ArticlePDF Available

Reconsidering Brain Death: A Lesson from Japan's Fifteen Years of Experience

Authors:

Abstract

Japan has been holding a nationwide debate over the nature of death for nearly twenty years. That debate led eventually to a law that gives citizens the opportunity to choose which of two views of death will apply to their own death. That law is now up for revision, and the debate is reving up.
Reconsidering Brain Death
: A Lesson from Japan’s Fifteen Years of Experience
Masahiro Morioka
-- Hastings Center Report 31, no.4 (2001): 41-46
Abstract: The Japanese Transplantation Law is unique among others in that it allows us
to choose between "brain death" and "traditional death" as our death. This paper reports
the ongoing revision process of the current law (as of 2001. See the Note at the end of
this paper).
*Page numbers in the original are marked by [(preceding page) / (following page)].
Western scholars have recently been entertaining doubts about what had
once seemed to be a settled consensus among them on the concept of death. In
1997, for example, Robert D. Truog pointed out several problems arising from
the concept of whole-brain death and showed us three alternatives, namely, (a)
returning to the traditional standard based on the permanent cessation of
respiration and circulation, (b) recognizing the objections of particular
religious views to the concept of brain death, and (c) giving permission to
remove organs from brain dead patients, patients in persistent vegetative
states, and anencephalic newborns whether they are alive or not (1). In 1999,
Stuart Youngner and colleagues published a collection of essays titled The
Definition of Death that featured reevaluations from various perspectives of
brain death and its alternatives (2). In this book, Robert Veatch argued that we
should permit patients to choose “an alternative definition of death provided
that it is within reason and does not pose serious public health or other societal
concerns” (3). Veatch insisted that whole-brain death should be the default
definition of death, but that we should permit, in addition, traditional
cardiopulmonary death and higher-brain death as reasonable minority views.
Finally, in 2000, Michael Potts and colleagues published another
collection, Beyond Brain Death, offering further objections to the concept of
brain death (4).
This is a strange scene to a Japanese bioethicists. Japan has held nationwide
discussions of brain death and transplantation since 1983, and the points that
have emerged in the recent Western writings are very familiar there. But
American and European bioethicists do not necessarily know of the recent
Japanese debates, mainly because of the language barrier. Japan’s Organ
Transplantation Law, enacted in 1997, permits people to choose between brain
death and traditional death by writing their preference on a donor card (5). It
is akin to the “conscience clause” found in New Jersey’s Declaration of Death
Act, which Veatch identifies as an attempt to allow people to choose an
alternative concept of death, and which Robert Olick said “signals a new
direction for the [41/42] development of public policy governing the
declaration of death in pluralistic communities” (6).
The Japanese transplantation law permitted organ translation in Japan, but it
also generated new problems we had not anticipated.
A Brief History of the Japanese Debates
Japan’s first heart transplantation from a “brain dead” patient was
performed in 1968, several months after the world’s first heart transplantation
in the Republic of South Africa. However, Dr. Juro Wada, who performed the
operation, was accused of illegal human experimentation and also of poor
judgment in the determination of death. This event engendered grave doubt
about brain death among journalists and the public. The heart “heart
transplantation” became taboo for fifteen years.
In 1983, the Ministry of Health and Welfare established an ad hoc
committee on brain death and transplantation, which then started to establish
criteria for brain death. At the same time, the Japanese Transplantation
Society began to publicize the necessity and urgency of organ transplants. In
1985, criteria for brain death were announced. The committee distinguished
“medical criteria for brain death” from “the concept of human death” and
declared that the latter depended on the consensus of the Japanese people.
Two well-known journalists, Michi Nakajima and Takashi Tachibana,
immediately published popular books that criticized the concept of brain
death. Nakajima insisted in her book, Invisible Death, that ordinary people at
the bedside of a family member could not accept brain death because the brain
dead patient’s body was still warm and moist (7). She concluded that brain
death is an “invisible death” that conflicts with everyday intuition. In Brain
Death, Tachibana analyzed the medical aspects of the concept of “whole brain
death” and concluded that the Japanese criteria for brain death could test only
the cessation of the brain’s observable functions, not the actual death of all
brain cells (8). He insisted that if some brain cells remained alive after the
determination of brain death (which is unknown, since an
electroencephalogram cannot detect the activities of cells deep inside the
brain), some inner consciousness might exist inside the patient’s brain, just as
in cases of “locked-in syndrome.” Their books became bestsellers.
Tachibana’s book sold more than 100,000 copies, and more than one hundred
other books concerning brain death and transplantation were published from
1985 to the early 1990s.
The Prime Minister’s special committee on brain death and transplantation
presented its final report in 1992. The committee reviewed the brain death
debates of the 1980s and concluded that brain death is human death and that
the donor’s prior intention to donate organs is necessary for organ removal.
