area. Parents
were contacted by phone and were compensated for their participation.
4.1.2. Apparatus
The apparatus resembled that used by Bower (1967). It involved two iden-
tical alleys containing identical screens and separated by a one-way mirror.
Only one alley was visible at any one time. Shifts between the alleys were
accomplished instantaneously by extinguishing the lights in one alley and
illuminating those in the other alley. During those shifts, naive adult obser-
vers were not aware that they were shown two different alleys. It appeared
merely as though one alley underwent a brief flickering of illumination.
Alleys. The apparatus consisted of a large wooden box in the shape of an
inverted “L”. A one-way mirror 38 cm high and 81 cm wide divided this box
to form a front and a side alley (see Figure 2). Infants faced the mirror
through an opening 38 cm high and 43 cm wide at one end of the front alley.
The two alleys were of the same color and dimensions: both were painted
black, and both were 38 cm high, 61 cm wide, 122 cm deep on one side and
61 cm deep on the other. In addition, both alleys contained an unpainted
wooden screen 28 cm high, 20 cm wide, and 1 cm thick. Each screen was
attached by hinges to the floor of its respective alley and was positioned 20
cm from the side walls and 30 cm from the back wall. To one side of each
screen (right in the front alley, left in the side alley) was attached a thin metal
pulley, 11 cm in diameter. One half of each pulley stood above the floor of
the alley, and the other half hung beneath it. The two pulleys were operated
by identical manual cranks located underneath the alleys. By means of these
cranks, the two screens could be moved back and forth through a 180-degree
arc.
A wooden box 15 cm high, 10 cm wide, and 10 cm thick could be intro-
198 R. Baillargeon et al.
Figure 2. Top view of the apparatus.
Front
Alley
, Kl
I
Screens
Side
Alley
\ \ \ \ \ \ W
\ One- way
\ \ Mirror
\ \ \
duced into the front alley through a hidden door in its back wall. This box
was painted bright yellow and was decorated with small red stars. During the
test, the box was centered 8 cm behind the far edge of the screen when the
screen lay in its initial position on the floor of the alley, toward the infant.
Lighting. Miniature bayonet light bulbs were affixed to the ceiling of each
alley. Bands of black cardboard hid these light bulbs from the infant’s view.
More lightbulbs were used in the front alley to equalize the luminance of the
two alleys, because the one-way mirror considerably reduced the amount of
light that reached the infant’s eye from the front alley.
The lights in the two alleys were wired in such a way that one could reverse
their illumination condition by depressing a single switch. When the front
alley was lit and the side alley was dark, the one-way mirror functioned as a
window: infants looked through it into the front alley. When the side alley
was lit and the front alley was dark, it functioned as a mirror: infants saw the
side alley reflected in it. In each case, the alley that was not lit was not visible.
Object permanence in infants 199
Experimental chamber. A wooden frame 229 cm high and 213 cm wide
hung in front of the apparatus. This frame was covered with white muslin
except for an opening that coincided with the opening into the front alley.
Floorlength curtains hung on either side of, and perpendicular to, the muslin-
covered frame. Together, the curtains and the frame formed a three-sided
chamber that isolated the infant from the experimental room.
4.1.3. Events
Impossible test event. Two experimenters worked in concert to produce
this event. The first experimenter operated the front alley screen and con-
trolled the illumination condition of the alleys; the second experimenter op-
erated the side alley screen. To start, the first experimenter lit the front alley;
infants could see the screen, laid flat against the floor of the alley, with the
box clearly visible behind it. The first experimenter raised her screen at the
approximate rate of 30 degrees per second until it had completed a 120-degree
arc, at which point it made contact with the box. She then reversed the
illumination condition of the alleys, so that the side alley became lit. The
second experimenter, who held his screen in readiness in the 120-degree
position, then lowered it to the floor of the alley, away from the infant, at
the same approximate rate of 30 degrees per second. The entire process was
then repeated in reverse. The second experimenter raised his screen back to
the 120-degree position, at which point the primary experimenter again re-
versed the illumination of the alleys and then lowered her screen down to its
original position against the floor of the alley.
Each full cycle of movement lasted approximately 12 seconds. The box re-
mained occluded for about 10 of these 12 seconds: it was in view only during
the first and last seconds, when the screen was raised less than 30 degrees.
Cycles were repeated without stop until the recorder signaled that the trial
had ended (see below). At that point, the first experimenter extinguished the
lights in the alleys and brought her screen back to its starting position.
Possible test event. This display was produced by the first experimenter
alone. After lighting the front alley, she raised her screen at the same rate
of 30 degrees per second until it had moved 120 degrees and contacted the
occluded box; she then lowered her screen back to its initial position against
the floor of the alley. Each cycle of movement--one 120-degree movement
away from the infant and one 120-degree movement back toward the infant-
lasted approximately 8 seconds. The box was totally occluded for about 6 of
these 8 seconds. Cycles were repeated without stop until the recorder signaled
that the trial had ended (see below). At that point, the first experimenter
extinguished the lights in the alley and returned her screen to its starting
position.
