Article

Logical empiricism and psychiatric classification

Comprehensive Psychiatry (Impact Factor: 2.26). 01/1986; 27:101-14.
Source: PubMed

ABSTRACT Nosology has become a widely discussed topic in psychiatry with the appearance of DSM-III. Most current treatments of diagnostic categorization, however, presuppose a particular philosophy of science: logical empiricism. Ideas of Carl G. Hempel, a leading proponent of logical empiricism. can be shown to illuminate the contemporary classification of mental disorders. Moreover, the importance attached by many prominent psychiatrists to operational definitions in nosology can be seen to grow from logical empiricist roots. Even the etiology of mental disorders can be placed within a logical empiricist framework. We describe this logical empiricist position in order to prepare for alternative approaches to classification.

Download full-text

Full-text

Available from: Michael Schwartz, Jul 08, 2015
1 Follower
 · 
120 Views
  • Source
    • "If different clinicians labelled the same patients with different diagnoses, then the minimal basis for any scientific activity (namely, the use of technical words to mean the same things/phenomena) was at risk. Accordingly, nosographists worked on improving reliability and, following some of Hempel's suggestions (Hempel 1965; Schwartz and Wiggins 1986), they introduced in the classification operative diagnostic criteria aimed to provide a framework for comparison of data gathered in different centres and to promote communication between investigators (Feighner et al., 1972). It should be stressed that the study of Feighner et al., which can be considered as the most direct forerunner of the DSM-III, used the words illness, diagnostic category, disorder, clinical picture, syndrome, psychiatric condition as synonyms. "
    [Show abstract] [Hide abstract]
    ABSTRACT: In view of the publication of the DSM-V researchers were asked to discuss the theoretical implications of the definition of mental disorders. The reasons for the use, in the DSM-III, of the term disorder instead of disease are considered. The analysis of these reasons clarifies the distinction between the general definition of disorder and its implicit, technical meaning which arises from concrete use in DSM disorders. The characteristics and limits of this technical meaning are discussed and contrasted to alternative definitions, like Wakefield's harmful/dysfunction analysis. It is shown that Wakefield's analysis faces internal theoretical problems in addition to practical limits for its acceptance in the DSM-V. In particular, it is shown that: a) the term dysfunction is not purely factual but intrinsically normative/evaluative; b) it is difficult to clarify what dysfunctions are in the psychiatric context (the dysfunctional mechanism involved being unknown in most cases and the use of evolutionary theory being even more problematic); c) the use of conceptual analysis and commonsense intuition to define dysfunctions leaves unsatisfied empiricists; d) it is unlikely that the authors of the DSM-V will accept Wakefield's suggestion to revise the diagnostic criteria of any single DSM disorder in accordance with his analysis, because this is an excessively extensive change and also because this would probably reduce DSM reliability. In conclusion, it is pointed up in which sense DSM mental disorders have to be conceived as constructs, and that this undermines the realistic search for a clear-cut demarcation criterion between what is disorder and what is not.
  • Nordic Journal of Psychiatry 01/1987; 41(6):437-440. DOI:10.3109/08039488709097034 · 1.50 Impact Factor
  • Source
    [Show abstract] [Hide abstract]
    ABSTRACT: In their book, The Perspectives of Psychiatry, Paul R. McHugh and Phillip R. Slavney propose four basic perspectives to undergird and inform the practice of psychiatry. These are the perspectives of diseases, dimensions, behaviors, and life stories. The authors redescribe these four perspectives in terms of their underlying “logics”: law-governed causality, comparative and quantitative concepts, teleology, and narrative, respectively. After explicating the general nature of a psychiatric perspective, the authors show how such a perspectivism can resolve disputes concerning the different methods of psychiatry and how it can avoid the shortsightedness of sectarianism.
    Comprehensive Psychiatry 05/1988; 29:237-51. DOI:10.1016/0010-440X(88)90047-8 · 2.26 Impact Factor