But the report also contained a minority opinion that brain death should not be
considered human death. The objection to brain death was stronger than had
been anticipated. In 1994, an organ transplantation bill was presented to the
Diet to enable organ removal from brain dead patients if family consent was
obtained, but it did not pass. In 1997, two organ transplantation bills were
presented simultaneously to the Diet reflecting starkly opposed views of brain
death. One, introduced by Rep. Taro Nakayama, stated that brain death is
equivalent to human death. The other, introduced by Rep. Seiichi Kaneda,
stated that a brain dead patient is still alive but that organs can be legally
removed if two conditions are met ---- the donor has made a prior declaration
of a desire to donate organs, and the family consents to organ removal. A
harsh debate was provoked, and the Kaneda bill was rejected. Yet the
Nakayama bill was completely revised, and a unique law passed the Diet (9).
In 1999, Japan’s second heart transplantation from a brain dead donor was
performed (thirty-one years after the first). There have been fourteen
transplantation cases from brain dead donors up to the present.
Japan’s Organ Transplantation Law
The law does not provide a uniform answer to the question, “What is
human death?” Instead, it allows people to choose between traditional death
and brain death. The law states that if a person wants to be an organ donor
after brain death has occurred, he or she must record that intention on a donor
card or label beforehand. That person will then be considered dead when brain
death is diagnosed. Those who object to brain death and transplantation do not
need donor cards. They are considered to be alive until the heart stops beating.
Additionally, family consent is also necessary both for legally declaring death
at brain death and for organ removal. Strictly speaking, “family consent” in
this law means that the family does not express objections.
Thus in Japan we are free to choose which of two conceptualizations of
death will be legally recognized at our death. Japan’s transplantation law
shares this “pluralism on human death” with New Jersey’s brain death law,
but while New Jersey considers brain death the default definition of death,
Japan takes traditional death as the default.
It is illuminating to see how the law is to be applied. First, a patient is
“clinically” diagnosed as brain dead in a hospital. It should be noted that a
“clinical” brain death diagnosis is to be distinguished from a “legal” brain
death diagnosis. The clinical diagnosis is a tentative one. When a patient goes
into a deep coma, for example, physicians try to reach a clinical determination
of whether brain death has occurred. The determination does not require an
apnea test (that is, a test to see whether breathing has [42/43] stopped) since
the test might be detrimental to the patient’s body.
If the patient does not have a donor card, or has declared against
transplantation, then he or she is considered “alive” until the heart stops
beating. Physicians are not allowed to reach a legal diagnosis of brain death
(including an apnea test) on the patient.
If the patient has a donor card, and the patient has agreed to brain death
and organ donation (and designated the names of transplantable organs on the
donor card), then a transplantation coordinator comes and asks the family
members if they also agree to legal diagnosis of brain death and organ
removal for transplantation. If they agree, physicians start to make a legal
diagnosis of brain death following the Japanese criteria for brain death, which
include an apnea test. The transplantation team comes in. Organ procurement
begins.
There have been long discussions since 1997 of the pros and cons of this
law. The law is unique among contemporary brain death laws around the
world, but it has created problems we had never thought of before its
enactment. Three criticisms have been considered especially important.
First, many critics hold that the concept of human death should be one and
universal. According to the law, a patient without any brain functions is
“dead” if he or she carries a donor card and the family does not object to the
legal brain death diagnosis, but “alive” either if he or she does not carry a
donor card or if the family objects to brain death. Critics insist that this
variability is inconsistent and irrational. A similar argument was made in the
United States, where Alexander Capron called it the problem of a “bifurcated
legal standard” (10).
A second criticism has been that requiring the donor’s prior declaration is
too stringent a restriction. The most important characteristic of Japan’s Organ
Transplantation Law is that it makes the donor’s prior declaration of intent to
be an organ donor a necessary condition of organ removal. This means that
when a brain dead patient does not have a donor card, physicians cannot
remove organs even if the family members entirely agree to transplantation.
This restriction may mean that the law does nothing to increase the number of
removed organs. In many other countries, by contrast, organs can be removed
even if the donor’s wishes are unknown, as long as the family members agree
to the removal.
The donor’s prior declaration principle has a close connection to the law’s
pluralism on human death. If a brain dead patient lacks a donor card, then we
cannot determine whether that patient thought of brain death as human death.
Thus if the physicians make a legal brain death diagnosis, they may violate
the patient’s right to determine his or her concept of human death. Further,
such a violation would be a deep wrong: many Japanese think that a person’s
understanding of death is a very important and deeply personal thing that may
be unknown even to a person’s family members. This is the major argument
for requiring the donor’s prior declaration.