200 R. Baillargeon et al.
Habituation event. The habituation event was exactly the same as the im-
possible event, except that the yellow box was absent. Both alleys were used
to produce this event. We sought to habituate infants to the slight changes
in noise and illumination that accompanied the shifts between the alleys, to
minimize the possibility that such factors would lead infants to look longer
at the impossible event.
4.1,4. Procedure
Each infant was seated on a parent’s lap in front of the opening into the
front alley. The infant’s head was approximately 30 cm from the opening, 61
cm from the one-way mirror, and 152 cm from the back wall of the front
alley. The parent wore occluding glasses and was instructed not to interact
with the infant while the experiment was in progress.
The infant’s looking behavior was monitored by two observers who viewed
the infant through peepholes in the muslin frame that hung in front of the
apparatus. The observers could not see the experimental events and they
were not told the order in which the test events were presented. Each ob-
server was given a button box connected to an event recorder and was in-
structed to depress the button when the infant looked into the opening of the
display box. Inter-observer agreement for each infant was calculated on the
basis of the number of seconds for which the observers agreed on the direc-
tion of the infant’s gaze, out of the total number of seconds the habituation
and test trials lasted. Agreement was calculated for 18 of the infants and
averaged 93% per infant. The looking times of the primary observer were
also registered on a clock. By monitoring this clock, another assistant, the
recorder, was able to signal the ending of each trial and to determine when
the habituation criterion was met (see below).
Infants were presented repeatedly with the habituation event following an
infant-control procedure (after Horowitz, 1975). Each habituation trial ended
when the infant looked away from the event for 2 consecutive seconds after
looking at it for at least 4 consecutive seconds, or when the infant looked at
the event for 120 seconds. The inter-trial interval was 3 seconds. Habituation
trials continued until the infant reached a criterion of habituation: a 50% or
greater decrease in looking time on 3 consecutive trials, relative to the infant’s
looking time on the first 3 trials. If the criterion was not met within 14 trials,
the habituation phase was ended at that point. This occurred for only 1 of
the 21 infants. The other infants took an average of 7.35 trials to reach
criterion.
After the habituation phase, the yellow box was introduced into the front
alley. Infants were given two 3-second pretest trials to call their attention to
the presence of the box. During these trials, the screen lay flat against the
Object permanence in infants 201
floor of the alley, with the box standing clearly visible behind it. Following
these trials, testing began. Infants were given 3 pairs of test trials, with the
impossible and possible events being presented on alternate trials. Eleven
infants saw the impossible event first, and 10 infants saw the possible event
first. The criteria used to determine the ending of the test trials were the
same as for the habituation trials.
Of the 21 infants in the experiment, 5 contributed fewer than 3 pairs of
test trials to the analyses. Four infants contributed only 2 pairs, 3 because of
fussiness and 1 because the primary observer could not follow the direction
of his gaze. Another infant contributed a single pair: one pair was eliminated
because of fussiness and one pair because of equipment failure.
4.2. Control experiment
4.2.1. Subjects
Subjects were 22 full-term infants ranging in age from 4 months, 26 days
to 5 months, 29 days (mean age: 5 months, 10 days). An additional 8 infants
were eliminated from the experiment. 3 because of experimenter error, 1
because of equipment failure, and 4 because of fussiness. All infants were
from the Philadelphia area. Parents were contacted by phone and were com-
pensated for their participation.
4.2.2. Apparatus and events
The apparatus and events were the same as in the principal experiment,
except for the placement of the box during the familiarization and test trials.
The yellow box in the front alley was positioned 8 cm behind and to the left
of the screen so that the screen’s path of movement was not obstructed. Since
both the front and the side alleys were used in producing the HO-degree test
event, an identical yellow box was placed 8 cm behind and to the right of the
screen in the side alley.
4.2.3. Procedure
As in the principal experiment, infants were given habituation trials until
they met the habituation criterion. All infants met the criterion before com-
pleting 14 habituation trials; the mean number of trials to criterion was 7.32.
Following habituation, infants were given two pretest trials during which the
screen lay flat against the floor of the alley, with the yellow box to one side.
To minimize the possibility that infants would attend only to the box on the
test trials, the pretest trials were presented using an infant-control procedure.
Specifically, each pretest trial ended when the infant looked away from the
display for 2 consecutive seconds after looking at it for at least 4 cumulative
202 R. Baillargeon et al.
seconds. Each pretest trial lasted 9.18 seconds on average. Following these
trials, infants were given 3 pairs of test trials, with the 180- and the 120-degree
events being presented on alternate trials. Twelve infants saw the 180-degree
event first and 10 saw the 120-degree event first. The criteria used to deter-
mine the beginning and end of the habituation and test trials were the same
as in the principal experiment. Inter-observer agreement was calculated for
21 of the infants and averaged 92% per infant.
