Article

Self-awareness and action

Institute of Cognitive Neuroscience, University College London, 17 Queen Square, WC1N 3AR, London, UK.
Current Opinion in Neurobiology (Impact Factor: 6.77). 05/2003; 13(2):219-24. DOI: 10.1016/S0959-4388(03)00043-6
Source: PubMed

ABSTRACT In this review we discuss how we are aware that actions are self-generated. We review behavioural data that suggest that a prediction of the sensory consequences of movement might be used to label actions and their consequences as self-generated. We also describe recent functional neuroimaging experiments and studies of neurological and psychiatric patients, which suggest that the parietal cortex plays a crucial role in the awareness of action.

Download full-text

Full-text

Available from: Chris D Frith, Aug 23, 2015
1 Follower
 · 
197 Views
  • Source
    • "Indeed in adults , free will is not just a tool for explaining human actions in others or in general ; it is fun - damental to our agentive experience . Simple actions , such as moving my hand across a surface , or lifting my finger to press a button , feel to us as if they are freely willed – not caused by external forces , but rather by ' ' ourselves ' ' ( Blakemore & Frith , 2003 ; Haggard & Tsakiris , 2009 ; Wegner , 2002 ) . In Experiments 2 and 3 , we ask how chil - dren reason about choice as it applies to their own actions . "
    [Show abstract] [Hide abstract]
    ABSTRACT: Our folk psychology includes intuitions about free will; we believe that our intentional acts are choices and that, when such actions are not constrained, we are free to act otherwise. In a series of five experiments, we ask children about their own and others' freedom of choice and about the physical and mental circumstances that place limitations on that freedom. We begin with three experiments establishing a basis for this understanding at age four. We find that 4-year-olds endorse their own and others' ability to "do otherwise" only when they or others are free to choose a course of action, but not when others' actions are physically impossible (Experiment 1), their own actions are physically constrained (Experiment 2), and their own actions are epistemically constrained (Experiment 3). We then examine developmental changes in children's understanding of actions and alternatives that lead to more adult-like free will intuitions. Across two experiments, 6-year-olds, but not 4-year-olds, endorse another person's (Experiment 4) or their own (Experiment 5) freedom to act against stated desires. These age-related changes suggest relationships between a belief in free will and other cognitive and conceptual developments in theory of mind, self-control and self-awareness that take place in early childhood. Copyright © 2015 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
    Cognition 05/2015; 138. DOI:10.1016/j.cognition.2015.01.003 · 3.63 Impact Factor
  • Source
    • "These problems may result from abnormalities in processes underlying the experience of self-agency — i.e., the feeling that one causes one's own actions and the consequences of those actions. Indeed, patients often experience difficulties in distinguishing their own actions and subsequent outcomes from those produced by others (Schneider, 1957; Blakemore and Frith, 2003). "
    [Show abstract] [Hide abstract]
    ABSTRACT: People usually experience agency over their actions and subsequent outcomes. These agency inferences over action-outcomes are essential to social interaction, and occur when an actual outcome corresponds with either a specific goal (goal-based), and matches with action-outcome information that is subtly pre-activated in the situation at hand (prime-based). Recent research showed that schizophrenia patients exhibit goal-based inferences, but not prime-based inferences. Intrigued by these findings, and underscoring their potential role in explaining poor social functioning, we replicate patients' deficit in prime-based agency inferences. Additionally, we exclude the account that patients are unable to visually process and attend to primed information. Copyright © 2015 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
    Schizophrenia Research 04/2015; 164(1-3). DOI:10.1016/j.schres.2015.03.015 · 4.43 Impact Factor
  • Source
    • "Desmurget and Sirigu, 2009), it has been demonstrated that AHP follows a brain damage located within the same cortical network that is responsible for motor monitoring in the lateral premotor and insular cortex (Berti et al., 2005; Fotopoulou et al., 2010; Garbarini et al., 2012; Karnath et al., 2005; Moro et al., 2011; Vocat et al., 2010). Consequently, the well-established framework of a forward model of normal motor control (Blakemore and Frith, 2003; Wolpert et al., 1995) has been employed to predict the pattern of intact and impaired neurocognitive mechanisms pinpointing the distorted motor awareness of AHP patients. The model posits that, when a subject has the intention to move and the appropriate motor commands are selected and sent to the appropriate motor areas, a prediction (forward model) of the sensory consequences of the movement itself is formed on the efference copy of the programmed motor act. "
    [Show abstract] [Hide abstract]
    ABSTRACT: In anosognosia for hemiplegia, patients may claim having performed willed actions with the paralyzed limb despite unambiguous evidence to the contrary. Does this false belief of having moved reflect the functioning of the same mechanisms that govern normal motor performance? Here, we examined whether anosognosics show the same temporal constraints known to exist during bimanual movements in healthy subjects. In these paradigms, when participants simultaneously reach for two targets of different difficulties, the motor programs of one hand affect the execution of the other. In detail, the movement time of the hand going to an easy target (i.e., near and large), while the other is going to a difficult target (i.e., far and small), is slowed with respect to unimanual movements (temporal coupling effect). One right-brain-damaged patient with left hemiplegia and anosognosia, six right-brain-damaged patients with left hemiplegia without anosognosia, and twenty healthy subjects were administered such a bimanual task. We recorded the movement times for easy and difficult targets, both in unimanual (one target) and bimanual (two targets) conditions. We found that, as healthy subjects, the anosognosic patient showed coupling effect. In bimanual asymmetric conditions (when one hand went to the easy target and the other went to the difficult target), the movement time of the non-paralyzed hand going to the easy target was slowed by the 'pretended' movement of the paralyzed hand going to the difficult target. This effect was not present in patients without anosognosia. We concluded that in anosognosic patients, the illusory movements of the paralyzed hand impose to the non-paralyzed hand the same motor constraints that emerge during the actual movements. Our data also support the view that coupling relies on central operations (i.e., activation of intention/programming system), rather than on online information from the periphery.
    Cortex 06/2013; 49(6):1694-1703. DOI:10.1016/j.cortex.2012.08.017 · 6.04 Impact Factor
Show more