The donor’s prior declaration principle created a third problem, the
problem of qualification as a donor. In Japanese civil law, the will of a person
under fifteen is legally invalid. This implies that the donor card written by a
child under fifteen is also invalid; hence organ removal is impossible from
him or her. Unfortunately, however, the heart of an adult is too big to be
transplanted into a child’s body. For this reason, small children with severe
heart diseases are taken overseas to wait for brain dead child donors. Many
people are sympathetic to these recipient children.
These problems notwithstanding, public attitudes about brain death and
transplantation seem supportive of the basic framework of the present law. In
contrast to the United States, there have been many public opinion surveys in
Japan on brain death and transplantation since the 1980s (11). For more than
fifteen years, about 40 to 50 percent of the Japanese people have thought of
brain death as human death, and about 20 to 40 percent that brain death is not
human death.
In May 2000, the Prime Minister’s Office conducted a survey of the public
views of the donor’s prior declaration and family consent requirements (12).
In this survey, about 21 percent held that the donor’s prior declaration is
sufficient for the legal brain death diagnosis and organ removal, and that
family consent is not necessary. Seventy percent felt that both the donor’s
prior declaration and family consent are necessary. Only 2.1 percent felt that
family consent alone is sufficient and that the donor’s prior declaration is
unnecessary.
Proposals for Revision
A supplementary provision in the Organ Transplantation Law stipulated
that the law would be [43/44] reconsidered three years after its enactment, in
October 2000. Thus several proposals for revising the law appeared last year,
and a hot debate started again.
In August 2000, a research group on brain death and transplantation,
funded by the Ministry of Health and Welfare, submitted a report to the
ministry containing a proposal that had been drafted initially by Saku
Machino, a professor at Sophia University and a subdirector of the group (13).
The proposal held that brain death is equivalent to human death without
exception and that family consent is sufficient for organ removal unless the
brain dead person has previously refused to be a donor. In the case of a minor,
the consent of persons in parental authority is sufficient unless the minor brain
dead person has previously refused to be a donor. Most importantly, the
proposal would deny pluralism on human death and reject the donor’s prior
declaration principle, both of which are basic to the present law. Moreover,
the proposal goes on to assert that every one of us has already made an
“inherent self-determination” to be an organ donor. Some diet members and
recipient groups supported this proposal.
In December 2000, the Japanese Council for Transplant Recipients
announced another proposal that would deny pluralism on human death. This
proposal also held that brain death is equivalent to human death without
exception, but it asserted that for adults, both donor’s prior declaration and
family consent are necessary for organ removal. For children under fifteen,
the consent of persons in parental authority is sufficient.
Masahiro Morioka, the author of this paper, and Tateo Sugimoto, a child
neurologist, officially announced in February 2001 a proposal that had been in
the works for some time prior (14). The proposal held that for adults, both
donor’s prior declaration and family consent are necessary for the legal brain
death diagnosis and organ removal, and it went on to recommend that for
children under fifteen, similarly, donor’s prior declaration plus the prior
consent of persons in parental authority be required (15). Thus this proposal
took pluralism on human death and the requirement of a donor’s prior
declaration seriously and tried to extend them to children under fifteen. The
proposal came in two variants, one prohibiting organ removal from children
under six, on grounds that children under six lack the ability to express their
will consistently, and the other raising the age limit up to twelve.
The Morioka and Sugimoto proposal would never force children to express
their will concerning brain death and transplantation, however. It simply
suggests that we must hear children’s own opinions if we consider them
potential candidates for brain dead donors. The proposal may be viewed as a
compromise between the restrictions on organ removal in the current law and
the impetus to make organ transplantation possible for children with severe
heart diseases.
In Invisible Death, Michi Nakajima stated that transplantation might be
accepted, but the idea of brain death was totally unacceptable. In 1991, a
citizen group published a draft transplantation law that took up this idea. The
group argued that we did not have to define brain death as human death in
order to remove organs from brain dead donors. In 1997, Rep. Seiichi Kaneda
presented a bill to the Diet stating that a brain dead patient is alive but that if
the donor has made a prior declaration of intent to be a donor and the family
consents, organs can be legally removed from the brain dead patient.
Kaneda’s bill was rejected, but many people who are skeptical about brain
death still support his idea. One proposal for revising the Organ
Transplantation Law, developed in October 2000 by Yutaka Teruteru
Nishimori, a graduate student, rejects brain death but insists that the donor’s
prior declaration to donate organs is alone sufficient for organ removal from a
living brain dead adult (16). In effect, the Teruteru proposal pursues a limited
version of one of Truog’s alternatives, that of removing organs from brain
dead patients, patients in persistent vegetative states, and anencephalic
newborns even if they are considered to be alive. So far, however, there has
been no discussion of organ removal from patients in persistent vegetative
states and anencephalic newborns in Japan. There seems to be a tacit
consensus that removing organs from them would be unacceptable.