Of the 22 infants who participated in the experiment, 5 contributed fewer
than 3 pairs of test trials to the analyses, due to fussiness: 4 contributed 2
pairs and 1 contributed 1 pair.
5. Result
5.1. Principal experiment
The results of the principal experiment were clear-cut: infants showed a
strong, consistent preference for the impossible over the possible test event.
Figure 3a presents the mean looking times during the habituation and test
phases of the experiment. Infants’ looking times during the test trials were
compared by means of a 2 x 3 x 2 mixed model analysis of variance with
Order (impossible or possible event first) as the between-subjects factor and
with Trial (first, second, or third pair of test trials) and Event (impossible or
possible) as the within-subjects factors. Since the design was unbalanced, the
SAS GLM procedure (SAS Institute, 1982) was used to calculate the analysis
of variance. The only significant effect was that of Event, F( 1,83) = 13.66,
p = 0.0004.
5.2. Control experiment
The results of the control experiment were quite different: infants showed no
overall preference between the 180- and the 120-degree test events.
Figure 3b presents the mean looking times to the habituation and test
events. Infant’s looking times during the test trials were analysed as in the
principal experiment. There was no effect of Event, F(1,88) = 0.67, p =
0.4157. However, there was a significant effect of Trial, F(2,88) = 6.68, p =
0.0020, and two significant interactions: that between the Order and Event
factors, F(1,88) = 6.76, p = 0.0104, and that between the Order, Event, and
Trial factors, F(2,88) = 3.96, p = 0.0226. Analysis of the simple interaction
of Order and Event, for each test pair (Keppel, 1982, pp. 306-309), yielded
a significant interaction for the first (F(1,88) = 12.95, p = 0.0005) but not
Object permanence in infants 203
Figure 3. Looking times of subjects in the principal and control experiments to the
habituation and test trials. *
E
t-
60
50
40
30
20
IO
0
I- 60
ii?
3 50
8
J 40
30
20
IO
0
A. Princi
-2 - I
pal Experiment
i
Tent l
&ossible Event
-- v--
B. Control Experiment
-6 -5 -4 -3 -2 -I I 2 3
Habituation Trials Test Trials
*The habituation trials are numbered backwards from the trial in which criterion was reached.
204 R. Baillargeon et al.
for the second (F(l,SS) = 0.17) or the third (F(1,88) = 1.99, p = 0.1621) test
pair (note 1). To study the interaction obtained on the first test pair, an
analysis of the simple main effect of Event was conducted for each Order
condition (Keppel, 1982, pp. 309-311). These analyses revealed that infants
who saw the 180-degree event first looked longer at this event than at the
120-degree event, F(1,88) = 17.23, p = 0.00008, whereas infants who saw
the 120-degree event first looked equally at the two test events, F(1,88) =
1.17, p = 0.2815.
6. Discussion
The results of the principal experiment are easily summarized: infants showed
a marked preference for the impossible over the possible event. Further,
infants showed this preference on all three pairs of test trials, regardless of
the order in which they saw the two events. The results of the control exper-
iment were very different: only infants who saw the 180-degree event first
showed a preference for that event, and that only on the first test pair; infants
who saw the 120-degree event first looked equally at the two events on all
three test pairs. These results provide evidence that infants in the principal
experiment looked longer at the impossible event not because they preferred
the 180-degree screen movement, but because they expected the screen to
stop against the occluded box and were surprised, or puzzled, when it failed
to do so.
The results of these experiments indicate that 5-month-old infants under-
stand that an object continues to exist when occluded. These results suggest
that infants who, according to Piaget’s (1954) scale, have just entered stage
3 already endow objects with some permanence. Such results call into ques-
tion several aspects of Piaget’s description of the development of object per-
manence. First, they call for a reinterpretation of the behaviors-visual antici-
pations, interrupted prehensions, deferred actions, and so on-Piaget ob-
served in stage 3 infants. Piaget maintained that these behaviors reflect a
primitive phenomenalism, rather than a belief in object permanence: “In the
present behavior patterns . . . the search only continues the earlier act of
accommodation . . . the expected object is still related to the action itself” (p.
11). Since our results cannot be interpreted in terms of the extension or the
‘Because the design was unbalanced, we also analysed the simple effect of Order x Event for each test
pair using the method od unweighted means recommended by Myers (1979, pp. 109-119). The results of these
analyses were very similar to those reported in the text: Pair 1: F(1,88) = 11.67, p = 0.00096; Pair 2: F(1,88)
= 0.15; and Pair 3: F (1.88) = 2.31, p = 0.132.
Object permanence in infants 205
reproduction of an earlier action, they provide unambiguous evidence of
object permanence in stage 3 infants. As such, they suggest that Piaget was
mistaken in his interpretation of stage 3 behaviors and that these behaviors
are guided by a belief in object permanence, rather than by an egocentric
phenomenalism .