Finally, some have proposed a complete ban on organ removal from brain
dead patients. Through the 1980s and 90s, citizen groups that objected to the
idea of brain death accused the physicians who removed organs from brain
dead patients of homicide (17). This sentiment prompted Tomoko Abe, a
Member of Parliament, and her supporters to call for abolishment of the law.
The movement is supported by adherents of Oomoto-kyo, a new religion
based on Shintoism, who are distributing “anti-donor cards” to the public.
Ongoing Concerns
Japan’s Organ Transplantation Law has three pillars, namely, pluralism on
human death, the donor’s prior declaration principle, and family consent.
Pluralism on human death. The significant proportion of the Japanese
people who reject the idea of brain death usually say that a brain dead patient
whose body is warm and moist cannot be seen as a corpse because the essence
of humans exists not only in one’s mind, but also in one’s body. They reject
the notion that the essence of humans lies in self-consciousness and
rationality. They think that a warm, living body is an integral part of the
person. This view seems to draw some support from the ongoing physical
activities that brain dead people may engage in. Thus critics sometimes refer
to a [44/45] pregnant Japanese woman who reportedly gave birth to her child
while brain dead. They note that brain dead patients sometimes move their
hands toward the chest automatically and show a praying posture (known as
the Lazarus sign) (18). Even decerebrate posture (that is, an unusual extension
and rotation of limbs) has appeared in brain dead patients, which implies the
existence of some living neurons in the brainstem (19). And Alan Shewmon
has reported that many brain dead patients’ hearts continue beating for more
than a month (and in one case, for 14.5 years) (20). We must admit that a
brain dead person is completely different from a cold and pale corpse.
I think our right to choose which concept of human death will be applied
to our death must be defended. How we understand death is very important
for how we understand life, and so for how we understand ourselves. It is a
matter of personal philosophy and religious belief. And these different views
of death are not irrational. But at the same time, we should confine the choice
to traditional death and brain death. We must not enlarge death to include
persistent vegetative states or anencephaly. Bioethicists in the English
speaking world often speak of “cerebral death” as human death. But there are
reports of exceptional patients in a persistent vegetative state who recover
from it with intensive nursing care, and even become able to write and/or
speak (21). The difference between brain death and a persistent vegetative
state is that while the former never recovers, the latter has a slight chance of
recovery. I believe it should be our rule that a human being who can
voluntarily breathe is alive no matter what his or her condition is. Veatch
emphasized that an alternative definition of death should be “within reason.”
However, reasonable reasons might vary from one culture to another, and the
“reasons” bioethicists recognize might be different from those of ordinary
people.
Donor’s prior declaration and family consent. The principle that there
must be a prior declaration from the donor of a desire to donate organs is
based on the premise that we have the right to determine our own idea of life
and death, and also that we have the right to express our own will to donate
organs after brain death. It may be interpreted as a kind of self-determination
principle that protects the patient’s prior will from outside interference. The
requirement of family consent is based on the idea that human death happens
not only to the dying person, but also to the family members at the bedside.
This idea might sound strange, since it is the patient that is dying, but it is the
felt reality for many ordinary people in Japan that the dying person and the
family share the dying process and the death itself, and that even after the
diagnosis of brain death the family continues to share the dying process with
the patient. I have elsewhere called this phenomenon “brain death as a feature
of human relationships,” and Yoshihiko Komatsu has called it “resonating
death” (22). This so-called “human relationship-oriented analysis of brain
death,” which has become very popular in Japanese bioethics, suggests that
the family has some right to say something about the legal brain death
diagnosis and the removal of organs.
In my view, we should retain the donor’s prior declaration principle, even
if it may reduce the number of removed organs. For one thing, the stipulation
that donor’s prior declaration and family consent are required for brain death
diagnosis and organ removal is necessary to introduce transplantation from
brain dead donors to Japan, where many people are still skeptical about the
idea of brain death. Further, as noted, people should be accorded the right to
determine the criteria by which they will die, given its importance to their
lives. And finally, the decision whether to diagnose legal brain death is also a
matter of terminal care. When a person is clinically brain dead and does not
have a donor card, this may be a sign that we must keep away and leave the
body to a less heavily medicalized dying process.
The requirement for family consent when the clinically brain dead patient
has expressed a will to donate calls for further public discussion. It may be
that in such cases, the family’s objections should be ignored. This will be a
delicate and controversial topic for the Japanese.
The remaining big problem is organ removal from brain dead children
under fifteen. If we had not introduced the donor’s prior declaration principle,
we would never have faced such a difficult problem. Many Japanese seem to
think that the family can decide these cases. It is my personal view, however,
that children too should have the right to decide which concept of death they
will die under (23). The United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child
stipulates that children have the right [45/46] to express their opinions and
that adults are obligated to hear children’s voices. In Japan, about 20 to 40
percent of adults reject the idea of brain death, believing that organ removal
from “silent” children might well violate their unexpressed basic rights. At the
same time, I also share the sentiment that children with severe heart diseases
should be able to obtain heart transplantation. Thus the coming debate about
the Organ Transplantation Law will be very difficult and complicated.