Second, our findings call for a reinterpretation of stage 3 infants’ failure
to search for hidden objects. Piaget (1954) believed that these infants do not
search because they do not yet view objects as permanent entities that con-
tinue to exist when concealed by other objects. Since our results indicate that
infants of 5 months do confer permanence to objects, they imply that factors
other than or in addition to infants’ beliefs about objects contribute to the
emergence of search behavior. What might these factors be? One relevant
factor might be the development of short-term memory (e.g., Bower, 1967).
Young infants might fail to search for hidden objects simply becayse they
forget their presence; as their memory improves, infants would become more
likely to remember, and to search for, hidden objects. However, there are
reasons to question this explanation. Piaget’s observations on deferred ac-
tions suggest that stage 3 infants can remember the location of objects for
several seconds at a time. In addition, the results of our first experiment
suggest that infants could remember the presence of the box behind the
screen for at least 3 seconds (the time it took the screen to reach the box
after it was occluded) and perhaps for as long as 6 to 10 seconds (the occlusion
times for the possible and the impossible events). Few search studies require
retention times longer than those.
A more likely explanation for young infants’ failure to search for hidden
objects, one already alluded to in the introduction, is that young infants may
be generally unable to coordinate separate actions into means-end sequences.
This explanation appears especially plausible in light of Uzgiris’s (1973) ob-
servation that infants begin to search for hidden objects at about the same
age they begin to engage in reversible actions, pushing and pulling objects,
crumpling and straightening them, putting them in and taking them out of
containers, and so on. It is as though infants began, at 8 or 9 months, to map
out their behavioral repertoire, discovering what actions produce what out-
comes, and then learning to combine these actions to achieve increasingly
complex goals.
We are not alone in proposing that search behavior reflects the interaction
of different factors. In recent years, investigators have identified several fac-
tors that appear to play a role in the development of search behavior in stage
4, stage 5, and beyond (DeLoache, 1984; Sophian, 1984). For example, three
factors that have been implicated in stage 4 infants’ search errors are a deficit
in memory for spatial locations (e.g., Bremner, 1978; Cornell, 1981; Cum-
206 R. Baillargeon et al.
mings and Bjork, 1977; Lucas and Uzgiris, 1977), a sensitivity to proactive
interference (e.g., Schacter and Moscovitch, 1983), and an inability to inhibit
repetitive actions due to poor neurological control (e.g., Diamond and
Goldman-Rakic, 1983).
We have questioned Piaget’s claims about the time at which object perma-
nence is attained, and the behaviors by which it is manifested. Despite these
differences, however, one aspect of Piaget’s (1954) theory seems exactly right
to us. According to Piaget, the development of the object is intimately tied
to the development of the concepts of time, space, and causality: “A world
composed of permanent objects constitutes not only a spatial universe but
also a world obeying the principle of causality in the form of relationships
between things, and regulated in time, without continuous annihilations or
resurrections” (p. 3). Like Piaget, we believe that a notion of object perma-
nence is not an isolated conceptual attainment but an inseparable aspect of
the infant’s knowledge of how objects behave in time and space. Our exper-
iments provide evidence that by 5 months of age, infants already appreciate
two aspects of the behavior of objects. First, they understand that an object
continues to exist when occluded, and that it exists not as a disembodied
image residing somewhere behind the occluder but as a solid, three-dimen-
sional entity occupying a specific spatial location. Second, they understand
that an object can move only through space not occupied by other objects.
Recently, researchers have begun to investigate infants’ knowledge of other
aspects of the behavior of objects. Their experiments suggest that young
infants understand that objects tend to move on undeviating paths (Baillar-
geon, 1984), to move continuously through space and over time (Spelke and
Kestenbaum, 1984), and to begin moving only when contacted by other ob-
jects (Leslie, 1984).
From this perspective, occlusion transformations are simply a subclass of
all the transformations that occur in the physical world, and the notion that
objects continue to exist when occluded is only one aspect of the infant’s
object concept. The general problem for research is not to establish whether
young infants believe objects are permanent. Rather, it is to determine what
infants know about the displacements and transformations of objects, and
how they attain and represent this knowledge.
References
Baillargeon, R. (1984) Reasoning about hidden obstacles: Object permanence in 6- to S-month-old infants.
Paper presented at the Biennial Meeting of the International Conference on Infant Studies, New York,
April.
Object permanence in infants 207
Bower, T.G.R. (1967) The development of object permanence: Some studies of existence constancy. Percep.
Psychophys., 2, 411418.
Bower, T.G.R. (1972) Object perception in infants. Perception, I, (1).
Bower, T.G.R. (1974) Development in Infancy. San Francisco: Freeman.