Commentators on organ transplantation sometimes ask why the Japanese
continue to reject brain death while people in other countries have accepted it.
And several answers have been proposed (24). I want first to confirm that
most people in Japan accept brain death, according to opinion surveys.
Roughly 20 to 40 percent of the Japanese people object to brain death, but
recent studies show that roughly the same portion of the American population
shares these doubts (25). And in 1997, 30 percent of the German Diet
Members supported a bill declaring that brain death is not human death (26).
These reports suggest that 20 to 40 percent of the population in every country
might have some doubts about the idea that brain death is equivalent to human
death. Interestingly, the countries in which strong objections to brain death
appeared --- Japan, Germany, and Denmark --- were those that had something
like a nationwide debate on brain death in the 1980s and 1990s. In these
countries, the mass media covered the topic and ordinary people joined the
debate. In contrast, in North America and in some European countries, the
debate was restricted to the medical and bioethical spheres, and the views of
ordinary people were not necessarily reflected. Why does Japan have the
policy it does? In my view, it is because the country held a prolonged nation-
wide debate.
References
1. R.D.Truog, “Is It Time to Abandon Brain Death?” Hastings Center
Report 27, no.1 (1997):29-37.
2. S.J.Youngner et al., eds., The Definition of Death: Contemporary
Controversies (Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1999).
3. R.M.Veatch, “The Conscience Clause,” in The Definition of Death:
Contemporary Controversies, ed. S.J.Youngner et al. (Baltimore, Md.: Johns
Hopkins University Press, 1999), pp.137-60, at 140.
4. M.Potts, P.A.Byrne, and R.G.Nilges eds., Beyond Brain Death: The Case
against Brain Death Criteria for Human Death (Dordrecht, The Netherlands:
Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2000).
5. Veatch listed only one article concerning Japan, which published in 1991.
6. R.S.Olick, “Brain Death, Religious Freedom, and Public Policy: New
Jersey’s Landmark Legislative Initiative,” Kennedy Institute of Ethics
Journal 1, no.4 (1991): 275-88, at 285.
7. M.Nakajima, Invisible Death (Mienai Shi) (Bungei Shunju, 1985).
8. T.Tachibana, Brain Death (Noshi) (Chuo Koron Sha, 1986).
9. M.Nakajima, Brain Death and Organ Transplantation Law (Noshi to Zoki
Ishoku Ho) (Bunshun Shinsho, 2000).
10. A.M.Capron, “The Bifurcated Legal Standard for Determining Death”
in The Definition of Death, ed. Youngner et al., pp.117-36.
11. L.A.Siminoff and A.B.Bloch, “American Attitudes and Beliefs about
Brain Death,” in The Definition of Death, ed. Youngner et al., pp.183-93.
12. < http://www8.cao.go.jp/survey/zouki/index.html>
13. The full text of Machino’s Proposal is provided on the webpage:
http://member.nifty.ne.jp/lifestudies/ishokuho.htm. The information on the
ongoing revision process is provided by the web site of the International
Network for Life Studies, http://www.lifestudiesnetwork.com/.
14. M.Morioka, “Give Children Opportunities to Express their Opinions on
Brain Death and Transplantation by Donor Cards (Kodomo nimo Dona Kado
niyoru Iesu No no Ishihyoji no Michi o),” Ronza, March-April (2000): 200-
09. M.Morioka, “Protect the Donor’s Prior Declaration Principle (Zoki Ishoku
Ho, Honnin no Ishihyoji Gensoku wa Kenji seyo)” Sekai, October (2000):
129-37. The full texts are provided on the webpage:
http://member.nifty.ne.jp/lifestudies/ishokuho.htm.
15. The English translation of the Morioka and Sugimoto proposal is provided
on the web page: http://www.lifestudiesnetwork.com/. In the case of children,
“prior consent of persons in parental authority” must be written down “in
advance” on a donor card.
16. Y.T.Nishimori, “A Proposal for the Revision of Organ Transplantation
Law Based on the Anti-brain-death Argument (Noshi Hiteiron ni motozuku
Zoki Ishoku Ho Kaiseian ni tsuite),” Gendai Bunmeigaku Kenkyu 3 (2000):
139-79. http://www.kinokopress.com/civil/0302.htm.
17. Y.Watanabe, “Brain Death and Cardiac Transplantation,” in Beyond Brain
Death, ed. Potts et al., pp.171-90.
18. A.H.Ropper, “Unusual Spontaneous Movements in Brain-dead
Patients,” Neurology 34 (1984): 1089-92.