Bower, T.G.R., Broughton, J.M., and Moore, M.K. (1971) Development of the object concept as manifested
in the tracking behavior of infants between 7 and 20 weeks of age. J. exp. Child Psychol., 11,182-193.
Bower, T.G.R., and Wishart, J.G. (1972) The effectsof motor skill on object permanence. Cog., 1,165-172.
Bremner, J.G. (1978) Spatial errors made by infants: Inadequate spatial cues or evidence of egocentrism?
Brit. J. Psychol., 69, 77-84.
Cornell, E.H. (1981) The effects of cue distinctiveness on infants’ manual search. J. exp. Child Psychol., 32,
330-342.
Cummings, E.M., and Bjork, E.L. (1977) Piaget’s stage IV object concept error: Evidence of perceptual
confusion, state change, or failure to assimilate? Paper presented at the Meeting of the Western
Psychological Association, Seattle, April.
DeLoache, J.S. (1984) Oh where, oh where: Memory-based searching by very young children. In C. Sophian
(ed.), Origins of Cognitive SkilLr. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Diamond, A., and Goldman-Rakic, P. (1983) Comparison of performance on a Piagetian object permanence
task in human infants and rhesus monkeys: Evidence for involvement of prefrontal cortex. Paper
presented at the Annual Meeting of the Society for Neuroscience, Boston, November.
Gratch, G. (1975) Recent studies based on Piaget’s view of object concept development. In L.B. Cohen and
P. Salapatek (eds.), Infant Perception: From Sensation to Cognition. Vol. II. New York: Academic
Press, 51-99.
Gratch, G. (1976) A review of Piagetian infancy research: Object concept development. In W.F. Overton and
J.M. Gallagher (eds.), Knowledge and Development: Advances in Research and Theory (I). New York:
Plenum.
Harris, P.L. (1985). The development of search. In P. Salapatek and L.B. Cohen (eds.), Handbook of Infant
Perception. New York: Academic Press.
Horowitz, F.D. (ed.) (1975) Visual attention, auditory stimulation, and language discrimination in young
infants. Mono. Sot. Res. Child Dev., 39, (5-6).
Keppel, G. (1982) Design and Analysis: A Researcher’s Handbook (2nd edition). Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Prentice-Hall.
Leslie, A.M. (1984) Spatiotemporal continuity and the perception of causality in infants. Perception, in press.
Lucas, T.C., and Uzgiris, I.C. (1977) Spatial factors in the development of the object concept. Dev. Psychol.,
13, 492-500.
Myers, J.L. (1979) Fundamentals of Experimental Design. 3rd edition. Boston: Allyn and Bacon.
Piaget, J. (1952) The Origins of Intelligence in Children. New York: International University Press.
Piaget, J. (1954) The Construction of Reality in the Child. New York: Basic.
SAS User’s Guide: Statistics, 1982 Edition. Gary, NC: SAS Institute Inc., 1982.
Schacter, D.L., and Moscovitch, M. (1983) Infants, amnesics, and dissociable memory systems. In M. Mos-
covitch (ed.), Infant Memory: Its Relation to Normal and Pathological Memory in Humans and Other
Animals. Volume 9 in Advances in the Study of Communication and Affect. New York: Plenum Press.
Schuberth, R.E. (1983) The infant’s search for objects: Alternatives to Piaget’s theory of concept development.
In L.P. Lipsitt and C.K. Rovee-Collier (eds.), Advunces in Jnfuncy Research. Vol. 2. Norwood, NJ:
Ablex.
Sophian, C. (1984) Developing search skills. In C. Sophian (ed.), Origins of Cognitive Skills. Hillsdale, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum.
Spelke, E.S., and Kestelbaum, R. (1984) Spatiotemporal Continuity and Object Persistence in Znfuncy. Unpub-
lished manuscript, University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia.
Uzgiris, I.C. (1973) Patterns of cognitive development in infancy. Merrill-Palmer Quart,, 19, 181-204.
208 R. Baillargeon et al.
Une nouvelle methode a servi a etudier la permanence de I’objet chez les nourrissons. Des enfants de 5 mois
ont et6 habitues avec un Ccran bougeant d’avant en arriere a la fa~on d’un pont-levis. Apres atteinte du critere
d’habituation, une boite est placee derriere I’ecran. Les enfants sont confront& a dew situations: une situation
possible et une situation impossible. Dans la premiere situation, l’ecran s’arrete quand il atteint la boite
cachee, dans I’autre I’ecran continue sa rotation a travers I’espace occupt par la boite. Les resultats montrent
que les enfants regardent plus I’evenement impossible que I’CvCnement possible. Ce resultat indique que (I)
les enfants comprennent que la boite continue d’exister, a la m&me place, apres qu’elle ait ttC cachee par
I’tcran et (2) qu’ils s’attendent a ce que l’ecran s’arrete contre la boite cachee. 11s sont surpris ou intrigues
quand elle ne le fait pas. Une experience controle dans laquelle la boite Ctait plade a c&C de I’ecran conforte
I’interprttation des resultats. Pris dans leur ensemble, les resultats de ces experiences montrent que, contraire-
ment a ce que pensait Piaget (1954) les enfants de S mois realisent que les objets solides ne se dtplacent pas
a travers un espace occupt par d’autres objets solides.