19. J.Marti-Fabregas et al., “Decerebrate-like Posturing with Mechanical
Ventilation in Brain Death,” Neurology 54 (2000): 224.
20. D.A.Shewmon, “Chronic ‘Brain Death,’” Neurology 51 (1998): 1538-45.
21. K.Higashi et al. reported on a sixty-one-year-old woman who was in a
vegetative state for three years before gradually recovering from it. She finally
regained the ability to read a newspaper and write her name skillfully.
K.Higashi et al., “Five- Year Follow-up Study of Patients with Persistent
Vegetative State,” Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery, and Psychiatry 44
(1981):552-54. See also W.F.M. Arts et al., “Unexpected Improvement after
Prolonged Posttraumatic Vegetative State,” Journal of Neurology,
Neurosurgery, and Psychiatry 48 (1985): 1300-03.
22. M.Morioka, Brain Dead Person: From the Viewpoint of Life
Studies (Noshi no Hito) (Hozokan, 1989, 2000)
http://www.lifestudiesnetwork.com/braindeadperson00.html;
Y.Komatsu, Death Resonates (Shi wa Kyomei suru) (Keiso Shobo, 1996).
23. See ref. 14, Morioka, “Give Children Opportunities to Express their
Opinions.”
24. Cf.M.Morioka, “Bioethics and Japanese Culture,” Eubios Journal of Asian
and International Bioethics 5 (1995): 87-90.
http://www.lifestudiesnetwork.com/japanese.html; M.Lock, “On Dying
Twice: Culture, Technology and the Determination of Death,” in Living and
Working with New Medical Technologies, ed. M.Lock et al. (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2000), pp.233-62.
25. See ref.11, Siminoff and Bloch, “American Attitudes and Beliefs about
Brain Death.”
26. K.Nakayama, “Anti-brain-death Arguments in the United States and
Germany (Amerika oyobi Doitsu no Noshi Hiteiron),” Horitsu Jiho 72, no.9
(2000):54-59.
(c)2001 The Hastings Center. Reprinted by permission. This article originally appeared in
the Hastings Center Report (2001).
Note: The Japanese transplantation law was revised in July 2009. “Pluralism
on human death” and “the donor’s prior declaration principle” were deleted
from the revised law.
... Dobrym przykładem jest tu Japonia. Liczni wierni reprezentujący tradycyjną dla tego kraju religię shinto nigdy nie zgodzili się z uznaniem tych, którzy są w śpiączce i których ciała są żywe, za zmarłych (Abe, 2001;Morioka, 2001). Potrafili zainicjować na rzecz tych pacjentów społeczną kampanię, w trakcie której opublikowano setki książek w ogromnym niekiedy nakładzie. ...
... Sprzeciwy te muszą być przez lekarzy uwzględnione. Masahiro Morioka podkreśla, że w Japonii diagnoza kliniczna śmierci mózgowej jest tylko diagnozą wstępną i "nie wymaga próby badania bezdechu", ponieważ "ta próba mogłaby być szkodliwa dla ciała pacjenta" (Morioka, 2001). Szczególnie widoczne stają się te dylematy w przypadku dzieci (Morioka, 2011: 108). ...
Article
Full-text available
The Montreal conference (2012) adopted the definition of death as „permanent loss of conscious- ness and permanent loss of all brainstem functions”. This definition aspires to cover with its scope all types of death that could be reduced to this definition as a phenomenon. This definition is based on the assumptions contained in the Harvard Report of 1968, which defined death as an irreversible coma. This approach to death has been criticized by some doctors, philosophers, theologians, lawyers, journalists and religious circles. In most countries, these protests were ignored by state legislation and the influential media, resulting in no apparent social opposition to the neurological criteria for death and the later introduced cardiac death criteria. In some countries, however, the legislation provides for the possibility of objecting to these death criteria, which allows them to be avoided for declaring death by anyone who disagrees with them. Japan and the state of New Jersey in the United States have developed statutory solutions for this purpose that could be an example for other countries. Meanwhile, this is not the case and the societies of most countries in the world have in effect imposed definitions and criteria of death with which 20–40% or even more citizens do not agree. This undermines their civil rights and therefore needs to be changed, especially since there is a desire for further legal changes that would legalize consent to death by organ donation (death by organ donation). This in turn would mean an open questioning of the principle that we do not kill some patients in order to save others, and the mission of doctors is only to heal patients, not to kill them.
Chapter
In this chapter, we discuss whether death requires permanent or irreversible cessation of function. We argue that death requires only permanent cessation of function, ultimately focusing on the application of this argument to determining death by neurologic criteria. Throughout history, we have relied on permanent cessation of function. The genuine possibility of reversing the cessation of function became real only from about the 1700s. The gradual introduction of the requirement of irreversibility reflects the ethical norm that everything should be done to revive a patient where this is possible and appropriate. However, this norm does not apply to patients for whom resuscitation is not appropriate. Since permanence covers both patient cohorts, it is a sound criterion for declaring death. Influential defenses of irreversibility, such as that of Don Marquis, are subjected to critical scrutiny.
Chapter
There are several foci of ethical concern when families and surrogates object to the declaration of death by neurologic criteria. This chapter examines the implicit metaphysical and moral commitments and dualism implied by neurologic criteria for death. When these commitments and worldviews are unshared by patients and surrogates, they give rise to distrust in healthcare providers and systems and to injustice, particularly when medicolegal definitions of death are coercively imposed on those who reject them. Equally concerning for justice is that the coercive force of laws and medical standards concerning death by neurologic criteria are disproportionately experienced by cultural, ethnic, and racial minorities. Ethical obligations to respect persons and patient autonomy, promote patient-centered care, foster and maintain trust, and respond to the demands of justice provide compelling ethical reasons for recognizing reasonable objections, defined as those objections that accept an already socially, medically, and legally recognized alternative, namely, death by circulatory-respiratory criteria.
Chapter
Medicine and health care generate many bioethical problems and dilemmas that are of great academic, professional and public interest. This comprehensive resource is designed as a succinct yet authoritative text and reference for clinicians, bioethicists, and advanced students seeking a better understanding of ethics problems in the clinical setting. Each chapter illustrates an ethical problem that might be encountered in everyday practice; defines the concepts at issue; examines their implications from the perspectives of ethics, law and policy; and then provides a practical resolution. There are 10 key sections presenting the most vital topics and clinically relevant areas of modern bioethics. International, interdisciplinary authorship and cross-cultural orientation ensure suitability for a worldwide audience. This book will assist all clinicians in making well-reasoned and defensible decisions by developing their awareness of ethical considerations and teaching the analytical skills to deal with them effectively.
Chapter
Medicine and health care generate many bioethical problems and dilemmas that are of great academic, professional and public interest. This comprehensive resource is designed as a succinct yet authoritative text and reference for clinicians, bioethicists, and advanced students seeking a better understanding of ethics problems in the clinical setting. Each chapter illustrates an ethical problem that might be encountered in everyday practice; defines the concepts at issue; examines their implications from the perspectives of ethics, law and policy; and then provides a practical resolution. There are 10 key sections presenting the most vital topics and clinically relevant areas of modern bioethics. International, interdisciplinary authorship and cross-cultural orientation ensure suitability for a worldwide audience. This book will assist all clinicians in making well-reasoned and defensible decisions by developing their awareness of ethical considerations and teaching the analytical skills to deal with them effectively.
Chapter
Medicine and health care generate many bioethical problems and dilemmas that are of great academic, professional and public interest. This comprehensive resource is designed as a succinct yet authoritative text and reference for clinicians, bioethicists, and advanced students seeking a better understanding of ethics problems in the clinical setting. Each chapter illustrates an ethical problem that might be encountered in everyday practice; defines the concepts at issue; examines their implications from the perspectives of ethics, law and policy; and then provides a practical resolution. There are 10 key sections presenting the most vital topics and clinically relevant areas of modern bioethics. International, interdisciplinary authorship and cross-cultural orientation ensure suitability for a worldwide audience. This book will assist all clinicians in making well-reasoned and defensible decisions by developing their awareness of ethical considerations and teaching the analytical skills to deal with them effectively.
Chapter
Medicine and health care generate many bioethical problems and dilemmas that are of great academic, professional and public interest. This comprehensive resource is designed as a succinct yet authoritative text and reference for clinicians, bioethicists, and advanced students seeking a better understanding of ethics problems in the clinical setting. Each chapter illustrates an ethical problem that might be encountered in everyday practice; defines the concepts at issue; examines their implications from the perspectives of ethics, law and policy; and then provides a practical resolution. There are 10 key sections presenting the most vital topics and clinically relevant areas of modern bioethics. International, interdisciplinary authorship and cross-cultural orientation ensure suitability for a worldwide audience. This book will assist all clinicians in making well-reasoned and defensible decisions by developing their awareness of ethical considerations and teaching the analytical skills to deal with them effectively.
Chapter
Medicine and health care generate many bioethical problems and dilemmas that are of great academic, professional and public interest. This comprehensive resource is designed as a succinct yet authoritative text and reference for clinicians, bioethicists, and advanced students seeking a better understanding of ethics problems in the clinical setting. Each chapter illustrates an ethical problem that might be encountered in everyday practice; defines the concepts at issue; examines their implications from the perspectives of ethics, law and policy; and then provides a practical resolution. There are 10 key sections presenting the most vital topics and clinically relevant areas of modern bioethics. International, interdisciplinary authorship and cross-cultural orientation ensure suitability for a worldwide audience. This book will assist all clinicians in making well-reasoned and defensible decisions by developing their awareness of ethical considerations and teaching the analytical skills to deal with them effectively.