... Burke, 1952;M. B. Burke, 1980), suggesting that human visual system may actively predict the trajectory and existence of occluded moving objects to maintain a consistent perception of a moving object (Baillargeon, 1987;Baillargeon et al., 1985;Clark, 2013;Friston, 2005;Leslie, 1984;Peters & Kriegeskorte, 2021;Spelke et al., 1995;Spoerer et al., 2017;Teichmann et al., 2022;Yuille & Kersten, 2006). ...
... This finding reveals that SCB can be sensitive to spatiotemporal continuity cues, but it may require a more compelling and naturalistic object motion context to emerge. Spatiotemporal contiguity effects have been frequently found for other aspects of object recognition in previous studies, indicating that the human brain can integrate elements of the same moving object in different time stages to maintain a stable experience (Baillargeon, 1987;Baillargeon et al., 1985;Flombaum & Scholl, 2006;Leslie, 1984;Mitroff & Alvarez, 2007;Spelke et al., 1995). ...
Article
Full-text available
People integrate “what” and “where” information to recognize objects. Even when irrelevant or uninformative, location information can influence object identity judgments. When two sequential stationary objects occupy the same location, people are faster and more accurate to respond (sensitivity effects) and are more likely to judge the objects as identical (spatial congruency bias [SCB]). Other paradigms using moving objects highlight spatiotemporal contiguity’s role in object processing. To bridge these gaps, we conducted two preregistered experiments asking how moving objects’ locations (trajectories) affect identity judgments, both at fixation and across eye movements. In Experiment 1, subjects fixated a constant location and judged whether two sequentially presented moving stimuli were the same or different object identities. The first stimulus moved linearly from behind one occluder to another. The second stimulus reappeared (still moving) continuing along the same spatiotemporal trajectory (Predictable trajectory), or from the same initial location (Same Exact trajectory), or a different location (Different trajectory). We found the strongest sensitivity and SCB for Same Exact trajectory, with a smaller but significant SCB for Predictable trajectory. In Experiment 2, subjects performed a saccade during occlusion, revealing a robust SCB for Same Exact trajectory in retinotopic coordinates, with a smaller SCB for Predictable trajectory in both retinotopic and spatiotopic coordinates. Our findings strengthen prior reports that object-location binding is primarily retinotopic after both object and eye movements, but the presence of concurrent weak SCB effects along predictable and spatiotopic trajectories suggests more ecologically relevant information may also be incorporated when objects are moving more continuously.
... From early childhood, infants begin to make sense of their surroundings through visual input, laying the foundation for their cognitive and intellectual development [1,2,3,4,5,6]. They effortlessly develop the ability to predict the trajectory of a thrown ball and understand causeand-effect relationships, such as the outcomes of collisions between objects [7]. ...
Preprint
Full-text available
Humans readily grasp physical principles via visual observation, underpinning our ability to model the world and reason about events. In contrast, AI systems often fail to extract consistent physical rules from video, relying on black-box mechanisms that produce implausible outcomes. We introduce the Intuitive World Model (IWM), designed to learn physical principles directly from vision, mimicking human intuition. Drawing inspiration from developmental psychology, IWM utilizes a modular architecture to decompose interactions into force-based dynamics. Through observing objects collide and interact via charges, it identifies intrinsic properties like mass and charge and learns representations analogous to Newton's and Coulomb's laws. This paradigm uniquely allows neural networks to provide explicit explanations for physical phenomena and conduct counterfactual reasoning consistent with learned physical laws. Our work demonstrates that a developmentally-inspired approach empowers AI to acquire explicit, interpretable physical knowledge from observation, mirroring a core aspect of human intelligence.
... This ability, known as intuitive physics (J. R. , enables comprehending physical concepts (Baillargeon et al., 1985;Baillargeon & Graber, 1987;Kim & Spelke, 1992), predicting physical dynamics (P. W. Battaglia et al., 2013;C. ...
Preprint
Full-text available
The role of mental simulation in human physical reasoning is widely acknowledged, but whether it is employed across scenarios with varying simulation costs and where its boundary lies remains unclear. Using a pouring-marble task, our human study revealed two distinct error patterns when predicting pouring angles, differentiated by simulation time. While mental simulation accurately captured human judgments in simpler scenarios, a linear heuristic model better matched human predictions when simulation time exceeded a certain boundary. Motivated by these observations, we propose a dual-process framework, Simulation-Heuristics Model (SHM), where intuitive physics employs simulation for short-time simulation but switches to heuristics when simulation becomes costly. By integrating computational methods previously viewed as separate into a unified model, SHM quantitatively captures their switching mechanism. The SHM aligns more precisely with human behavior and demonstrates consistent predictive performance across diverse scenarios, advancing our understanding of the adaptive nature of intuitive physical reasoning.
... Some researchers argued that he underestimated children's cognitive abilities. Subsequent studies showed that children could perform certain tasks at earlier ages than Piaget suggested when the tasks were simplified or made more familiar (Baillargeon, Spelke, & Wasserman, 1985;Gelman & Baillargeon, 1983). For example, younger children might demonstrate understanding of object permanence or conservation if tested in contexts that are meaningful to them. ...
Article
Full-text available
This study explores the developmental theories of Jean Piaget, Lev Vygotsky, and Michael Tomasello, three seminal figures in the field of cognitive psychology. Piaget's theory of genetic epistemology emphasizes the biological stages of cognitive development, highlighting how children construct knowledge through active interaction with their environment. Vygotsky introduces a sociocultural perspective, asserting that cognitive development is fundamentally shaped by social interactions and cultural tools, particularly language. Tomasello builds upon these foundations by integrating comparative primate studies, proposing that shared intentionality and cultural learning are unique to human cognition. Through a comprehensive examination of their theories, this study compares and critiques their contributions, illuminating the evolution of developmental psychology from individualistic to more socially and culturally integrated models. The analysis underscores the significance of integrating biological, social, and cultural factors in understanding cognitive development. The conclusion reflects on the enduring impact of these theorists on contemporary psychology and suggests directions for future research that bridges their perspectives.
... A more conceptual explanation of increasing visual scanning cannot be excluded completely, however. Infants show astonishment when objects appear not to be solih with other objects obstructing the spatial pathway or passing through them (Badlargeon, Spelke, & Wasserman, 1985;Spelke, 1988Spelke, , 1994Spelke, Breinlinger, Macomber, & Jacobson, 1992). Perhaps the years it takes children in middle childhood to improve visual search IS I~nked to the critical review of knowledge that objects must be solid and intact, which contradicts the changing understanding of space insofar as space and spatial axes extend infinitely through objects (Lange-Kiittner, 1994, Lange-Kiittner & Reith, 1995. ...
Article
Full-text available
The present study investigated whether sensitivity to object violations in perception as well as in action would vary with age. Five-, 6-, and 11-yr.-old children and adults solved tasks which involved perception only, motoric indication of parts, actual assembly of parts, and drawing of a violated figure. In perception, object violation was the only factor showing change across age groups, with violations being increasingly noticed. In composition tasks involving motor components, object violation was just one factor besides quantity of parts and type of segmentation contributing to task difficulty and showing increase in performance across age groups. Analysis of object violations in visual structure required abilities similar to those needed when analysing shape interference. Improved visual detection and graphic construction of object violation seemed not to occur because segmentation increased quantitatively but more likely because fast perceptual processes came under scrutiny.
... Some examples that blend online reasoning and dynamic physics utilise a Minecraft environment [Fan et al. 2022;Wang et al. 2023c], but they typically evaluate LM based agents performance on more general tasks such as exploration and skill acquisition, as opposed to specifically focusing on physics reasoning and understanding. Following investigations of intuitive physics [Kubricht et al. 2017] in human beings [Baillargeon 1995;Baillargeon et al. 1985;Kim and Spelke 1999;Spelke et al. 1992] and machine learning [Battaglia et al. 2016[Battaglia et al. , 2013Piloto et al. 2022;Smith et al. 2019;Watters et al. 2017], [Jassim et al. 2024] proposes the GRASP benchmark to evaluate more systematically intuitive physics understanding in multimodal LMs. Results stress a lack of perceptual understanding as a major shortcoming, that [Balazadeh et al. 2024] proposes to improve upon via simulation-to-reality fine-tuning of a modular, specialised visual LM. ...
Preprint
Full-text available
We present an interactive and explainable automated coaching assistant called CueTip for a variant of pool/billiards. CueTip's novelty lies in its combination of three features: a natural-language interface, an ability to perform contextual, physics-aware reasoning, and that its explanations are rooted in a set of predetermined guidelines developed by domain experts. We instrument a physics simulator so that it generates event traces in natural language alongside traditional state traces. Event traces lend themselves to interpretation by language models, which serve as the interface to our assistant. We design and train a neural adaptor that decouples tactical choices made by CueTip from its interactivity and explainability allowing it to be reconfigured to mimic any pool playing agent. Our experiments show that CueTip enables contextual query-based assistance and explanations while maintaining the strength of the agent in terms of win rate (improving it in some situations). The explanations generated by CueTip are physically-aware and grounded in the expert rules and are therefore more reliable.