Chapter
Medicine and health care generate many bioethical problems and dilemmas that are of great academic, professional and public interest. This comprehensive resource is designed as a succinct yet authoritative text and reference for clinicians, bioethicists, and advanced students seeking a better understanding of ethics problems in the clinical setting. Each chapter illustrates an ethical problem that might be encountered in everyday practice; defines the concepts at issue; examines their implications from the perspectives of ethics, law and policy; and then provides a practical resolution. There are 10 key sections presenting the most vital topics and clinically relevant areas of modern bioethics. International, interdisciplinary authorship and cross-cultural orientation ensure suitability for a worldwide audience. This book will assist all clinicians in making well-reasoned and defensible decisions by developing their awareness of ethical considerations and teaching the analytical skills to deal with them effectively.
Chapter
Medicine and health care generate many bioethical problems and dilemmas that are of great academic, professional and public interest. This comprehensive resource is designed as a succinct yet authoritative text and reference for clinicians, bioethicists, and advanced students seeking a better understanding of ethics problems in the clinical setting. Each chapter illustrates an ethical problem that might be encountered in everyday practice; defines the concepts at issue; examines their implications from the perspectives of ethics, law and policy; and then provides a practical resolution. There are 10 key sections presenting the most vital topics and clinically relevant areas of modern bioethics. International, interdisciplinary authorship and cross-cultural orientation ensure suitability for a worldwide audience. This book will assist all clinicians in making well-reasoned and defensible decisions by developing their awareness of ethical considerations and teaching the analytical skills to deal with them effectively.
Article
Full-text available
An 18-year-old girl suffered a severe head injury in a traffic accident. As a result, she was vegetative for about 21/2 years. She then showed signs of a gradually returning responsiveness. Six years after the accident, she is now able to comprehend and communicate, shows considerable interest in her surroundings and is able to establish interpersonal relationships. Moreover, the improvement is still continuing. Her severe contractures, however, prevent her from making full use of these regained mental capacities. Such a mental recovery after such a long-lasting vegetative state of traumatic origin has not previously been described.
Chapter
This stimulating collection of essays is the product of face-to-face dialogues among anthropologists, sociologists, and philosopher-historians, all of whom focus their attention on the newly created biomedical technologies and their application in practice. Drawing on ethnographic and historical case studies, the authors show how biomedical technologies are produced through the agencies of tools and techniques, scientists and doctors, funding bodies, patients, clients, and the public. Despite shared concerns, these essays reveal that the authors have achieved no consensus about the objectives of their research, and the deep epistemological divides clearly remain - making for provocative reading.
Book
Beyond Brain Death offers a provocative challenge to one of the most widely accepted conclusions of contemporary bioethics: the position that brain death marks the death of the human person. Eleven chapters by physicians, philosophers, and theologians present the case against brain-based criteria for human death. Each author believes that this position calls into question the moral acceptability of the transplantation of unpaired vital organs from brain-dead patients who have continuing function of the circulatory system. One strength of the book is its international approach to the question: contributors are from the United States, the United Kingdom, Liechtenstein, and Japan. This book will appeal to a wide audience, including physicians and other health care professionals, philosophers, theologians, medical sociologists, and social workers.
Article
"Whole brain death" (neurological death) is well-established as a legal standard of death across the country. Recently, New Jersey became the first state to enact a statute recognizing a personal religious exemption (a conscience clause) protecting the rights of those who object to neurological death. The Act also mandates adoption through the regulatory process of uniform and up-to-date clinical criteria for determining neurological death.
Article
Striking arm movements are described in five brain-dead patients. The arms flex quickly to the chest from the patient's side, the shoulders adduct, and in some patients, the hands cross or oppose just below the chin. The limbs then return to the patient's side, sometimes asymmetrically. These movements are precipitated after several minutes by hypoxia or ischemia when the ventilator is removed terminally, or during apnea testing. Families of brain-dead patients should be dissuaded from remaining in the room with the patient after the ventilator is turned off.
Article
One hundred and ten patients with persistent vegetative state, were followed up for a period of five years from 1973 to 1978. Seventy-three per cent of the patients died during the period while about 10% of them recovered partially from the vegetative state. Among the recovered patients, only three became able to communicate, but two of these are not independent for their daily activites. Reactivity and clinical symptoms of 30 survivors were examined, but no great changes occurred during the last two years of the study.
Article
Despite its familiarity and widespread acceptance, the concept of "brain death" remains incoherent in theory and confused in practice. Moreover, the only purpose served by the concept is to facilitate the procurement of transplantable organs. By abandoning the concept of brain death and adopting different criteria for organ procurement, we may be able to increase both the supply of transplantable organs and clarity in our understanding of death.