Article
Full-text available
Humor is a universal aspect of human culture, serving both social and cognitive functions. This study investigates humor's influence on infant learning, focusing on physiological, behavioral, and emotional responses. Building on previous research, we examined three questions: (1) Does humor affect infants' behaviors during a social learning task, such as looking, laughing, and smiling? (2) Does humor enhance learning, and is this effect age-dependent? (3) Can arousal, measured by heart rate variability (HRV), explain the relationship between humor and learning? We tested 88 infants aged 14–22 months, exposing them to either a humorous or neutral demonstration of a tool-use task. We assessed infants’ performance after demonstration and coded social gazes and emotional reactions. We also analyzed physiological arousal indicators, namely heart rate variability (HRV), through a connected wristband. Our analyses revealed that infants exposed to humorous demonstrations showed enhanced learning compared to those in the neutral condition, independently of whether they laughed or not. This suggests that laughing does not mediate the effect of humor on learning. Additionally, infants in the humorous condition looked more at the experimenter, which could indicate increased engagement or attentional processes. Finally, our HRV analyses revealed that infants who succeeded in the task exhibited higher HRV than those who did not. This study is the first to explore the mechanisms underlying humor’s effect on infant learning, emphasizing its complexity and the need for a multidimensional approach integrating cognitive, behavioral, and physiological factors.
Article
Piaget and Spelke offer contrasting theories on the development of object permanence. Piaget suggests object permanence is a key milestone of the sensorimotor stage of development, occurring at 9 months of age, whilst Spelke proposes this develops earlier at 5 months. Their differing perspectives on the development of object permanence are reflective of their methods used to measure this (close observational studies of tasks or laboratory experiments using indirect measures of object permanence understanding). Their stances on object permanence reflect their broader perspectives on child development – whilst Piaget’s constructivist approach emphasises the importance of learning and environment interaction in development, Spleke emphasises the role of innate cognitive processes in providing a foundation for the development of concepts such as object permanence. This essay critically analyses these methods to explain how they have influenced both Piaget’s and Spleke’s conclusions on object permanence and other developmental milestones. By exploring the strengths and limitations of each framework, this essay evaluates their contributions to contemporary understanding of how knowledge develops in early childhood.
Chapter
Full-text available
The title of this book—infant memory—appears straightforward. On reflection, however, it becomes apparent that the term memory applies to many different facets of an organism’s ability to conserve and utilize the effects of its experiences. The multiple senses in which memory can be, and has been, used range from what Piaget and Inhelder (1973) labeled “memory in the wide sense,” including acquisition of skills, vocabulary, and adaptive responses, to what they labeled “memory in the strict sense”— the ability to consciously reflect on a specific incident in one’s personal past. Few would deny that it is possible to use the term memory in the foregoing manners. What are the consequences for the study of infant memory?
Book
The study of infant memory has flourished in the past decade for a number of reasons, not the least of which is the tremendous growth of interest in normal and pathological adult memory that began in the late fifties. Despite its common lineage to other areas of memory research, however, infant memory has perhaps been the least integrated into the mainstream. In reading the literature, one gets a sense of discontinuity between the study of infant memory and memory at all other stages of development from childhood to old age. The reasons for this are not hard to find. The techniques used to study memory in infants are usually very different from those typically used even in children. These techniques often limit the kind of inferences one can draw about the nature of the memory systems under investigation. Even when terms, concepts, and theories from the adult literature are applied to infants, they often bear only a loose relationship to their original usage. For example, an infant who stares longer at a new pattern than an old one is said to "recognize" the old one and to have a memory system that shares many characteristics with a memory system that makes recognition possible in adults. Simi­ larly, an infant who emits a previously learned response, such as a leg kick, to an old stimulus is said to "recall" that response and to be engaged in processes similar to those of adults who are recalling past events.
Article
Piaget found that infants in the first year of life will not remove a cloth or a cup that they have seen cover a toy. Part of the difficulty is a motor skill problem. However, deficits in motor skill are not sufficient to account for the failure in the situation. We cannot assume that out of sight is out of mind for such infants for they will reach out to obtain an object that has been made to go out of sight by switching off the room lights, leaving the baby in total darkness.RésuméPiaget a trouvé que les enfants de moins d'un an n'enlévent pas une couverture avec laquelle ils ont vu couvrir un jouet. Une partie de cette difficulté est due à des problèmes d'habilité motrice. Cependant nous estimons que les problèmes d'ordre moteur, ne suffisent pas pour rendre compte des échecs dans cette situation. On ne peut assurer que ‘être hors de la vue’ signife ‘être hors de l'esprit’ pour les enfants. En effet ceux-ci essayent d'attraper un object qui est devenu invisible lorsqu'on a éteint la lumière de la pièce en les laissant dans l'obscurité.
Article
… the object is known because of conformity to a prior conception … an idea is tentative…. It controls an action to be performed, but the consequences of the operation determine the worth of the directive idea, the directive idea does not fix the nature of the object [Dewey, 1960, p. 288].